Manuskript Rauischholzhausen Steiner
Manuskript Rauischholzhausen Steiner
Manuskript Rauischholzhausen Steiner
„Eine Ansicht, welche das wahre Wesen der Historie vernichtet?“ Criticizing
the enlightenment’s view of man and history
Benjamin Steiner
Goethe-Universität Frankfurt
„An opinion that devastates the true essence of history“ – the deep conviction of telling
history how it actually took place, was common among historians long before Leopold
von Ranke coined his famous and still often quoted phrase: „wie es eigentlich gewesen“.1
In fact, it wasn’t the towering historian of the Germanic and Romanic peoples, but a
lowly school teacher from Augsburg who pleaded for a truthful history already in the
beginning of the 19th century. Georg Heinrich Kayser is long forgotten and not much is
known about his career and life. His only publication remains the Geschichts-Tafeln zum
Gebrauche der Gymnasial-Anstalten from 1812, a short collection of historical tables for
I chose the Geschichts-Tafeln by Kayser among many examples of the genre of Historical
Tabular Works, which appeared all over the early modern period in great number – I
counted well over 200 distinct titles which can be attributed to tabular historiography.3
1 Leopold von Ranke: Geschichten der romanischen und germanischen Völker von 1494 bis 1514.
Zur Kritik neuerer Geschichtschreiber, Leipzig / Berlin 1824, VI.
2 [Georg Heinrich] Kayser: Geschichts-Tafeln zum Gebrauche der Gymnasial-Anstalten von
Kayser, Professor am Gymnasio zu Augsburg, Zweyte veränderte und verbesserte Auflage, 1.
Heft, München / Burghausen: Ernst August Fleischmann, 1812; a second volume appeared only
in 1814. Kayser’s Geschichts-Tafeln does not seem to have received large attention, only very few
exemplars can be found in libraries today.
3 Cf. the online-database for early modern historical tabular works: Historische Tabellenwerke,
http://www.sfb-frueheneuzeit.uni-
muenchen.de/projekte/zusatz/HistorischeTabellenwerke/Index.html, 17.1.14; for extensive
discussion cf. Benjamin Steiner: Die Ordnung der Geschichte. Historische Tabellenwerke in der
Frühen Neuzeit, Köln / Wien / Weimar 2008; for a more general account on historical tables see
1
Kayser’s œuvre signifies the end of a period in which the writing history achieved a high
the Chronicon by Eusebius of Caesarea written around the year 311.4 This patristic
timelines in order to determine the greater anciennité of the biblical history against
pagan claims to chronologies that reached beyond the crucial year of 4000 BC – the year
of the creation of the world. Eusebius has been translated from Greek to Latin by
Hieronymus in the 6th century and served to be the standard textbook for history during
After the invention of print, tabular historiography remained popular, in fact, came
about to see its golden age. The 16th century has been for scholars, as Anthony Grafton
pointed out, a century of chronological science. Not only Martin Luther devised his own
tabular scheme to calculate the present point in time and in relation to the expected
arrival of Judgement Day – supposedly 6000 years after the creation of the world.6
Others, especially the late 16th century scholar from Leiden, Johann Justus Scaliger,
devoted his whole erudition and scholarly life to the study of chronology, which included
a modern edition of the Eusebius-Chronicon that marked one of the greatest philological
Anthony Grafton / Daniel Rosenberg: Cartographies of time. A History of the timeline, New York
2010.
4 Cf. the modern edition of Eusebius von Caesarea: Die Chronik des Hieronymus, hg. und in
zweiter Auflage bearbeitet im Auftrage der Kommission für spätantike Religionsgeschichte der
deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin von Rudolf Helm (Eusebius Werke, Bd. 7),
Berlin 1956.
5 Cf. for detailed analysis of the editorial history of this book A. Alden Mosshammer: The
Chronicle of Eusebius and Greek Chronographic Tradition, Lewisburg 1979.
6 Martin Luther: Supputatio Annorum Mundi D. M. Lutheri, Wittenberg: Georgium Rhau, 1541.
7 Cf. Anthony Grafton: Joseph Scaliger. A Study in the History of Classical Scholarship, 2 Bde.,
Oxford 1983/93; esp. II, Part 4 on the Thesaurus temporum (1606).
2
sophisticated in regards to the erudition involved in its making during the 17th and 18th
on this development in this volume, as can be studied in detail in his admirable book
Following, I want to extend on a point which seems to express not only a specific problem
of the history of historiography, but also of the general view of historians on the nature
of human being as historical agents. First, I will turn to Kayser’s Geschichts-Tafeln and
philosophical debate that arose in Germany around 1800. Kayser’s account is not one
3
movement known as German Idealism. But it represents a simple but widely distributed
belief that history in its essence should be more than a realization of a philosophical
idea. Having said this, I will show that Kayser argues not only against so called
speculative historiography, but also against an understanding of history that treats the
past by enumerating mere facts without grasping them as parts of a continuous whole –
thereby becoming somewhat speculative, too, but more in a Rankean than a Hegelian
sense. Finally, I will conclude in relating Kayser’s critique to the German enlightenment
contemporary August Ludwig Schlözer and his view on the historical agency in a history
as science. This will show that Kayser, taken as a representative of a commonly held
1.
4
Kayser’s Geschichts-Tafeln, of which I show here the first leaflet, appeared in their
second edition in 1812 – a second leaflet was obviously published a few months later, but
no exemplar is conserved as well as there is not a first edition to be found. The presented
digitalized example above is from the University Library in Munich. The first table
shows the beginning of history. Kayser dates it on the year 2000 BC – clearly framed in
Tafeln represent a secularized version of the categories according to Scripture and other
ancient texts. Typically, the nations that remain here are Egypt, Assyria, Syria, Juda
(the secularized Hebrew tradition), Phoenicia, Greece, and Italy; only Asia Minor –
Kayser does not mention sources, which is typical for authors of such historical tabular
accounts. What is, however, untypical for the early modern tradition is the rather
extensive and elaborate narrative on the different entries. Especially the first
chronological entries are revealing for the lacking brevity which was seen essential for
the facticity of the historical information in tables. For Egypt he notes for the year 2000:
„The social order established early. Influence of religion on the former. Priest caste, as a
allegorical pictorial script. Thebes.“ For Italy he states: „Uncertainty about the
5
indigenous population“, as he continues enumerating Umbrians, Etruscans, and
Ligurians etc.
Turning away from sweeping over the tableau, Kayser gives – as it is also common with
accounts of this genre – detailed instructions on how to use the tables properly. Also, he
manner and full of socio-philosophical programmtic ideas. History, in his opinion, has
reflecting on the inner depth of the human being („die innersten Tiefen seiner selbst“). It
is history that connects the individual to the deceased ancient societies. Thus, the
present time becomes clear to the individual as a result of all previous human
endeavours. And all the individuals that have once existed become alive again and while
being presented to the historian, Kayser writes in a rather Hegelian tone, he learns to
reflects on himself by looking at the deed of others. Therefore, history serves as the
earthly tribunal of the Last Judgement – das Weltgericht; and as such it is a principal
2.
this, then, the well known story of the German ideal of Bildung? This has been aptly
writes in Ueber die Aufgabe des Geschichtsschreibers, is nothing else than an act of a
11 Cf. Wilhelm von Humboldt, Über die Aufgabe des Geschichtsschreibers (1821), in: Gesammelte
Schriften, hg. v. Albert Leitzmann, Berlin 1905 ND 1968, IV, 35-56,
12 Georg G. Iggers, Deutsche Geschichtswissenschaft. Eine Kritik der traditionellen
Geschichtsauffassung von Herder bis zur Gegenwart, Wien / Köln / Weimar 1997, 80
6
Kayser strongly objects to this belief of the coninciding of subjective understanding and
the objective narrative. Instead, he attacks the central premice of German Idealism and
Since Schelling, Kayser writes, the before mentioned „opinion that devastates the true
rejects the conception of the human being that constitutes history a priori. The Idealist
treatment of history did not produce historical accounts as such, but rather a
matters one has no choice than to retreat on the material of history, the sources. As
luminary example serves Thucydides who not only treated things, „how they are“, and
expects tacit understanding for possible underlying ideas. He also gives individuals like
the Athenian politician Alcibiades a particular role as historical agent who does more
The down-to-earth criticism, that is put foreword by Kayser, is not without parallel. The
reason (as Hegel wanted it) or ethical ideas (as Humboldt saw it), and the general
distance towards a Zeitgeist of subjectivity have also led authors like Friedrich von
Schiller to a very distinct understanding of history in its most practical sense.15 Both,
Kayser and Schiller, saw it as their job to convey history, in the class room and on stage.
13 Cf. also Thomas Prüfer, Wilhelm von Humboldts „rhetorische Hermeneutik“. Historische
Sinnbildung im Spannungsfeld von Empirie, Philosophie und Poesie, in: ders. and Daniel Fulda
(ed.), Faktenglaube und fiktionales Wissen. Zum Verhältnis von Wissenschaft und Kunst in der
Moderne, Frankfurt am Main 1996, 127-166, and Hans-Michael Baumgartner, Die subjektiven
Voraussetzungen der Historie und der Sinn von Parteilichkeit, in: Reinhart Koselleck (ed.),
Objektivität und Parteilichkeit in der Geschichtswissenschaft, München 1977, 425-440.
14 Kayser 1812, Preface.
15 Cf. Friedrich von Schiller: Was heißt und zu welchem Ende studiert man Universalgeschichte?
Eine akademische Antrittsrede, in: Der teutsche Merkur, 4 (1789), 105-135.
7
History, therefore, had to stand aside philosophical conceptions and ideal constructions.
While Schiller divised narrative strategies to overcome this philosophical bias, Kayser
turned to the sources (Quellen) and to facts (Thatsachen) – the material for his historical
tables.
3.
There recurs the old 18th century struggle between the Göttingen historians Johann
Christoph Gatterer and August Ludwig Schlözer of how to write universal history.16
Gatterer claims to study historical facts in detail, with all „precision“ that can be
attained by using all the auxiliary sciences like chronology, heraldy or meterology.17
Schlözer, by contrast, prefers to see history „as a whole“; no racial and cultural
distinction, like the enlightenment historians of France and Scotland would have it, but
Geschichts-Tafeln and his insistance on sources and facts have to be situated in this
Every study, writes Kayser, that leads to a thorough knowledge of history, has to start
with the sober collection of facts. This can only be achieved by looking directly at the
historical sources. Through second-hand knowledge one only enters the realm of
speculation. Facts and source material, however, should facilitate the free discourse of
16 Cf. Gierl 2012, bes. 366 ff.
17 Johann Christoph Gatterer, Vom historischen Plan, und der darauf sich gründenden
Zusammenfügung der Erzählungen, edited by H. Blanke / D. Fleischer, Frommann-Holzboog ed,
Theoretiker der deutschen Aufklärungshistorie. Band 2: Elemente der Aufklärungshistorik
(=Fundamenta Historica 1.2), Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt 1990, 621-662; Johann Christoph Gatterer:
Einleitung in die synchronistische Universalhistorie zur Erläuterung seiner synchronistischen
Tabellen, 1. Aufl., Göttingen: Vandenhoek, 1771.
18 August Ludwig Schlözer: Vorstellung seiner Universal-Historie, Göttingen, Gotha: Johann
Christian Dieterich, 1772, 5 f.
8
history in the class room: „Der frey gehaltvolle Vortrag“ – the freely held, wholesome
lecture, captivates the youthful mind. To speak freely, without constraints, Kayser
continues, cannot be learned, that quality can only be acquired by birth, through God.19
No matter how one sees it, history has to be understood by its framework, its Gerüst,
that includes dates, names of places and persons. Kayser is aware of the usual criticism
and ridcule that has been uttered by his contemporaries about this „earlier“ form of
historical education. The mnemonic technics like historical tables were seen as tiresome,
boring and even falsifying a correct understanding of history. Schlözer called it memory
necessity of tables, and gives three reasons: 1) Tables denote what everybody has to
know by heart; 2) they serve for preparation, in the sense that they elude to numbers,
names and places in fashion that they seem to be familiar during the lecture; 3) they
consists that the table compels the viewer to become active and attentive in forming the
raw material to organic life and to history with a „soul“. Tables, therefore, facilitate the
task to grasp history from its factual material state as a whole, as it has been wished by
Schlözer.
Zusammenhang“), the causalities of events, in short: history as it has actually took place.
Surprisingly, the tables in Kayser’s view do not serve precise historiography. On the
contrary, they are means to derive the essence of history from a mere collection of facts.
Usage of synoptic overviews, sweeping over the synchronic and diachronic relations,
immersing in the study of details constitutes the necessary activity of the student to
understand history as a form of communicating with the past. Kayser’s position is not
very far from the one of the speculative historians he criticizes in the beginning of his
19 Cf. Kayser 1812, Vorwort
9
preface. Only, he sees no disadvantage in studying the facts and sources beforehand very
closely, before he introduces via free discourse the element of life to the tabular
framework.
4.
Ludwig Schlözer. Schlözer believed in human agency in history. He did not see men as
mere willing executioners of a general course of history. His position, I would say, could
be described as being in the middle of the positivist approach of the historians connected
to the French and Scottish enlightenment (as well as his rival Gatterer) and the
Like Kayser, Schlözer seems to have been a teacher, a popular one, if one compares him
to his Göttingen colleague Gatterer, who had not as many listeners in his lecture on
universal history. This was no coincidence: Historians of this sort, emphasized history as
a story that everybody should understand – they saw the universality of universal
history not so much in its quantity and precision of encyclopedic knowledge, but more in
the general sentiment that history could convey concerning the general human
condition.
Schlözer’s premise was the universality of humanity in all cultures. One of his more
conjunctures: the second part of his being is indetermination.“20 In his Vorstellung seiner
Universal-Historie from 1772 Schlözer elaborated (as Gierl has shown, in opposition to
Gatterer’s precise history) also on the necessity of collecting the material from
specialized histories. It forms in its entirety the „aggregate“ of all histories, which
20 Schlözer 1772, 6: „Der Mensch ist von Natur nichts, und kann durch Conjuncturen alles
werden: die Unbestimmtheit macht den zweiten Theil seines Wesens aus.“
10
constitutes in a way whole.21 But the universal historian has to achieve a „system“, in
which world and mankind are united, and are selected, ordered and formed from all
parts of the aggregate in relation to each other. Only a general oversight that comprises
the whole can form the aggregate to become a system. All states of the earth have to be
How to achieve this universal unification? Schlözer proposes, very similar to Kayser, a
new form of historical tabular synopsis. These tables have to combine synchronistic
be shown in the tabular order contrary to a mere Zeitzusammenhang that does not relate
historical facts. But it cannot be achieved by mere artistry either, as would later be
In a later work, Über die Geschichtsauffassung from 1784, Schlözer ridicules both
He has to have all pure facta always standing by for his use; he must know „all“ facta
that lie in his subject; and he has to have all facta in a light order and comfortable
register in front of himself, since all the facts have to be right available during a possible
genial moment. This, Schlözer believes, is impossible. No painter can mix his colours all
by himself.23
fulfill five duties: He needs to know all facta without one exception, e.g. Charlemagne, in
11
homilis etc.; he needs to know all these facta in context – with diplomatic assidiousness –
but also, Schlözer adds, with the mentioning of all sources and evidence, that support
the factum or do not support it; he has to order the chaos of information chronologically,
has to pile up everything that happened, for example, in the year 800, divide it up, add
little numbers into the margins, apposite column titles, different colour codes etc.;
edition, not even a word about him, that cannot be found also at the proper place in his
excerpts. Such a book, Schlözer closes sardonically, he would title „Materia historiae
Caroli M.[agni]“.24
The latter type of historian, whom Nietzsche would have called an archivalist historian,
parodizes the empiricist and positivist historian that usually was associated with the
statistical treatment of history and man by enlightened philosophers. This polemic also
was directed against a certain scientific treatment of man, as it was proposed by the
Scottish Enlightenment.25 Kayser and Schlözer tried to find a middle way, basically with
performative aspect of making history come to life again. They called for active
participation of a reader of tables, for example, or pointed out the necessity of oral
persuasion during a lecture in the class room. History, therefore, could only be
The success of this approach to history became evident in the 19th century. Not so much
because historical knowledge became more precise, better documented or less religiously
biased, but because history meant something to people. History could serve as a human
24 Ibid., 595 f.
25 Cf. Annette Meyer: Von der Wahrheit zur Wahrscheinlichkeit: Die Wissenschaft vom Menschen
in der schottischen und deutschen Aufklärung (Hallesche Beiträge zur europaischen Aufklärung),
Tübingen 2008.
12
science in a sense that it did not need complex prerequisites to be properly understood.
History was about human beings. It was written by them, written about them, and
written for them. The purpose of history and historiography, that is how I understand
the sentiment of the Zeitgeist that is expressed in works by Kayser or Schlözer, was to
rather tautologically: as human beings saw themselves in the past through history.
13