Collier y Levitsky Democracy Wwith Adjectives
Collier y Levitsky Democracy Wwith Adjectives
Collier y Levitsky Democracy Wwith Adjectives
David Collier
and
Steven Levitsky
The recent trend toward democratization in countries throughout the globe has challenged
scholars to pursue two potentially contradictory goals: to develop a differentiated
conceptualization of democracy that captures the diverse experiences of these countries; and to
extend the analysis to this broad range of cases without ‘stretching’ the concept. This paper
argues that this dual challenge has led to a proliferation of conceptual innovations, including
hundreds of subtypes of democracy—i.e., democracy ‘with adjectives.’ The paper explores the
strengths and weaknesses of three important strategies of innovation that have emerged:
‘precising’ the definition of democracy; shifting the overarching concept with which democracy is
associated; and generating various forms of subtypes. Given the complex structure of meaning
produced by these strategies for refining the concept of democracy, we conclude by offering an
old piece of advice with renewed urgency: It is imperative that scholars situate themselves in
relation to this structure of meaning by clearly defining and explicating the conception of
democracy they are employing.
RESUMEN
iii We are thus not primarily concerned with the literature on advanced industrial democracies,
although this literature is an important locus of intellectual reference in the studies we are
examining. In a few places we have included conceptions of historical forms of democracy that are
used as points of comparison in studies of contemporary cases. We also have included studies of
countries that are not actually part of the recent episode of democratization but whose relatively
new democracies are frequent points of comparison in the literature under review—for example,
Venezuela and Colombia.
iv Giovanni Sartori, “Concept Misformation in Comparative Politics,” American Political Science
Review 64 (1970). Sartori actually refers to a ladder of “abstraction” (p. 1040). However, because
the term ‘abstract’ is often understood in contrast to ‘concrete,’ this label can be confusing. We
therefore find that it expresses the intended meaning more clearly to refer to a ladder of
generality.
v David Collier and James E. Mahon, Jr., “Conceptual ‘Stretching’ Revisited: Adapting
Categories in Comparative Analysis,” American Political Science Review 87 (1993), 850–52.
The larger goal of the analysis is to clarify and place in perspective the diverse usages of
the concept of democracy that have emerged in these studies. Scholars often employ different
forms of conceptual innovation intuitively rather than self-consciously, and one of our basic
purposes is to encourage the more self-conscious use of these strategies. In addition, it
becomes clear that these authors have gone far beyond offering only broad categorical contrasts
between democracies and nondemocracies, in that they have provided numerous distinctions
regarding different aspects and gradations of democracy. These distinctions represent an
important innovation in the description of democracy, which in turn has fundamental implications
for how scholars analyze the causes and consequences of democracy.
Two initial caveats are in order. First, scholars introduce conceptual and terminological
innovations for various reasons, and not only in pursuit of the two-fold goal just discussed. For
example, they sometimes produce new terms to provide synonyms that they can use to
overcome the rhetorical problem of numerous repetitions of the same term in the course of an
analysis. However, the analytic goals of conceptual differentiation and avoiding conceptual
stretching appear to be central to understanding the proliferation of conceptual forms observed
here. Second, along with the ‘qualitative’ literature that is the focus of the present discussion,
valuable quantitative indicators have been developed that also provide a basis for comparing
recent cases of democratization. vi Ultimately, it will be productive to integrate the insights
contained in these two literatures. However, an essential prior step, which is our present concern,
is to learn more about the complex structure of meaning that underlies the treatment of
democracy in the qualitative literature.
The conceptual innovations analyzed in this paper are introduced with reference to the
concept of democracy as it has been applied to the structure of national politics. To discuss these
innovations an appropriate first step is to summarize the definitions and conceptions of
democracy found in research on recent democratization.
In his famous analysis of “essentially contested concepts,” the philosopher W.B. Gallie
vi Alex Inkeles, ed., On Measuring Democracy: Its Consequences and Concomitants (New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 1991) brings together an important part of this work. Kenneth A.
Bollen, “Liberal Democracy: Validity and Method Factors in Cross-National Measures,” American
Journal of Political Science 37, no. 4 (1993), is a particularly important effort to evaluate alternative
quantitative measures. For a somewhat skeptical view of these quantitative measures, offered by
scholars whose focus is more centrally on Western Europe, see David Beetham, ed., Defining
and Measuring Democracy (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 1994).
argues that democracy is “the appraisive political concept par excellence.” vii Correspondingly,
one finds endless disputes over appropriate meaning and definition. However, the purpose of
Gallie’s analysis is not to legitimate such disputes but to show that a recognition of the contested
status of concepts opens the possibility of understanding each meaning within its own framework.
With reference to democracy, he argues that “politics being the art of the possible, democratic
targets will be raised or lowered as circumstances alter...,” viii and he insists that these alternative
standards should be taken seriously on their own terms.ix In this spirit, our analysis focuses on
the particular set of standards for evaluating democracy that have emerged for the purpose of
studying the specific domain of cases that are of concern here.
As a point of entry, we examine a spectrum of definitions that have appeared in these
studies. We cannot do justice to all the nuances of meaning, yet we are convinced that this
summary identifies certain definitional and conceptual benchmarks that have played a crucial role
in orienting these studies. The definitions examined here are primarily ‘procedural,’ in the sense
that they focus on democratic procedures rather than on substantive policies or other outcomes
that might be viewed as democratic. Many are also ‘minimal’ definitions, in that they deliberately
focus on the smallest possible number of attributes that are still seen as producing a viable
definition (although, not surprisingly, one finds disagreement about how many attributes are
needed for the definition to be viable). For example, most of these scholars differentiate what
they view as the more specifically political features of the regime from characteristics of the society
and economy, arguing that the latter are more appropriately analyzed as potential causes or
consequences of democracy rather than as features of democracy itself.x Much of the usage by
these authors is linked to explicit definitions that are easy to situate within this spectrum. Other
xi This term is found in Terry Lynn Karl, “Imposing Consent: Electoralism vs. Democratization in
El Salvador” in Paul W. Drake and Eduardo Silva, eds., Elections and Democratization in Latin
America, 1980–1985 (La Jolla, CA: Center for Iberian and Latin American Studies, University of
California, San Diego, 1986), 34.
xii As noted below in the discussion of ‘precising,’ other analysts have proposed additional
definitional requirements that could lead to a further expansion of the procedural minimum
definition. However, these innovations have not been adopted by enough scholars to be
included in the figure.
Figure 1
These are the principal definitions employed in Not defined; Often not
this literature; often presented and applied with plays important explicitly
Associated Meanings considerable care role in forming defined
subtypes
Reasonably Often
competitive elections, Yes Yes Yes Yes not
devoid of massive included
fraud, with broad
suffrage.
Socioeconomic equal-
ity; and/ or high levels
of popular participation Yes
in economic, social,
and political
institutions.
Kirkpatrick 1981; O'Donnell and Karl 1991; Not explicitly Fagen 1986;
Vanhanen 1990; Schmitter 1986; Schmitter and discussed. See Harding and
Fukuyama 1992; Diamond, Linz, Karl 1991; analysis below of Petras 1988;
EXAMPLES Chee 1993; also and Lipset 1989; Huntington the subypes Jonas 1989;
Schumpeter Di Palma 1990; 1991; presented in Miliband 1992;
1947. Mainwaring Valenzuela Figure 6. Gills, Rocamora,
1992; also Linz 1992; and Wilson 1993;
1978. Rueschemeyer, Harnecker 1994.
Stephens, and
Stephens 1992;
Loveman 1994.
*Heavy line in figure brackets those definitions and conceptions that form an ordered scale.
literature by explicitly rejecting the idea of a procedural definition,xiii and often they do not include
the procedural guarantees that are central to the other definitions just discussed. Because many
of these authors do not present a formal definition, we refer to this in the figure as a
‘definition/conception.’
These alternative definitions are not equally prevalent. In the literature we examined, the
electoralist definition has been used by a number of scholars. However, this usage raises
concern about overextending the concept of democracy by applying it to countries—such as El
Salvador, Mexico, and Singapore in the 1980s—that satisfy the criterion of elections yet where
the violation of civil liberties is common. In light of this concern, a substantial consensus has
emerged around a procedural minimum or expanded procedural minimum definition.
Furthermore, scholars who employ a procedural minimum definition would generally have no
objection to including some reasonable criterion of effective power to govern (as specified in the
expanded procedural minimum approach) as a defining attribute.xiv Maximalist definitions, which
correspond to a conception of democracy that was common in the field of Latin American studies
in the 1960s and 1970s, have continued to be employed. However, a great many scholars who
work on the recent wave of democratization have deliberately avoided this approach.
It merits emphasis that a clear ordering is present within this set of definitions and
conceptions. Although this spectrum of meanings does not form a perfect ‘cumulative scale,’xv
with the exception of the last column on the right each subsequent definition or conception
includes all of the attributes entailed in the previous ones (see heavy line in the figure). This
ordering plays a critical role in giving structure to the conceptual innovations analyzed in the
remainder of this paper.
xiii Susanne Jonas, “Elections and Transitions: The Guatemalan and Nicaraguan Cases” in John
A. Booth and Mitchell A. Seligson, eds., Elections and Democracy in Latin America (Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press, 1989), 129–30; and Ralph Miliband, “The Socialist
Alternative,” Journal of Democracy 3 (July, 1993), 120–21. Critiques of this rejection are found in
Giovanni Sartori, The Theory of Democracy Revisited (Chatham, NJ: Chatham House, 1987); and
Huntington, “The Modest Meaning of Democracy.”
xiv Some other authors have discussed the importance of these aspects of democracy, but
without taking the step of entering them into the formal definition. See J. Samuel Valenzuela,
“Democratic Consolidation in Post-Transitional Settings: Notion, Process, and Facilitating
Conditions” in Scott Mainwaring, Guillermo O’Donnell, and Valenzuela, eds., Issues in Democratic
Consolidation: The New South American Democracies in Comparative Perspective (Notre Dame:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1992); William C. Smith and Carlos H. Acuña, “Future Politico-
Economic Scenarios for Latin America” in Smith, Acuña, and Eduardo A. Gamarra, eds.,
Democracy, Markets, and Structural Reform in Latin America (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction,
1994); and Terry Lynn Karl, “The Hybrid Regimes of Central America.” Journal of Democracy 6,
no. 3 (July 1995).
xv See Delbert C. Miller, Handbook of Research Design and Social Measurement, 5th edition
(Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications, 1991), 177–78; and R. J. Mokken, A Theory and
Procedure of Scale Analysis with Applications in Political Research (The Hague: Mouton, 1971).
Though identifying this spectrum of definitions is a useful step toward understanding the
meanings of democracy in this literature, such definitions do not fully govern usage. Democracy is
a complex concept, and the various formal definitions presented by different authors do not
resolve, once and for all, what democracy really ‘is.’ Rather, these definitions and conceptions
commonly serve to provide a meaning that is useful in relation to the specific research goals of a
given author and the specific cases under analysis. As we show in the following sections, when
these goals change, or when different cases become the focus of analysis, authors introduce a
variety of conceptual innovations and shifts in meaning.
The conceptualizations of democracy found in this literature are complex, in part due to
the great heterogeneity of cases on which analysts have focused. While the presence of
relatively competitive elections in many postauthoritarian settings suggests that the concept of
democracy is relevant, the obvious difference between these regimes and well-established
democracies both creates the need for concepts that provide more fine-grained distinctions
regarding different kinds of democracy and also raises a concern about avoiding conceptual
stretching. Our central argument is that the complex usage of this concept reflects the alternative
approaches adopted by different authors in addressing these two problems. We now turn to an
examination of three basic strategies they have employed.
xvi A ‘precising definition’ is one that is designed to include or exclude specific cases. See
Giovanni Sartori, “Guidelines for Concept Analysis” in Sartori, ed., Social Science Concepts: A
Systematic Analysis (Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications, 1984), 81; and Irving M. Copi and Carl
Cohen, Introduction to Logic, 9th ed. (NY: Macmillan, 1994), 173–75. In Social Science
Concepts (42), Sartori also uses this as a verb, as in ‘to precise’ a definition.
new context. This strategy of precising addresses the issue of conceptual differentiation, in the
sense of adding a further differentiating criterion for establishing the cut-point between
democracy and nondemocracy. The strategy may thereby also address the issue of conceptual
stretching, because it avoids applying the label ‘democracy’ to cases that, in light of this new
criterion, the analyst sees as incompletely democratic.
In contrast to some of the other strategies, precising is undertaken by scholars who have
a strong interest in formal definitions and who, as the concept of democracy is applied to a wider
range of cases, become concerned about the appropriateness of available definitions. For
example, the emergence of the expanded procedural minimum definition presented above in
Figure 1 involved precising. In several Central American countries, as well as in South American
cases such as Chile and Paraguay, one legacy of authoritarian rule is the persistence of ‘reserved
domains’ of military power over which elected governments have little or no authority.xvii Hence,
despite free or relatively free elections, civilian governments in these countries are seen by some
analysts as lacking effective power to govern. In light of these authoritarian legacies, and often in
response to claims that because these countries have held free elections they are ‘democratic,’
some scholars have modified the prior definition of democracy by specifying as an explicit criterion
that the freely elected government must to a reasonable degree have effective power to rule.
With this revised definition, even though they held relatively free elections, countries such as
Chile, El Salvador, and Paraguay have thereby been excluded from the set of cases classified as
‘full’ democracies. xviii It could be argued that these scholars did not create a more demanding
definition of democracy but rather adapted the definition to explicitly include an attribute that we
may take for granted in advanced industrial democracies. In this manner, they avoided treating as
full democracies those countries that lacked this attribute.
A second example of precising is found in discussions of what might be called a
‘Tocquevillean’ definition of democracy, which includes a focus on selected aspects of social
relations. In analyzing postauthoritarian Brazil, scholars such as Weffort and Guillermo O’Donnell
have been struck by the degree to which rights of citizenship are undermined by the pervasive
semifeudal and authoritarian social relations that persist in some regions of the country. In light of
this concern, Weffort added the definitional requirement of “some level of social equality” for a
country to be considered a democracy, and O’Donnell introduced a closely related stipulation.xix
O’Donnell, “Challenges to Democratization in Brazil,” World Policy Journal 5, no. 2 (1988), 298;
and O’Donnell, “Transitions, Continuities, and Paradoxes” in Mainwaring, O’Donnell, and
Valenzuela, eds., Issues in Democratic Consolidation, 48–49.
xx Authors who have included horizontal accountability in their definitions include Karl,
“Dilemmas of Democratization,” 165; and Alan R. Ball, Modern Politics and Government (Chatham,
NJ: Chatham House, 1993), 45–46.
xxi Jonathan Hartlyn, “Crisis-Ridden Elections (Again) in the Dominican Republic:
Neopatrimonialism, Presidentialism and Weak Electoral Oversight,” Journal of Interamerican
Studies and World Affairs 36, no. 4 (Winter 1994); and Guillermo O’Donnell, “Delegative
Democracy?” Journal of Democracy 5 (1994). Other authors who have addressed the issue of
checks on executive power include Luis Abugattas, “Populism and After: The Peruvian
Experience” in James Malloy and Mitchell Seligson, eds., Authoritarians and Democrats: Regime
Transition in Latin America (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1987); and G.M. Tamás,
“Socialism, Capitalism, and Modernity,” Journal of Democracy 3, no. 3 (July 1992).
government to qualify post–1990 Chile as a ‘borderline’ democracy. xxii
xxii Rhoda Rabkin, “The Aylwin Government and `Tutelary’ Democracy: A Concept in Search of a
Case?” Journal of Interamerican Studies and World Affairs 34, no. 4 (Winter 1992–93), 165.
Second, more broadly, one must recognize the potential problem of ‘definitional
gerrymandering,’ xxiii in which definitions become excessively flexible to the point where a basic
consistency of meaning is lost. Thus, it would hardly be productive if scholars created a new
definition every time they encountered a somewhat anomalous case. However, the contrast
between the first and third examples of precising discussed above shows that scholars may in fact
impose constructive limits on precising. In the first example, the inability of elected governments
to exercise effective power was seen as invalidating their democratic character. By contrast, in the
third example involving heavy-handed assertions of power by the president, a crucial point is that
these presidents are elected leaders. Hence, it appears more plausible to treat these cases as
democratic and to avoid precising—as long as a general respect for civil liberties and ongoing
presidential elections is maintained and the legislature and opposition parties are not banned or
dissolved (as did occur in Peru in 1992).
Finally, excessive contextualization also poses the risk of bringing back into the definition
of democracy attributes that authors had initially decided to exclude. An example is the concern
with social relationships in the Tocquevillean approach. These authors could be seen as
remaining within a procedural framework, in the sense that they argue that political participation
becomes less meaningful in the context of extreme social inequality. Nonetheless, this
conceptual innovation reintroduces features of social relations in a way that does represent a
major shift in relation to earlier recommendations about which attributes should be included in
definitions of democracy.
Figure 2
xxiv This follows the example of Linz’s analysis of what he viewed as a poorly institutionalized
case of authoritarianism in post–1964 Brazil, which led him to speak of an authoritarian ‘situation.’
See Juan J. Linz, “The Future of an Authoritarian Situation or the Institutionalization of an
Authoritarian Regime: The Case of Brazil” in Alfred Stepan, ed., Authoritarian Brazil: Origins,
Policies, Future (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973).
the overarching concept constitutes another way of limiting and refining the claims about what is
deemed to be an incomplete case of democracy. In this manner, O’Donnell seeks to avoid
conceptual stretching by establishing a higher and a lower standard for democracy and declaring
that Brazil meets only the lower standard.xxv
From the standpoint of a concern with maintaining a procedural definition of democracy,
this innovation can be seen as a better solution to the problem that O’Donnell and others had
initially tried to address by creating the Tocquevillian definition through precising. Thus, in
conjunction with shifting the overarching concept, democratic ‘regime’ continues to have a
procedural definition, and this concern with the broader functioning of citizenship in the context
of authoritarian patterns of social relations is addressed via the concept of the state.
The strategy of shifting among alternative overarching concepts thus usefully serves to
avoid conceptual stretching at the same time that it introduces finer differentiation—in this
instance by creating an additional analytic category. The disadvantage of this approach may well
be that because so many different overarching concepts have been employed, the potential for
scholarly confusion is enormous—especially if one considers the possibility of combining eleven
or more overarching concepts with the hundreds of adjectives employed in forming subtypes of
democracy.
Forming Subtypes
The third and most important strategy of conceptual innovation is the creation of
subtypes. A ‘subtype’ is understood here as a derivative concept formed with reference to and as
a modification of some other concept. The most common means of forming subtypes is by adding
an adjective to the noun ‘democracy,’ as in ‘competitive democracy,’ and the subtypes we have
examined are generally formed in this manner. In other cases, the subtype appears to be created
with reference to the concept of democracy, but the term democracy is not used in the name of
the subtype—e.g., ‘electoral regime.’ In analyzing these subtypes, it is essential to underscore
the fact that their meaning cannot necessarily be inferred exclusively on the basis of the specific
terms employed in naming the subtype. Terms that appear similar may be used to mean quite
different things, and the definitions and actual usage of each author must also be considered.xxvi
We first consider two approaches to forming subtypes that correspond to Sartori’s original
recommendations and then turn to diminished subtypes.
xxv O’Donnell, “On the State, Democratization, and Some Conceptual Problems,” World
Development 21, no. 8 (1993).
xxvi This is why we insist in the classification of subtypes presented below that the subtypes
cannot be evaluated on the basis of terms taken in isolation. Rather, the classification is based on
the usage of the specific authors whom we cite.
Sartori’s Strategy for Differentiation
In Sartori’s pioneering article on the use of concepts in comparative analysis, one of his
basic goals is to show how greater conceptual differentiation can be achieved by moving down
the ladder of generality to concepts that 1) have more defining attributes and 2) correspondingly
fit a narrower range of cases. These concepts provide the more fine-grained distinctions that for
some purposes are invaluable to the researcher. xxvii With reference to the concept of
democracy, this move down the ladder is often accomplished by the creation of what we will call
‘classical’ subtypes,xxviii which in the context of the present discussion are understood as
specific yet full instances of democracy. Thus, ‘federal democracy,’ ‘multiparty democracy,’ and
‘parliamentary democracy’ are seen as particular kinds of democracies at the same time that they
are viewed as definitely being democratic (by whatever standard the author is employing). In
research on recent cases of democratization, the use of classical subtypes to achieve
differentiation is found, for example, in the important debate on the consequences of
‘parliamentary’ versus ‘presidential’ democracy (see Figure 3). xxix Other classical subtypes refer
to additional aspects of political structure, as in ‘two-party’ democracy, and to the antecedents of
the current regime, as in ‘postauthoritarian’ democracy.
Descending the ladder of generality provides useful differentiation, and indeed these
subtypes have offered analytic distinctions of fundamental importance. Yet the classical subtypes
formed in this manner may leave the analyst more vulnerable to conceptual stretching, given that
they presume the cases under discussion to be fully democratic. If the particular case being
studied is marginally democratic, then the use of these classical subtypes as a tool of conceptual
differentiation may not be appropriate. Particularly in the first phase of this literature, when
scholars believed they were dealing with incomplete or ‘uncertain’ democracies,xxx there was a
strong inclination to use labels that signaled a recognition of these limits. To do this, analysts
needed concepts that distinguished among different degrees of democracy, in addition to
Figure 3
Achieving Differentiation versus Avoiding Conceptual Stretching
REGIME
DEMOCRACY
Achieving Differentiation
Using Classical Subtypes of Democracy
Parliamentary democracy (Linz 1994)
Two-party democracy (Gasiorowski 1990)
Postauthoritarian democracy (Lipset 1994)
Diminished Subtypes
Diminished subtypes have played a central role in this literature because they can
contribute both to avoiding conceptual stretching and to achieving greater differentiation. They
xxxiii Because they are less than complete instances, it might be objected that they are not
really ‘subtypes’ of democracy at all. Drawing on a term from cognitive linguistics, one can refer to
them as conceptual ‘blends’ which are derived in part from the concept of democracy. However,
to avoid referring repeatedly to ‘subtypes and blends,’ it seems simpler in the discussion below to
call them subtypes. See Gilles Fauconnier and Mark Turner, “Conceptual Projection and Middle
Spaces,” Report No. 9401, Department of Cognitive Science, University of California, San Diego,
1994.
xxxiv It merits emphasis that these authors may not think of themselves as forming subtypes of
democracy but rather as informally using an adjective in conjunction with the noun ‘democracy.’
However, from a linguistic or cognitive point of view they are thereby creating analytic categories,
and the fact that the resulting subtypes are often used in the title of their articles, or at key points
in the introduction or conclusion, suggests that these conceptual innovations do play an
important role in framing their research.
a. Partial Democracies: Subtypes Derived from Procedural Minimum and Expanded Procedural
Minimum Definitions
These subtypes tend to be employed by scholars studying cases that are either ‘in
transition’ or have remained only partially democratized, including a number of countries in Central
America, Southeast Asia, Africa, and much of the former Soviet Union. This form of subtype is
generally derived in relation to the procedural minimum definition presented in Figure 1, in that
these scholars treat free elections, universal suffrage, and the protection of basic civil liberties as
essential features of democracy. Most of these subtypes serve to differentiate cases on the basis
of a specific attribute that is missing or weakened—for example, free elections, full suffrage, full
electoral contestation, and civil liberties. Because each of these attributes is considered by the
author to be a defining element of democracy, the subtypes generated are necessarily seen as
less than fully democratic. Hence, these subtypes serve to distinguish different forms of ‘partial’
democracy.
Figure 4 presents selected examples of these subtypes. The organization of the figure is
intended to call attention to systematic correspondences between the meanings of the subtypes
and the spectrum of definitions of democracy discussed above. Beginning with the left column in
the figure, we find those subtypes that do not meet even an electoralist standard for being
democratic. The subtypes in the first group (a) in the left column refer to cases where elections
are basically fraudulent. Here, analysts see the missing attribute as fundamentally invalidating
democracy, and consequently they use dismissive terms such as ‘façade’ or ‘sham’ democracy.
Where elections are held and the missing attribute is full suffrage (b), we find terms such as
‘oligarchical’ or ‘proto-’ democracy. Where elections are basically competitive, but the attribute of
full contestation is missing (c), as when important parties are banned from electoral competition,
we find terms such as ‘controlled’ and ‘restrictive’ democracy.
Turning to the next group of subtypes (d), we find that one or more of these essential
features of democracy is missing but that the missing trait is not specified. It is clear from the
author’s usage that these subtypes at most correspond to an electoralist definition, but because
the exact placement on the spectrum of definitions is not clear, they have been placed between
the first and the second column. Examples of these subtypes include ‘partial,’ ‘quasi,’ and ‘semi’-
democracy.
Moving to the right in the figure, the subtypes grouped in the second column (e)
correspond in their meaning to the electoralist definition of democracy. Here, in dealing with
cases where elections are reasonably free and competitive but civil liberties are incomplete,
scholars have used terms such as ‘electoral’ and ‘illiberal’ democracy.
Finally, the subtypes in the group (f) located in the third column of Figure 4 correspond in
their meaning to the procedural minimum definition of democracy. The emergence of these
19
Collier and Levitsky
--------------- - -- -----
0"
~
~"
~
iii"
-
=-
:III
=-
> >
'"'
.. :;
;;:
=
;:;
..,
=
-
c:
...
..,
..,
..to
= to
~ t":
c ~
i ;;-
,.,
;;-
n
>
>D
>D
.....
iO
'"
,r a
s:
------ -;:; -- '--
=
... ....
;;-
...
... ,.,
=
:ij" ..;:;
'"
=-
'"'>
:;
,-:;--,
c:
;;-
-o..
n
- -
:;;-
CIJ
;:; ~
.. ...
,.,
;:;. :;
0>
=
::I
..
o...
-...
::!
=
-...
..C
n
0-
=
'"
"Co
..
=
-
~
?
:i"
Er
c
3
----------------------
oII
o II
~ --
C,):i"
::.3
~ c
-..
oto;
::'I
:: -.
-o.
=
::I
5' -..
CI:1
C
-
=
-------------------------
subtypes shows how the creation of diminished subtypes may occur in conjunction with
precising. Thus, scholars who created the expanded procedural minimum definition through
precising introduced new diminished subtypes in which the missing attribute was the effective
power of the elected government to govern. Examples include ‘protected’ and ‘tutelary’
democracy.
Having introduced the basic idea of how diminished subtypes work, we can now return to
the relationship between these subtypes and the ladder of generality. We have already argued
that if these subtypes simply had fewer defining attributes than does the concept of a full
democracy, then within the framework of the ladder of generality diminished subtypes should be
more general than the concept of democracy itself, i.e., they would refer to more cases. In this
sense, they would follow the pattern noted above of inverse variation between the number of
defining attributes and the number of cases referred to. However, the diminished subtype does
not merely have fewer defining attributes. Rather, it specifies certain attributes that are missing.
As a consequence of specifying these missing attributes, it refers to a particular type of partial
democracy and not to full democracy. The question of whether these diminished subtypes refer
to a larger or smaller number of cases than does the root concept of democracy is an empirical
one.
Figure 5 illustrates one possible pattern of inclusion and exclusion of cases that may
occur in conjunction with creating a diminished subtype, as opposed to climbing the ladder of
generality, using the illustrative cases of contemporary Spain and Guatemala. Whereas Spain, but
probably not Guatemala, would be seen as fully democratic in terms of the procedural minimum
definition, climbing the ladder of generality we find that the broader concept of ‘electoral
regime’xxxv encompasses both cases. On the other hand, the diminished subtype of ‘limited
democracy’ would include only Guatemala, and specifically not Spain. Thus, the diminished
subtype of limited democracy refers to a case that does not fit the root concept of democracy.
xxxv This subtype is understood to have the meaning explained on pages 14–16 above in the
discussion of Figure 3.
Figure 5
A More General
Concept
ELECTORAL
REGIME
Cases
Spain and
Guatemala
LIMITED
DEMOCRACY DEMOCRACY
Cases Cases
Spain but not Guatemala but not
Guatemala Spain
* The diminished subtype is placed to the right side of ‘democracy’ in the figure, rather than above
or below it, to underscore the fact that it is not located on the ladder of generality.
and social problems faced by many democracies. The differentiating criteria employed in forming
these subtypes are derived not from elements of the procedural minimum or expanded
procedural minimum definitions, as is the case for the subtypes presented in Figure 4, but rather
from the prototypical conception of established industrial democracy introduced in Figure 1. This
conception is based on a constellation of attributes, listed in Figure 6, that are commonly
perceived to be found in the political and social systems of advanced industrial countries. As
Figure 6
noted above, by including these attributes, which are seen as characteristic of democracies that
are understood to ‘function properly,’xxxvi this conception goes well beyond basic procedural
xxxvi It might be added that this prototypical conception typically does not take account of the
serious political and economic crises recently experienced by some of these advanced industrial
countries.
definitions. The subtypes formed in this manner are often presented with little attention to
definitions.xxxvii
We have identified more than one hundred of these subtypes, examples of which are
included in Figure 6. Most of the examples in the figure refer to cases in which one or more
specific elements in this prototypical conception are understood to be weakened or absent.
Some of these subtypes are concerned with basic features of the regime. Thus, where regime
consolidation is weak (a), scholars refer to ‘fragile’ and ‘insecure’ democracy. Where horizontal
accountability xxxviii—i.e., ‘checks and balances’ vis-à-vis the executive—is incomplete (b), one
finds such subtypes as ‘caudillistic’ and ‘delegative’ democracy.
Many subtypes in the figure refer not to the regime itself but to other features of the
political systems that are commonly found in industrial democracies. Thus, where the level of
effective citizen participation is low (c), scholars have used subtypes such as ‘depoliticized’ and
‘low-intensity’ democracy. If the government or the regime is seen as ineffective or unresponsive
(d), subtypes such as ‘blocked,’ ‘impotent,’ ‘overinstitutionalized,’ and ‘weak’ democracy are
employed. Where commitment to social welfare policies is weak or absent (e), one finds, for
example, ‘conservative’ and ‘neoliberal’ democracy. In cases where national sovereignty is weak
(f), scholars have used subtypes such as ‘internationally dependent,’ ‘neocolonial,’ and ‘US-
imposed’ democracy.
Subtypes associated with this prototypical conception at times include features of the
society and economy that advocates of minimal and procedural definitions have specifically
argued should be excluded from the definition of democracy (see again Figure 6). Thus, where
socioeconomic conditions are seen as unfavorable to democracy (g), one finds reference to ‘low-
income’ and ‘poor’ democracy, and for cases characterized by low levels of sociopolitical stability
(h), scholars refer to ‘socially explosive’ and ‘conflictive’ democracy. Finally, some of these
subtypes refer more generically to a weakened version of this prototypical conception (i) in which
the particular missing features are not clear: for example, ‘incomplete’ and ‘problematic’
democracy.
An ambiguity regarding this group of subtypes merits comment. In contrast to the
subtypes that represent a diminished form of a procedural minimum definition, this second group
consists of subtypes introduced by authors who explicitly or implicitly view them as referring to
regimes that meet basic procedural definitions of democracy. Because the differentiating
features are not explicitly treated by the authors as defining features of democracy, their absence
xxxvii As with other authors whose definitions are not explicit, we have often inferred the
meaning from the larger framework of the authors’ analysis and from the way the subtype is
applied to specific cases.
xxxviii This term was suggested by Guillermo O’Donnell, “Delegative Democracy?” 61.
does not make the regime less democratic from a formal definitional standpoint. In this sense,
these might in fact be seen as classical subtypes vis-à-vis the procedural minimum definition. On
the other hand, these authors can be seen as creating diminished subtypes because they are in
effect treating these regimes as incomplete and problematic in relation to this often implicit
conception of advanced industrial democracy. Thus, in this case, the distinction between
classical and diminished subtypes depends on the perspective from which the subtypes are
viewed.
xxxix Bruce Michael Bagley, “Colombia: National Front and Economic Development” in Robert
Wesson, ed., Politics, Policies, and Economic Development in Latin America (Stanford: Hoover
Institution Press, 1984), 125–27.
and ‘hybrid democratic-authoritarian regime.’xl
The second group of diminished subtypes (Figure 6), which we have characterized as
identifying ‘problematic’ democracies, refers to cases that are understood as democracies in terms
of the procedural minimum definition yet are seen as problematic in relation to a prototypical
conception of advanced industrial democracy. On the positive side, one may argue that readers
of the literature on democracy readily understand these subtypes as conveying salient
information about the cases under discussion, and in this sense they are useful. Yet several
concerns may be raised about these subtypes. First, the root conception from which the
differentiating attributes are derived is generally not clearly stated by the authors. Although the
authors often provide enough information for us to be able to identify the conception of
democracy in relation to which the subtype is treated as a diminished form, there is often a lack of
explicit reflection on the part of the authors about the standard they are employing. Though many
of these authors purport to use a procedural minimum definition of democracy, it is clear that their
implicit understanding of ‘full’ democracy is actually far more elaborate. Indeed, many of the
diminished subtypes listed in Figure 6 introduce as criteria for differentiation some of the very
social and economic attributes that proponents of procedural and minimal definitions have argued
should be excluded from the definition of democracy. Hence, these social and economic
features are creeping back into many authors’ conceptions of democracy, although these
conceptions are rarely, if ever, made explicit. This implicit conception of ‘full’ democracy needs to
be more carefully examined.
Moreover, in some cases one observes an unfortunate interaction between the imprecise
character of these subtypes and their tendency to convey a negative evaluation of the case or
cases under discussion. They at times place scholars in the position of appearing to write critically
about given cases but without situating their negative evaluation in the context of a careful
conceptualization of democracy and its subtypes. This does not strike us as a productive route to
follow. O’Donnell’s analysis of delegative democracy is a good model for avoiding this problem, in
that he offers an intricate conceptualization of how the delegative character of these regimes
undermines democratic consolidation.xli For each of these subtypes, it is worth asking whether
xl These subtypes might appear to resemble those presented in the upper part of Figure 3. Yet
in terms of their meaning they correspond more closely to the examples in Figure 4—with the
crucial difference that they do not identify the cases to which they refer with the term democracy.
These examples are drawn from Karl, “Dilemmas of Democratization,” 180; Karl “Imposing
Consent,” 195; Larry Diamond, “Economic Development and Democracy Reconsidered” in
Diamond and Gary Marks, eds., Reexamining Democracy (Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications,
1992), 99; Karl, “The Hybrid Regimes of Central America,” 72; and Catherine M. Conaghan and
Rosario Espinal, “Unlikely Transitions to Uncertain Regimes? Democracy without Compromise in
the Dominican Republic and Ecuador,” Journal of Latin American Studies 22 (October 1990),
555.
xli O’Donnell, “Delegative Democracy?” 66–68.
there is an equivalent analytic payoff. In some cases, what is at least implicitly being treated as a
problem of democracy might be better understood as involving underlying problems of societies
that happen to have democratic regimes.
Concluding Observations
Scholars who study recent democratization have faced the two-fold challenge of
developing conceptualizations of democracy that not only achieve finer differentiation among
cases but also avoid stretching the concept. We have examined various strategies of conceptual
innovation employed to meet this challenge with the aim both of making more comprehensible
the complex structure of meaning that has emerged and of offering observations on the strengths
and weaknesses of the different strategies. The first two strategies—precising the definition of
democracy and shifting the overarching concept with which democracy is associated—can be
used both to avoid stretching the concept of democracy and to provide finer differentiation.
However, if either strategy is carried too far, it can lead to confusion about meaning and usage.
With regard to strategies based on the formation of subtypes, Sartori’s alternative approaches of
descending and climbing the ladder of generality can, respectively, help either in providing finer
differentiation or avoiding conceptual stretching, but cannot do both at once.
Finally, diminished subtypes can achieve both goals simultaneously, and they often serve
to provide vivid, compelling labels for the specific forms of democracy of concern to the analyst.
Consequently, the creation of diminished subtypes is the most common form of conceptual
innovation in this literature. At the same time, the value of diminished subtypes is greatly reduced
if scholars do not offer clear definitions and if they unreflectively separate the root conception
used in deriving subtypes from their own definition of democracy. It is similarly counterproductive
to generate numerous terms for subtypes that mean basically the same thing.
To conclude, four points should be emphasized. The first concerns the understanding of
democracy in graded, as opposed to dichotomous, terms. Various scholars have pointed to the
need to move beyond a dichotomous conceptualization of authoritarianism and democracy and
recognize the ‘hybrid’ or ‘mixed’ character of many postauthoritarian regimes.xlii As this paper
shows, this recognition has indeed occurred—and on a rather large scale. Not only have scholars
studying regimes in Latin America, Africa, Southeast Asia, and the former communist countries
emphasized the ‘partial’ or ‘hybrid’ nature of many new democracies, they have also identified,
often through the use of numerous subtypes, the diverse configurations of features found in
xlii James M. Malloy, “The Politics of Transition in Latin America” in Malloy and Seligson, eds.,
Authoritarians and Democrats, 236–57; Conaghan and Espinal, “Unlikely Transitions to Uncertain
Regimes?” 555; Hartlyn, “Crisis-Ridden Elections,” 94–96; Karl, “The Hybrid Regimes of Central
America”; and Weffort, Qual democracia? 89–90.
these regimes. What has been lacking is an effort to understand how the treatment of these
hybrid regimes has been organized conceptually.
This paper has sought to initiate that effort. It is evident that within the general framework
provided by the spectrum of definitions in Figure 1, analysts have introduced a series of
gradations into their conceptualizations—to such an extent that it may be appropriate to
reconsider the old distinction between quantitative researchers who think in terms of ‘degree’ and
qualitative researchers whose categories capture differences in ‘kind.’ Although the studies
under discussion here would conventionally be viewed as involving qualitative research, at a
number of points these analysts appear to be working with an implicit ordinal scale of degrees of
democracy rather than with a large number of nominal distinctions. To the extent that this ordinal
scale is made more explicit and is employed more systematically, the goal of conceptual
differentiation will be better served.
Second, this more differentiated understanding of democracy is important not only for the
purpose of description, but also because democracy is often used as a variable in causal analysis.
A large literature has treated democracy as an outcome to be explained, including both major
works of comparative-historical analysis and the old and new literature on ‘social requisites.’ Other
studies have looked at the impact of democracy, and also of specific types of democracy, on
economic growth, income distribution, economic liberalization and adjustment, and international
conflict. Given the diverse definitions of democracy found in these writings, as well as the
numerous subtypes that have been proposed, it is not surprising that these causal analyses have
often reached contradictory conclusions. We hope that the present discussion can serve as a
step toward a greater consistency of meaning and usage that will provide a more adequate basis
for causal assessment.
Third, our analysis suggests that although scholarship on the recent wave of
democratization initially embraced procedural and minimal definitions, recent work reflects a shift
toward more elaborate definitions and conceptualizations. This trend can be seen in many of the
innovations discussed in this paper, including the various efforts at precising, O’Donnell’s
distinction between democratic ‘states’ and democratic ‘regimes,’ and the widespread use of
subtypes to refer to new democracies that meet procedural minimum criteria for democracy but
lack other—often ‘substantive’—features that are viewed as characteristic of established industrial
democracies. Although many of these conceptual innovations may be criticized both for lack of
clarity and for adding attributes to the concept of democracy that are better kept distinct, they do
seem to reflect a growing concern that the mere existence (and persistence) of basic democratic
‘procedures’ does not guarantee the existence of the broader range of political, economic, and
social outcomes that we have come to associate with democracy as it is practiced in the
industrialized West. As many of the new democracies in Latin America, Eastern Europe, and
other parts of the world continue to survive but not thrive, these conceptual innovations are likely
to continue. At the same time, it is reasonable to raise again the issue posed above: Do the
‘problematic’ features that are the focus of these shifting conceptions of democracy really entail
attributes of democracy itself, or are they better understood as underlying problems of societies
that happen to be democratic?
We conclude by offering an old piece of advice with renewed urgency. The complex
structure of meaning generated by the strategies of conceptual innovation discussed above
offers scholars an impressive array of terms and conceptions that may be applied to the study of
democratization. Given this complexity, it is imperative that scholars situate themselves in relation
to this structure by clearly defining and explicating the conception of democracy they are
employing.
A
Procedural Minimum: O’Donnell and Schmitter, Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative
Conclusions, 8; Larry Diamond, Juan J. Linz, and Seymour Martin Lipset, Democracy in
Developing Countries: Comparing Experiences with Democracy (Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner, 1989), 6–7; Giuseppe Di Palma, To Craft Democracies, 16; Scott Mainwaring,
“Transitions to Democracy and Democratic Consolidation: Theoretical and Comparative
Issues” in Mainwaring, O’Donnell, and Valenzuela, eds., Issues in Democratic Consolidation,
297–98. See also Juan J. Linz, The Breakdown of Democratic Regimes (Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1978), 5.
Maximalist: Richard Fagen, “The Politics of Transition” in Richard Fagen, Carmen Diana Deere,
and José Luís Coraggio, eds., Transition and Development: Problems of Third World
Socialism (NY: Monthly Review Press, 1986), 258; Timothy Harding and James Petras,
“Introduction: Democratization and Class Struggle,” Latin American Perspectives 15, no. 3
(1988), 3–4; Jonas, “Elections and Transitions,” 129–30; Miliband, “The Socialist
Alternative,” 122–23; Gills, Rocamora, and Wilson, Low Intensity Democracy; and Marta
Harnecker, “Democracy and Revolutionary Movement” in Susanne Jonas and Edward J.
McCaughan, eds., Latin America Faces the Twenty-First Century: Reconstructing a Social
Justice Agenda (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1994), 64.
Figure 2
Silvio Duncan Baretta and John Markoff, “Brazil’s Abertura: Transition to What?” in Malloy and
Seligson, eds., Authoritarians and Democrats, 62; James M. Malloy, “The Politics of Transition
in Latin America,” 236; Frances Hagopian and Scott Mainwaring, “Democracy in Brazil:
Problems and Prospects,” World Policy Journal 4, no. 3 (1987), 485; O’Donnell, “Challenges
to Democratization in Brazil,” 281; and O’Donnell, “On the State, Democratization, and Some
Conceptual Problems,” 1360.
Figure 3
Civilian Regime: John A. Booth, “A Framework for Analysis” in Booth and Seligson, Elections
and Democracy in Central America 26.
Competitive Regime: Ruth Berins Collier and David Collier, Shaping the Political Arena:
Critical Junctures, the Labor Movement, and Regime Dynamics in Latin America (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1991), 354.
Electoral Regime: James Petras and Fernando Ignacio Leiva, Democracy and Poverty in
Chile: The Limits to Electoral Politics (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1994), 89.
Façade Democracy: Seymour Martin Lipset, “The Social Requisites of Democracy Revisited,”
17.
Phantom Democracy: Ralph Goldman, “The Nominating Process: Factionalism as a Force for
Democratization” in Gary E. Wekkin, Donald E. Whistler, Michael A. Kelley, and Michael A.
Maggiotto, eds., Building Democracy in One-Party Systems: Theoretical Problems and Cross-
Nation Experiences (Westport, CT: Praeger, 1993), 66.
Pseudodemocracy: John Higley and Richard Gunther, eds., Elites and Democratic
Consolidation in Latin America and Southern Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1992), 6.
Protodemocracy: Atul Kohli, “Democracy amid Economic Orthodoxy,” Third World Quarterly
14, no. 4 (1993), 677.
Stable Limited Democracy: Higley and Gunther, Elites and Democratic Consolidation, 5–6.
Controlled Democracy: Bruce Michael Bagley, “Colombia: National Front and Economic
Development,” 125.
Partial Democracy: Robert Wesson, ed. Democracy: A Worldwide Survey (NY: Praeger,
1987), 9.
Quasi Democracy: Stephan Haggard and Robert Kaufman, “The Prospects for Democracy” in
Haggard and Kaufman, eds., The Politics of Economic Adjustment (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1992), 326.
Formal Democracy: Larry Diamond, “Promoting Democracy in the 1990s: Actors, Instruments,
and Issues,” revised version of a paper for the Nobel Symposium on “Democracy’s Victory
and Crisis” (Uppsala, Sweden, 1994), 1.
Limited Democracy: O’Donnell and Schmitter, Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Tentative
Conclusions, 9.
Immature Democracy: Michael L. Kelley, Michael A. Maggiotto, Gary D. Wekkin, and Donald E.
Whistler, “The Democratic Impulse and the Movement toward Democracy: An Introduction” in
Wekkin, Whistler, Kelley, and Maggiotto, Building Democracy, 7.
Caudillistic Democracy: Richard Hillman, Democracy for the Privileged: Crisis and Transition
in Venezuela (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1992), 24.
Populist Democracy: Philippe C. Schmitter and Terry Lynn Karl, “The Types of Democracy
Emerging in Southern and Eastern Europe and South and Central America” in Peter M. E.
Volten, ed., Bound to Change: Consolidating Democracy in East Central Europe (NY:
Institute for EastWest Studies, 1992), 56.
Dual Democracy: Smith and Acuña, “Future Politico-Economic Scenarios for Latin America,”
20.
Input Democracy: Jan Knippers Black, “Elections and Other Trivial Pursuits: Latin America and
the New World Order,” Third World Quarterly 14, no. 3 (1993), 545.
Controlled Democracy: Franz J. Hinkelammert, “Our Project for the New Society in Latin
America: The Regulating Role of the State and Problems of Self-Regulation in the Market” in
Jonas and McCaughan, eds., Latin America Faces the Twenty-First Century, 25.
Sick Democracy: Antonio Stempel Paris, Venezuela: Una democracia enferma (Caracas:
Editorial Ateneo, 1980).
Spectrum of Definitions
Expanded
b. Missing Attribute: Full Suffrage Procedural Minimum Procedural Minimum
Exclusionary democracy (Remmer 1986) Definition Definition
Oligarchical democracy (Hartlyn and of Democracy of Democracy
Valenzuela 1994)
Protodemocracy (Kohli 1993)
Stable limited democracy (Higley/Gunther 1992) Elections, Full Suffrage,
Elections, Full Suffrage, Civil Liberties, and
Civil Liberties Effective Power to
c. Missing Attribute: Full Contestation
Govern
Asian-style democracy (Neher 1994)
Controlled democracy (Bagley 1984)
De facto one-party democracy (Leftwich 1993)
Restrictive democracy (Waisman 1989)
= Subtypes