DIALOGIC CONSTITUTIONALISM PDF
DIALOGIC CONSTITUTIONALISM PDF
DIALOGIC CONSTITUTIONALISM PDF
SCHOOL OF LAW
BY:
WYCLIFFE K. KOSKEY
LLB/264/14
SUPERVISOR;
SEPTEMBER, 2017
1
DECLARATION
I hereby declare that this is a product of my own work and to the best of my knowledge has
not been submitted to any other academic institution for grant of any educational award. Due
acknowledgement has been made of all the materials that have been used in preparation of
this dissertation.
SIGNATURE:……………………… SIGNATURE:…………………
SUPERVISOR
i
DEDICATION
I dedicate this to my beloved late Mum Anne Koskey whom I made a promise that some day
To my Dad and Mum, Pr. William Koskey and Mrs. Dorcas Koskey to whom they toiled
every day to see to it that I get every need required to undertake my studies. Thanks for your
“For he dedicated his heart to seek the law of the Lord and to do it, and to teach statutes and
ii
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
First and foremost, I want to thank God almighty for the enabling strength, good health,
wisdom during the process of writing this paper. Thank you, God, for everything that
whose guidance and insight, I have been able to write this paper. His ideas, information,
critic and appraisal has improved my research skills and has made the journey of
research a journey of exploring knowledge and wisdom. You have made me a scholar
sir.
To all my lecturers at Moi University School of Law, you have contributed positively to
To my brother Wilson Kipkoech Letting , his moral support and guidance has enabled
I am indebted to one Sandra Kosgey who worked with me, writing with me, editing my
work and reading it in every step of the way. Thank you my dear, it was not easy we
made it through.
To my friend and brother and partner in crime Isoe Joel Oyugi who also on his part
dedicated his time to read through my work and ask questions on the same. Your
To my dear friend and sister Emmaculate Lusigi. Thank you for being there for me, for
your moral support and encouragement in every step of the way. Thank you, I salute
you my dear.
iii
To my group members, Chileshe Kathy Kalimi, Justus Mutunga, Isaac Kawai Steve, John
Mwangi, Sylvia Andesia, David Kiplelgo, Lilian Wameyo, Loraine Sibika, Sharon
Merabtara, Nellie Nowel Masaki, Ajak Jok Ajak, Brian Waballa. I lack words to say you
are my family.
Finally to my good friends who helped me in one way or another; Valerie Kosgei,
You guys made my life in Law school one of the best. Wherever you shall be may the
iv
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS
v
LIST OF CASES
Kenyan cases.
Mitu-Bell Welfare Society v Attorney General Petition No. 164 of 2011(2013) Eklr
Kenya Airports Authority v Mitu-bell welfare society & 2 others Civil Appeal No. 218 of
2014(2016) Eklr
The institute of Social Accountability & Another v The National Assembly Petition No. 71 of
2013[2015] Eklr
Residents of Joe Slovo Community, Western Cape v Thubelisha Homes and Others 2009 (9)
BCLR 847 (CC)
vi
TABLE OF CONTENTS
DECLARATION ........................................................................................................................ i
DEDICATION ...........................................................................................................................ii
LIST OF CASES....................................................................................................................... vi
1.8 Conclusion...................................................................................................................... 14
vii
2.3.1 Separation of Powers. .............................................................................................. 22
2.5 Conclusion...................................................................................................................... 28
3.5 Conclusion...................................................................................................................... 41
ADJUDICATION. ............................................................................................................... 42
4.3.1 Dialogic Modalities According to Nicholas Orago and Miyawa O. Maxwel. ........ 47
viii
4.3.4 Judicial review and Striking Down of Legislations................................................. 60
4.5 Conclusion...................................................................................................................... 64
5.1 Conclusion...................................................................................................................... 66
BIBLIOGRAPHY .................................................................................................................... 73
ix
CHAPTER ONE
“I speak for bringing law back to politics and politics back to law” -Frank Michelman
1.0 INTRODUCTION
Constitutional Dialogue is a fairly contemporary and nebulous concept that has not been
clearly defined and conceptualized in the Kenya‟s jurisprudence. It connotes that in the
process of interpretation of the constitution; the courts should not be left alone to interpret but
should involve other levels of government. It has been argued that dialogue between courts
and other political branches of governance not only conceive constitutionalism but also
enable the innovative institutional features of the Bill of rights to be better incorporated into
Klare, it is an enterprise of inducing large scale social change through non-violent political
pro-active and inclusive deliberation on how best to interpret and implement the constitution.
The Courts being the guardian of the constitution ought to be at the forefront in ensuring that
the aspirations of Kenyans are met by the political branches of Government. However, Chief
Justice Hon. Fraser submits that “the relationship between courts and legislatures is complex
and challenging, it however need not be controversial and conflicted as long as each
1
Bateup , Christine A., "The Dialogic Promise: Assessing the Normative Potential of Theories of Constitutional
Dialogue" (2006) Brooklyn Law Review 71 New York University Public Law and Legal Theory Working
Papers .Paper 11.http://lsr.nellco.org/nyu_plltwp/11
2
Karle Klare, “Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism”(1998) 14 South Africa Journal on Human
rights 146,149
1
understands and respects the institutional role played by the other.”3The intricacies of this
Dialogue as a theory emerges from the literary world as a social phenomenon propounded by
Bakhtin who appraises that life is in its nature dialogic, meaning that to live is to participate
in dialogue: to ask questions, to heed, to respond, to agree. A person participates wholly and
communication. Zlatev expounds this theory to include an interaction between nature and
nurture.5 Bakhtin reconciles this by submitting that “discourse lives beyond itself in a living
impulse toward the object, that if we are to detach ourselves for the impulse we remain naked
capable of being applied beyond linguistics or literary criticism. 7 From a linguistic world,
In the legal sphere, Jürgen Harbemas and Frank Michelman emerge as the leading theorists of
dialogue. Habermas develops the notion of the “public sphere” as a discursive space, distinct
from the state in which citizens participate and act through dialogue and debate. 8 He
establishes the discourse theory which through a communicative power and the law as a
3
The Honorable Chief Justice Catherine A. Fraser, “Constitutional Dialogues Between Courts and Legislatures:
Can we Talk?”(2005) Forum Constitutionnel.
4
Mika Lahteenmaki and Hannele Dufya (Eds.) Dialogues on Bakhtin: Interdisciplinary Readings, “ From
„Psycholinguistic‟ to a dialogical psychology of Language aspects of the Inner discourse” (1998) University of
Jyvaskyla Centre for Applied studies ISBN 951-39-2408-4 pg. 87 See also Bakhtin, M.M. “Problems of
Dostoevsky‟s poetics” (1984) Trans. C Emerson.
5
Zlatev, J. “Situated embodiment: studies in the emergence of spatial meaning” (1997) Stockholm: Gotab
6
Bakhtin M.M “The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays”(1981) Edited by Michael Holquist and Translated by
Coryl Emerson University Of Texas press Austin and London
7
Holquist. M,“ Dialogism. Bakhtin and his world” (1990) London: Routledge. See also ibid( n. 4)
8
Ilan Kapoor, “Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism?” The relevance of the Habermas-Mouffe
Debate for Third world Politics(2002) Alternatives 27, 459-487. See also Habermas, “Structural
Transformation of the Public Sphere”, Thomas Burger, trans. (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1989); and Craig
Calhoun, ed. Habermas and the Public Sphere (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1992.
2
rights.9 Discourse to him is one intended to search for arguments and offer justifications,10 he
believes that it excludes no one though the only limits is demarcated by the force of those
with a better argument while the procedure is self-correcting hence participants can change
center of this discourse theory is the insistence on procedure and institutions but in addition
to this assertion, it must be inclusive, coercion free and open and symmetrical hence an ideal
speech situation.12 This theory has however immense criticism and alternative proposal due
to its limitations.13
Following the Habermasian school of thought, Frank Michelman14 develops the dialogic
conception of politics, in a response Owen Fiss‟ objections to any identification of law and
politics15 against the Critical studies movement16, argues that politics is normative activity
which he envisions as a process of reasons17, his concept sees politics as pragmatic which is
some kind of ethical argument that is historically and culturally situated and conditioned but
proceeds without foundations hence adopts a potentially transformative attitude towards that
history.18 He therefore finds a connection between politics and law though dialogue.
9
Jürgen Habermas “Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a discourse Theory of Law and Democracy;
Trans. By William Rehg (1996) The MIT Press, Cambridge Massachusetts
10
Habermas, “Theory and Practice” p. 18.
11
Habermas (Ibid. n.9)
12
Habermas, “Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action,” C. Lenhardt and S. Weber Nicholsen,
trans.(Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990),88-89, 197;
13
See for example Mouffe Chantal, “Deliberative Democracy of Agonistic pluralism”(2000) Political Science
Series 72 Institute of Advanced studies, Vienna December 2000; Anne Elizabeth Stie, “Evaluating the
Democratic legitimacy of Institutionalized decision-making procedures. A deliberative perspective (.nd)
ARENA, Centre for European Studies, University of Oslo
14
Frank L. Michelman,” Bringing the Law to Life: A Plea for Disenchantment” (1989) Cornell Law Review
Vol. 74 Issue 2 January 1989 pg. 256-269
15
Fiss, “The Death of Law”,(1986) 72 Cornell Law review 1,2, 9-10
16
Fiss, “Conventionalism,”(1985) 58 California Law Review 177; See also Fiss, Objectivity and
Interpretations,(1982)34 Stanford Law Review. 739. Cited from Fiss‟s Stevens Lecture
17
Ibid (n.14) pg. 256. See also Michelman, Conceptions of Democracy: The Case of Pornography Regulation,
(1989) 56 Tennessee Law Review.
18
Ibid( n. 14) pg. 256. See also D. Herzog, “Without foundations: Justification in Political Theory” (1985); R.
Rorty, “Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature”. (1979)
3
Both theorists provide perspectives on Constitutional adjudication and Constitution built on
Dialogue theories which form the center of this research, Constitutionalism, Michelman
opines, that it is a theory which as a normative political theory is characterized by its dual
Habermas, argues that in order to fulfil the socially integrative function of the legal order and
the legitimacy claims of law, court rulings must satisfy simultaneous conditions of consistent
constitutional adjudicators to be the organs or the generators of the public values upon whose
dialogism22, the object in this case is constitutionalism guided by the values. In the Kenyan
Constitutional adjudication falls under a transformative project but narrows down to the niche
played by the judicial institution of governance. It connotes the role played by the courts in
within that „holistic, value-based framework which the constitution repository bind its
people24, therefore the jurisprudence emanating from this value- drenched notion is known as
19
Ibid (n.14) pg. 256; See also Frank L. Michelman, “Law's Republic,” (1988) 97 Yale Law Journal. 1493,
1499-1503.
20
Michelman, Supra (n.19) p. 1529; See also CR. Sunstien, “Interest groups in American Public Law,” (1985)
Stanford Law Review 38: 59 where she arrives at reasoned analysis requirement geared towards the discursive
mode of the legislative process. Cited from Harbemas Ibid. (n. 9)
21
Fiss, Ibid (n. 16 above)
22
Bakhtin Ibid ( n. 6)
23
Dikgang Moseneke, “The Fourth Bram Fischer Memorial lecture on Transformative Adjudication”(2002)
Delivered at the Nelson Mandela Civic Theatre, Johannesburg, 25 April 2002.
24
Coetzee v Government of the RSA 1995 (4) SA 631 (CC) para 46 (per Sachs J)
4
transformative adjudication25, though Justice Sachs26 accepts the difficulty of this kind of
adjudication. Ideologically transformative adjudication draws form the liberal legalism school
of thought, this notion however faces the challenge that this kind of jurisprudence leads the
adjudication that calls for a conscious and proactive move which the researcher intends to
adjudication.
which provides for the appropriate remedies for enforcing the Bill of rights in any
proceedings brought under Article 22. Secondly is Article 20(5) which though arguable
implies that in enforcing any right under Article 43 if the state claims it does not have
resources; it is the responsibility of the state to show that the resources are not available but a
court or a tribunal may not interfere with a decision by a state organ. This provision implies a
model of dialogue though with a condition attached to it. Thirdly is, as argued by Peter W.
Hogg and Allison A Bushell that “where a judicial decision is open to legislative reversal,
modification or avoidance, then it is meaningful to regard the relationship between the court
invalidated legislations and suspended that invalidation to allow the parliament to rectify that
The concept of constitutional dialogue requires a proactive approach where the courts
imperatively goes beyond its powers or acts innovatively and creatively in opening up a
forum for dialogue. Therefore judicial activism is of essence in creating an environment for
25
Moseneke- Transformative Adjudication Ibid(n. 23).
26
Pretoria City Council v Walker 1998(2) SA 363 (CC) para 101
27
Moseneke- Transformative Adjudication Ibid (n.23)
28
Hogg, Peter W. and Bushell, Allison A. "The Charter Dialogue between Courts and Legislatures (Or Perhaps
the Charter of Rights Isn't Such a Bad Thing after All)." Osgoode Hall Law Journal 35.1 (1997) : 75-124.
http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol35/iss1/2
5
dialogue. The judiciary has been traditionally known as a court of finality in decision but
distributive justice demands that the best solution is through an involvement of all actors in
Separation of powers as a principle in the constitution has emerged as a challenge in the past
half a decade premised on the principle of distinct, independent yet interdependent. More
specifically the friction between the Courts and the Legislature hence threatening the
independence of the judiciary while threatening to cripple the government. The Concept of
making a critical decision on behalf of the majority.30 This study proposes a dialogic
approach to finding a better way for keeping the relation going for the good of the people.
The Kenyans engaged in deliberation and dialogue through the stake-holders and
representatives from across the country in coming up with the constitution. It‟s therefore
submitted that Kenyans as we implement the constitution ought to build within themselves a
value system and a culture modeled around Dialogic constitutionalism led by the courts.
This study is premised on the jurisprudence emerging from the court which implies a
difficulty in the exercise of separation of powers and judicial review. Dialogue implies “a
process by which a court of law, in structural suits, entertains an exchange and discussion
between litigants on how best to redress a human rights inconsistency of state policy or
action.”31It is described on the other hand that dialogue over Constitutional meaning should
29
Alexander M. Bickel, “The least dangerous Branch” 16 (Vail-Ballou Press, Inc. 2nd ed.
(1986)
30
Michael c. Dorf, “The Majoritarian Difficulty and the Theories of Constitutional Decision Making”(Dec
2010) Journal of Constitutional Law Vol 13:2 page 286-288
31
Miyawa O. Maxwell “Judicial Enforcement of Socio-Economic rights: A case for Dialogic approach in
crafting appropriate judicial remedies” G62/69047/2011 June 2014 Accessed from
http://erepository.uonbi.ac.ke:8080/xmlui/bitstream/handle/11295/74238/Mawaya_Judicial%20enforcement%20
of%20socio-economic%20rights.pdf?sequence=3
6
be conceived as taking place simultaneously between the judiciary and the democratic
interpretation.
This study explains two major concepts; First is the taking for dialogic approaches in
rights. The remedies provided under Article 23(3) which the word “appropriate relief”
implies an opportunity for innovation in coming up with the remedies. Secondly is the
declaration of invalidity of legislation and a suspension of its invalidation leaves room for
dialogic approach in letting the legislative arm rectify the law and ensure it meets the
In the case of Mitu-Bell Welfare Society v Attorney General33 invoked the structural interdict
where a dialogic model was invoked where upon the court called upon the state to assist by
showing if, and how, it is addressing or intends to address the rights of citizens to the
attainment of the social economic rights, and what policies, if any it has put in place to ensure
that the rights are realized progressively, and how the petitioners in this case fit into its
policies and plans.34This case became a new jurisprudence and implies dialogic approach in
enforcing socio-economic rights despite the fact that parties appealed and the Court of
Secondly in The Institute of Social Accountability & Another v The National Assembly36
32
See Bateup (supra) n. 1
33
Mitu-Bell Welfare Society v Attorney General Petition No. 164 of 2011(2013) eKLR
34
Para 78 in Mitu-bell case
35
Kenya Airports Authority v Mitu-bell welfare society & 2 others Civil Appeal No. 218 of 2014(2016) eKLR
36
The institute of Social Accountability & Another v The National Assembly Petition No. 71 of 2013[2015]
eKLR
7
Act(CDF Act). The court invalidated the legislation and in suspending the invalidation
asserted that it would be appropriate in these circumstances as it would allow the legislature
time to correct the defective legislation while avoiding chaos and disarray in a system that
has been established for over a decade.37This case implies of a model of Dialogue which
gives room for the other party to communicate back through a piece of legislation rectifying
This study seeks to establish a dialogic constitutionalism as a model concept of the process
of government capable to conceptualize and facilitate this process through judicial activism in
partnership with the other levels of government. It is submitted that in the process of
achieving a transformation of the society, a deliberative and dialogic model should be used as
a means to an end.
Constitutional dialogue seem impracticable and close to impossible unless a judicially activist
move is made it forms the center of going beyond tradition to transform without a dispute.
This study seeks to mitigate a solution to the difficulties arising from Separation of Powers
and the Counter-majoritarian difficulty and any other difficulty that may arise forthwith. The
study guided by a comparative analogy shall exam the impact the process of dialogue will
37
Para 148 supra
8
1.3 Research Questions.
Several questions arise in the exercise of Constitutional dialogue. But at the center of this is
study is the issue of under what model of Constitutional dialogue be actively implored in the
Kenyan Legal framework and what impact will it have on majorly the Bill of rights. Some of
by the courts?
2. How have the Kenyan courts been innovative and creative in modelling the
3. Is Dialogic model the best solution to the Counter- majoritarian difficulty and
Separation of powers?
Kenyan context?
mainly comparative analogy from foreign jurisprudence mainly the South African, Canadian,
1.5 Methodology.
The methodology implore here is qualitative. The research is based on analysis of existing
documents. Secondary methods of date collection have been used in the compilation of this
paper. These include: the use of textbooks, dictionaries of law, Journal articles, newspaper
articles and Internet sources. Scholarly writings from foreign jurisprudence have also been
used and also the 2010 Kenyan Constitution. Statutes have been used in considering the
9
process of Constitutional dialogue from the Legislature. Having a deeper analysis of these
There are a number of scholarly writings on Dialogic constitutionalism mainly from foreign
jurisprudence. Constitutional dialogue has been perceived based on the court‟s invocation of
their powers. These authors shall guide the researcher in exploring the loopholes arising from
importance to mention are two scholarly works in Kenya that have explored this area of
study, they however fail to critically asses the role of the court in dialogue. This study is
centered on this.
Christine A. Bateup38 analyzes the different theories of constitutional dialogue applied around
the world, providing each of its weaknesses and strengths as a model of dialogue, she
assesses the normative value of each theory. Bateup‟s argument arrives at a conclusion that a
fusion of the equilibrium and partnership models of Dialogue.39 Her analysis shall guide the
researcher in modelling and remodeling the Kenya theory of Dialogue through analysis of the
Peter W. Hogg and Allison A. Bushell40 enumerate the dialogue being undertaken by the
Canadian Supreme court in mainly striking down legislations and allowing the parliament to
re-aline that piece of legislation to the values in the Canadian Charter. Their model of
dialogue, in this paper, fails to provide the aspect of the power of the court to summon the
other arms of government to explain through a structural interdict. The authors therefore
38
Christine A. Bateup- The Dialogic Promise supra n. 1
39
Supra page 84
40
Hogg and Bushell (Ibid n. 28)
10
define their dialogic theory as where a judicial decision is open to legislative reversal,
modification, or avoidance, then it is meaningful to regard the relationship between the court
and the competent legislative body as a dialogue hence „Charter-speak‟41. The researcher,
will take into consideration the age of the Canadian legal system and shall be guided by their
experience and structure in determining how we can better develop of Dialogical framework.
Vanice Regina Lirio de Valle42 on the other hand draws the researcher‟s attention to the
Brazilian model of dialogic constitutionalism which emerges as a unique one from the
Canadian model. The author explores their history which like the Kenya‟s was transformed
though the promulgation of a new constitution. Their system introduces a constitutional made
of public hearings, Amicus curiae and office of the Justice- Rapporteur who plays a
significant role in dialogue. Among other unique features where the legislative arm fails to
act the court issues a writ of injunction to the legislative arm as omission. This model shall
guide us in expounding our model of dialogue to other areas especially the public.
approach based on the concept of minimum core obligations. She analyzes this comparison
economic rights to reality thus introducing the concept of translation which connotes the
process of realizing the socio-economic rights. Thus advocating for an open, responsive and
41
Supra n.38
42
Vanice Regina Lirio de Valle, “Dialogical Constitutionalism Manifestations in the Brazilian Judicial Review”
28th February 2015
43
Stu Woolman and Michael Bishop (eds), Constitutional Conversations (2008) Pretoria University Law Press.
44
Sandra Liebenberg, „Socio-Economic Rights: Revisiting the Reasonableness Review/Minimum core Debate
Chapter 18. Cited from Constitutional Conversations. (Supra n. 6) page 303
45
Marius Pieterse, „Reply: On „Dialogue‟, „Translation‟ and „Voice‟: A Reply to Sandra Liebenberg. Cited for
Constitutional Conversations. (supra n. 6)
11
substantive participation in the exercise of dialogue. Both authors agree that a transformative
interpreting socio-economic rights and seeks to apply their work in this thesis.
Keenan D. Kmiec46 explores the origin of Judicial activism and establishes its meaning
includes First invalidation of the arguably constitutional actions of other branches, secondly,
argues that the structural remedies adopted by the courts in enforcing Socio-Economic rights
in Latin America, he however submits that greater impact is achieved where constitutional
courts engage in “Dialogic Activism”. Thereby introducing this new concept and addressing
the political and institutional impact such actions hold on the society and government. This
study shall benefit from Cesar‟s work in determining the impact of Kenya‟s constitutional
concept applicable in the process of realizing the socio-economic rights. In its applicability,
he establishes three levels that is, at the political level in the development of legislative policy
and program framework, Secondly, is at the level of constitutional litigation in the courts and
finally, in fashioning of the judicial remedies after the conclusion of litigation. 50 Orago‟s
46
Keenan D. Kmiec, “The Origin and Current Meanings of Judicial Activism”(2004),92 California Law
Review 1441 Available at: http://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/californialawreview/vol92/iss5/4
47
Caesar Rodriguez- Garavito, “Beyond the Courtroom: The Impact of Judicial Activism on Socio-Economic
Rights in Latin America. (2011) Texas Law Review Vol 89:1669.
48
Orago Nicholas Wasonga, “Poverty,Inequality and Socio-Economic Rights: A Theoretical Framework for the
realization of socio-economic rights in the 2010 Kenyan Constitution.”(2013) Centre for Human rights,
University of Pretoria. 16th August 2013
49
Supra n.43 Chapter 3 pages 121-161
50
Ibid n. 43 Chapter 4 page 183
12
scholarships, despite being motivated by foreign jurisprudence establishes Kenya‟s ideology
of dialogue, he emerges from a unique school of thought, which the researcher shall heavily
rely on in developing the arguments of how best can a transformative mode of adjudication
Miyawa O. Maxwel51 in his thesis makes a case for dialogic approach in coming up with
judicial remedies which provides evidence of dialogue in the Kenyan constitution. The
scholar establishes the need and importance of applying dialogue in interpretation of socio-
economic rights provision with the other levels of government. This scholarship emerges as a
new conversation which needs to be explored and expounded upon guided by his yardstick.
Kenya, he introduces dialogic Judicialism which presupposes that the judicial arm of
government should share with others the role of constitutional interpretation and thereby
neutralizes the Counter majoritarian difficulty. The researcher seeks to apply his work as a
Chapter One is the proposal which is the general introduction of dissertation, it provides in
brief what the research shall discuss and achieve at the end.
Chapter Two shall conceptualize Dialogic Constitutionalism by defining and establishing its
theoretical basis as an emerging concept and its need as a solution to the Counter-majoritarian
perspective.
constitutionalism in the endeavor to guide the formulation of the Dialogic approach form the
51
Miyawa Ibid (n.29)
13
comparative jurisdiction. Which includes but limited to; South Africa, Canada, Brazil and
Columbia
Chapter Four shall deal with the Kenya‟s Dialogic Constitutionalism and shall undertake a
theoretical analysis guided by the comparative analysis. The practicality of this concept shall
Chapter Five finalizes this research by making recommendations and concluding the analysis
of this concept.
1.8 Conclusion.
In conclusion, this chapter lays the background for this study by theorizing the concept of
dialogue and further establishes the objective and the problem intended to be dealt with in the
study. The introduction leads the researcher to the next chapter which intends to
conceptualize Dialogic constitutionalism and lay basis for its application in separation of
14
CHAPTER TWO
2.1 Introduction.
society. It is a distinct ideology that creates certain obligation on the part of the judge
especially in public interest litigation. An understanding of this concept shall enable the
by the judicial arm of government. It requires a critical and analytical look as it will
greatly impact on the rationality, process and end-result of dialogue. The Constitution
through its provisions lays an obligation to the court to transform the legal culture and
this context, it shall highlight concerns in the process of adjudication that is separation
dialogic constitutionalism which had been theorized in the earlier chapter into the
developing democracies.
These are terminologies or concepts that Moseneke argues in his speech that it is an
invitation upon the judges and judicial officers to a new plane of jurisprudential
creativity and self reflection about the legal method, analysis and reasoning consistent
15
with the transformative roles.52 This obligation must be conceptualized and traced back
to its beginning. In order to establish this concept, I shall analyze two concepts;
Transformative constitutionalism must be looked at from the lens of legal culture and
legal history. Legal transformation endeavors a new schooling of the incoming and
constitutional values.54 The urgent priority being to transform the judicial mindset,55
this mindset requires an analytical outlook and discursive approach to the culture and
history of the society in that legal setting. Kenyan courts should embolden themselves
with judicial mindset alive to the historical and cultural setting of the Kenyan people
Legal culture, Karl Klare and Davis describe it to mean the characteristic legal values,
of lawyers at a given, historically situated time and place, this definition is not
52
Dikgang Moseneke- Transformative Adjudication” Supra n. 23
53
See K Klare- Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism Supra n. 2: “By transformative
constitutionalism I mean a long-term project of constitutional enactment, interpretation, and enforcement
committed (not in isolation, of course, but in a historical context of conducive political developments) to
transforming a country‟s political and social institutions and power relationships in a democratic, participatory,
and egalitarian direction. Transformative constitutionalism connotes an enterprise of inducing large-scale social
change through nonviolent political processes grounded in law. I have in mind a transformation vast enough to
be inadequately captured by the phrase „reform‟, but something short of or different from „revolution‟ in any
traditional sense of the word. In the background is an idea of a highly egalitarian, caring, multicultural
community, governed through participatory, democratic processes in both the polity and large portions of what
we now call the „private sphere”
54
Dennis M. Davis & Karl Klare, “Transformative Constitutionalism and the Customary Law” (2010) 26 South
African Journal on Human Rights. Pg 405
55
Du Plessis v De Klerk [1996] (3) SA 850 (CC); 1996(5) BCLR 658(CC) para 119(Kriegler J) where he stated
that “the inarticulate premises, culturally and historically ingrained”
56
Dennis M. Davis & Karl Klare ( Ibid n. 3)
16
professional sensibilities, habits of mind, intellectual reflexes, recurring argumentative moves
that which counts as persuasive legal argument; the enduring political and ethical commitments
that influence professional discourse; inarticulate premises that are culturally and historically
ingrained 57
narrative, encompassing both past and future, which gives meaning to thought and
actions .58It is different from political ideology since it differs from either being
particular country form the other. This leads the lawyers, in the absence of searching
and critical examination of the legal culture and its multifaceted and diffuse influences
on interpretive practices, to a deeply embedded cultural code to shape their ideas and
steer their reactions to legal problem.59 It is however submitted that the aspect of legal
culture that creates tension is not the historical aspect of it but the deeply entrenched
The notion of legal history or legal tradition, draws mainly from the common law and is
closely linked to the notion of legal culture. A legal history cannot be explicitly defined
but can be described based on the past, in the Kenyan context, Mutunga CJ (as he then
was , captures it in describing the intent of the constitution, that there is no doubt that
the constitution is a radical document, that looks to a future that is very different from
our past, in its values and practices. It seeks to make a fundamental change from the 68
57
Ibid See also Du Plessis v De Klerk (1996) 3 SA 850(CC) para 119
58
Chanock, “The Making of South African Legal culture 1902-1936- Fear, Favour and Prejudice” (2001) 23
59
Karl Klare (Ibid n. 1); See also AJ Van der Walt, “Legal History, Legal culture and Transformation in a
Constitutional Democracy”(2005) Stellenbosch University.
60
AJ Van der Walt( Ibid n. 59) page 5-6
17
years of colonialism, and 50 years of independence .61 In the South African context,
…what their constitution expressly aspires to do is to provide a transition from those grossly
of human rights; democracy and peaceful coexistence and development opportunities for all
for that tradition. The South African society was characterized by apartheid, inequality,
racism among others, AJ Van der Walt describes this legal history in the context of land
without constitutionalism64, abuse of political power among others. Legal history led to
the need for transformation to establish a new legal culture. This however cannot be
and application. I shall turn my attention to the notion of adjudication before embarking
on the above.
Judicial function can be best illustrated in the following short story: two people in the
state of nature are squabbling over a piece of property, they come to an impasse, and
rather than resorting to force, turn to a third party, a stranger, for a decision. The court
replaced by the sovereign sending out his officers throughout the realm to speak the
61
Jasbir Singh Rai & Others v Tarlochan Singh Rai& Others Petition No. 4 of 2012 (Review of Court of
Appeal judgment Civil Appeal No. 63 of 2001) para 89. See also In the Matter of the Principle of Gender
Representation in the National Assembly and the Senate Advisory Opinion of the Supreme Court (Reference No
2 of 2012) Para 8 Of Mutunga CJ Dissenting Opinion.
62
S v Makwanyane [1995] (3) SA 391(CC) para 62
63
AJ Van De Walt Ibid(n. 59)
64
Okoth Ogendo „Constitutions without constitutionalism: A reflection on an African paradox‟
18
law and to see it is obeyed.65 A conceptualization of adjudication greatly, though
arguably depends on the theory of law and the applicability of that law. This norm has
mechanism. Its appreciation will guide the researcher in determining what connotes
transformative constitutionalism.
At the core of judicial function is adjudication. Lon Fuller66, from his naturalist theory of
resolution which is similar to the above anecdote.67 )ts function includes adjudicative
bodies which owe their powers to the consent of the litigants as agreed upon
submissions and tribunals that assume adjudicative powers. 68 This idea of this concept
is traditional in the sense that it is centered on dispute resolution and does not
appreciate Public Interest litigation. Abram Chayes develops from this traditional
conceptualization, and underscores that the trial judge has increasingly become the
creator and manager of complex forms of ongoing relief, which have widespread effects
on persons not before the court and require the judge s continued involvement in
rather than a fact- finding, and upon finding a mischief a cure to it is devised.70
The Critical Legal realists, centered their theory of law on judging and therefore
65
Shapiro, Courts, in 5 Handbook on Political science 321-71 (F. Greenstein & N. Polsby eds. 1975
66
Lon L. Fuller, “The Forms and Limits of Adjudication” (1978-1979) 92 Harvard Law Review 353 at 354
67
See also Alec Stone Sweet & Jud Matthews, “Proportionality Balancing and Global Constitutionalism” (2008)
47 Columbia Journal Transnational Law 71 at 81
68
Lon L. Fuller (supra n. 66)
69
Abram Chayes, “The Role of the Judge in Public Law Litigation”(May, 1976) Harvard Law Review Vol. 89,
No. 7, pp 1281-1316 Accessed from http://www.jstor.org/stable/1340256
70
Abram Chayes (Supra n. 69) pp 1297
71
S Hoctor „Legal Realism‟ in C Roederer & D Moelllendorf Jurisprudence ( 2004) pp 158- By Formalism we
mean the idea that the legal process involves the mechanical application of rules, that judges decide cases „on
19
method and also on false distinctions between public and private law, they critique
externally the place of law in politics and society.72 Realists, as submitted by Elizabeth
progressively proposed a recognition of the politics of law with the private and public
realm and the need to engage both the rules and underlying values to change the rule,
this view has had particular implication in the South African Transformative project.74
adjudication in the context of structural reform, he puts it thus )t is the social process
because of the constitutional character of the public values. The Judge attempts to give
meaning to our constitutional values in the day to day running of the institution.77
This mode of adjudication is premised on the belief that our constitutional values
cannot be fully secured without effectuating basic changes in the structure of the
institution.78 Structural suits arose in the American legal system, whereby the Judges
had to confront state bureaucracy over constitutional values and had to undertake a
the basis of distinctly legal rules and reasons that justify a unique result, and that law and rights are discovered
not made.
72
WB Le Roux & K Van Marle „Crtical Legal Studies‟ in C Roederer & D Moellendorf (supra. 20) Chapter 10
73
E. Mensch „The History of Mainstream Legal Thought‟ in D Kairys(ed)(1998) in The Politics of Law; a
progressive: Critique 3 eds
74
Catherine Albertyn and Dennis Davis „Legal Realism, Transformation and the Legacy of Dugard‟ (2010) 26
South African Journal on Human Rights page 192 discusses the implication of legal realism on the South
African Transformative Constitution.
75
Owen M. Fiss „The Forms of Justice‟ (1979) Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series Paper 1220 Cited
from:
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers
76
Owen M. Fiss (Supra n. 75)
77
Ibid n. 75
78
Ibid n. 75 pp 2
20
restructuring of the organization and therefore eliminate the threat to the values.79 It
constitutional values, history and the social ideal to give meaning to the constitutional
values, he searches for what is true, right and just for not only the parties but the society
at large.80 According to Owen Fiss, the Judge is not a participant in the interest group
politics but that his main function is to give concrete meaning and application to the
constitutional values.81 Karle Klare raises the bar for this requirement, that
adjudication is or is supposed to be the most reflective and self- conscious the most
grounded in reasoned argument and justification and the most constrained and
structured by text, rule and principle. 82 It is not just to give a concrete meaning but to
The argument by Owen M. Fiss, laid the basis for the Transformative project in South
Africa and Kenya and other jurisdictions. Despite certain distinctions and improvement,
it has acquired a status of being a norm since in the American society, some aspects of
their legal culture and tradition were structurally transformed such as desegregation in
schools, but most of the African countries needed a complete transformation rather
79
Ibid n. 75, See for example Brown v Board of Education 347 US. 483(1954; Cooper v Aaron 358 US 1
(1958)
80
Ibid n. 75, See Dworkin Ronald, „No Right Answe‟r, In Law, Morality and Society (1977) Hacker & J. Raz
(eds.)
81
Ibid n. 75
82
Ibid n. 23
83
Ibid n. 75, See also Owen Fiss, „Objectivity and Interpretation‟(1982) Stanford Law Review 744-745; See also
Thomas Nagel, „ Subjective and Objective‟, in Mortal Questions 196(1979) Harvard Law Review.
21
than a structural reform, the basis laid by Owen, acts as a guide to the place of
certain concerns arise in Transformative adjudication which I shall explore in this part.
Law and politics, as put by Karle Klare and others, cannot be insulated from each other;
like all aspects of human and social life, the law is radically contextual, inescapable
positioned within a larger set of social and political structures that cannot be observed
other hand, opines that law is politics, in the context of being dialogic politics85
admonishing Owen Fiss on the death of law? 86, Frank Michelman reconciles this, in a
response to Owen Fiss, that laws is best understood as a form a politics hence making a
plea through dialogue, that we can bring the law back to politics and politics back to the
law.87 Politics therefore cannot be ignored in adjudication, they are either part or
against it. Two concerns among others arise concerning politics and adjudication these
When the legislative and executive powers are united in the same person, or in the same body of
magistrates there can be no liberty; because apprehensions may arise, lest the same monarch or
senate should enact tyrannical laws, to execute them in a tyrannical manner. Again, there is no
liberty, if the judiciary power be not separated from the legislative and executive. Were it joined
with the legislative, the life and liberty of the subject would be exposed to arbitrary control; for
84
Ibid n. 75 See also AJ Van der Walt Ibid n. 59
85
A. Boshoff, „Law as Dialogical Politics‟(2004) TSAR 2004.4
86
Owen M. Fiss-The Death of Law? Ibid 51
87
Frank Michelman- Bringing the Law to Life Ibid n. 14
22
the judge would then be the legislator. Were it joined to the executive power, the judge might
behave with violence and oppression. 88
It connotes, three distinct principles, first, that the same persons shall not form part of
more than one of the three organs of government, one organ of government should not
control or interfere with the work of another and finally that one organ of government
should not exercise the functions of another.89 Lord Artkins famously stated that power
tends to corrupt and absolute power corrupts absolutely . )n principle it means, the
therefore distributed, but each body acts as a check and balance against each other.
The ways and means of exercising the doctrine of separation of powers is unique in each
country in the modern democracy. The exercise of each power is intended to, by all
means possible, to ensure that there is no interference in the exercise of the distinct
function or that there is no tension existing between the three levels of government that
could cripple the government. The concern arises in the exercise of checks and balance
The Judiciary has time and again come under fire in the attempt to review decisions of
the Executive and Legislature. At certain times, tension has risen to an extend of
interfering with the workings of the judiciary. The issue being whether it is justified for
the courts, to interfere and purport to make decisions on behalf of the rest of the level of
government and on the other hand, whether the courts being guardians of the
constitution should defer from interfering with the political decision and stick
formalistically to what they are mandated to do. To deal with this issue, several scholars
88
Montesquieu „The Spirit of Laws Book XI‟ (1873) 174.
89
Montesquieu (supra n. 88)
90
Article 6(2) of the Kenyan Constitution.
23
have proposed for dialogue between the levels of government. However, the researcher
that when the Supreme court declares unconstitutional a legislative act or the action of
an elected executive, it thwarts the will of representatives of the actual people of the
here and now; it exercises control, not in behalf of the prevailing majority, but against
it. 91 Waldron goes further to argue …in allowing decisions by the courts to override
legislative decisions fails to satisfy the important criteria of political legitimacy .92 On
the contrary, Mark Graber justifies the role of judicial review that it does not serve to
thwart or legitimate popular majorities but rather, the practice alters the balance of
power between the various political movements that struggle for power in a pluralist
democracy.93 It essentially means, the problem or difficulty arising where the court
legislative action and court review. It is centered on public policy and opinion.
This difficulty arises where the Judges, who are unelected and perceived unpopular and
who are politically represented by the legislators by virtue of being voted in by the
people. When Judges invalidate a law, they potentially disrupt the relationship between
elected officials and their constituents.94 Friedman interrogates this concept and draws
91
Alexander M. Bickel- The Least Dangerous Branch Ibid. 29
92
Waldron, Jeremy „The Core of the Case against Judicial Review‟ Yale Law Journal‟ (2006) 115: 1346- 1406
93
Mark A. Graber „The Non-Majoritarian Difficulty: Legislative Deference to the Judiciary‟ (1993) Studies in
American Political Development 7(1); 35-73
94
Kastellec Jonathan P. „Empirically Evaluating the Counter-majoritarian Difficulty: Public opinion, state
policy and Judicial Review before Roe v Wade ‟ (2016) Journal of Law and Courts, Princeton University Cited
from http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c
24
to him, encompasses the …extent to which the judiciary is accountable to majority
will 95 while the substance majoritarianism involves, judicial decisions that interfere
with or actually comport with majority rule. 96 He goes further to break down that
seeks to respond on whether the courts have relied upon evidence of popular will in
deciding the case 97 and secondly, the result majoritarianism which examines whether
the actual results of judicial decisions correspond with that of the majority in
preference. 98
majoritarian and the next anti- majoritarian depending on the public opinion. It must be
understood that for a judicial decision to be counter- majoritarian, it must replace the
status quo with a new policy even farther away from the public s ideal point while for a
judicial decision to be pro-majoritarian, it must replace the status quo with a policy
closer to what the public prefers.99 It means that a simple critic or a dissent on the
the aim of transforming the society which may turn out to be either pro or counter
majoritarian depending on the legal culture and history. This therefore presents a
difficulty as it would certainly, render the judicial decision impracticable or bad law
95
Barry Friedman, „Dialogue and Judicial Review‟ (1993) Michigan Law Review 93: pp 588
96
Barry Friedman ( Supra n. 95) pp 589
97
Barry Friedman (Ibid n 95) pp 589
98
Barry Friedman(Ibid n. 95) pp 589 See also Bassok, Or, and Yoav Dotan “Solving the Counter-majoritarian
Difficulty?” (2013) International Journal of Constitutional Law 11 (1): 13–33 who make a similar distinction.
99
Berry, Chris, Ethan Bueno de Mesquita, and Jacob Gersen, „Pro-Majoritarian Courts.‟( 2013)
Working paper, Harris School, University of Chicago.
25
inclusive interpretation and a room for discussion before arriving at a decision that may
Lon Fuller, through his polycentric concerns defined as a matter in which a decision
would have a wide unforeseen consequences for a multitude of other people who are
not before the court.100 He envisions a mixed form of adjudication101 which he argues
that a process of collaborative decision making which ought to give an opportunity for
In Structural Reforms, Owen M. Fiss analyzes the place of the judge in giving meaning to
the values and provides a perspective on dialogue that the judge is entitled to exercise
power only after he has participated in a dialogue about the meaning of the public
values.104He goes ahead to establish that there are special qualities that are required in
dialogue, First he argues, that judges are not in control of their agenda, but are
100
Lon L. Fuller- The forms and limits of adjudication Ibid n. 66
101
L Fuller & KI Winston- The forms and limits of adjudication Ibid. 66, at 353.
102
Lon L. Fuller & Winston- The forms and limits of adjudication Ibid 66
103
Lon L. Fuller & Winston- The forms and limits of adjudication Ibid n. 66
104
Owen M. Fiss- The Forms of Justice Ibid n. 75
26
compelled to confront grievances or claims that would otherwise prefer to ignore. 105
Secondly, Judges do not have full control over whom they must listen to, 106 Thirdly,
that Judges are compelled to speak back or to respond to the grievance or the claim
and to assume individual responsibility for that response 107 and finally that Judges
must also justify their decisions .108 Therefore the task of a judge should be seen as
giving meaning to our public values and adjudication as the process through which that
Further, Chayes relying on Bentham s Judge and Company 110, puts it that judicial
participation should not be by way of sweeping and immutable statements of the law,
but in the form of a continuous and rather tentative dialogue with other political
itself in the dialogue and the power of judicial action to general assent over the long
Finally, Karle Klare justifies the place of dialogue in adjudication that in order to be
transformative and transparent, rights discourses and legal reasoning need to be more
candid and self-conscious about the politics of adjudication, indeed, they need to make a
105
Owen M. Fiss- The Forms of Justice Ibid n. 75 pp 13
106
Owen M. Fiss- The Forms of Justice Ibid n. 75 pp 13
107
Owen M. Fiss- The Forms of Justice Ibid n. 75 pp 13
108
Owen M. Fiss- The Forms of Justice‟ Ibid n. 75 pp 13
109
Owen M. Fiss- The Forms of Justice Ibid n. 75 pp 14
110
See C. J W Allen, „ The Law of Evidence in Victorian England‟ (1997) 54; See also Stephen C. Yeazell, „
Judging Rules, Ruling Judges‟, (1998) Law and Contemporary Problems Vol 61: No. 3
111
Abram Chayes( Ibid n. 69) pp 1316
112
Abram Chayes( Ibid n. 69), See also Alexander Bickel, „The Supreme Court, 1960: The Passive Virtues,‟
(1982) 75 Harvard Law Review 40, 47-51
113
Karle Klare Ibid n. 2
27
in the new South African legal regime that it lacks a strong tradition of substantive
Therefore, based on the above it is inevitable to assert that dialogue indeed plays a key
issues arising as we shall discuss later, that impede or render dialogue in transformative
adjudication close to impossible especially in a legal culture like the Kenyan one. A
2.5 Conclusion.
concept is therefore intertwined and is placed upon the Judge or the adjudicator to
facilitate dialogue to achieve a just and right decision. However, it should be noted
the researcher establishes that Dialogue can deal with these concerns.
The next chapter delves into a comparative study where Dialogic constitutionalism has
114
Karle Klare. Ibid n. 2
28
CHAPTER THREE
3.1 Introduction.
Dialogic constitutionalism has been developed in other jurisdiction, the model adopted
the Kenyan courts. It shall guide the researcher to understand the loopholes and find a
constitutionalism. This chapter shall endeavor to explore the Canadian, South African
shall seek to determine the place and role of the Judge in constitutional dialogue.
Before delving into comparative study. It must be understood that, Mark Tushnet
forms of judicial review.115 This approach however reckons its own weaknesses, which
David Landau develops a dynamic theory of judicial review which connote a set of tools
to exist between weak- form and strong form of judicial review, his argument is
developed from an understanding of the fragile level of our democracy. 116 Therefore as
much as dialogue is a weak form of judicial review, there is need to look into the method
dialogue theories, and arrive at an understanding that the mode of dialogue that has the
potential of the highest normative potential is one that fosters a society- wide and
115
Mark Tushnet, „Social Welfare Rights and the Forms of Judicial Review‟(2004) 82 Texas Law Review 1895.
See also Mark Tushnet, „New Forms of Judicial Review and the Persistence of Rights- and Democracy-Based
Worries‟,(2003) 38 Wake Forest Law Review 813, 821 835;
116
David Landau, “A Dynamic Theory of Judicial Role‟ (2014) Boston College Law Review November 2014
117
Christine A. Bateup- The Dialogic Promise Ibid n. 1
29
alive to the different models of constitutionalism and the levels of democratic maturity
Canadian legal framework, in it are provisions that distinctively limit the legislature and
makes provisions on derogation on rights that in turn promotes dialogue between the
judiciary and the legislature.118 Hogg and Bushell develop the notion of dialogue from
meaningful to regard the relationship between the court and the competent legislative
the courts review of the legislation to the charter values and requires them to carry out
the objectives or the legislature being forced to modify its objectives to accommodate
the concerns raised the courts.120 Their scholarship sparked a wide study on the subject
In Ford v Quebec121, the Supreme court of Canada struck down Quebec s law banning the
use of languages other than French in commercial signs, in a response after the decision,
a new law was enacted that continued to ban the use of any language but French in all
outdoor signs.122 In Rocket v Royal College of Dental Surgeons of Ontario123 where the
118
Sections 1 and 33 of the Charter of Rights and Freedoms 1982
119
Peter W Hogg and Allison A. Bushell- The Charter Dialogue between Courts and Legislatures Ibid n. 28
120
Hogg and Bushell- The Charter Dialogue between Courts and Legislatures Ibid n. 28
121
Ford v Quebec[1988] 2 SCR 712
122
Hogg and Bushell - The Charter Dialogue between Courts and Legislatures Ibid n. 28. Refer An Act to
Amend the Charter of the French Language, S.Q. 1988, c. 54, s. 10.
123
Rocket v. Royal College of Dental Surgeons of Ontario (1990) 1 SCR 232
30
new guidelines were enacted.124 It must be noted that such may take long before they
Dialogue, Hogg and Bushell assert that it can be an apt description of this relationship
between the courts and the legislative bodies. It is hard to claim that an unelected court
is thwarting the wishes of the people126; this argument propound dialogue as a solution
to the counter-majoritarian difficulty. The Charter speak, they purport that the resulting
purpose clauses suggests that the Canadian legislatures are engaging in a self- conscious
dialogue with the judiciary.127 They justify that any legislation is dialogue, because
legislative action is a conscious response from the competent legislative body to the
words spoken by the courts.128 Thus legislative sequel is dialogue hence charter speak.
Concerning the issue of politics and the law, they argue that judicial review is not a a
veto over the politics of the nation 129 but rather the beginning of a dialogue as to how
best to reconcile the individualistic values of the charter with the accomplishment of
social and economic policies for the benefit of the community as a whole.130
In a response to Hogg and Bushell, Christopher Manfredi and James Kelly131 in a find
empirical and normative issues to their thesis, that judicial nullification is an indicator
of judicial interference with the democratic will.132 They thus reckon that the dialogue
124
0. Reg. 220/94, s. 1 (enacted pursuant to the Dentistry Act, 1991, S.O. 1991, c. 24).
125
See for example Quebec (A.G) v Quebec Protestant School Boards (1984) 2 SCR. 66 which 9 years before a
new legislation was enacted.
126
Hogg and Bushell Ibid n. 28
127
Hogg and Bushell Ibid n. 28
128
Hogg and Bushell Ibid n. 28
129
Ronald Dworkin, “The Forum of Principle” (1981) 56 New York University Law Review 469 at 469
130
Hogg and Bushell Ibid n. 28 at 105
131
Christopher P. Manfredi & James B. Kelly, „Six Degrees of Dialogue: A Response to Hogg and
Bushell‟(1999) Osgoode Hall Law Journal 373: 513-527. Accessed from
<www://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol37/iss3/1>
132
Christopher Manfredi & James Kelly Supra n. 131 above
31
between courts and legislatures is both more complex and less extensive hence
developing the six degrees of dialogue which they further classify as either positive and
dialogue.133 They contend that legislative sequels must be positive exercise to constitute
genuine dialogue and to facilitate an equal relationship between judges and legislators
equal relationship and instead facilitates a hierarchical relationship that limits genuine
dialogue.134 Baker and Knoff135 emphasize this notion on the dialogue being a two- way
lingers around hence terming the charter design a bad thing. (ogg, Bushell and
Wright137 revisit the implication of their theory on the Supreme court since 1997, the
court in Vriend v Alberta138, )acobucci J. made a general point out that the work of the
legislature is reviewed by the courts and the work of the court in its decisions can be
Bastareche J notes that Judicial review was not a veto over the politics of the nation,
but was rather the beginning of a dialogue between courts and legislatures.140
133
Christopher Manfredi & James Kelly Ibid n. 131; “Positive Dialogue is characterized by legislative actors
amending sections, while negative dialogue involves elected officials repealing Acts and Sections of Impugned
laws, engaging in legislative “Prequels” before the Supreme Court of Canada decides a case”
134
Christopher Manfredi & James Kelly Ibid n. 131
135
Baker D and Knopff R. „Minority retort: A parliamentary power to resolve judicial disagreement in close
cases‟
(2002) Windsor Yearbook of Access to Justice 21: 348.
136
See Christopher Manfredi & James Kelly Ibid n. 131
137
Peter W. Hogg, Allison A. Bushell Thornton and Wade K. Wright, “Charter Dialogue Revisited: Or “Much
Ado About Metaphors”( 2007) Osgoode Hall Law Journal 45.1: 1-65. Retrieved from:
<www://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol45/iss1/2>
138
(1998) 1 S.C.R 493 at 566-67
139
M v H [1999] 2 S.C.R 3 at 181
140
Supra n. 139 at 181
32
Iacobucci J, carries on this theme in Bell Express Vu Limited Partnership v Rex141 where in
justifying striking down a legislation, that it would force parliament to revisit the issue,
that in this way, a forum for dialogue among the branches of governance would be
retained142. Emanating from this, they hold that there is no need to invoke the idea of
dialogue in order to insist that judge not engage in reconstructive surgery on legislative
The above cases imply the appreciation of the idea of dialogue by the Canadian Supreme
court after Hogg and Bushell developed this notion. However, arising from this revisit,
finding that legislative responses should not count as dialogue because they amount to
Thus, to reconcile this, the researcher notes the nature of this idea of dialogue still
developing and the it metaphorical and normative remodeling as scholars still delve
into it. It is submitted that this conversation on dialogue shall greatly guide the
141
[2002] 2 S.C.R 559
142
Supra n.141 at 598-99, this was a minority view.
143
Hogg, Bushell and Wade Ibid n.137
144
Emmett MacFarlene, „Dialogue or Compliance? Measuring legislatures‟ policy responses to court rulings on
rights‟(2013) International Political Science Review 34:39 Accessed from
<www://ips.sagepub.com/content/34/1/39>
33
3.3 South Africa.
The Kenyan constitutional framework shares a great similarity with that of the South
Africa despite different legal history, the transformative initiative shares great
rights that courts in granting appropriate remedies may grant.145 It requires parties to
report back to court, which therefore acquires the courts a supervisory jurisdiction
upon the government and other actors, known as ex post jurisdiction.146 The researcher
in assessing the South African jurisprudence shall concentrate on the place of the
Structural interdict, Owen Fiss defines it to be the formal medium through which the
into conformity with the Constitution. The judge seeks to reform institutions by
efforts. Structural interdict has certain salient characteristics, First, the court establishes
the breach of a right by the government, then directs that government to fulfil its duties
under the constitution subsequent to which the government and other actors are
required to prepare and present before the court the detailed situation report which is
mostly by way of affidavits on the possible solutions.147 Secondly, the court assesses
through a hearing process involving all parties which the court ways against the
145
Rosalind Dixon, „Creating Dialogue about Socio-economic Rights: Strong Form versus Weak Form Judicial
Review revisited‟(2007) International Journal of Constitutional Law 393
146
Mitra Ebadolahi, „Notes: Using Structural Interdicts and The South African Human Rights Commission to
achieve Judicial Enforcement of Economic and Social Rights in South Africa‟, (2008) New York University Law
Review, Vol. 83 1565-1606 at 1591.
147
Ian Currie and Johann de Waal(Eds.), Remedies, in The Bill of Rights Handbook (2005) 5th Edition
34
constitutional yardsticks.148 Thirdly, a final order which incorporates all the proposed
plans and any other orders necessary, the court may amend its own decisions and
failure to obey may attract contempt of court proceedings.149 The use of structural
interdicts places the court at the center of the reform intended as it is the engineer of
The South African Courts invoked the structural interdict in Government of the Republic
of South Africa v Grootboom150 which was an eviction case about Irene Grootboom and
nine hundred others who were residents in an informal area. Upon eviction from a
private land, they moved to the high court seeking recourse, the High court established
that the government was under obligation to provides basic shelter to children who had
been rendered homeless alongside their parents.151 The court upon hearing the matter,
the judge made an order declaring that the respondents had certain obligation and gave
them three months to report on the implementation of the order. On the next hearing,
the government offered an alternative to the previous order. The final judgment agreed
with the high court and the alternative accommodation offered by the Government and
accessibility of the HIV/AIDS drug known as navirapine, the court made a supervisory
order that imposed a duty on the government to take certain steps and report to court
148
Supra (n. 147)
149
Ibid (n. 147)
150
[2000](11) BCLR 1169 (CC)
151
Violation of Section 28(1) of the South African Constitution.
152
[2002](4) BCLR
153
Treatment Action Campaign v Minister of Health and Others, 2002(4) BCLR 356 (A)
35
and to report back to court within 3 months.154 Similarly, in S v Zuma and 23 similar
cases155, upon the urging of an amicus concerning making reports to the court on the
existing situations and plans to solve the constitutional breach of juvenile offenders
Dialogue is alluded in the above cases, Marius Pieterse156 reckons that the court acts as
the dual translators of and translation venues for socio- economic rights, the
adjudication, he opines, provides virtually the only space for contributory voices to the
more powerful institutional players.157 The place of the court in dialogic approach at
Judging using the structural interdict remedy is at the center stage of providing a venue,
analyzing the claims brought before the court, finding the fault, finding a justification for
invoking supervisory jurisdiction and thereby allowing time for the parties to make
plans and to report back. This observation of the South African use of structural
interdict shall guide us in determine the Kenya s approach to dialogue from the court.
conceptualize this concept that it happens when communities and government talk and
listen to each other, and try to understand each other s perspectives so that they can
154
Ibid n. 38 para 85-87
155
[2004](4) BCLR 419(E)
156
Marius Pieterse „On „dialogue‟, „translation‟ and „voice‟: A reply to Sandra Liebenberg‟ Cited from Stu
Woolman & Michael Bishop ( Eds.) Constitutional Conversations(2008) Pretoria University Law Press
157
See D Davis „Soco-economic rights in South Africa: The record of the Constitutional Court after 10
years‟(2004) 5(5) Economic and Social Rights Review 3 7.
158
Lilian Chenwi & Kate Tissington, „Engaging meaningfully with Government on Socio- economic rights: A
focus on the right to housing‟(2010) Community Law Centre
36
achieve a particular goal159. The process should be well structured, coordinated,
or mediation since both parties are equal and the decision fronted from the process is a
In Occupiers of 51 Olivia Road and Others v City of Johannesburg and others.161 The
which the City and those about to become homeless would talk to each other
meaningfully in order to achieve certain objectives. 162 This was a matter challenging
the decision by the City of Johannesburg policy to demolish residences that we termed
to be bad buildings for the safety and health reasons. The (igh court found that the
housing program was in breach of the constitutional and statutory obligations while the
Supreme Court of Appeal ruled in favor of the City based on the legislation permitting
eviction of residents living in unsafe and unhealthy buildings. On further appeal to the
Constitutional Court, the court issued an interim order in the matter compelling the
159
Lilian Chenwi & Kate Tissington ( Ibid n. 158)
160
Lilian Chenwi & Kate Tissington( Ibid n. 158)
161
2008 5 BCLR 475 (CC) hereinafter Olivia road case
162
Olivia Road Case (Supra n. 161) para 14
163
Olivia road Case ( Ibid n. 161) para 22
37
the Constitutional court elsewhere in Joe Slovo case164 which was also an eviction case
that the requirement of engagement flows from the need to treat residents with respect
and care for their dignity. 165 It must be noted that meaningful engagement occurs
before an eviction since it can prevent dissatisfied people from having to go to court. 166
The dialogic approach anchored on the court arises when the court orders engagement
and lists out the objectives, thus directing how the engagement is to go about and
thereby issues an interim order. Thereby the court gives room for the parties to figure
out the best solution. The nature of this case is one that requires a balance and a
response the need to solve the situation keeping in mind the history of the people of
South Africa. This remedial approach by the South African is a guide to the Kenya s
Colombia has enjoyed democracy for a long time since they enacted their constitution in
1991 and started the process of reforming their society. Their institutional framework
portrays weaknesses especially the legislature and executive167 partly due to a weak
party system.168 )n a response, the assembly created a new Defensor del Pueblo
investigating wrongdoing, mobilizing public opinion, and filing judicial actions and
164
Residents of Joe Slovo Community, Western Cape v Thubelisha Homes and Others 2009 (9) BCLR 847 (CC)
para 238 and 244
165
Olivia Road case(Ibid n. 161) paras 10-11; Grootboom case( Ibid n.150) para 83
166
Lilian Chenwi & Kate Tissington (Ibid n. 158)
167
See Rodrigo Uprimny, The Constitutional Court and Control of Presidential Emergency Powers in Colombia,
in Democratization and the Judiciary: The Accountability Function of Courts in New Democracies( 2004) 46,
65 tbl.3 where the President often used his sweeping emergency powers to legislate directly, by passing
congress all together; 1970-1991; See Ronald R. Archer & Matthew Shugart, The Unrealized Potential of
Presidential Dominance in Colombia, in Presidentialism and Democracy in Latin America,(1997) 110, 133-6
Cambridge University Press.
168
See George Tsebelis, Veto Players, How Political Institutions Work (2002) Princeton University Press,
Princeton.
38
The Colombian Constitutional Court (hereinafter CCC) was given the power to hear
accion de tutela. )n nature, the Tutelas are inexpensive to bring, are heard very
quickly, and can be used to enforce any of the fundamental rights in the constitution
The CCC has been described as activist in its approach to among others Tutelas. In
January, 2004, the CC aggregated the constitutional complaint of 1,150 displaced family
and handed down the famous T-025 of 2004170 which the court declared that the
it associated with the systemic failures in state action.171 The court ordered as a mean to
eradicate the root causes, a series of structural measures which spawned to a lengthy
There are several other decisions handed down by the CCC that in their nature are
structural and vary in circumstance which include non- compliance with the state s
obligation to affiliate numerous public officials to the social security system173, massive
prison over-crowding174, lack of protection for human rights defenders175, and failure
169
See Manuel José Cepeda, Judicial Activism in a Violent Context: The Origin, Role, and Impact of the
Colombian Constitutional Court,(2004) in 3 Washington University Global Studies Law Review 529, 554- 557
170
Corte Constitucional [C.C.] [Constitutional Court], enero 22, 2004, Sentencia T-025/04, available at
<www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/relatoria/2004/t-025-04.html>
171
T- O25 of 2004(Supra n. 170) at 80-81
172
T-025 of 2004 ( Ibid n. 170) at 75-80.
173
C.C., febrero 2, 2000, Sentencia SU-090/0, available at
<www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/relatoria/2000/SU090-00.html> , Sentencia T-535/99, available at
<www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/relatoria/1999/T-535-99.html> ; C.C., marzo 5, 1998, Sentencia T-068/98 ,
available at <www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/relatoria/1998/T-068-98.html> ; C.C., Sentencia SU-559/97,
available at <www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/relatoria/1997/SU559-97.html>
174
C.C., Sentencia T-153/98, available at www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/ relatoria/1998/ T-153-98.html>
175
C.C. Sentencia T-590/98, available at <www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/relatoria/1998/T-590-98.html>
39
to announce an open call for public notary nominations.176 This kind of judicial activism
David Landau and Julian Lopez177 argue is based on the overall conception of the
empirically evaluated from their outcomes to be rights revolution 179 and the
César Rodríguez-Garavito181 does an empirical study on these structural cases and its
impact thus developing the Dialogic activism. 182 He propounds for dialogic activism,
since court controlled factors due to the kind of orders issued and the court s
monitoring capability.183 He argues further that dialogic rulings set broad goals and
clear implementation paths through deadlines and progress reports and secondly, a
mechanisms such as public hearings which in the end result deepen democratic
176
C.C., Sentencia SU-250/98 , available at <www.corteconstitucional.gov.co/relatoria/1998/SU250-98.html>
177
David Landau and Julián Daniel López-Murcia „Political Institutions and the Judicial Role: An application
in context, the Case of the Colombian Constitutional Court‟ (Instituciones Políticas y el papel de los jueces:
aproximaciónen contexto. el caso de la corte constitucional colombiana) (2009) Vniversitas. Bogotá
(Colombia) N° 119: 55-92,
178
David Landau and Julián Daniel López-Murcia( Supra n. 63)
179
Charles R. Epp, „The Rights Revolution: Laywers, Activists and Supreme Courts in Comparative
Perspective‟ (1998) 1-2
180
Ran Hirschi, „Towards Juristocracy: The Origins and Consequences of the New Constitutionalism‟ (2004)
defines Juristocracy to be expansive judicial power that resulted from constitutional reforms shifting power from
representative institutions to the judiciaries.
181
César Rodríguez-Garavito- Beyond the Courtroom Ibid n. 47
182
See César Rodríguez-Garavito Ibid n. 181 ; See also Rosalind Dixon- Creating Dialogue About
Socioeconomic Rights: Strong Ibid n. 145
183
César Rodríguez-Garavito Ibid n. 181
184
César Rodríguez-Garavito Ibid n. 181
40
The Colombian Dialogic model is different especially on Socio-economic rights is very
different from that of the South Africa or as that by Mark Tushnet185. Their strategy an
intense cooperation with the other branches especially the executive and what makes it
unique is that it is not intended to catalyze democratic process but to take whatever
action deemed necessary to solve the policy problem. It elucidates certain kind of
confidence to issue out precise directives or to revise the bill passed by parliament
dialogue is that the court as adjudicators give room for a wide range of ideas and
options to be taken by the executive and further creates an incorporated and collective,
consultative forum from the political and private actors to achieve democracy and
development.
3.5 Conclusion.
The comparative study undertaken above give a direction on how the courts should
develop the dialogic approach to Judging, it brings to mind the challenges that the
Courts are likely to face and the need to incorporate these approaches as they attempt
to model and modify the Kenya s approach to adjudication to suit the dialogic approach.
Suffice to note each of the above legal systems have theorized and applied dialogic
approach differently based on the legal history, tradition and culture. It goes without
concluding that Kenya s legal system is unique and thereby our dialogic approach is
unique and we must develop it keeping in mind its unique but guided by a comparative
study.
185
Mark Tshunet- Weak Courts, Strong Rights Ibid 115
41
CHAPTER FOUR
ADJUDICATION.
4.1 Introduction.
The courts in Kenya have made attempts to interpret the constitution Dialogically
rather than the traditional the monologist approach to judging. However, the study of
this concept is still nebulous and still faces a greater challenge in its practicableness in
developing democracies. From the previous chapter, it must be noted that each
appreciating this fact, Kenya s dialogic approach shall be different from the foreign
jurisdictions since our legal history and culture is different from those of other
jurisdictions.
The researcher appreciates the fact that he is not the first to try and fashion the Dialogic
undertaken a theoretical study on this subject. The researcher therefore builds on their
arguments with the need to focus on the process to be undertaken by the court in
ensuring that dialogue is meaningfully achieved and further interrogate the obligation
required by the other parties and further the effectiveness and implication of dialogue
that the dialogue theories ought not to empirically and normatively have a monopoly on
186
Nicholas Wasonga Orago- Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic Rights Ibid n. 48
187
Miyawa O. Maxwell- Judicial Enforcement of Socio-Economic rights Ibid. 31 See also Miyawa O. Maxwel,
„Dialogic Landscape In Kenya: An Emerging Trend in Socio-Economic Rights Enforcement‟ Accessed from
https://osgoode.academia.edu/MiyawaMaxwel
188
Bateup Christine A. - The Dialogic Promise Ibid n. 1
42
achieve or create an effective dialogic environment, the court should go against legal
Dialogue involves a process in which the court gives room for discursive and
conversational exchange with parties to a suit in a bid to formulate the most workable
this room that needs to be established to create an environment for dialogue and an
atmosphere for discourse, which reconciles the argument by Jurgen Habermas that
there ought to be fair procedures which he calls it an ideal speech situation which
ought to be free and uncoerced, further according to him it should be inclusive and open
and symmetrical that is each participant can initiate, continue, and be able to question
the discussion on the topic.190He therefore argues for the institutionalism through legal
This chapter shall seek to narrowly analyze the process of undertaking dialogue by the
court. The researcher shall purposively interpret the provision of the constitution that
give room for dialogue by the court. Upon establishing the interpretive approach to
dialogic constitutionalism, the researcher finds that there are two main areas that are of
interest to the subject matter at hand. First is the Adjudication and Enforcement of
Socio-economic rights and secondly, the Judicial review and striking down of
189
Daniel M. Brinks and Varun Gauri, “A New Policy Landscape: Legalising Social and Economic Rights in
the Developing World” in Gauri, Varun and Brinks Daniel (eds) Courting Social Justice: Judicial Enforcement
of Social and Economic Rights in the Developing World [2008] (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2008), 30
190
Jurgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, C. Lenhardt and S. Weber Nicholsen,
trans. (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990),88-89, 197; and idem, Legitimation Crisis, Thomas McCarthy, trans.
(London: Heinemann, 1976), 107-109; and Seyla Benhabib, „Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic
Legitimacy,‟ See also Ilan Kapoor, „Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism? The Relevance of the
Habermas- Mouffe Debate for Third World Politics, (2002) Alternatives 27, 459-487
191
See Jurgen Harbermas, „Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and
Democracy,‟(1998) William Rehg, trans. Cambridge MIT press,
43
legislations. Finally the researcher shall explore the future implications and challenges
the court, it must be understood that these provisions are broad and give a great
latitude to the courts to adjudicate in a manner that promotes dialogue. The first
provision is Article 23(3) which makes provision for the authority of the courts to
uphold and enforce the Bill of rights thus arguably justifying the idea of dialogue.
First, Article 23(3) has been variedly that it is broadly formulated to give room for the
wide scope for the remedies, by the use the word including it essentially means that
the list is not exhaustive and therefore that the courts can develop this remedies in
order to suit the situations brought before them as Miyawa Maxwel puts it that the
constitution implicitly contemplates other unspecified remedies for rights other than
those listed.192 Elsewhere, the court have interpreted the use of the word including to
mean that grounds listed not exhaustive 193 Thus the court may introduce new
the use of the phrase that the court may grant appropriate relief (emphasis my own).
It has been interpreted especially from other jurisdictions that the court must deploy
creativity and innovation to enforce the values and norms of the constitution.194 The
192
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic Rights Ibid n. 31 page 111
193
See for example Erick Gitari v Non-Governmental Coordination Board & Another [2014] Eklr Petition No.
440 of 2013
194
Similar to that of South Africa Section 38, 172(1) (b)
44
effective remedy for without it being effective remedy for breach, the values underlying
and the rights entrenched in the Constitution properly be upheld or enhanced. 195 The
constitution and that it is necessary the courts should even fashion new remedies or
modify the existing remedies to secure the protection and enforcement of the important
rights.196 The courts must forge new tools and shape innovative remedies which
Further, Article 20(5) provides that in the enforcement of Socio-economic rights, that
the State has the sole responsibility to answer on questions relating to resources
dependent programs. This provision, is argued to be novel in the sense that it makes the
state accountable to the judiciary with regards to social welfare programs. 198 The state
is under an obligation to demonstrate that the resources are not available199 which
Miyawa Maxwel opines that this is an interactive phase in adjudication where the court
at the point when the State responds to the court on the availability of resources,
195
Fose v Minister of Safety and Security [1997] (7) BCLR 851 (CC) para 69
196
Ibid para 19
197
See Dikgang Moseneke- Transformative Adjudication Ibid 23
198
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic Rights Ibid n. 31 page 113
199
Article 20(5) (a)
200
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic Rights Ibid n. 31page 113
45
Further, Under Article 20(5) (c) it provides that the court may not interfere with a
decision by a state organ concerning the allocation of available resources, solely on the
basis that it would have reached a different conclusion. This provision must be read
together with Article 21(2) which provides that the State shall take legislative, policy
and other measures, including the setting of standards, to achieve the progressive
realization. Therefore where the state alleges that there is inadequate resources to meet
the outlined welfare initiatives, it must explain such a deficiency to the court which the
court will evaluate using the standards enshrined Article 21(2).201 The court thus may
not invalidate the structural programs merely on the account that it would reach a
different conclusion.202 The provision thus seeks to ensure that the court does not
impose a remedial option but that the government to undertake a legitimate role in
remedy selection process and to explain that to the court in an engagement forum while
The researcher finds other provisions that give the court power and room to undertake
dialogue and further have the power to enjoin parties to the dialogue. The constitution
makes provision for the right to institute court proceedings,204 further makes provisions
on the doctrine of locus standi and public interest litigation.205 The court has the power
authority.207Thus the court ought to interpret the Bill of rights in a manner that
promotes the values and principles and in accordance with the spirit, purport and
201
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic rights Ibid n. 31 page 113
202
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic rights Ibid n. 31 page 113
203
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic rights Ibid n. 31 page 113
204
Article 22(1) as read together with Article 258
205
Article 22(2) and (3) See also the Mutunga rules[2010]
206
Article 165(3) d)
207
Article 165(6)
46
objects.208 Clear the constitution uphold a dialogic approach to adjudication rather than
monologic approach.
The researcher shall attention into specific areas where the court attempted to
Socio-Economic rights are justiciable and can be enforced before a court of law.
Dialogue comes in during the adjudicative process and in the enforcement process since
appears to be a dynamic and static process that keeps changing and therefore just like
three levels of undertaking a proper Dialogue.209 The first level he argues occurs at the
political level that in the process of developing the legislative, policy and programmatic
the courts and the third level is during the fashioning of judicial remedies after the
208
Article 20(4)
209
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic Rights Ibid n. 48
210
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 165
47
constitutional litigation.211 This research is limited to the second and third level of
Dialogue.
The Second and Third level of Dialogue is one that is facilitated by the court. The Second
level, Nicholas Orago argues as one that occurs during the litigation, in which he who
has the power to plead also has the power to interpret. 212 The Kenyan constitution
entitles a wide range of persons capable of institute petition through public interest
litigation and thus can participate and enhances the level of dialogue.213 In this level of
dialogue, its nature is tripartite which entails the parties and the participation of the
policy.214 He goes ahead to submit that the court, at this level, the court ought to adopt a
interpretation of the entrenched SERs215. It demarcates the content, scope, and extent of
the rights which includes the delineation of the minimum core content of the rights and
further undertakes the strict application of the limitation clause.216 In the litigation
stage the court shall adopt a two-stage approach that is parties to the case adduce
evidence and make an affirmative case of a violation of SER, the strategy applied here
ought to aim at the overall achievement of the transformative agenda that is social
justice.217 The second level, the political institutions will be required to adduce evidence
211
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 165
212
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 1 page 189; See also. A Sajo
„Constitutional adjudication in light of discourse theory‟ (1995-1996) 17 Cardozo Law Review 1193, at 1201;
213
See Article Article 22 and 23 which the court noted that “persons shall have free and unhindered access to
the courts for the enforcement of their fundamental rights and freedoms as read together with Article 258” Cited
in John Harun Mwau & 3 others v Attorney General & 2 others, High Court Petition No. 123 of 2011
214
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic Rights Ibid n. 48 page 190; See also Article 156(4)
on the role of the Attorney General
215
See M Tushnet- Social welfare rights and the forms of judicial review Ibid 115
216
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic Rights Ibid n. 48 page 192; See also Article 24 of
the Constitution which provides for the Limitation clause.
217
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 191; See also Sandra
Liebenberg, Socio-economic rights adjudication under a transformative constitution (2010) 37-38.
48
indicating that the limitation of the right as being reasonable and justifiable.218 The
court must retain a sufficient latitude in order to be able to undertake more drastic
The third level, as per Nicholas Orago deals with the type of remedy the courts adopt
and the kind of monitoring mechanisms that the courts will establish to ensure the
adopting moderate remedies which ought to be in line with the concept of separation
of powers. In doing so, the court acknowledges and defers the constitutional
planning and implementation of SER policies.221 This level thus encompasses certain
Dialogical remedies, he develops three distinct stages that is the right declaration
stages, the remedy proposal stage and the monitoring or supervision stage.222 The first
stage, he argues, is where the court establishes whether any rights has been infringed
and the degree of infringement, if it finds a violation it makes a declaration. The second
stage, the court directs the government to initiate some action or commence a program,
under this, dialogic decisions should allow the implementation of the proffered
remedial choices to run for a defines periods of time. The final stage connotes the
monitoring process which allows a forum for all actors and parties involved to discuss,
218
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 191; See also KG Young „A
typology of economic and social rights adjudication: Exploring the catalytic function of judicial review‟ (2010)
8(3) International Journal of Constitutional Law 385, at 395
219
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 192
220
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 200
221
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 200; See also Tushnet-
Social Welfare right Supra 30 above 1910; Rodriquez- Garavito- Beyond the Court Room Ibid n. 47
222
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic rights Ibid n. 31, Developed from César
Rodríguez-Garavito- Beyond the Court Supra n. 36; Mark Tushnet- Social Welfare Rights Ibid 115; Mark
Tushnet- New Forms of Judicial Review Ibid 115
49
set deadlines, the alternative structural choices which have been proposed by the
government and adopted by the court.223 The court thus supervises its decisions and
may review its own decisions as it may deem necessary.224 Upon establishing the
perspectives and approach of the two leading scholars in Kenya on this subject, the
researcher turns his attention to the Jurisprudential analysis emanating from the Court
of Appeal with intent to build on and find solution to hurdles, challenges that face the
Hardly a year after the promulgation of the Constitution, a petition was filed concerning
the right to housing225 and property226 in the case of Mitu-Bell Welfare Society v Attorney
General & 2 others227. The petitioners were residents of Mitumba village which was
situated near Wilson airport. After a short notice of 7 days, the 2nd respondent
demolished their houses despite having a court preventing the same. The court upon
finding that the state had failed in its obligations as per Article 21(1) and that the rights
of the petitioner s rights had been violated and finding that there was no form of
participation and consultation.228 The court issued the following orders that the
respondents do provide by way of an affidavit within 60 days the current state policies
and programmes on the provisions of shelter and access to housing, that the
respondents do furnish copies of such policies and programmes to the petitions and
other relevant state agencies, further that respondent do engage and report back to the
223
Mark Tushnet- Social Welfare Rights Supra n. 115
224
Miyawa O. Maxwel – Judicial Enforcement of Socio- Economic rights Ibid n. 2 page 116
225
Article 43
226
Article 40
227
Petition No. 164 of 2011[2013] Eklr
228
MituBell welfare society case Para 73
50
court on the progress within 90 days.229 The court in this matter applied the theoretical
However, the respondent did not comply with the court order but opted for an appeal,
In Kenya Airports Authority v Mitu- Bell Welfare Society & 2 others,230 which the
appellants challenged the scope and power of the lower High court to grant appropriate
relief in accordance with Article 23 of the Constitution. The appellate court raised
several issues that highlight the hurdles to be faced in the process of dialogue. The upon
…Article of the Constitution that permits the (igh court to grant an appropriate relief
should not be construed to be provision that permits the high court to borrow legislations from
other countries and through judicial interpretation embed them into the laws of Kenya. Article
23(3) is not a legislative instrument for the courts that it permits the High court to be innovative
and creative in crafting appropriate relief on a case by case basis. It is our considered view that
under the political question doctrine, a court has no jurisdiction to make orders relating to policy
policy. 231
It must be noted that this ruling has been interpreted to have watered down the
progressive realization of the enforcement tools of Socio-economic rights and that the
court was not transformative but rather formalistic and paid more attention to
and not static, it is theorized to keep on changing rather than remain constant. The
appellate stands as the precedent over the lower courts including the holding in the
High court.
229
Mitu-Bell welfare society case Para 79
230
Civil Appeal No. 218 of 2014[2016] Eklr
231
Kenya Airports Authority case. Para 112
51
Following the above, several questions arise. First, whether the court was justified to
hold that the decision in the High court was final and if so, how best can the court
ensure that we achieve the dialogic agenda if the judgment is deemed final? Secondly,
how can the court acquire jurisdiction upon granting a structural interdict? And what
ought to be the nature of orders granted by the court in order to facilitate dialogue?
Thirdly, should the court enjoin another party to the petition, if not, under what
processes can another third party be enjoined into the process of supervision and
reporting back? Finally, what ought to be the most appropriate process to ensure
supervision and reporting back to court in Kenya. I shall seek to respond to this issues
This question centers around the high court judgment decision in Mitu-Bell Welfare
Society case232 which the appellate court interrogated whether that judgment was final
thus functus officio. The Court of appeal interrogated on what is a judgment and
whether a judgment can be interim or must be final and dispositive of the issues and
dispute between the parties. It inquired on whether a court in the name pf granting
appropriate remedies or relief under the provisions of Article 23(3) of the Constitution
deliver a partial judgement and reserve powers to receive additional pleadings, reports
or affidavits and thereby make further orders. 233 The appellate court ruled to the
negative on this question by adopting to the doctrine of functus officio, that once a court
has passed a judgment after a lawful hearing, it cannot reopen the case and thus the law
ensures the principle of finality.234 Thus the court once it has granted its decision it
232
Mitu-Bell Welfare society case above
233
Kenya Airways Authority case para 67
234
Kenya Airways Authority case para 69
52
terminates its own jurisdiction. )t thus held that the concept of partial judgment or
interim judgment after hearing of the parties is unknown to Kenyan law… 235
The researcher disagrees with the Court of appeal on the issue of finality of decision,
since the theory of Dialogue is based on the notion that the court cannot have a final say
in the constitutional interpretation. The court ought to allow room upon rendering its
Boudreau v Nova Scotia236, )ocabucci J. noted that Remedies may require novel and
creative features. Tradition and history cannot be barriers to what reasoned and
approach must remain flexible and responsive to needs of a given case. Among the
The finality of decision will cripple the agenda of supervision and reporting back in a
rights approach, I find that the courts ought to come with ways to ensure that theirs are
not rendered final and further come up ways to ensure that the court is capable of
The court has to device a way of ensuring that it retains its jurisdiction in order to be
capable of following up with its decisions rather than rendering them finally and thus
ineffective. It is a fact the jurisdiction is acquired by law and that the courts get their
power from the law. However, as noted by the court of appeal, there is no law that
235
Kenya Airways Authority case para 71
236
[2003] SCR 3
53
provides that the court may have an interim judgment. I find that there are two possible
Under this, borrowing from the Columbian jurisdiction, that what Cesar Garavito calls it
monitoring237, after issuing the final decision, the court can say that this is not the final
The issue that may arise if a court expressly retains jurisdiction for the purposes of
monitoring is can the court deny or limit a party from appealing to the higher or
appellate court. I find it that a court cannot deny a party from appealing further to a
higher court, further as a researcher, I advocate the courts must justify in its ruling that
the issues before it to be so polycentric and complex to equal the status of the
agree with the trial court and thus enable it to proceed with the supervision and thus
Under this aspect, it connotes an innovative way of the courts not issuing a finally
judgment but a preliminary ruling to the extent that the procedure will be that the
parties undertake their obligations as the case proceeds where the next mention date
will be the reporting sessions until a final judgment is granted. The Indian Supreme
237
Cesar Rodriquez Garavito- Beyond the Courtroom Ibid n. 47
238
Manuel José Cepeda-Espinoza- Transcript: Social and Economic Rights Ibid n. 169
54
Court in the People’s Union for Civil Liberties v Union of India239 which concerned right to
food, the court issued extensive preliminary orders requiring the government to
introduce midday meals in all government assisted primary schools; provides food
security benefits through a card system among other orders.240 Thus in order to ensure
The Preliminary orders ought to be made where it is urgent and the effect of the
endangers life. Such orders should be made in situations that require radical and
immediate solutions.
Upon the court retaining its jurisdiction and granting an order for the parties to report
back to it on the policies and programs planned by the state to cure the state of violation
enumerated by the court during the ruling. Supervision is one of the elements of
structural interdicts, Iain Currie and Johan de Waal241 opine that the government is
ordered to prepare and submit a comprehensive report, the submitted plan is expected
the court evaluates whether the proposed plan in fact remedies the constitutional
infringement and whether it brings the government into compliance with its
constitutional obligation.242 The court of Appeal in the above matter on this issue held
that
239
Writ Petition No. 196 of 2001 Available at http://www.righttofoodindia.org/case/case.html> Accessed on 01st
September 2017
240
PUCL case Supra 239.
241
Iain Currie & Johan de Waal- Remedies Ibid 147
242
Iain Currie & Johan de Waal- Remedies Ibid 147
55
…what would the trial court do with such policies if tabled would the court interfere or evaluate
the soundness of the policy. A court should not act in vain and issue orders and directions that it
cannot implement. It held the opinion that ….it is advisable for the courts to practice self-restraint
government rather than as put forth by Frank Michelman, to be an invitation of the law
back to politics, through dialogue. The intention of the court as alluded above is to
powers. In the process of supervision, there two main issues that must be responded to
by the court, first is what mode of reporting back or supervision will be applicable and
a) Mode of Supervision.
The mode of supervision depends on several factors mainly, the level of violation and
the court s capacity to undertake the process of supervision, and finally, the proposition
made by the state. The court may have to choose from these two ways:
The Court in this aspect undertakes that it shall be reported back to within the
deadlines and time frames set out by the court itself. In this approach, the court is
actively involved in the process that is occasional live public hearing are held where the
government is called upon to report on the progress made and the parties and the civil
society may cross- examine on the evidence brought out by the State. The Colombian
Constitutional court has time and again undertake direct supervision, for example in T-
56
024 case243 which concerned IDPs where the Director in charge of IDPs was put to stand
The direct supervision has its disadvantage in Kenya mainly being that there is a high
rate of case backlog thereby it could be impossible to hold occasional public hearings
This connotes the divesting of jurisdiction from the court to an independent body or a
body that represents the interests of the petitioners and other interested groups. The
main role of the commission is to carry out interviews, reports and make observation on
on Forced Displacement which was a coalition of NGOs was assigned to monitor the
implementation of T-025 case.245 Also the South African has obligated the South Africa
promote respect for (uman rights and the the protection, development and attainment
of human rights, as well as with monitoring and assessing the observance of Human
rights in the Republic.246 Mitra Ebadolahi makes a case for the use of SAHRC in the
In the Kenyan context, Nicholas Orago advocates for the use Kenya Human Rights and
Equality Commission (KHREC) which under the constitution has the function and power
to conduct investigations248 and has power to issue summons to a witness for the
243
Corte Constitucional [C.C.] [Constitutional Court], enero 22, 2004, Sentencia T-025/04 Ibid n. 170
244
César Rodríguez-Garavito- Beyond the Courtroom Ibid 47
245
Cesar Garavito Rodriguez- Beyond the Courtroom Ibid n. 47
246
Provided under Section 184(1) of The South African Constitution [1996] Chapter 9
247
Mitra Ebadolahi- Notes: Using Structural Interdicts Ibid n. 146
248
Article 252(1) of the Constitution of Kenya
57
purposes of investigation.249 Therefore it is best suited to carry out the responsibility of
It must be noted that there shall be financial and budgetary implications on the process
of monitoring and supervision. Nicholas Orago argues that the substantive content of
the policy, including fiscal and budgetary imperatives are not contained in the
judgment, but are discussed and designed in an inclusive and participatory deliberative
remedial commission and also during monitoring process.250 Thus it the question of
In concluding this part, I opine that the court may apply both methods of supervision
that is through the live court and through supervisory commission with intent to ensure
b) Enjoining of Parties.
In this aspect, the Appellate court criticized that by the High court seeking to enjoin
other third parties like the Pamoja trust, who are not party to the suit and are un-
pleaded issues would amount to throwing back the parties into the arena of litigation
and contesting issues over which they came for determination by the trial court. 251 I
the judicial intervention is a way to mobilize the political process but to mobilize it in a
way in which participation is not only linked to the very specific party s interest in the
case but that promote a broader participation in the decision making that will lead to
249
Article 253(3) of the Constitution of Kenya.
250
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 205
251
Kenya Airways Authority Case para 94
58
the fulfillment of the Orders of the court. 252 It is thus a decisional participation.253 The
approach of enjoining the parties thus is not public participation but a decisional
Under this aspect, it connotes where a court makes the orders asking the State, upon the
court declaring the rights, to report back on its policy and program plans it intends to
undertake to fix the violation of rights state. It is submitted that the such orders must be
broad in order to allow a great latitude form the State to be able to choose among
several options available but also the court must retain to itself sufficient latitude to
the decisional aspect to the State but care must be taken as noted by Mclaughin J, that
deference should not be carried to the point of relieving the government of the burden
which the charter places upon it of demonstrating that the limits it has guaranteed
This limitation on the nature of rights is pegged on the argument by Tushnet that
Courts should not enforce strong social welfare rights with weak remedies because
those remedies may well become strong ones, which in turn will lead courts to
transform to strong social welfare rights into weak ones. 256 The court should thus
should reserve power to itself in order to be able to make new decision in light of the
progress and setbacks in the process of the implementation of the original judgment
252
Manuel José Cepeda-Espinoza-Transcript: Social and Economic Rights Ibid 169
253
Manuel José Cepeda-Espinoza- Transcript: Social and Economic Rights Ibid 169
254
C. Mbazira, Litigating socio-economic rights in South Africa (2009) chapter six.
255
RJR MacDonald v Canada [1995] 3 SCR 199 para. 136; Provisions cited are similar to Article 24, 21(1) of
the Constitution of Kenya
256
Mark Tushnet- Social Welfare Rights Ibid 115
59
and to encourage discussion among actors.257 Thus strengthening the adjudicative
dialogue.
that is that it should be orders that target with precision towards the regulatory
bottlenecks.258 In this regard the court makes at first depending on the rights targeted,
broad and not targeted to fix key specific aspects since the evidence before the court at
first instance is too general, then afterwards during the supervision, the court will be
able to review its decision to a very concrete and specific follow up and thus render a
targeted transformative orders after the initial judgment and once there is enough and
weighty evidence.259 While in other situations such as the right to health, the court in
making targeted orders towards main problems in the healthcare system ought to be
careful and be able to sustain the follow up.260 The orders therefore should portray
prudent activism that is that the courts don t try to fix the problem but leaves the
fixing of the problem to the competent agencies.261 Finally, the time frames also
This is the second approach by the courts to dialogue. It is derived from the Hogg and
Bushell case for Dialogue when the court strikes down legislation passed by parliament
when in response to this the legislature undertakes to remove, amend or change that
257
Cesar Rodriguez- Beyond Court Room Ibid n.47
258
Manuel José Cepeda-Espinoza-Transcript: Social and Economic Rights Ibid 169
259
Manuel José Cepeda-Espinoza-Transcript: Social and Economic Rights Ibid 169; See also T- 025 – IDPs
case where the court made at first broad orders then later narrowed to specifics Ibid 170
260
Manuel José Cepeda-Espinoza-Transcript: Social and Economic Rights Ibid 169; See also T-O24 on the right
to health court made targeted specific areas. See also Cesar Garavito- Beyond the Courtroom Ibid n. 47 who
compares both cases Ibid n.170
261
Manuel José Cepeda-Espinoza-Transcript: Social and Economic Rights Ibid 169
60
legislation then it amounts to dialogue.262 In this part the researcher shall be
others263 was a suit brought before court seeking a declaration that the Security
unconstitutional. The court used the severance remedy keeping in mind the Limitation
of rights under Article 24,264 and went further ahead to sever each contended provision
of the statute, weighing that provision against the constitution especially the bill of
rights while finding whether that provision is justifiable to be limited under Article
24.265It thereby severed several provisions of the statute and in suspending those
provision266 and thus innovatively warned the bodies such as the media that are
exploiting its own privileges and rights.267 In response to this the Senate came up with
Security Amendment Bill 2015 which intended to cure the issues raised by the court.
Further, The Institute of Social Accountability & Another v The National Assembly &
others( hereinafter The CDF Act case) 268 which concerned the constitutionality of the
Constituency Development Fund Act (CDF Act), the court applied severance and found
that … Sections and of the CDF Act introduce a conflict of roles and in this way
threaten to violate the division of functions between the national and county
governments…”269 It went further to find that Section 24 of the said Act violates the
262
Peter W Hogg and Allison A. Bushell- The Charter Dialogue between Courts and Legislatures Ibid n. 28
263
Petition No. 12 of 2015[2015] eKLR
264
CORD case Para 235- 273 in the supra n. 263
265
Refer to CORD case Para 273-281(Article 34), Para 282-308(Article 31), Para 309-330(Article 49),Para
331-349(Article 50(2)j) ), Para 350-354(Article 49(1) h)) Ibid n. 263.
266
CORD case Para 463 ibid n. 263
267
CORD case Para 457- 459 ibid n. 263
268
Petition No. 71 of 2013[2015] Eklr hereinafter The CDF Act case
269
The CDF Act case Para 110 supra n. 268
61
principle of separation of powers.270 The court went on explaining what the use of
severance means and said thus …the court must unbundle the specific provisions of the
proposed legislation to see if and to what extent they satisfy the criteria set out under
Article 110(1) of the constitution… .271 The parliament in response to this sort to amend
the constitution to introduce the CDF fund as a one of the funds in the constitution.
The Kenyan courts seem to have favored suspension of declaration of invalidity for a
period of time and have avoided to strike down a legislation since as the court noted
that it is a very serious legal and constitutional step to suspend the operation of
statutes and statutory provisions and therefore the courts must wade with oare,
prudence and judicious wisdom. 272 Therefore the courts have been very conscious
alive of the doctrine of separation of powers and the likelihood of a legislative gap
effective dialogue in the Kenyan context, the response is to the affirmative. Guided the
invalidity rather than striking it down, it created three conditions that is where the
immediate striking down of legislation would pose a danger to the public, or would
threaten the rule of law or would result in the deprivation of benefits from deserving
persons 274 Despite this, it is noted that the Canadian courts have largely ignored in the
subsequent cases. Sujit Choudhry and Kent Roach hold that the suspended declaration
270
The CDF Act case Para 112 Ibid n. 268
271
The CDF Act case Para 138 Ibid n. 268
272
CORD case para 122 Ibid n. 268
273
[1992[ 2 S.C.R 679
274
Schachter Case Ibid 273 at 719
62
of invalidity can be viewed as a form of legislative remand, whereby unconstitutional
legislation is sent back for reconsideration in light of the court s judgment. 275
If after the period of suspension is over without the legislation making the changes then
the declaration of invalidity take effect. It essentially means that a suspension period is
some sort of invitation of the legislature to dialogue. McFarlene puts it that where there
is no response it does not amount to dialogue. But if there is a response as to the court
some sort of new law or amendment that differs from the court ruling then it shall
according to the researcher amounts to be described as dialogue. But I find that more
constitutionalism.
As a researcher, I remain optimistic that the courts especially the Higher courts in the
land (Supreme Court and Court of Appeal) will adopt dialogic judicialism during
Kenya, the courts should shun from continuing to embrace legal culture that dictate
The court ought to further strive to ensure inclusivity in interpreting the constitution.
275
Sujit Choudhry & Kent Roach, “Putting the Past Behind Us?” (2003) 21 Supreme Court Law Review (2d)
205 at 233
276
Emmett Macfarlane- Dialogue or compliance? Ibid n. 144
63
The Effect of SERs is immense and has down in the history of Columbia in the Judgment
T-025 that impacted greatly in the spheres of social, economic and political rights. Cesar
Garavito does an empirical study on the impact of a dialogical decision. First, it had an
unlocking effect which shook up state bureaucracies in the targeted sector. 277Secondly,
It had a coordination effect that dealt with the structural policy failures.278Thirdly, it had
allocations and monitoring of the program279. Fourthly, it had participatory effect that
opened up judicial proceedings and policy making to a broad range of governmental and
non-governmental actors.280 Finally, it had sectoral and reframing effect in the targeted
area. On the court, the result was deepening democratic legitimacy on constitutional
4.5 Conclusion.
This chapter has developed and filled the loophole that the Court of Appeal highlighted
in appeal case of Mitu-Bell. The scholars on this subject had undertaken on the
there are two main types of dialogic models that I have attempted to discuss, that is
researcher concludes that dialogue is possible with regards to enforcing SERs if the
277
Cesar Rodriguez- Beyond Court room Ibid n. 47 at 1683
278
Cesar Rodriguez- Beyond Court room Ibid n. 47 at 1684
279
Cesar Rodriguez- Beyond Court room Ibid n. 47 at 1684
280
Cesar Rodriguez- Beyond Court room Ibid n. 47 at 1685
281
Rosalind Dixon- Creating Dialogue About Socioeconomic Rights Ibid 145
64
Therefore, dialogue is well-modelled in the Kenya s adjudication system, it only a matter
of implementing.
The next just concludes and recommends guided by this chapter how to better the
65
CHAPTER FIVE
This chapter seeks to conclude the argument put forth in the study of Dialogic
It follows that it seeks to assess whether the study has achieved the objectives set out at
judicialism on the part of the court, the litigants, the civil rights groups and the State
5.1 Conclusion.
This study had set out objectives in the form of questions as to whether the Kenyan
legal framework has appreciated the notion of dialogue by the court and how the courts
have been innovative and creative in enforcing socio- economic rights. Further to assess
whether dialogue is the best model to deal with the challenges of the doctrine of
separation of powers and counter-majoritarian difficulty. Finally, this study sort to critic
Socio-economic rights in Kenya. The first chapter theorizes dialogue as a concept which
The study gives a legal backing through marrying the theory of dialogue with the word
The second chapter conceptualized the concept of transformative adjudication with the
intention finding the place of dialogue in the architect of adjudication. The researcher
and correlating it with the concept of adjudication as propounded by Owen Fiss and
66
Abram Chayes. This chapter addresses the concerns on counter-majoritarian difficulty
and Separation of powers, thus making a case for dialogue as probable solution to the
above concerns. The researcher concludes that in deed dialogue has a place in
The Third chapter studied comparative analogy from other jurisdiction on their models
of dialogue. The Canadian model of dialogue espoused by Hogg and Bushell is derives
from where the courts strike down a legislation, in response the legislature either
amends or changes, that amounts to dialogue. The South African model encompasses
the use of court orders mainly through structural interdicts and meaningful
engagement in Olivia road case, both espouse aspects of the theory of dialogue attached
to the court. Further, Columbian jurisdiction models its dialogic approach through
intense structural interdicts as evident in T-025 and T-024 case where the Columbian
its orders through public hearing sessions and establishing of supervision commissions.
It concludes that each country has unique model of dialogue depending on the political,
The previous chapter has delved into trying to model the Kenya s approach to dialogue
from the courts. It builds the argument from the theoretical arguments by Nicholas
Orago and Miyawa O. Maxwel who undertook an empirical study on this subject matter
before the conclusion of Mitubell welfare case. The parties preferred an appeal to the
Court of Appeal CA which raised certain issues from the (igh court s ruling that in this
research forms the integral impact on dialogue processes. The researcher devices ways
67
to deal with the interpretive approach taken by the Court of Appeal with intent to make
dialogue a success. Further, the chapter responds to the affirmative that suspension of
as dialogue.
In assessing on whether the study has achieved the objectives set out above, it is the
finding of the researcher that Kenya s legal framework indeed appreciates the concept
of dialogue and that its in the process of taking shape in the courts approach to this
theory. Courts have been innovative and creative but more needs to be done which
finding that dialogue is practicable but is dynamic and takes different shapes such that
certain legal discourses and processes may not be deemed dialogue but has been
described as such. It is this dynamic nature that obliges the courts to maneuver through
5.2 Recommendations.
The recommendation targets specific areas in the stages of dialogue as discussed in the
researcher shall recommend which in essence are the obligations arising in order to
make dialogue a success. These are: the litigants, the court, the state and the civil rights
groups.
These are the parties to a petition that may result in the beginning of a dialogue process
mostly in SERs matter where the court may order structural interdicts. The parties
ought to adopt a structural litigation strategy that is one that most concerns the people
68
which is within the Public interest litigation(PIL) strategies.282 In this sense, the court is
The litigants ought to guide the court towards appreciating the polycentric concerns
arising from the petition which shall attract the attention that this is not a matter to be
dealt by the court but it should incorporate other levels of government in the decision
making. Further, the parties ought to adduce cogent evidence, evidence form a wide
range of persons affected by the violation of that socio-economic right with intent to
bring out the need for reform on the right. Such evidence ought to represent the state of
affairs if possible of the whole country, and must reflect on the legal culture and history
Where a litigant is not satisfied by ruling of the High court or any other court, the party
should go further and seek opinion from a higher court probably the Supreme Court.
Comparative jurisprudence has it that effective dialogue occurs at the supreme court
and seen through by the lower courts. Finally, the litigants during the supervision and
reporting sessions ought to participate actively in the process, guided by to main issue,
first is to guide the court in balancing the interests of the individual vis a vis those of the
affected society and secondly, keep the court in track with the objectives and intent of
This is the political arm of government that is mostly represented by the Attorney
General (A.G). The Attorney General, in order to make dialogue a success, ought to
comply with the court order to file affidavits within a certain time frame and show what
282
Nicholas Orago - Poverty, Inequality and Socio-economic rights Ibid n. 48 page 197
69
policy and budgetary allocation the government is undertaking to deal with violation of
In compliance, the government should come with cogent plans that promote social
justice and equality, not one that benefits a select few. In this regard, the A. G must
appreciate that the follow up and supervision is not an interference into the other level
of government but an invitation into the process of decision-making process. That the
The Government in the process of dialogue ought to accept the inclusion of civil society
and NGOs into the decision- making process rather than limit them from holding the
decision-making.
These are the groups that are enjoined into the process of supervision and reporting
back sessions. They ought to basically help the court collect evidence and come up with
reports on what the government is doing and the impact of the process on the victims
These groups therefore, ought to guide the court to make specific and targeted orders to
certain areas that have not been dealt with. That is it guides the court from making
The court is the main body in the process of Dialogue. It begins and ends the process of
dialogue and sees to it that it is done. In the process of litigation, the court ought to
70
weigh the litigation strategy to the effect that it ensures that the individual rights and
The ought to in the ruling stage, make preliminary orders where necessary if the matter
at hand is urgent then such response ought to be made. The nature of the subsequent
orders ought to be broad but precise to avoid any confusion or misinterpretation, the
court should set reasonable time lines that will enable the parties to respond. The
determination and orders therefore ought to give a latitude to the government and a
for dialogue.
In granting a structural interdict, the court ought to carefully weigh the rights at issue
against the limitations therefore. Thus in giving the orders should be aware of the
dangers that may arise and pose a challenge to the court. In Modder East Squatters &
Another v President of the Republic of South Africa,283 the court of Appeal noted the
Structural interdicts have a tendency to blur the distinction between the executive and the
judiciary and impact on the separation of powers. They tend to deal with policy matters and not
with the enforcement of particular rights. Another aspect to take into account is the comity
between the different arms of the State.284 Then there is the problem of sensible enforcement: the
state must be able to comply with the order within the limits of its capabilities, financial or
otherwise285. Policies also change, as do requirements, and all this impacts on enforcement. It
further noted that the time limits appear to be unrealistic and there is no indication of what is
expected of the state apart from the generalized obligation to comply with constitutional duties
283
[2004] Supreme Court of Appeal Case Nos 187/03 and 213/03
284
See also President of the Republic of South Africa and others v South African Rugby Football Union and
others
2000 (1) SA 1 (CC) para 234
285
Minister of Health and others v Treatment Action Campaign (No 2) and others 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para
37-38.
71
in some unspecified way. The order justifies queue-jumping in prioritization which is
inappropriate… 286
Despite the above challenges raised, the court should not be cowed into not granting
structural interdicts but should find ways to maneuver with the malleable nature of
Thus, the court should be activist and transformative to see to it that Dialogue is done.
The court should further be able to review its own orders in the manner where they
move from broad orders to narrow and specific order. In this regard, the court ought to
mark the end of the structural interdict, that is it ought to know when the objectives it
set have been achieved and thus end the process. The Constitutional Conversation
Continues…
286
Supra n. 98 para 39-40
72
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Books
Alexander M. Bickel, “The least dangerous Branch” 16 (Vail-Ballou Press, Inc. 2nd
ed.(1986)
Bakhtin M.M “The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays”(1981) Edited by Michael Holquist
and Translated by Coryl Emerson University Of Texas press Austin and London
Dworkin Ronald, „No Right Answe‟r, In Law, Morality and Society (1977) Hacker & J. Raz
(eds.)
Ian Currie and Johann de Waal(Eds.), Remedies, in The Bill of Rights Handbook (2005) 5th
Edition
Jürgen Habermas “Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a discourse Theory of Law
and Democracy; Trans. By William Rehg (1996) The MIT Press, Cambridge Massachusetts
(Cambridge: MIT Press, 1989); and Craig Calhoun, ed. Habermas and the Public
73
Inner discourse” (1998) University of Jyvaskyla Centre for Applied studies ISBN 951-39-
2408-4
Owen Fiss, “The Death of Law”,(1986) 72 Cornell Law review 1,2, 9-10
Stu Woolman and Michael Bishop (eds), Constitutional Conversations (2008) Pretoria
Journals.
AJ Van der Walt, “Legal History, Legal culture and Transformation in a Constitutional
Alexander Bickel, „The Supreme Court, 1960: The Passive Virtues,‟ (1982) 75 Harvard Law
Bassok, Or, and Yoav Dotan “Solving the Counter-majoritarian Difficulty?” (2013)
Caesar Rodriguez- Garavito, “Beyond the Courtroom: The Impact of Judicial Activism on
Socio-Economic Rights in Latin America. (2011) Texas Law Review Vol 89:1669
Catherine Albertyn and Dennis Davis „Legal Realism, Transformation and the Legacy of
CR. Sunstien, “Interest groups in American Public Law,” (1985) Stanford Law Review 38: 59
D Davis „Soco-economic rights in South Africa: The record of the Constitutional Court after
74
David Landau, “A Dynamic Theory of Judicial Role‟ (2014) Boston College Law Review
November 2014
Dennis M. Davis & Karl Klare, “Transformative Constitutionalism and the Customary Law”
2002.
Frank L. Michelman, “Law's Republic,” (1988) 97 Yale Law Journal. 1493, 1499-1503
- „Bringing the Law to Life: A Plea for Disenchantment” (1989) Cornell Law Review
Lon L. Fuller, “The Forms and Limits of Adjudication” (1978-1979) 92 Harvard Law Review
Barry Friedman, „Dialogue and Judicial Review‟ (1993) Michigan Law Review
Manuel José Cepeda, Judicial Activism in a Violent Context: The Origin, Role, and Impact of
the Colombian Constitutional Court, (2004) in 3 Washington University Global Studies Law
75
Mark Tushnet, „New Forms of Judicial Review and the Persistence of Rights- and
- „Social Welfare Rights and the Forms of Judicial Review‟(2004) 82 Texas Law
Review 1895.
Michael c. Dorf, “The Majoritarian Difficulty and the Theories of Constitutional Decision
Mitra Ebadolahi, „Notes: Using Structural Interdicts and The South African Human Rights
Africa‟, (2008) New York University Law Review, Vol. 83 1565-1606 at 1591.
Owen Fiss, Objectivity and Interpretations, (1982)34 Stanford Law Review. 739.
Ronald Dworkin, “The Forum of Principle” (1981) 56 New York University Law Review 469
Rosalind Dixon, „Creating Dialogue about Socio-economic Rights: Strong Form versus Weak
Stephen C. Yeazell, „ Judging Rules, Ruling Judges‟, (1998) Law and Contemporary
The Honorable Chief Justice Catherine A. Fraser, “Constitutional Dialogues Between Courts
Waldron, Jeremy „The Core of the Case against Judicial Review‟ Yale Law Journal‟ (2006)
76
Internet Sources
Abram Chayes, “The Role of the Judge in Public Law Litigation” (May, 1976) Harvard Law
Bateup , Christine A., "The Dialogic Promise: Assessing the Normative Potential of Theories
of Constitutional Dialogue" (2006) Brooklyn Law Review 71 New York University Public
Christopher P. Manfredi & James B. Kelly, „Six Degrees of Dialogue: A Response to Hogg
and Bushell‟(1999) Osgoode Hall Law Journal 373: 513-527. Accessed from
<www://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol37/iss3/1>
court rulings on rights‟(2013) International Political Science Review 34:39 Accessed from
<www://ips.sagepub.com/content/34/1/39
Hogg, Peter W. and Bushell, Allison A. "The Charter Dialogue between Courts and
Legislatures (Or Perhaps the Charter of Rights Isn't Such a Bad Thing after All)." Osgoode
http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol35/iss1/2
opinion, state policy and Judicial Review before Roe v Wade ‟ (2016) Journal of Law and
https://osgoode.academia.edu/MiyawaMaxwel
77
Miyawa O. Maxwell “Judicial Enforcement of Socio-Economic rights: A case for Dialogic
from
http://erepository.uonbi.ac.ke:8080/xmlui/bitstream/handle/11295/74238/Mawaya_Judicial%
20enforcement%20of%20socio-economic%20rights.pdf?sequence=3
Framework for the realization of socio-economic rights in the 2010 Kenyan Constitution.”
2013www.etd.uwc.ac.za/xmlui/bitstream/handle/11394/2174/Orago_LLD_2013.pdf?sequenc
Owen M. Fiss „The Forms of Justice‟ (1979) Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship Series
Peter W. Hogg, Allison A. Bushell Thornton and Wade K. Wright, “Charter Dialogue
Revisited: Or “Much Ado About Metaphors”( 2007) Osgoode Hall Law Journal 45.1: 1-65.
78