Rights Sociological Perspectives (Lydia Morris)
Rights Sociological Perspectives (Lydia Morris)
This pioneering new book suggests how different traditions of sociological thought
can contribute to an understanding of the theory and practice of rights. A substantial
opening chapter reviews the emerging field of sociology and rights, and therefater the
volume is divided into four parts, each with a brief introduction:
Edited by
Lydia Morris
First published 2006
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada
by Routledge
270 Madison Ave, New York, NY 10016
This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2006.
“To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s
collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.”
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group
© 2006 Lydia Morris for selection and editorial matter; the
contributors for individual chapters
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or
reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic,
mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter
invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any
information storage or retrieval system, without permission in
writing from the publishers.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
A catalog record for this book has been requested
Contributors vii
Acknowledgements xi
Sociology and rights – an emergent field 1
LYDIA MORRIS
PART I
Political economy and rights 17
PART II
Status, norms and institutions 73
PART IV
The clash of rights 187
Bibliography 253
Index 280
Contributors
All contributors to this book are, or have been, members of the Sociology
Department at the University of Essex. I wish to acknowledge here the
debt that many of us owe to our one-time colleague Bryan Turner, and his
enduring interest in the study of rights, a topic he viewed as ripe for socio-
logical intervention. We also owe much to the Human Rights Centre here at
Essex for stimulating and coordinating intellectual interest and activities in
the area of rights. My own work for this book was completed during sabbati-
cal leave, first at the Center for European Studies at Harvard University
(September to December 2004), and then at the Centre for the Study of
Human Rights at the London School of Economics (February to June 2005).
I greatly appreciate the stimulation and support I received in both places and
hope that this end product repays their interest.
Lydia Morris
Essex
Sociology and rights – an
emergent field
Lydia Morris
Notes
1 Such as the British Human Rights Act (1998).
2 Quoted in Pickering and Watts Miller (1993: 56), from Leçons de Sociologie
(1950: 74).
3 Quoted in Cladis (1992: 1), from La science positive de la morale en Allemagne
(1887).
4 Quoted in Cladis (1992: 115), from ‘The determination of moral facts’ (in
Durkheim, 1974: 59).
5 An example was the notorious primary purpose rule, abolished in 1997, which
required applicants for family unification to demonstrate that the primary purpose
of the marriage did not have an economic motivation.
6 Quoted in Lukes (1991: 176).
Part I
Political economy
and rights
The opening part of the book contains three chapters that fall roughly into
the tradition of political-economy analysis, in which an emphasis is placed
on the holistic understanding of a social formation, through a focus on the
political and economic relationships that underpin social life. The first of
these chapters considers a radical critique of the liberal tradition of rights,
though from a position generally accepting of the priority placed on
individual well-being, and on equal worth. The argument of the chapter,
however, challenges the broader assumptions that have prevailed in rights
discourse, notably a view of the individual as divorced from both benign and
malign dependencies. Neglect of the former underestimates the extent to
which individual identity is located in interpersonal relations, while neglect
of the latter underestimates the effect of socio-economic inequality on access
to, and the value of, individual freedoms. Instead of questioning this frame-
work, it is argued that existing human rights guarantees seem to operate
from within and to offer forms of amelioration that contain rather than
challenge inherent tensions. A similar argument was advanced by Marshall
(1950), but Benton goes further, in advocating an approach that places
rights in a much wider context, and asks, for example, why restraint on the
actions of others should be so central to well-being, and what the implied
sources of harm might be.
When viewed in truly universal terms, the answer to this question extends
to the system of trade regulation disadvantaging the poorer countries of the
world, tied to export-led growth, a high reliance on imports, low public
spending and gross indebtedness; a package that siphons off a large propor-
tion of their available revenue. The broader context of rights and possible
harms would also take in the ‘organised non-liability’ endemic in the ‘risk
society’ (Beck, 1992), linked to damaging occupational histories and
environmental hazards, both of which are most likely to characterise life at
the lower end of the class hierarchy. These harms are not readily addressed
by an individualised regime of rights, and even assuming that they were, the
liberal model carries the implied assumption that if secured from such harms
all individuals have the capacity to construct for themselves a fulfilling life.
Benton argues that this view neglects both the impact that unequal access to
18 Political economy and rights
material, cultural and educational resources can have on such a capacity,
and the interpersonal relations and community bonds that for many are the
source of meaning in life. His argument closely connects with attempts to
develop a more enabling approach to rights by a focus on capabilities (Sen,
1999; Nussbaum, 2000), and leads to Benton’s alternative vision for a
regime of rights that recognises the underpinnings of effective presence and
agency in society, and the interpersonal relationships on which it builds.
The second chapter to adopt the political economy approach also evokes
questions about the nature of interpersonal and community dependencies in
the context of pension rights. It is, in addition, concerned with larger-scale
issues shaping the generation and commitment of resources to address the
pressing problem of provision for old age. If we accept Turner’s bodily
frailty and social precariousness as a basis for claims to rights, none could
seem as unquestionable as a right to support in old age, yet the basis and
substance of pension rights has become a pressing problem in contemporary
capitalist society. Truly universal state pensions tend to take the form of
minimal, residual provision, though ageing populations in the developed
world mean this still poses a huge challenge to national exchequers. Occu-
pational pensions have become less and less viable, and in private schemes,
while there is a right to be fairly and honestly treated, the market risk of
investing is borne by the contributor, and there is no guarantee of a pension.
The variable mix of public and private provision in operation can be
construed more readily as a system of civic stratification (as outlined in
Chapter 4) than as a viable system of universal entitlement, especially when
tax relief on private schemes, which favours wealthier savers, is taken into
account.
At the heart of the pensions problem lies the question of the relationship
across generations and the nature and degree of responsibility that the cur-
rent taxable population carries for the contemporary elderly. In a tax-based
system, each contributor pays not for their own needs in old age, but for the
needs of the prior generation. When the age cohorts are dramatically out of
balance this relationship either imposes a huge responsibility on a small
cohort or undermines the entitlements of the larger cohort. So what does a
system of cross-generational justice look like in these circumstances, and
who bears the cost of a socially responsible approach to old age? When
pensions are considered in this light, the language of rights seems rather
distant, and the approach serves instead to highlight the difficult configur-
ation of rights, resources and the location of responsibility. The temptation
for states to privatise all provision, thereby opting for a system of self-
responsibility, is immense, but as Blackburn points out, an expensive
solution given the marketing and salary costs of private providers. It would
also be a classic example of the desocialised, atomised individual represented
by the classical liberal model of rights discussed in Chapter 1, and is of
course grossly inequitable.
The third example of a political economy approach to rights also grapples
Political economy and rights 19
with the problem of ageing, but in relation to the right to physical care. The
issue of a right to care is in some respects more complex than that of
the right to a pension, requiring the recognition of caring as fundamentally
relational, but separable from other aspects of a social relationship, and
identifiable as a form of work. As in the case of pensions, making the
philosophical case for a right to care is rather less challenging than the
implementation of such a right in practice. This requires not only the accept-
ance of a universal principle, as in the ‘frailty’ theory of rights, but also the
delivery of particularised provision, according to differing dependencies
and vulnerabilities. Again like pensions, the place of each individual in
the underpinning roles and relationships will shift as they move through the
life course. As Chapter 3 makes clear, the ensuing nexus of rights, relation-
ships and responsibilities will be historically and culturally variable, and
care is therefore to be analysed as an embedded feature of contrasting
systems of exchange, reciprocity and obligation premised on very varied
socio-economic arrangements.
Of course, the recognition of a right to care also entails a more difficult
decision to identify cases in which the resource investment may be too great
when weighed against the diminishing benefits. In this sense, the right to care
requires judgements of relative desert, which are partially resource driven,
and which will be resolved differently according to the social, economic
and cultural context. The comparative approach advocated in Chapter 3 is
particularly revealing in this respect, and demonstrates how the concept of
rights need not be confined to legally based claims and calls on the state. It
may equally operate in the context of culture and tradition, based, for
example, on kinship obligations and expectations, often gendered, that
operate to varying degrees in different societies. We might also find that
several systems of provision operate simultaneously in any given society,
embodying different types of exchange relations and yielding multiple
and possibly conflicting expectations and obligations. Different systems will
also raise their own problems with respect to equity, standards, monitoring
and respect for the rights of both givers and receivers of care.
1 Do we need rights?
If so, what sort?
Ted Benton
Liberty consists in being able to do anything that does not harm another
person. Thus the exercise of the natural rights of each has no limits
except those which assure to other members of society the enjoyment of
these same rights; these limits can be determined only by law.
(Article 4 of the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen,
1789)
Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for the health
and well-being of himself and his family, including food, clothing, hous-
ing and medical care and necessary social services, and the right to
security in the event of unemployment, sickness, disability, widowhood,
old age or other lack of livelihood in circumstances beyond his control.
(Article 25)
Note
This chapter presents a condensed and reworked version of the argument given in
more detail in Chapter 4 of Benton (1993).
2 Return of the proletariat?
Pension rights and pension
finance in the ageing society
Robin Blackburn
Care is high on the public and political agenda, not only in Western welfare
states, but increasingly on a global scale with recognition of the care ‘deficit’,
work/life balance and international chains of care (e.g. Ehrenreich and
Hochschild, 2003) as shared international issues. Fundamental normative
and practical questions are raised about the principles and provision of
care, with implications for rights as well as for claims, including potential
expansion of both the terrain of rights and the groups on whose behalf they
are claimed.
Perhaps the simplest way to understand this emergent crisis is as a con-
sequence of the disruption of earlier modes of looking after those unable to
care for themselves. Multiple changes have impacted on ways of caring that
were previously taken for granted or integrated with other activities, so
disembedding them from their cultural, social and economic underpinnings.
The shift in welfare states from a male breadwinner to a dual earner model,
heightened emphasis on individual worth and dignity, the effects of urban-
isation and economic development for traditional kin-based structures and
responsibilities, life course alterations arising from increased longevity and
time spent in education and retirement, are just some of the changes. At the
same time as provoking new problems of care, this disordering also provides
a stimulus to new ways of thinking about how care is conducted, acknow-
ledging historical and cross-cultural variety, and the different groundings for
rights implicit in differing modes of provision.
Such concerns are at the heart of this chapter, which explores the different
kinds, bases and understandings of rights associated with different social
organisations of care. The approach is informed by a number of core
premises. First, groups conceived as dependent and in need of care are con-
structed socio-historically. There is nothing universal or fixed about care
needs. On the contrary, they are emergent, changing, specific to time and
place and immensely variable. Second, needs may be met by care provision-
ing systems that also differ considerably across cultures, nations and history,
both in how they are organised and in the extent to which they are differen-
tiated from other social relations. Third, varied systems of provisioning have
their own correlative sets of ‘rights’. Again these may take many forms:
56 Political economy and rights
informal or formal, prescribed by tradition and convention or by laws
enforced through criminal justice systems. They may be understood as a
‘private’ matter between individuals and families or publicly recognised and
articulated. This framework for care rights conceives of systems of care as
overall processes that include provision as well as entitlement. An economic
sociology perspective will be evident in the focus on exchange, reciprocity
and obligation, the work and cost of care and the conditions shaping
its demand, delivery and consumption. However, since socio-economic
relations may be understood only in relation to the culture and history
with which they are bound, elaboration of the argument draws on a wide
disciplinary range of evidence and analysis.
A brief review of approaches to care, drawing out some its social particu-
larities, precedes a discussion of issues raised in applying a rights perspective
to this field, notably those of provision and correlative duties. The central
parts of the chapter elaborate the argument that differing modes of care in
different times and circumstances give rise to contrasting kinds of rights, a
proposition that is then explored in greater detail and cross-culturally with
respect to elder care.
Conclusion
The analytical framework outlined in this chapter is rooted in an under-
standing of the practice and activity of care as a relational process between
receivers and givers, usually involving exchange. This supports a substantive
concern with historical, cultural and national variation between different
overall systems of care provision and the rights that attach to them.
Approached this way, the many different possible groundings and kinds of
rights come into sharp focus. Informal, taken-for-granted expectations and
personal or traditional obligations are equally to be considered under the
heading of rights as formalised entitlements or state-enforceable laws pre-
scribing citizen- or employment-based rights or putative human or universal
rights with their international sanctions. I have concentrated on the right to
receive care, but other additional rights, which there is not space to discuss,
would be directly implicated in this. The right to give care is the most obvi-
ous, but the rights of care workers (paid and unpaid) would also be signifi-
cant, especially with respect to employment and working conditions. In the
Developing an economic sociology of care and rights 71
case of migrants, whose contribution to care work is so crucial in many parts
of the world, entry and residence rights come to the fore.
To develop the analytical perspective I distinguished schematically
between state, familial, market and voluntary modalities of care and the
rights associated with them, drawing attention also to the diverse everyday
understandings that may accompany them. Exploring the particular case of
elder care across a range of times and places reveals considerable variability
in provision, rights and expectations, confirming the argument that rights
are shaped according to the socio-economic, political and cultural circum-
stances in which they are found. However, relativity does not imply relativ-
ism. A concept of rights as emergent and expanding is entirely consonant
with the view that rights are particular to the context of which they are a
part. This too raises horizons beyond the scope of the chapter towards polit-
ical questions about the most effective ways of establishing a strong footing
for rights to care on the political agenda. This could be approached by
redefining citizenship to include care or through campaigns in support of an
ethic of care and degendered moral philosophy. An alternative or additional
strategy would be to direct greater scrutiny at the governance of systems of
care with the aim of entrenching norms of best practice and collective social
responsibility. This could arguably side-step the problem that rights can
only be demanded of others, the state or employers. The capabilities para-
digm of Nussbaum and Sen might provide another potential route to the
same objectives. But whatever means are deployed, rights are a historical
achievement rather than natural or automatic. They change and expand in
scope or terrain, but only as the result of concerted human action.
Notes
1 Although the right to give care is a dominant theme in current policy discussion,
this chapter focuses on the right to receive, given that this is the more basic
right and would need to be established before the right to give could become an
effective question.
2 My prime research interest in care is as work. The material for this chapter is
drawn from comparative research currently being undertaken collaboratively
with Dawn Lyon on modes of paid and unpaid care work and employment in
Europe. This is part of a larger research programme on ‘Transformations of work:
new frontiers, shifting boundaries, changing temporalities’ funded by the ESRC
(Award RES-051–27–0015), for whose support I am extremely grateful.
3 There are exceptions where familial responsibility is a legal requirement. For
example, in Germany until recently, adults in need of long-term care were obliged
to turn first to their children for some financial support even if they fell below the
social assistance threshold (Ostner, 1999: 112).
4 The material for this section is drawn from interviews with care experts in Europe
and other respondents from East Asian countries, in addition to published
sources. I am grateful to Andrew Canessa, Colin Samson and Rob and Ja Stones
for ethnographic information about conditions for the elderly in the Andes,
sub-Arctic and Thailand.
Part II
Status, norms
and institutions
The second part of this volume groups together three chapters that, in differ-
ent ways, illustrate the significance of normative ideals and status difference
for an understanding of entitlement and implementation with respect to
rights. An emphasis on status is most explicit in Chapter 4, which considers
the Marshallian heritage in the light of Weber’s (1948) writings on status,
and Lockwood’s (1996) subsequent work on civic integration and class
formation. Though Marshall was interested in the effect an equal status of
citizenship could have on ameliorating the inequalities of the market, he was
aware of the possible influence that class prejudice and inequalities of wealth
could have on the implementation of rights. He also saw that citizenship
rights themselves could function as a basis for inequality, and Lockwood
expands these insights through his concept of civic stratification; a system of
inequality generated by the rights that can be claimed from the state. This
inequality functions on two dimensions: the formal designations of inclusion
and exclusion with respect to rights, and the informal processes of gain and
deficit. He notes, but does not develop, the idea that particular groups
or particular areas of rights can undergo periods of expansion with respect
to entitlement, such that the map of rights is never fixed but subject to
contestation and change.
Chapter 4 explores the application of these ideas to the analysis of
welfare and work in the context of debate both on ‘the underclass’ and on
immigration and asylum. The chapter considers the dominant arguments of
the ‘underclass’ debate and the emergence of an increasingly contractual
welfare policy, setting out the status issues associated with these develop-
ments. These operate through both the differing conditions of benefit
imposed on different claimant groups and the degrees of stigma that may be
attached to dependence. Most vulnerable are the long-term unemployed
and single parents, and Morris notes the possibility that negative percep-
tions of these groups are fuelled by policy rhetoric emphasising respon-
sibilities over rights. The chapter then moves on to consider the varying
circumstances of migrants and asylum seekers with respect to work and
welfare rights, arguing that ‘universal personhood’ with respect to rights
has yet to be fully established. The emphasis is instead on the role that a
74 Status, norms and institutions
differentiated system of rights can play in the process of management and
control, though such systems do not go unchallenged. Instead, work
and welfare rights operate within a contested terrain of both expansions and
contractions, and rather than guaranteed certainties we find a negotiated
pragmatism.
Chapter 5 presents the claim that ‘women’s rights are human rights’ as a
claim to equal status, though the status dimension of the analysis goes fur-
ther and deeper than this assertion. The chapter begins with a juxtaposition
of Turner’s search for ontological foundations and Waters’s social con-
structionist position vis-à-vis rights, and finds a parallel in feminist debates,
through Nash’s normative commitment to equality and Walby’s focus on
structural changes in a gender regime as possible bases for rights claims. In
presenting her account of the platform and achievements of feminist organ-
isations in the struggle for rights, Elson draws on both positions. She high-
lights how a change in gender regimes from a domestic to a more public
form can mean enhanced public status for women, and how an engagement
with the language of human rights rather than women’s rights is a status
issue. The Human Rights Sub-Commission on the Status of Women had to
fight to make the claim to equal status a reality, even in terms of the alloca-
tion of recognition and resources within the UN. Similarly, the international
response to the Convention for the Elimination of Discrimination against
Women was to view it as in some sense secondary, and this is reflected in the
number of reservations registered by signatory states.
To make their claims tell, women had to establish themselves not just
as women but as ‘half of humanity’. The argument that systematic abuses
arising out of gender-specific issues are human rights abuses is both an
endictment of androcentrism in perceptions and definitions of human
rights, and a challenge to the underpinning status order. Similarly, ‘the per-
sonal is political’ is a claim for status recognition of relations in the personal
and private domain, which has traditionally played a poor second to the
public sphere. This questioning of the established status order does not stop
there, however, as the issue of recognition erupts again when feminist post-
colonial theorists shine the light of equality on ethnocentric conceptions of
women’s rights and human rights. The chapter moves on to consider the
danger of reifying and essentialising difference through recognition, and
considers the arguments for both revaluing and degendering ‘female’ qual-
ities; the former recognising and the latter challenging difference. Finally, in
acknowledging the constraints of legal discourse, Elson argues for an appeal
to moral legitimacy in attempts to transform practices, perceptions and
understanding.
Chapter 6 focuses on the implementation of established norms through
the example of anti-racist policy in the EU, which legitimises EU-level action
to combat discrimination. The chapter distinguishes two related processes:
the importation of new ideas and ideals, in which social movements
play a prominent role; and their translation into policy, which involves
Status, norms and institutions 75
the mediation of differences and competition for resources. The former is
rooted in a cultural dynamic and the latter in an institutional dynamic – and
the move from one to the other is seen to be critical for the translation of
norms into rights. One problematic aspect of this ‘translation’ can be the
way that different actors seek to represent norms in terms of their own pre-
established interests and orientations, which can highlight the existence of
contrasting perspectives on the ultimate goal of anti-racism. Thus, status
and struggle can still be an issue, and as a relatively recent area for active
intervention, anti-racist norms have encountered certain difficulties in mov-
ing from broad principles to concrete interventions. Some of these difficul-
ties have been related to both recognition and resource issues, as competing
policy frames and embedded interests come together in a complex coalition
of activists and bureaucrats.
The growing primacy of anti-racist policy on the EU agenda has thus been
conducive to broad alliances, but less so to the cohesive framing of policy,
and a clear direction for anti-racist policy has yet to emerge. Interaction with
other aspects of social inclusion is also revealing, as the advocacy groups –
who play a significant role in the EU policy world – confront the need to
coordinate their complementary but at times competing interests. This same
tension also exists within the key institutions of the EU – the European
Parliament and the Commission – alongside an implicit contradiction
between member states which embrace differing varieties of assimilation
and multiculturalism. In practice, the question of ‘fit’ with the established
EU project has meant that economic rights tend to take precedence and
translate into an emphasis on integration through the labour market. How-
ever, the chapter argues that broad normative agreement is in itself a signifi-
cant achievement, and that even where the details of implementation remain
unclear or contested, such agreement serves to secure a significant value
position outside the realm of individual choice.
4 Social rights, trans-national
rights and civic stratification
Lydia Morris
We saw in the introduction to this volume that ‘rights’ have recently risen
to prominence as a focus for social, political and intellectual debate, yet as
Turner (1993) has argued, sociology as a discipline has no obvious founda-
tion for a contemporary theory of rights. While a sociology of citizenship
has to some extent served as a substitute, a number of critiques (e.g. Brubaker,
1989; Bottomore, 1992; Soysal, 1994) have argued that available frame-
works (usually based on Marshall’s (1950) classic work) are inadequate
to address a set of pressing contemporary issues. These include the growth
of transnational migration, the alleged expansion of ‘post-national member-
ship’, and the proliferation of positions of partial membership, to which we
can add the erosion of the social rights of full citizens. The analytical tools to
do justice to such phenomena are, however, underdeveloped and although
there have been various attempts to address this gap, there is as yet no
satisfactory comprehensive framework.
The introduction notes that one response to the question of how to think
sociologically about rights has been to move beyond nationally bounded
citizenship and to invoke the universal. However, while there has been grow-
ing interest and speculation about the scope and potential of universalism
(Turner, 1993; Soysal, 1994; Meyer et al., 1997), there has also been an
awareness of the limitations imposed by definitions of the national interest,
and a variety of recent contractions with respect to entitlement. In this con-
text, a focus on the power of universalism has only rarely engaged with a
number of common limitations and even erosions in the delivery of universal
human rights to non-citizens, much less with the constraints that are increas-
ingly imposed on full citizens. A growing emphasis on duties alongside
rights has been the site of some instances of contraction in contested areas of
provision, most notably in the area of welfare support, whose status as a
universal human right is far from clear. By addressing the specific issue of
welfare rights in the broader context of both the classical and emergent
literature on citizenship rights and migrant rights, this chapter seeks to
point the way to one possible foundation for a sociological approach to the
field that could yield a more nuanced analysis of rights than has yet been
available.
78 Status, norms and institutions
Class, status and power
One foundation for a fuller sociological approach to the issue of rights may
be found in Weber’s (1948) classic essay on class status and party, which
addresses the distinction between the social order or distribution of honour,
and the economic order of class situations determined by market position.
The key to class situation is the disposal of property through exchange in the
market, which functions to the great disadvantage of the propertyless, with
only their services to sell. Weber continues: ‘Those men whose fate is not
determined by the chance of using goods or services for themselves on the
market, e.g. slaves, are not, however, a class in the technical sense of the
term. They are rather a status group’ (ibid.: 183). A status situation is then
defined as: ‘every typical component of the life fate of men that is determined
by a specific positive or negative social estimation of honour’. For con-
temporary society Weber’s comments yield two dimensions of status, which
may be related: first, a fate determined outside the market; second, a posi-
tion defined by the values governing conferment (or otherwise) of social
honour. He also notes that status groups will tend to constitute com-
munities, and that ‘stratification by status goes hand in hand with a
monopolisation of ideal and material goods and opportunities’ (ibid.: 190,
emphasis added).
Status, as Weber defines it, is argued to be a hindrance to the operation of
the free market, and once a status order has established stability, its transla-
tion into legal privilege can easily follow. The relevance of this notion of
status for the study of rights lies in the conception of a formal position
outside the market, which in contemporary society is likely to be state sup-
ported,1 the less formalised dynamic attributing social honour to different
social groups, and the interesting possibility that these two dimensions may
coincide. One other aspect of Weber’s essay should be noted before we move
on, and that is the distinction between communal action, related to feelings
of mutual belonging, and societal action, based on a rational means – ends
orientation. The relevance of this distinction will become clear later in the
chapter, and potentially engages with two different possible bases for rights:
mutuality and contract. For the present, is takes only a short step to see the
relevance of Weber’s observations on status for a sociological understanding
of rights, in both their conception and operation.
Civic stratification
David Lockwood’s (1996) work on civic integration and class formation
systematically addresses a number of the issues sketched out or only hinted
at in the pieces by Weber and Marshall. His focus is on the way in which the
‘institutional unity’ of citizenship, market and bureaucracy mediates the
impact of social class in structuring life chances and identity. In capitalist
welfare state democracies, the common legal status of citizenship is argued
to have reduced institutionalised status difference but enhanced the institu-
tionalisation of power (embodied in state bureaucracies), such as to limit
incongruities in both fields. In terms of hierarchical status, this leaves only
what he terms the weaker forms of social inclusion and exclusion, and defer-
ence and derogation. However, like Marshall, Lockwood wishes to pose the
question of how far the central institutions of society function efficiently in
‘delivering the goods’, and what contribution they make to securing social
integration. In doing so, he throws light on a number of the key points of
interest listed above.
He notes, for example, that much of the legitimising effect of an equal
status of citizenship stems from the role of bureaucracies that oversee the
inequalities and rewards attaching both to occupational positions and to the
delivery of citizenship rights, by the application of impersonal rules (as
through the tax and welfare systems). Furthermore, like Marshall he sees
civil and political rights as a basic requirement for the functioning of capital,
leaving only the ‘fine-tuning’ of social rights to mediate the potential conflict
between status and contract. This means that governments have only limited
room for manoeuvre, which must rest on some form of selectivity based on
merit or demerit; in other words, the designation of deserving and undeserv-
ing claimants. Lockwood (1996: 536) also agrees with Marshall that ‘citi-
zenship remains an ideal whose actualisation is always less than complete’
and that its operations will therefore provide a potential focus for the
structuring of group interests, conflict and discontent.
This possibility is then explored with reference to two axes of inequality;
the presence or absence of rights, and the possession of moral or material
resources. The distinction captures the two different dimensions of status
referred to earlier, which are implicit in Weber’s essay, the one derived from
a formalised position,2 and the other principally from prestige factors of
either honour or wealth, which will often operate informally. On the basis of
Social rights, trans-national rights and civic stratification 81
these two axes of inequality, Lockwood derives what he terms four types
of civic stratification – civic exclusion, civic gain, civic deficit and civic
expansion – which are in fact two sets of paired oppositions. Civic gain and
deficit refer to the enhanced or impaired implementation of rights,3 civic
exclusion refers to the formal denial of rights, while expansion may refer to
either the expanding claims of particular groups, or the expanding terrain of
rights more generally – and universal human rights are given as an example.
Bechhofer (1996) has already argued that civic exclusion and expansion sit
uneasily together, and here I suggest a slight amendment, pairing exclu-
sion with inclusion to denote formal access to rights, and introducing a
third opposition, civic expansion and contraction, to refer to the shifting
character of a regime of rights or of a specific area within its ambit.
Notes
1 For example, single mothers, the disabled, the long-term unemployed, the
elderly.
2 For example, location vis-à-vis the market, or immigration status.
3 Lockwood (1996: 537) makes a further division into the three sub-areas of
power, stigmatisation and fiscal deficits.
4 A New Labour Government came to power in 1997 and has continued the trend
to tighter conditions on welfare benefits, especially, but not exclusively, for the
unemployed.
5 See Lockwood (1996) for an argument that the potential for collective identity
and action is unlikely to be realised.
6 Detention facilities for asylum seekers in Britain rose from 900 in 1997 to 1750
in 2004 (Guardian Weekly, 24 September 2004). Their use is not confined to
rejected applicants.
7 See European Court of Human Rights case D v. UK, application number
30240/96.
8 Council Directive L 16/44 will extend this right to long-term resident TCNs.
9 Usually limited to the immediate nuclear family (as in Germany), but possibly
including dependent parents (as in Italy).
10 A European Court of Human Rights ruling in 1985 found gender discrimination
in Britain’s rules on family unification, which disadvantaged women seeking
unification with a spouse, as compared with men. The clear objective of the rule
had been job protection, and the British response was to equalise downwards,
further limiting the rights of men (Bhabha and Shutter, 1994: 76).
11 For British examples, see 1996 AII ER 385, and 1997 1 CCLR 85.
12 For a challenge to this argument, see Bloch and Schuster (2002).
13 Five acts plus the Human Rights Act (HRA), which also has a bearing.
5 ‘Women’s rights are
human rights’
Campaigns and concepts
Diane Elson
The claim that ‘women’s rights are human rights’ has served as a focus
for organizing and advocacy by large numbers of feminist organizations
throughout the world since the early 1990s. However, during the same
period many feminist social and political theorists have been very critical of
the concept of ‘universal rights’, and of the deployment of the concept of
‘women’. This chapter explores what lies behind this apparent discord and
discusses how far feminist theory and practice can be reconciled.
To provide a framework for sociological interpretation, I draw on the inter-
change in Sociology between Bryan Turner and Malcolm Waters (Turner,
1993, 1997; Waters, 1996) and on two recent articles in Economy and Society
by feminist theorists Kate Nash and Sylvia Walby (Nash, 2002; Walby, 2002).
neither the use of the notion of equal rights nor demands on the state are
entirely new within feminism, but both the extent of the use of univer-
salist conceptions of human rights . . . and the extent of the orientation
to states constitute new developments. This raises a number of questions
as to how this is to be understood and why this is happening.
(Walby, 2002: 533)
By the early 1990s this demand to stop men’s violence against women
was articulated in international forums, including those of the UN. . . .
This was translated into language and concepts more appropriate for
the predominantly male forum of the UN, that is the language of human
rights rather than men’s oppression of women.
(Walby, 2002: 541)
Bunch noted the existence of CEDAW but doubted its capacity to address
violence against women effectively, arguing that ‘Within the UN, it is not
generally regarded as a convention with teeth’ (ibid.: 496), and that it is
treated by governments and most NGOs as a document dealing with rights
that are ‘secondary’ to real human rights. (These arguments were supported
by other feminist commentators, such as Stamatopoulou, 1995). About one-
third of states that have ratified CEDAW have entered substantive reserva-
tions to various articles of the treaty, meaning that they have not undertaken
to implement it in full. This is more than for any other international human
rights treaty. Some of the reservations in effect nullify some of the most
important provisions of the treaty (Zwingel, forthcoming).
What was required, argued Bunch, was something more radical: a ‘re-
visioning’ of human rights from a feminist perspective, without waiting
for ‘permission from some authority to determine what is or is not a
human right issue’ (Bunch, 1990: 497). At the core of Bunch’s ‘re-visioning’
is a requirement to break down barriers ‘between public and private, state
and non-governmental responsibilities’ (ibid.: 497). Only thus, she argued,
would abuses that ‘arise specifically out of gender such as reproductive
rights, female sexual slavery, violence against women, and “family crimes”
like forced marriage, compulsory heterosexuality and female mutilation’
(ibid.) be addressed. Bunch thus explicitly recognizes the androcentric-
ism of human rights (much criticized by feminist legal scholars, such as
Charlesworth, 1995; and feminist social theorists, such as Peterson and
Parisi, 1998), but believes that this is a historically determined aspect that
can be changed. I would suggest that her arguments may also be seen as an
extension of, rather than a break with, the claim of the autonomous femi-
nist groups of the 1960s and 1970s that ‘the personal is political’. They
also represent a challenge to the status order of the time, whereby the
position of women, and their associations with the private sphere, took a
poor second place to abuses of rights (especially civil rights) in the public
sphere.
Bunch envisages ‘re-visioning’ of human rights as a possibility because she
sees human rights as not only ‘one of the few moral visions ascribed to
internationally’ (Bunch, 1990: 488) but also as a dynamic and open-ended
idea, its meaning expanding ‘as people reconceive of their needs and hopes’
‘Women’s rights are human rights’ 101
(ibid.: 487). This is an approach that fits Nash’s approving description of an
‘anti-foundationalist’ approach as comprising:
But theory is never enough: Bunch recognized that feminists could not
change the meaning of human rights simply by argument; they had to work
through the ‘due process’ of human rights institutions to secure a new con-
sensus among governments, UN human rights institutions and human rights
NGOs. This was possible because the repertoire of human rights instru-
ments extends beyond the drafting, signing and ratifying of treaties, to
include the ‘General Comments and Recommendations’ of treaty bodies
(like the CEDAW Committee), the ‘Concluding Observations’ of these
bodies on reports submitted by governments, the reports of ‘Special Rappor-
teurs’ on specific topics and the deliberations of the UN General Assembly,
and of UN world conferences on specific topics.
UN world conferences are particularly important because accredited
NGOs are allowed to attend as observers, and because the practice has
grown of facilitating parallel or satellite NGO meetings, beside the inter-
governmental meetings. The UN Conference on Human Rights in Vienna in
1993 provided the ideal opportunity to promote a ‘re-vision’; and Bunch
was one of the leaders of a well-organized international movement of hun-
dreds of thousands of women from around the world that ensured that the
Vienna Declaration initiated the construction of such a new consensus
(Friedman, 1995). It stated that ‘the full and equal enjoyment by women of
all human rights’ must be a priority for national governments and the UN
system. It led to the appointment of a UN Special Rapporteur on Violence
against Women and the adoption of a Declaration on the Elimination of
Violence against Women by the UN General Assembly. Nash (2002: 417)
comments that ‘The use of human rights to challenge structures and
incidences of violence against women across the world has been the most
successful way of extending human rights to women.’
Nash then examines the text of CEDAW and finds that there is within it
some scope for all of these visions; including her ‘deconstructive’ position,
‘Women’s rights are human rights’ 105
for which she finds some support in article 5 (a) (the most radical article in
CEDAW), which requires states ‘To modify the social and cultural patterns
of conduct of men and women, with a view to achieving the elimination of
prejudices and customary and all other practices which are based on the idea
of the inferiority or the superiority of either of the sexes or on stereotyped
roles for men and women.’
This enables her to conclude that it is possible to understand human
rights in a way that does not undermine the post-structuralist commitment
to ‘continual contestation, disruption and difference’ (Nash, 2002: 416).
However, she has to admit that women’s movements across the world are
more oriented to the ‘difference’ model of equality, and that a commitment
to ‘deconstructive’ equality is rare (Nash, 2002: 427, 428). Certainly the
arguments used by Bunch for understanding violence against women as a
human rights violation reflect the ‘difference’ vision of equality. She quotes
approvingly the statement by Lori Heise that ‘This is not random violence
. . . the risk factor is being female’ (Bunch, 1990: 490). Although ‘compulsory
heterosexuality’ is included in the list of abuses of women, the argument
is for the most part constructed on the basis that there are two sexes, and
the problem is to end the domination of the female sex by the male sex.
It is not surprising that the post-structuralist values of continual contest-
ation and change do not have a widespread appeal to women. For all but
the most well-off and most self-confident, disruption is frequently experi-
enced as insecurity, not an opening up of exciting new possibilities, and
asymmetrical globalization often intensifies the negative aspects of social
flux. A focus on broadening and equalizing the range of capabilities enjoyed
by women and men is probably a more appealing form of fluidity than an
emphasis on continual contestation and complete openness. This might
be called ‘transformative’ equality, and has to be underpinned by support-
ive economic, social and political structures that enable people to experi-
ment and take risks by guaranteeing their enjoyment of the economic,
social and cultural human rights (such health, education, an adequate
standard of living and full participation in the public life of the commu-
nity). ‘Transformative’ equality thus encompasses what Nancy Fraser calls
‘transformative redistribution combined with transformative recognition’
(Fraser, 1995: 91): ‘Transformative’ equality would address the concerns
expressed by Nash, that we need a concept of equality that allows a woman
or man to claim they are discriminated against when they experience dis-
advantage through choosing to do something that is more typically associ-
ated with the other sex; but it would also address the issue of the economic,
social and political structures they need in order to be able to make those
choices.
Fortunately, CEDAW provides a flexible framework in which a variety of
different visions of equality can be accommodated; and which can be
appropriated by diverse groups of women in ways that best serve their
specific contexts. In the fifteen years since Bunch dismissed it as ‘toothless’,
106 Status, norms and institutions
its implementation mechanisms have been strengthened, and more women
have begun to use it as a reference point in struggles for their human rights at
national level (Landsberg-Lewis, 1998; Zwingel, forthcoming). It allows for
positive action measures to offset deeply embedded structural discrimin-
ation, and sets a standard of substantive, not merely formal, equality. It
encompasses economic, social and cultural rights, as well as civil and
political rights.
Though Nash, like Turner, is concerned with the social philosophy of
human rights, she is reluctant to anchor their moral appeal in anything out-
side her own biography. She concludes that ‘[t]hus those of us for whom
universal human rights are actually compelling can only trace the arguments,
situations, and political histories through which we have come to this pos-
ition; we will be able to find no ultimate justification for our belief and feel-
ings’ (Nash, 2002: 425). In this she is influenced by Rorty (1993), who argues
that there is no rational, extra-community point from which judgement can
be exercised. We may agree with this latter argument without concluding
that, therefore, we can only fall back on our individual biographies. Turner
(1993) argues for an anchor point, not in some rational extra-community
space, but in shared bodily and emotional experiences that are constitutive
of what it is to be human – though we find that even this is gendered.
This emphasis on human rights as rooted in what human beings share,
and in mutual recognition of our neediness, is important given the
undoubted priority that human rights give to individual autonomy. Nash
insists on the importance of individual autonomy because it enables fixed
gender identities to be continually contested; but she is concerned about the
charge that this is ethnocentric (Nash, 2002: 422). She resolves this
through a discussion of Uma Narayan’s critique of conceptualization of
culture as a unified totality, which, Narayan argues, is particularly prob-
lematic in relation to insubordinate groups within a culture (Narayan,
1997). Nash concludes that in the end it is impossible to avoid the
responsibility of making judgements about what is progressive and puts
forward the ideal of ‘deconstructive equality’ as the benchmark to guide
these judgements.
Walby argues persuasively that human rights are not necessarily indi-
vidualistic, in the sense of being in opposition to collective action, providing
examples where individual rights are claimed through individuals presenting
themselves as part of a group and taking collective action (Walby, 2002:
548). Individual autonomy does not have to imply disconnection from
others, from families and communities. Instead it can imply a reworking of
connection, so that instead of the connection being one of dependency it can
be one of mutuality (cf. Chapter 1). Individual autonomy does not mean
there are no legitimate constraints on individual behaviour. All human rights
are qualified by the obligation to respect the human rights of others.
Nor are individual rights necessarily in opposition to collective rights.
Collective rights always have to be exercised by persons. The questions
‘Women’s rights are human rights’ 107
are: who those persons are; through what process they come to have the
power to exercise those rights; and how accountable they are to the other
members of the collectivity. Individuals can have rights to a say in how
collective rights are exercised, and can have rights to use collective property
in stipulated ways. Individual rights should be distinguished from privatized
rights, which consist of rights to exclude others from the enjoyment of
something, and are exercised in the market through buying and selling for
commercial gain.
In some parts of the world women are engaged in a complex reconstruction
of the relation between individual rights and collective rights. An impor-
tant example is Mexico, where indigenous women are intervening in the
restructuring of rights taking place at federal, state and local level. This
restructuring is taking place both through amendments to the federal and
state constitutions (to some extent influenced by aspects of the human rights
system, especially the ILO Convention on the Rights of Indigenous People)
and through the reshaping of so-called ‘traditional’ customary law (usos y
costumbres), influenced by the new usos y costumbres introduced in the
Zapatista Autonomous Municipalities. Indigenous women have taken up
issues of domestic violence, forced marriage, equal participation in a wide
range of political arenas, rights to housing, education, jobs, medical care
and land rights (Hernandez Castillo, 1997; Gutierrez and Palomo, 2001).
Some Mexican researchers have described this as ‘indigenous feminism’,
which attempts to protect indigenous people’s rights and women’s rights
all at the same time, and which sees both as connected sets of individual
and collective rights (Hernandez Castillo, 1997; Sierra, 2003). Indigenous
women have been organizing to stake claims to use land for themselves
through the notion of collective indigenous rights (Stephen, 2003). There
is a national indigenous women’s network dedicated to getting women’s
rights enforced through processes of enlarging the autonomy of indigenous
communities. These women do not take their culture as static and univalent;
instead they strategize to reshape it. They do not see a dichotomy between
individual and collective rights. Instead they aim for a new synthesis.
Conclusions
Feminists who base their campaigns on the claim that ‘women’s rights are
human rights’ are generally well aware of the limitations of ‘actually exist-
ing’ human rights. They seek to transform human rights, as a concept, and
as a practice, while at the same time drawing on the moral force of human
rights.
There are continuities, and doubling backs, as well as breaks, in the
trajectory from a politics of small-scale autonomous feminist groups, to a
politics of engaging with state and inter-state institutions. Perhaps the most
important continuity is an insistence on breaking down the distinction
between public and private spheres of life; though there is also some continu-
ity of transformatory, anti-systemic politics. The engagement with human
rights, as distinct from citizenship rights, stems from an understanding of
the limitations, as well as the possibilities, of state action to end gender
inequality.
The politics of women’s human rights is certainly facilitated by the more
benign aspects of globalization, especially the diffusion of new communica-
tions technology. But it is also necessitated by the asymmetrical aspects of
globalization, which leaves many women with no recourse to citizenship
rights, and in a position whereby their access to rights is mediated by men.
Since human rights do not have a final and completely fixed meaning, they
can be understood in ways that are consistent with a post-structural femi-
nism committed to continual contestation and disruption, provided that the
latter also recognizes the importance of a commitment to equality. But in
the context of globalization, many women experience contestation and dis-
ruption as intensified insecurity, not expanded possibility. In this context, it
is important that human rights, as well as having a capacity for openness to
new meanings, are nevertheless grounded in an appreciation of the bodily
and moral frailty of human beings; and the importance of stabilizing the
110 Status, norms and institutions
right of all individual human beings to claim assistance from others, in a
mutually constituted and egalitarian system of interconnectedness.
Note
An earlier version of this chapter was presented at the Manchester Centre for Political
Theory, University of Manchester, at a conference in honour of Ursula Vogel, March
2005. Thanks are due to those present for helpful comments. Thanks are due to Kate
Nash and Sylvia Walby for alerting me to their innovatory contributions to the
sociology of rights; and to Lydia Morris for her editorial guidance.
6 Human rights, anti-racism
and EU advocacy coalitions
Carlo Ruzza
Efforts to clarify the mechanisms that further the diffusion and institutional-
ization of human rights have frequently concentrated on the role of norms in
the international arena. In connection to this issue, analysts have examined
how human rights have emerged as new transnational norms with a binding
impact on domestic regimes. However, the ways in which these norms
emerge, are connected to specific policies, and come to play a role, are
underspecified, as is the analysis of mechanisms operating in different types
of international arenas. This chapter examines the connection between the
concept of human rights as a global construct and anti-discrimination
policy, and more specifically the emergence and institutionalization of
anti-racist policy at the EU level. In this context, it elucidates some of
the mechanisms that favour the emergence and diffusion of norms in a
supranational setting: the EU.
The relevance of the EU as an expanding source of legislation in a growing
number of countries and policy areas is unquestioned, and it is therefore an
important setting in which to examine processes of norm diffusion. In add-
ition, as a setting that is broader than nation states but still connected to
them in clear and observable ways, the EU constitutes a good test case of
several types of interaction that take place between international and
domestic arenas. Examining specific forms of interaction between domestic
and international contexts also helps in clarifying the mechanisms that con-
nect the different levels of governance. Within the EU, anti-racist policy is a
relatively new policy area that is often connected to human rights.
In recent years, racism has again emerged as an important issue in the
political debate throughout Europe, raising a range of concerns and inter-
pretations. A set of new policy instruments has emerged. In particular, the
new article 13 of the Amsterdam Treaty legitimating EU-level action to
combat various forms of discrimination, including racial discrimination,
reflected the growing importance that this subject has acquired. Following
the approval of article 13, several related initiatives have also emerged in
recent years and were intentionally connected in legislative texts to the issue
of human rights. If anti-racism is defined in terms of human rights and
therefore constitutes an articulation of broad international norms, the
112 Status, norms and institutions
approval of anti-racist legislation then constitutes a good test case of
the mechanisms that connect broad principles and concrete policy decisions.
Studying the emergence and diffusion of transnational norms offers a
view of the sociological mechanisms that translate them into concrete and
enforceable operating standards.
In this chapter, I explore the operating modalities of the advocacy coali-
tion that has put anti-racism on the agenda, and also the reasons for both its
successes and its weaknesses. I argue that transforming a shared norm such
as the condemnation of racism into actual policy involves mediating among
contrasting policy frames, defining issues in such a way that a variety of
actors with contrasting interests and views can converge and focus their
efforts on a process of policy change. I examine the limitations to the
agenda-setting efforts of a complex coalition of Brussels-based activists and
bureaucrats, which has attempted to achieve a stronger policy response. I
explore its modes of operation and likely prospects, as well as examining
their promotional role and their responses to the initiatives already approved.
This examination allows the emerging policy process of anti-racism that
article 13 and two subsequent directives have jump-started to be put into
sociological context.
At the EU level anti-racism is characterised by a long history of declar-
ations of principle in which its character as a transnational norm and
definition as a human right has been enthusiastically supported and reiterated
by a range of political actors – notably in the European Parliament. How-
ever, concrete policy initiatives in this area were absent for at least twenty
years (Ford, 1992). This changed with the proposal and then the approval of
article 13, which emerged as the outcome of pressure exerted by a composite
advocacy coalition. It included a variety of institutional actors and networks
of non-governmental organizations (NGOs). Several public interest lobbies
and social movement organizations address the EU institutional context and
had a prominent role in advocacy activities in anti-racism and related
areas. They include organizations concerned with issues of anti-racism,
women’s issues and disability rights and movement-related groups, where a
range of political parties, NGOs, movements, organizations and churches
collaborate in representing the elderly, defending civil liberties, acting against
homelessness, or poverty, or on behalf of refugees, migrants and asylum
seekers. The role and number of these transnational organizations has grown
at the EU level, paralleling a growth of similar organizations in other
international arenas (Keck and Sikkink, 1998: 10).
While the support of non-state actors was important in representing
issues of human rights and the value of anti-racism in institutional con-
texts, without the support of EU-level institutional actors they would
not have been able to achieve policy change. It is therefore important to
differentiate between two processes. One is the importation of new ideas
in a policy environment, which in this case, and in other international con-
texts, is prominently affected by social movements and other conscience
Human rights, anti-racism and EU advocacy coalitions 113
constituencies. A second one is the specific sociological dynamics that help
to translate principles into policy proposals. The first kind of process
presupposes the formation of a sufficiently coherent discursive frame. The
second kind relates to the variables that facilitate the seizing of political
opportunities by an advocacy coalition, which also involves acquiring
needed resources, mediating among conflicting interests, action repertoires
and operating procedures. The first type relates to cultural dynamics that are
influenced by interactions between movements and the media and take place
in an increasingly global arena. The second refers to policy events that, even
when they take place in international settings, are the outcomes of complex
processes of intermediation taking place within specific policy communities.
As the introduction to this volume points out, the second type of process
includes a variety of moderating influences on the impact of globalised con-
ceptions of human rights emerging at the global level, such as considerations
of national interest, considerations of political expediency of specific actors,
etc. The relation between the two is therefore complex and has often been
seen as problematic. I review these two processes separately.
The Commission
The Commission has been concerned with racism for a long time. This is to
be expected, as the Commission has a tradition of identifying under-
thematised policy areas in which a European dimension can appear useful
and relevant. As Majone (1996) points out, regulatory decisions are often
related to societal values, hence policy-makers have a vested interest in the
cultural milieu. It is therefore to be expected that this interest grew when the
issue became socially more relevant. This is particularly the case for the top
122 Status, norms and institutions
tiers of the Commission, which typically act in a political function. The need
for legitimacy is, however, as in the case of Parliament, not the only reason
for supporting anti-racism. There are also broader generational and ideo-
logical factors at play behind the close connection between EU institutions
and NGOs. One activist said: ‘Activists very often have links that go back to
the sixties and the seventies with the people in government. I was able to tell
a Commissioner that he was a founder member of one of our organizations.
Especially now that there is a social democratic majority in the EU, many
ministers were supporters of NGOs.’ In addition to these general reasons for
involvement there are also specific ones that pertain to the bureaucratic
function of operative units in the area.
The main bureaucratic referent for anti-racism is a unit of Directorate-
General (DG) Social Affairs, which as a whole deals with the free movement
of workers – essentially a legal activity (revision of free movement legisla-
tion, action on complaints of infringement against member states, etc.). The
unit also deals with the social integration of immigrants, employment pro-
grammes of recognised refugees and action against racism. So the latter is
only one of the areas of concern. Activists described the last head of unit as
very committed – a ‘super-converted’ – and valued her political sense, her
ability to be realistic and effective in her demands, and achieve results.
The unit was created in 1958. It deals with matters, such as free move-
ment of labour, already included in the Treaty of Rome. Integration of
immigrants and refugees came later. Anti-racist policy was added in 1986.
The relevance of anti-racism work varies according to the tasks at hand,
ranging from a handful of people working in the sector to over twenty in
periods of special initiatives such as during the 1997 European Year against
Racism. Unfortunately, as this head of unit pointed out, mobility is very high
in DG Social Affairs and is encouraged by the hierarchy, but she points out
that racism is a very special field; if a position is posted, only personally
committed people tend to apply. There are therefore in operation dynamics
of selection that ensure continued bureaucratic commitment.
The anti-racist work done by units other than DG Social Affairs is not
dissimilar in being fairly activist in orientation. The ideological orientation
is, as with DG Social Affairs, sustained by a belief in the promotion of
Europe, not only for providing legitimacy to EU bodies, but for broader
reasons as well. Some activists say that there is in the Commission a funda-
mental belief that the European model has been an effective social model for
many years. It has provided security from wars and affluence, and there is a
desire to promote it as a philosophy not just within the EU but outside as
well. Hence voluntary organisations such as youth organisations and their
activists’ concerns are funded in places as distant as Georgia or the Maghreb
area. The Commission needs to know about society, and voluntary organ-
isations can provide space for reciprocal knowledge, ranging from activists
and volunteers brought to Brussels for consultations and represented in
Brussels, to EYF (European Youth Forum) staging Youth in Parliament
Human rights, anti-racism and EU advocacy coalitions 123
events (where 500 young people are brought to Brussels for a two- to
three-day debate on their living conditions, with the participation of EU
bodies’ representatives).
The division between an assimilationist and a multiculturalist approach
that characterises European anti-racism finds an echo in Brussels. This con-
tradiction hinders the anti-racist community’s progress towards identifying
shared goals, such as agreement on how best to spend money, where to
concentrate efforts and which groups to support. However, according to
some activists, the dominant institutional ethos is an assimilationist one,
which seems to emerge in interviews with civil servants. For instance, a
civil servant stressed that all steps should be taken actively to encourage
migrants’ access to ‘majority’ culture, but awareness of migrants’ cultural
diversity was never expressly mentioned. Much emphasis is placed on, and
funds are spent promoting, ‘minority’ integration. Policy provisions to
promote minority cultures and safeguard religious rights are more limited.
The two approaches are not easily combined, as they imply different allo-
cation of resources, but their contrast is even more of a problem for the unity
of the movement at large. From their small units in Brussels, institutional
actors can espouse a policy of channelling as much in the way of resources as
possible to a wide variety of organisations, which might have contrasting
approaches. At the same time, in terms of institutional discourse, regulators
often prefer to frame anti-racism in terms that are compatible with the
broader ethos of the European project. This is based on a neo-liberal ethos
within which anti-racism is better conceptualised not as an issue of distribut-
ing resources to disadvantaged groups in general or in terms of legislating
in order to combat neo-Nazi attacks against migrants. Instead, it will
more typically be seen as an issue of right of access to the markets that the
EU has been built to enhance and monitor – markets of goods, labour and
services. In this perspective racism mainly limits individuals as consumers
and workers.
Anti-racism is in fact more congruent with the broader EU ethos when
defined with reference to the role of the individual in the labour markets,
and in social institutions. In this sense, anti-racism is typically seen in terms
of a threat to rights. A brief excerpt from a Commission website encapsu-
lates the way in which anti-racism and more generally the struggle against
discrimination is conceptualised in Brussels:
Inter-organisational relations
This chapter has so far identified a set of personal and institutional concerns
of bureaucratic, political and civil society actors and argued that they are all
served by emerging conceptions of anti-racism and its connection to funda-
mental rights. The interconnection and compatibility between the discourse
of different institutional environments needs, however, to be qualified.
One has to address the issue of the extent of interconnection between
different actors.
It is not generally denied that there is a strict connection between dif-
ferent organisational environments. Their strict involvement in EU decision-
making is not accidental. As Peters (1992) has pointed out, the EU has
traditionally used strategies of bureaucratisation and fragmentation of nego-
tiations in order to diffuse conflicts and ‘technicise’ them. This creates an
integrated inter-organisational environment in which cohesion is valued and
is rooted in constant negotiations and the necessity to agree in the absence of
strong majoritarian decision-making rules. Support to principled positions
is one of the cohesion-enhancing mechanisms. Principles such as anti-
racism, but also environmental sustainability or gender rights, are frequently
recruited to its services.
These principles come to be reiterated in informal consultations and
sometimes uneasily conjugated with the neo-liberal values of competitive-
ness, efficiency and technical appropriateness, and have contributed to
determining a cohesive decision-making structure. Thus the informal pro-
cess of coordination among different political and non-political actors takes
place from the beginning of the decision-making process, a style of work
that has characterised the EU from its inception and was explicitly intended
by the Commission. In brief, we can identify a few interacting organisa-
tional environments that are unified by their participation in a structured
competition where compromise is necessary and in which facilitating factors
are bureaucratic procedures, some shared goals and some taken-for-granted
norms.
Human rights, anti-racism and EU advocacy coalitions 125
Despite their similarity, the different environments also operate according
to distinctive operating procedures, which, for instance, sociological neo-
institutionalists have usefully reduced to ideal types (Powell and DiMaggio,
1991). They are bureaucratic environments such as the Commission, polit-
ical environments such as the Parliament, the sector of business lobbying
and public pressure groups and social movements. In bureaucratic environ-
ments, transnational norms such as anti-racism are conceived as taken-
for-granted. They refer to procedures that need to be followed in a relatively
automatic fashion. In activist environments they are the subject of norma-
tive commitment and refer to moralised behaviours. In lobbying and some
organised civil society environments anti-racism indicates areas where insti-
tutional compliance is required to ensure resources or access, and compli-
ance emerges in a mimetic fashion. None the less, despite differences,
altogether the resulting organisational environment is generally integrated
and supportive of anti-racism, even if individual actors might not identify
with it. At the EU level, social movements operate in the absence of the
relatively homogeneous structures of the nation state and therefore often
face a less oppositional and concerted institutional reaction. The historical
form of the social movement that has emerged as a political challenger to the
state tends to take a different role in the fragmented EU environment (Marks
and McAdam, 1996).
These considerations point to the fact that the relationships among the
different organisational environments involved in EU decision-making are
not generally based on controversial stances. Instead, the inspiring principle
is a willingness to compromise in order to accommodate different interests.
Clearly, for negotiation to reach a compromise, interaction is often difficult
and protracted and occasionally engenders factious disputes. But in these
exchanges a cohesive value orientation is formed, where distinctive values,
information-processing mechanisms and goals emerge and bind a com-
munity of specialists. In the anti-racism field, technical competence might be
somewhat less important than in other fields, but is often supplemented by
the stronger value commitment that all the interviews have documented.
This institutional commitment, then, also has a personal dimension. For
instance, an activist pointed out: ‘The institutions with a mandate on racism
collaborate closely. In particular, the relevant sections of the Commission,
particularly DG Social Affairs and the European Parliament, particularly the
Committee on Civil Liberties, collaborate closely. The head of the relevant
unit and some staff go to most of the meetings of this committee, and there
are frequent personal contacts.’ Relations with movement representatives
and NGOs are also frequent, and are emphasised within key legal docu-
ments such as the first action plan against racism. The importance of
dialogue with institutions is also emphasised by the anti-racist movement, as
it emerges in in-depth interviews with all actors. They essentially share views
on priorities, and just as it is for anti-racism, this is also the case for other
areas of concern for social movements (Ruzza, 2006).
126 Status, norms and institutions
A content analysis of policy documents and presentation websites shows
that EU institutions and the anti-racist coalition view the main priorities
similarly, as: the necessity to concentrate on issues such as improving the
implementation of anti-racist legislation in member states, enhancing par-
ticipation, particularly participation of actors from civil society, emphasis-
ing the importance of human rights and related policy principles, and
improving knowledge in the field.
This said, important differences also exist between EU institutions and
anti-racist movements, which, however, could indicate that anti-racism as a
policy effort is not an area captured by vested interests, and in normative
terms does not simply reiterate institutional views – organised civil society
can play an independent role (Ruzza, 2006). In differing from movement
texts, EU texts emphasise the connection between anti-racism and their
institutionalised policy concerns. They emphasise the necessity to main-
stream anti-racism in all the EU policy areas and the European dimension of
the issue, and put less emphasis than anti-racist documents on the role of
member states.
The differences between anti-racist groups and EU institutions is none the
less mainly a difference of emphasis. The existence of a fairly integrated and
proactive anti-racist coalition that crosses different institutional environ-
ments is evident. Thus, even when conceiving the EU as a complex and
interconnected organisational environment, we can link specific inter-
organisational dynamics and general principles of human rights. Anti-racism
allows different kinds of actors to interact through a common language. It
allows the EU machinery as a whole to project an external image of concern
for topical issues that go beyond the often vilified concern for economic
prosperity. Article 13 and the subsequent legislation connect the Union to
shared social values.
These considerations make activists accepting of EU involvement but
also somewhat cynical. Their attitude varies from disenchanted scepticism
to belief in the personal commitment of institutional actors. Noting the
reiteration in EU bodies of anti-racist concerns, one activist said: ‘Regulation
of racism is a matter of fashion. Everybody says they are concerned about
racism. You had the Council of Europe’s campaign, “All different all equal”,
then the following year was the European Year against Racism. Now you
hear much more about it on television and the radio. In the newspapers
it has become a fashion. You have to be anti-racist. It is something in
the wind.’
Conclusions
In this chapter, the argument has been put forward that the institutionalisa-
tion of human rights principles depends on the extent to which emerging
global ideas about connected key aspects of social organisation, such as the
theme of ethnic discrimination and the fight against racism, are interpreted
Human rights, anti-racism and EU advocacy coalitions 127
through the narrative of the extension of rights and then redefined to serve
political purposes and justify the involvement of different classes of actors,
including social movements and organised civil society. Successful anti-
racism policy depends on several variables – one is the political legitimacy
that transnational NGOs are able to acquire, which is in turn related to their
ability to appear politically responsible defenders of universally supported
ideas and therefore able to allay the fears that their presence constitutes a
threat to the sovereignty of nation states (Hudson, 2001). This objective has
yet to be reached, and recently increasing preoccupations with security
have hindered EU-level anti-racism. None the less, with the involvement of
anti-racism movements in deliberative forums and the approval of new legis-
lation, important steps have been taken in this direction. This chapter exam-
ines the various reasons for this partial success, pointing in particular to the
need for political legitimacy of the supranational arena.
At the EU level, supporting legitimate universal principles contributes
to the legitimacy of the overall European project. In addition, connecting
anti-racism to neo-liberal values by relating specific legislation to the detri-
mental impact racism has on a well-functioning labour market improves
the ‘fit’ (Keck and Sikkink, 1998: 3) between universal principles and
the EU principles that characterise the process of European construction.
This further contributes to facilitating the mainstreaming of anti-racism in
European-level policies. When successful, human rights related ideas turn
into taken-for-granted assumptions whose precise nature and actualisation
may remain controversial and subject to advocacy pressure, but that are no
longer simply a matter of individual normative choice.
Participation in anti-racism policy is therefore fruitful at least in terms
of promoting a democratisation of the EU in terms of the expansion of
issue areas and range of actors involved (Dryzek, 1996: 5–6), but there
are costs associated to it. These relate to a forced definition of priorities
that, while enhancing the ‘fit’ with EU values and thus ensuring the
involvement of institutional actors, to an extent constrains the movements’
choices and distorts their objectives. As the debate on the underclass has
shown, there has been a growth of policies stressing social obligations above
social rights (see Chapter 4), and it is in this context that anti-racism finds
a role as an enabling factor in access to labour markets and connected
spheres.
However, on balance participation has proven useful, as objectives are
still unclear even within the movement, while resources are generally needed
for several activities on which all the movements’ viewpoints could con-
verge. In this respect, as theorists of deliberative democracy argue, deliber-
ation has a positive aggregative function for those engaged in it. In this
sense, the movement’s thematic fragmentation can be helped through its
EU-induced necessity to form EU-wide representative networks and to
engage in deliberative activities. Finally, another reason for valuing anti-
racism advocacy is that due to the impact of globalisation and the hollowing
128 Status, norms and institutions
out of the state, control over a growing range of issues has moved to the
international arena and is increasingly associated with civil society (Dryzek,
2000: 5). For this reason, it is important for anti-racism to be represented by
movements and to face directly other private and public interests.
Notes
1 For a discussion of different approaches within neo-institutionalism, see Peters
(2000).
2 For a review of the international relations literature on the role of global ideas and
more generally ‘knowledge approaches’, see Hasenclever et al. (1997).
3 There is a debate in the literature on the distinction between social movements
and public pressure lobbies. Some authors believe they should be differentiated,
others do not. Empirically, and as I will show, in the anti-racist field they are often
connected. With reference to the EU-level anti-racist movement, the distinction
is not useful and I will refer to mixed formations as ‘movement advocacy coali-
tions’ to indicate both their mixed character and the simultaneous engagement in
advocacy activities and protest events.
4 The Racial Equality Directive shields against discrimination in employment and
training, education, social security, health care, housing and other services, mem-
bership and involvement in organisations of workers and employers. The
Employment Equality Directive focuses on equal treatment in employment and
training irrespective of religion, disability, age or sexual orientation in employ-
ment, training and membership and involvement in organisations of workers and
employers. It also requires employers to make reasonable accommodation to
enable qualified disabled people to participate in training or paid labour.
5 Civil servants in considering all policies are obliged to take into account what has
been called ‘the European value added’; that is, they have to consider whether
policies have a positive impact in furthering the process of European integration.
6 http://europa.eu.int/comm/employment_social/fundamental_rights/index_en.htm
Part III
Meaning, interpretation
and rights
The notion of autonomy guides one to ask about the implications of these
two moments for the agent’s freedom. Both the normative conception of
autonomy and the ontological conception of duality can thus act as guiding
concepts for empirical research. It is ultimately an empirical question
whether or not an agent has the internal ability to revise their ends, can gain
sufficient critical distance5 from their conditions of socialisation, habit and
routine to be able to ‘question, re-examine, and revise (their) beliefs about
value’ (Kymlicka, 1989: 18). It is also an empirical question as to whether a
given agent believes there are likely to be external social costs and sanctions
associated with the exercise of autonomy, whether they are correct in their
beliefs and whether the costs would be too great for that individual to coun-
tenance.6 These are all empirical questions to which the researcher will be
guided by the concepts.
The role of social theory need not be restricted, however, to the process of
situating a particular rights issue within its phenomenological, social and
historical context. Proponents of some variants of social theory, bordering
140 Meaning, interpretation and rights
on political and moral philosophy but without their concern for systematic
and deductive reasoning, have spent much time encouraging readers to
think deeply about what it means for human beings to flourish and to avoid
suffering. This strand of ethical social theory has an affinity with the
phenomenological emphasis of structuration theory and with the respect for
the individual that, on my reading, motivates it. In fact, it is perhaps best
characterised as ‘socio-moral phenomenology’ and it is evident in a number
of otherwise disparate writers. It is there: in Richard Rorty’s plea for a
‘sentimental education’, which improves our ability to appreciate the simi-
larities between ourselves and peoples otherwise very unlike us, ‘such little,
superficial, similarities as cherishing our parents and our children’ (Rorty,
1993: 129), as well as our similarities with respect to pain and humiliation,
which novels and ethnographies can move us to understand (Rorty, 1989:
192); in Martha Nussbaum’s concern for us to expand our ‘recognition
and concern’ for others, to use narrative art to ‘see the lives of others with
more than a casual tourist’s interest’ (Nussbaum, 1997: 88); in Zygmunt
Bauman’s Levinasian invocation of ‘being-for the Other’, in which an
emotional engagement with the Other that comes before any thought about
what should or shouldn’t be done ‘casts her/him into the universe of under-
determination, questioning and openness’ (Bauman, 1995: 62). The power
of this kind of theory lies in its recognition of the profound levels of engage-
ment that can be secured by the force of narrative, emotion and sympathetic
identification. The danger of socio-moral phenomenology on its own is that
while its engagement focuses on the concrete, is grounded in real lives,
eschewing what it rightly or wrongly sees as the abstract rationalism of
much political and moral philosophy, the characters who people its narra-
tives are insufficiently anchored in their social circumstances, including the
normative aspects of those circumstances. By tracing the connections
between an agent’s narratives and phenomenology, on the one hand, and
her external social structures and networks on the other, structuration the-
ory can provide much of that anchoring. And by adding to structuration’s
emphasis on the normative, sanctioning, content of the social context a
sustained analysis of the moral legitimacy, or otherwise, of those norms-
within-context then political philosophy can potentially provide a powerful
commentary on that very context and the power relations that sustain it.
a man must not be held morally inferior on the basis of some physical,
racial or other characteristic he cannot help having. Thus a man whose
moral judgements about Jews, or Negroes, or Southerners, or women,
or effeminate men are based on his belief that any member of these
classes automatically deserves less respect, without any regard to
anything else he has done, is said to be prejudiced against that group.
(Dworkin, 1978: 249–50)
this would interfere with the right of individuals to do what they wish
with their rightfully acquired property. Robert Nozick even goes so far
as to argue that such taxation is the moral equivalent of granting prop-
erty rights in another person and ‘is on a par with forced labour’, and
hence an infringement of our most fundamental civil rights.
(Bellamy, 1999: 168; citing Nozick, 1974)
Even among those who advocate a positive conception of rights there may
well be a clash between those who wish to spend scarce resources on educa-
tion and those who wish to spend them on health care (Bellamy, 1999: 169;
also see O’Neill, 2002: 23–39). Behind all these disagreements lie variegated
views on the good life, on the optimum conditions required for human
beings to flourish. Thus, even within a liberal democratic culture one very
quickly comes up against the limits of agreement on basic rights.
There is the need here for close and detailed argument and for the ability
to examine the extent to which each side’s abstract moral arguments have
relevance and currency within the socially situated phenomenological
understanding of in situ social actors. There is the need for a kind of socio-
logically informed phronesis in which moral judgements are made on the
146 Meaning, interpretation and rights
basis of a close engagement with, and understanding of, unfolding contexts
of action.9 There is also, ultimately, the need to be able to articulate the
grounds of whatever differences remain.
Parekh thus believes not only that the interests of others in the community
beside the individual should be taken into account in thinking through issues
of self-harm, and that the avoidance of fear and suffering should not be
weighed lightly against the goods of autonomy, but also that there are many
factors inhabiting an Indian widow’s social context that would compromise
the translation of her formal autonomy into a meaningful substantive free-
dom of choice. Parekh’s account stands out as a work of political philosophy
that is quite remarkably context-sensitive. Notwithstanding this, however,
many of the issues he raises would still be susceptible to a good deal more
conceptually informed empirical analysis than he provides with respect to
particular individuals, such as Roop Kanwar and her significant others, and
148 Meaning, interpretation and rights
their networked circumstances of action. Such analysis could, for example,
explore more deeply the realities and intensities of the enduring values and
dispositions of the habitus of relevant agents, and of their perceived context
of choice. This would provide a potentially much richer picture of the
character and quality of autonomy in particular circumstances.
Conclusion
I will conclude briefly. I have set out the case for combining social theory
and political philosophy in the analysis of rights. I have advocated a case
study approach in the first instance, one that is modest, realistic and prag-
matic (cf. Stones, 1996: 36–8, 64–83) in drawing on a limited number of
elements from the vast literatures of social theory and political philosophy
to analyse the chosen case. The cases I have discussed here have explicitly
thematised some of the areas in which adopting the joint conceptual frame
of political philosophy and social theory is essential if key questions are to be
addressed. I believe it would be an entirely positive development if academ-
ics and doctoral researchers in sociology and related disciplines were able to
begin to employ concepts from political and moral philosophy alongside
those from social theory as their guides to research. Likewise, it would be an
exciting and potentially fruitful development if political philosophers began
to ask more questions about how social theory and sociological research
could ground and deepen their own analyses.
Notes
1 For an account of epistemological and methodological issues that provides more
background to these points, see Stones (2005: 120–7).
2 The notion of duality was formulated by Giddens in outlining his version of
structuration theory. See, for example, Giddens (1984) and Cohen (1989). In
Stones (2005), I have attempted to draw together insights from the critiques,
counter-critiques and empirical uses of structuration theory by many authors to
defend what is invaluable in the concept, while acknowledging the need to refine
and develop it.
3 It should be said, however, that the notion of autonomy is always thought within
the more general conception of liberalism and is not treated as an independent
and free-floating concept. If it was treated in the latter way, then one would
clearly be committing the same fallacy committed by a crude checklist version of
rights.
4 On communitarianism, see Sandel (1982) and Bell (1993). On multiculturalism,
see Gutmann (1992) and Parekh (2000). On virtue ethics, see MacIntyre (1981),
Rights, social theory and political philosophy 151
Crisp and Slote (1997) and Flanagan and Jupp (2001). Stout (1990) is an
interesting example of an argument for the compatibility of virtue ethics and
rights. Mulhall and Swift (1992) and Farrelly (2004) are excellent introductory
overviews to the field of contemporary political philosophy.
5 Nicos Mouzelis has carefully and usefully established the need for structuration
theory to conceptualise differences in the degree to which agents achieve some
critical distance from their perception of the social conditions of action. He
establishes the need for a continuum of possibilities ranging from the entirely
taken for granted to the critically reflective (Mouzelis, 1991: 28; 2000: 748–9).
6 See Stones (2005: 109–15) on the concept of irresistible social forces that
can severely limit the range of meaningful choices available to a supposedly
autonomous individual.
7 Durkheim (1984) argued that traditional societies are characterised by this kind
of solidarity in which few divisions of labour mean that individuals and institu-
tions are relatively undifferentiated and values, symbols and rituals are common
to the group, clan or tribe. This is in sharp contrast to the individualism of
modern societies.
8 This kind of claim always raises, of course, the question of who is designated by
‘you and I’ or ‘we’, and any claim that a particular group shares a set of moral
values can in principle be empirically tested, and the results will naturally vary
between societal groups and cultures.
9 Structuration theory, with its ability to think systematically about the com-
ponents of both the conjuncturally specific terrain of action and the agent’s
enduring dispositions and values, provides the tools with which to anchor phro-
nesis to firmer moorings than the intuitions of an agent’s judgement with which
it is usually associated. For an analysis of the notion of phronesis as employed by
both Aristotle and Gadamer, see Bernstein (1986: 99–104). See also Miller
(1991: 225–36).
10 Issues of age of consent and responsibility towards children raise a number of
additional complicated factors (see Montgomery, 2001: 80–101). For the sake of
clarity in the current argument I therefore just focus on young women above the
age of consent. Moreover, for the sake of this argument I focus on young women,
although sex workers do of course also include older women, boys, men and
transsexuals.
11 The notion of a ‘decision’ itself is in fact even more complicated than I am
suggesting here. In her study, Aoyama (2005: 124–7) carefully disaggregates and
problematises the notion.
12 See note 6 above.
13 Lucinda Joy Peach (2001: 167) has questioned whether most women in Buddhist
cultures have any understanding of themselves as individuals entitled to rights:
‘Thai and Burmese Buddhist women in particular are socialized to be relationally
and family oriented selves rather than autonomous, independent individuals.’
She argues persuasively for a feminist pragmatist perspective on human rights
that pays respect to the role of culture and religion in local cultures, and accepts
that a legal rights strategy is unlikely to be effective in empowering women who
lack ‘rights consciousness’ (ibid.: 184). On the other hand, fine-grained socio-
logical analyses of Thai women in situ, of the kind carried out by Whittaker
(2000) and Aoyama (2005), radically call into question Peach’s undifferentiated
characterisation of them as lacking an understanding of themselves as autono-
mous, independent individuals, as lacking ‘some sense of themselves as agents of
their own lives’ (Peach, 2001: 167, 184).
14 This is important even though, as we have seen in Parekh’s discussion of sati,
there are many reasons why the issue of autonomy is not necessarily the last
word on this matter.
8 Rights work
Constructing lesbian, gay
and sexual rights in late
modern times
Ken Plummer
This is schematic and I do not have space to develop all of this below.
Instead, I highlight only a few central issues.
154 Meaning, interpretation and rights
Constructing human rights
A starting concern must lie with those who see human rights as inalienable,
given, universal. They were heralded by natural law theories that somehow
see such rights as given and inhering naturally in the world. Most religions
subscribe to this view – rights (and obligations) may be seen to have been
inscribed in Hammurabi’s Code, the Bible, the Qur’an, the Vedas. But
for the interactionist, such texts do not have inherent meaning. This is
clearly witnessed by the debates, schisms, conflicts and different interpret-
ations such authoritative texts have generated throughout history. By con-
trast, others see rights as constructed: they are built by human beings.
Constructionist positions look at the struggles generated around human
rights, aware that meanings change over time and across different groups –
that such meanings are contested. Constructionists look at the ways in
which some people and groups (often social movements) are claims makers
and do what might be called ‘human rights work’. They clarify laws, write
justifications, generate reports and conferences, network in cyberspace, tell
stories and generally provide rhetorics for human rights. They provide evi-
dence and arguments, identify key types of people (homosexuals, transgen-
dered and people with AIDS), usually against a moral backdrop that helps to
identify ‘trouble’. Different claims makers and different moral backgrounds
would lead probably to a different sense of just what these rights should be.
So while gay activists champion ‘gay rights’, others would claim this
infringes their rights. Likewise, such claims depend upon audiences who will
hear and there is inevitable competition(s) between different claims to rights.
The world of sexual rights almost inevitably speaks to moral codes:
religious, organizational and humanitarian (see Plummer, 1995; Best, 2001;
Loseke, 2003, for accounts of the constructionist view in general).
1 Imagining ‘rights’.
2 Articulating/vocalizing: announcing ‘rights’.
3 Inventing identities: becoming storytellers about ‘rights’.
4 Creating social worlds of ‘rights’.
5 Creating a culture of ‘public rights’.
Sociologists ask ‘how the dimensions are carved out, how the number of
people drawn into concern about these discussions is increased, how a
common pool of knowledge begins to develop for the arena participants,
and how all these sub- processes increase the visibility of the problem’
(Wiener, 1981: 14). Rights have long histories stretching back to ancient
civilizations and religions, even though the language of rights – ‘rights talk’ –
only really starts to come into its own with the Enlightenment.
Stretching back into the nineteenth century, through pressure group activ-
ity and social movement building in a number of countries across the world,
‘claims’ were slowly made for the right to different kinds of sexual orienta-
tions and sexual activities. This chapter examines some of the claims made,
some of the stories told and some of the institutions built in order to create
new identities, make new laws and eventually establish codes of rights. It
also looks at the ways in which some lesbians and gays lay counter-claims
(radically rejecting the established, liberal, position), and seek counter-
publics, while other groups make more conservative claims to suggest that
gay and lesbians should not have rights. Rights models remain in contest-
ation. We shall also see how ‘sexual citizenship’ or ‘intimate citizenship’
156 Meaning, interpretation and rights
becomes a major discussion of the 1990s and comes to be applied to a wider
range of sexualities (such as transgender groups and sadomasochists).
Again, at the same time, the notion of ‘gay rights’ is heavily contested in
many countries across the world and is challenged at the United Nations and
in many religious organisations. This chapter outlines this contestation and
the agenda for the future, and argues that ‘rights’, once gained, are never
permanently settled, and can always be lost again.
The struggle for gay rights has assumed different emphases such that what
Rights work 157
was once hardly imaginable as ‘on the agenda’ has now become reality.
Thus, in its earliest days, the gay rights movement had as its focus the
ultimate decriminalization of homosexual acts – and perhaps the acceptance
(or tolerance) of homosexuality (even if as an illness). These were the ultim-
ate goals of the earliest gay movements. But by the times of Gay Liberation
Front (GLF), the claims made were much more strident. There was the claim
to legal equality; there was the claim to be accepted on equal grounds with
heterosexuals; there was the claim to equal opportunities in school and
work; there was the claim to be free from homophobic attack; there was the
claim to behave as heterosexuals might in the street – holding hands, even
kissing (Gay Is Good, pamphlet, 1970). The emphasis shifted from the
decriminalization of specific sexual acts to a wider acceptance of equal rights
for gays and lesbians. But as the movement gathered momentum, so the
claims became ever more bold and inclusive.
By the mid-1980s, claims were increasingly made that gays and lesbians
should have equal rights to what came to be known as ‘families of choice’
(Weston, 1991). A dual emphasis – on the rights to marriage and the rights
to raise children – became more and more prominent.4 Indeed, in a number
of countries where equal rights had been obtained in a number of areas (the
laws had been changed, equal opportunities charters had been introduced,
governments had incorporated the thinking of many gays and lesbians into
governmental policies), it was the only issue that seriously discriminated
homosexuality from heterosexuality. And hence in December 1988, the first
registered partnership took place in Denmark, followed in quick succession
by a number of Scandinavian countries (Sweden, Norway, Iceland, Finland)
and then others in Europe, the Netherlands being the first country to legis-
late for gay and lesbian marriages. Most countries within the European
Union have legislated for partnerships. And so have many other countries
across the world: from South Africa (also the first country to enshrine
gay rights in its charter), Brazil (a country that also tried to make this a
universal issue through the United Nations) and Mexico (though not – as is
common – without its setbacks). In the United States, the situation is much
more fractured, but one thing is clear: it has become a major source of
cultural division between the pro- and anti-gay lobbies. It seems to be a
major source of ‘irreconcilable differences’ (Caramagno, 2002).
Does all this change simply mean the discovery of hidden natural rights?
Or is it the active work of many people struggling to create a better life for
themselves and others. To grasp this would really require a full-scale histor-
ical study – something that has yet to be done (although there are now many
excellent general histories, e.g. Greenberg, 1988). Still, we can sense, if only
schematically, how the changes unfolded.
From around the mid- to late nineteenth century, the idea of ‘the homo-
sexual’ as a kind of person comes into being – the clinical creature found in
the writings of Richard von Krafft Ebing, for instance. Minor campaigns
begin that attempt to take the homosexual out of the realm of law and place
158 Meaning, interpretation and rights
him within a medical model of understanding and treatment. By the start of
the twentieth century, in the works of those like Havelock Ellis and Magnus
Hirschfield, we start to see claims being made over the rights of these homo-
sexuals – in the case of Hirschfield (whose work was ultimately destroyed by
the Nazis), we see the creation of a centre and an organization designed to
campaign for the rights not just of the homosexual but also the transsexual.
(On all this, see Lauritsen and Thorsdad, 1974; Weeks, 1990; Oosterhuis,
2000.) In the middle of the twentieth century, we see a proliferation of
rather low key, often apologetic (but sometimes communist) organizations
who start to put homosexual rights more and more on the political agenda
(see D’Emilio, 1983; Dorr Legg, 1994).
In the UK, a history extending from Oscar Wilde to the Wolfenden Report
helped to make a public language of homosexuality more and more access-
ible (Westwood, 1952, 1960). The Wolfenden Report was the result of a
government inquiry set up to look into several ‘homosexual scandals’ in the
early 1950s. This commission established a framework for moral discourse
in Britain about such matters. For all its flaws, it helped to make homo-
sexuality a public issue and crucial morals crusaders emerged around it – the
HLRS and the AT. It argued that there was an area of personal morality that
was simply not the law’s business. It argued for, and helped to create, a
public space controlled by the law and a private space that was not the law’s
business. Stuart Hall has identified this as ‘Wolfenden’s double taxonomy:
towards stricter penalty and control, towards greater freedom and leniency;
together the two elements in a single strategy’ (Hall, 1980: 14). Ultimately,
Wolfenden’s proposals came to be enshrined in the Sexual Offences Act
1967, which effectively decriminalised homosexuality in England and Wales
(but later in Scotland, 1980, and Northern Ireland, 1982). What Wolfenden
so clearly reinforced was a public/private split – and along with this the
culture of the closet. It was far from being a ‘rights document’, for while
homosexual acts between consenting adults were no longer illegal, this was
only so in private places between two consenting adults. The division of
public and private space was central to this, leaving the stigma of the past
still hanging over homosexuality and keeping it a crime in many situations.
For most gay men and indeed lesbians (who were not directly touched by the
law), this still meant that their lives would be conducted in the closet. Gay
cultures have been powerfully shaped by this: the culture of homosexuality
was one of passing and hiding (Wolfenden, 1957; Hall, 1980; Plummer,
1981; Jeffery-Poulter, 1991).
The next striking stage in the creation of gay rights was the emergence of
the GLF in a number of Western countries in the late 1960s and early 1970s.
In many respects a new social movement, it built on a politics of identity
to bring out ‘gays’ as self-identified people demanding rights. With new
slogans, lists of demands and rights, badges and marches, it raised public
awareness of homosexuality in a way that simply had not happened
before. It made ‘coming out’ a major political process at the forefront of gay
Rights work 159
politics. ‘Gay was good’ and it was going visible (Walters, 1980; Weeks,
1990; Power, 1995). These new groups soon divided – either into factions
that were more assimilationist, liberal and rights-oriented (seeking equal
rights with heterosexuals) or into those who were more radical and chal-
lenging (Marotta, 1981) – establishing a split that continues to this day (see
below).
Then came a broad phase that was bitter sweet: it was the arrival of HIV/
AIDS between 1981 and 1986, and ironically it worked to strengthen the gay
movement. For the first time, hitherto ‘outcast gays’ came to work with the
government in shaping policies. They became professionalized. More than
this, they had to deal with the linkage between gay rights and health rights –
in many ways the latter was much more acceptable than the former, and
hence new links over rights talks were established. Perhaps most signifi-
cantly, since HIV/AIDS was an international issue, it brought gay and health
rights on to a world stage. We see the first stages of an internationally recog-
nized gay movement (there were elements before but this firmly established
it – the International Lesbian and Gay Association (ILGA) was founded in
Coventry in 19795). I do not want to overstate this. AIDS was after all a
serious pandemic which brought chronic illness, early death and tragic
bereavement for many disproportionately young men. But, in an ironic
twist, it also brought a revitalization and professionalism to a slumbering
gay movement (Davies et al., 1993; Berridge, 1996).
In most ‘traditional’ societies the issue of gay rights remains abhorrent. Such
relationships will be recognized, and indeed are seen in opposition to human
rights. In many countries around the world today sexual minorities are
outcast: they may be bullied, harassed and mocked, be discriminated against
in work and school, suffer unfair arrest and imprisonment, be treated as ill,
be rendered the victims of ‘hate crimes’, fined, flogged, tortured, raped and
executed. They may be driven into self-loathing and suicide. More than
70 countries have laws that criminalize homosexual relations. In Iran,
Afghanistan, Saudi Arabia and Chechnya, gay sex can lead to the death
penalty. From Europe to Africa to the Americas to Asia, case after case of
torture, ill treatment, violence and discrimination against lesbians and gay
men is documented. In Colombia, ‘death squads’ routinely target and kill
gay men and transvestites as local authorities promote limpieza social (social
cleansing). The death squads operate without fear of prosecution as the
gunmen themselves are often police officers and gays are regarded as ‘dis-
posable people’. There are also very many cases of transgender rights
activists – ‘the ultimate gender outlaws’ – being abused across the world. In
short, sexual minorities are seen neither to deserve rights nor to be treated
in any ways as equals. (See Vanessa Baird, 2001, 2004, for documentation.)
Nor has ‘gay rights work’ had much success at the level of international
governmental organizations (IGOs), though rather more so with the informal
level of NGOs. In the world of public cultures of human rights like the
United Nations, sexual rights may be seen as the latest and a neglected issue
and their claims have been scarcely heard except through the women’s
movement. Although implicitly they may be read into various charters of
rights (the right to happiness and freedom etc. could surely also mean sexual
happiness and freedom6), and although they have (a much shorter) history
built from gay activism with their own gay charters, it is only very recently
that they have specifically and directly entered the international public
domain. And here it is mainly through the rights work of the women’s
movement, and especially the work of the transnational women’s health
movement, which became galvanized in the UN-sponsored women’s confer-
ences in Vienna (1993), Cairo (1994) and Beijing (1995), that the situation
started to change.7
In these debates many terms can get conflated: sexual rights, gay rights,
reproductive rights, intimate rights, human rights and a concern over sexual
abuse and violence. They are not the same and each needs to delineate its
own domain of duties and responsibilities. In particular, Miller suggests that
sexual rights and reproductive rights should not be conflated, as otherwise
individuals engaging in non-procreative sex (or non-sexual procreation?)
can be disenfranchised. We need to see how these rights connect differently
with different issues (Miller, 2000: 96). Miller also wants to be clear about
the right to be free from (what can be called a violations approach) and the
right to do something (a promotions approach).
Of course, such programmes as these have been open to much attack
within the United Nations. Rights are always heavily contested (Smith and
Windes, 2000). Indeed, they depend upon contestation in order to take
shape and be given life. Thus, the attacks on sexual rights come from many
sides: from the Vatican, from Muslim organisations, from the US govern-
ment and President Bush. And such right-wing and fundamentalist back-
lashes serve to make the rights claims more visible, while simultaneously
managing to impede them. Nevertheless, Rosalind Petchesky (2003: 39) is
hopeful about the future, suggesting that ‘slowly and incrementally, women’s
determination . . . to gain some control over their fertility and bodies was
starting to make an impact on international human rights’.
This includes such organizations as the Catholic Family and Human Rights
Institute, The Howard Center itself, Human Life International, the Family
Research Council, Concerned Women for America, the World Family Policy
Center and of course the Vatican. The Vatican has not only decreed in vari-
ous encyclicals, but also has ‘permanent observer’ status at the United
Nations. The ‘Holy See’ is the official face of the Vatican at the UN. It has led
to the World Congress of Families (WCF). It has also produced what Buss
and Herman (2003: xxxiii) have called ‘Christian right social science’. It has
played a key role at a number of international conferences (Cairo, Cairo+5;
Beijing, Beijing+5) with all kinds of strange bedfellows (not just Christians
with Muslims, but Catholics with Protestants) joining forces globally against
the ‘global liberal agenda’ – and more specifically with feminism, humanism
and lesbian and gay rights along with socialism, environmentalism and
‘new-age spirituality’. Sexual rights are strongly contested.
Again, she looks at the classic models of citizenship, and trying to see how
they may be applicable to lesbian and gay rights she finds them severely
lacking. She sees that claims to citizenship status generally are not just guilty
of strong male bias, a point made by many feminist writers. The problem
goes further: citizenship also privileges heterosexuality. ‘Within discourses
of citizen’s rights . . . the normal citizen has largely been constructed as male,
and . . . as heterosexual’. Hence she goes on from this to identify a number
of areas where the rights of sexual – as opposed to heterosexual – citizenship
should be claimed. She names three main areas of sexual citizenships
and rights. The main areas for her are: (a) seeking rights to various forms
of sexual practice in personal relationships, including pleasures and self-
determination (e.g. the right not to be raped, as well as the right to have
children); (b) seeking rights through self-identity definition, like the option
to name the kind of sexual person one is, alongside the right to self-
realization; (c) seeking rights within social institutions, meaning public val-
idation of various forms of sexual relationship, including the right to choose
partners and the right to public recognition (ibid.: 75). Her arguments lead
us to see that just as citizenship is racialized and gendered, so it has been
sexualized.
My own concerns have gone beyond the idea of sexual citizenship. While
this is an important issue, late modern times are witnessing a considerable
array of new personal or intimate dilemmas. Establishing rights and obliga-
tions around sexuality are important; but so too are the new decisions that
have to be taken over assisted conception (from surrogate mothering to the
freezing of sperm and embryos), the buying and selling of body parts, the
making of new kinds of families, the new ‘transitionings’ over gender (as
men become women and women become men), the development of new
relationships over the Internet and the new medical technologies such as
Viagra and ‘morning after pills’, which could change the ways in which we
conduct our personal lives. Again, these are all globally contested areas.
They lead to debates around what I have called elsewhere intimate citizenship
(Plummer, 2003).
Queering citizenship
A recent development has been a shift from the analysis of ‘sexual rights’ to
those that emphasize ‘queer theory’. This position, which developed in the
Rights work 165
late 1980s in the work of Butler, Sedgwick and Warner, challenged the
orthodox terminologies of gay, bisexual, lesbian, male and female and
advocated a language of deconstruction, destabilization and depolarization
(see Plummer, 2005). In this argument there could be no straightforward
view of sexual rights, which is seen as a process of the normalization of
sexuality. It shuns, for instance, the notion of the ‘good and responsible
lesbian and gay citizens’ who are inside the charmed circle of citizens, with a
world of gay and lesbian married couples raising their children. Instead, it
looks at a ‘a less respectable, dangerous gayness’ composed of the sexual
outlaw, the sexual fringe, the transgressor. Smyth (1994) makes a particular
point about the sexualized lesbian: to see lesbians as highly sexualized, fet-
ishistic, ‘fucking’ creatures poses a threat to the usually desexualized image
of the lesbian citizen. The radical edge of being gay and sexual cannot be
simply assimilated into a culture of rights and obligations.
The process being highlighted here has been called ‘normalization’ (Phelan,
2001). While the normal citizen has been stretched to include the homo-
sexual and the sexual being, it only includes those who fit a certain model –
those who want families, conform to gender roles, link love and sex. They
want to stress not their differences but their sameness, they want to have and
raise children, they want to be inside the armed forces: they share ‘family
values’. Often they are models of middle-class consumption and individual-
ism. All this has been challenged by the queer movement, which raises
orthodox ‘sexual rights’ as a problem, and starts to speak instead of ‘queer
rights’ as part of a new order entailing a transgression of all categories, a
celebration of marginalities and dissidence. For some this may mean the
arrival of ‘bi-theory’ and ‘gender bending’ as a way of unsettling the certain-
ties of the sexual and gender orders. It has meant, in almost ironic twist, the
arrival of gay men who have sex with women, and lesbians who have
sado-masochistic sex with men.
A leaflet circulating in 1991 put it bluntly:
Queer means to fuck with gender. There are straight queers, bi queers,
tranny queers, lez queers, SM queers, fisting queers in every single street
in this apathetic country of ours. . . . Each time the word ‘queer’ is used
it defines a strategy, an attitude, a reference to other identities and a new
self understanding. (And queer can be qualified as ‘more queer’, ‘queer’,
or ‘queerest’ as the naming develops into a more complex process of
identification.)
(Smyth, 1992: 17, 20)
Notes
1 Symbolic interactionism was a term coined by Herbert Blumer in 1937 (Blumer,
1969) to capture the grounded analysis and intimate familiarity with the creativity
of action in social life and the lived processes of everyday life and the languages
and meanings that emerge through them. Allied is the constructionist view, which
sees social life not as obdurate and fixed but as produced through social life
(Berger and Luckmann, 1967). It has been argued by Maines (2001) and Atkinson
and Housley (2003) that these positions are really quite widespread within soci-
ology, even if often not acknowledged. They are closely linked to the philo-
sophical traditions of pragmatism identified with Dewey, James and Mead, and
more recently Rorty. In any event such positions shape my arguments in this
chapter.
2 For example, see Martha Nussbaum’s (1999: Chapter 7) discussion. Here she
lists: the right to be protected against violence, and in general, the right to equal
protection under the law; the right to have consensual adult sexual relations with-
out criminal penalty; the right to non-discrimination in housing, employment and
education; the right to military service; the right to marriage and/or its legal
benefits; and the right to retain custody of children and/or to adopt.
3 Side by side with this listing is a concern over discriminations, which include
sexual offences laws, the use of beatings and tortures in custody, hate crimes,
invisibilities, the concern over young gays and lesbians and discriminations
against them, employment discrimination, freedom of expression and association,
religious leaders supporting discrimination (see Beger, 2004: 107).
4 As ever we must beware of the dangers of essentialising homosexuality and making
it look the same across cultures and throughout history. The important work of
the late historian John Boswell (1995) – although he was an essentialist – shows
that same-sex marriages have existed in the past.
5 In 1993, ILGA was granted ‘roster status’ as an NGO by the UN Economic and
Social Council (but this was later withdrawn, as they could not convince it that
they did not condone sex between adults and minors). It now has some 300 ILGA
Rights work 167
members groups in more than 80 countries (Felice, 1996: 48). Its key slogan is
that ‘gay rights are human rights’.
6 Generalist and abstract accounts of sexual rights often draw upon the broad
claims of earlier charters. For instance, the charter drawn at the World Congress
of Sexology in 1999 often just seems to add the word ‘sexual’ to rights that have
generally been at the forefront of the rights movement. To illustrate, they suggest
some eleven rights, such as the right to sexual freedom, which encompasses the
possibility for individuals to express their full sexual potential. However, this
excludes all forms of sexual coercion, exploitation and abuse at any time and
situations in life.
7 The first dealt with gender-based violence, sexual stratification, rape, sexual
slavery, harassment and exploitation. The 1994 conference dealt with sexual
health and came mainly from health lobbies and HIV prevention. The 1995
conference is more cautious.
9 The sociology of indigenous
peoples’ rights
Colin Samson and Damien Short
For two hundred years we have been subjected to death, abuse and
denial of dignity and basic human rights by the white usurpers of our
land. Today we are the products of the ravages of white settlement. . . .
As Aborigines began to sicken physically and psychologically, they were
hit by the full blight of the alien way of thinking. They were hit by the
intolerance and uncomprehending barbarism of a people intent on pro-
gress in material terms, a people who never credited that there could be
cathedrals of the spirit as well as of stone.
Conclusion
As the example of liberalism demonstrates, the dominant modes of analyses
of indigenous peoples rights do not question the legitimacy of the state
itself and assertions of sovereignty over indigenous peoples and their lands.
Such a critique would be fundamental to a critical sociological formulation
of indigenous peoples’ rights, and accords with many of the writings of
The sociology of indigenous peoples’ rights 185
indigenous scholars. A major area in which sociology can contribute to an
understanding of the broader issues surrounding the rights of indigenous
peoples is in its analysis of the role of the state, the histories by which states
came to create and assume authority over indigenous peoples and the
current social and political conflicts over the conceptualization of rights
themselves.
As former President of the UN Human Rights Commission and of Ireland,
Mary Robinson (2004) recently remarked, the expertise and research of
sociologists can play a vital role in making states responsible and chal-
lenging market fundamentalism. Human and other rights are fast becoming
the tools for making states accountable for the ethical treatment of all
populations. With pressing issues related to indigenous health, welfare and
cultural survival, a critical public sociology could actually operate as Mary
Robinson suggested. As long as it refuses to collaborate in the political
fiction that indigenous rights are solely state citizenship rights and recog-
nizes indigenous struggles to maintain cultural continuity, sociology could
help to challenge the current patterns of state and market dominance and
question the fatalistic notions that cultural distinctiveness is a thing of the
past.
Notes
1 For more extended commentaries on conceptions of rights as they were played
out between Europeans and indigenous peoples, see the extensive discussions
in Deloria (1985), Williams (1990), Tully (1995), Pagden (1995) and Keal
(2003).
2 The ‘stolen generations’ were the focus of the 2002 Oscar-nominated film Rabbit
Proof Fence.
3 As Wunder (1994: 33) has noted, such policies were direct violations of the
freedom of religion guaranteed by the Bill of Rights in the US Constitution.
4 With widespread substandard housing for aboriginal peoples in Canada, lawsuits
are now being brought against the federal government for violating the Constitu-
tion, which clearly spells out the government’s responsibilities for aboriginal
housing (Janzen, 2004).
5 This is not to say that classical sociological theory could not be valuable for
understanding particular social processes affecting indigenous peoples. Marxist
understandings of the expansion of capitalism could be used in interpreting
resource extraction policies on indigenous lands. Weber’s ideas of bureaucracy
could also be important in looking at state imposed land claims policies.
6 In a recent empirical study of the phenomenon of military toxic waste dumping
close to Indian reservations in the USA, Hooks and Smith (2004) note the
limited sociological literature on Native Americans and environmental injustice.
Environmental sociology, they argue, focuses on class and race dynamics in
urban areas, with capitalism, rather than the state, as the main causal force. Some
sociologists have, of course, written about American Indians in more depth.
Exemplars include Thornton (1987), Cornell (1988) and Nagel (1996).
7 Morgan (2004) has documented this predicament in the international arena. In
the Canadian national context studies by Brody (1981), Samson (2001, 2003) and
Nadasdy (2003) show how aboriginal peoples must configure themselves into
186 Meaning, interpretation and rights
culturally alien political forms and engage in processes that undermine group
solidarity in order to claim rights. This predicament is particularly acute
for northern hunting peoples, whose very survival has depended on consensus,
communitarianism and the avoidance of open conflict.
8 For an overview and discussion of these rights, see Pritchard (1998).
Part IV
The final part of this book deals less with a specific approach than a com-
mon problem: the clash of rights. The three chapters look respectively at
the rights of prisoners, the rights of mental health patients and the phenom-
enon of hate speech; all cases in which civil rights and freedoms have been
contested. Chapter 10 considers the justifications that have been given for
denying the civil rights of offenders by imprisonment. Philosophical justifi-
cations range from utilitarian arguments based on the claimed reduction of
future crime, to the categorical imperative of retribution. Sociological pur-
chase on such arguments includes the Marxist view of penal systems as the
protection of class interest, Durkheimian views of punishment as the asser-
tion of shared values and a Weberian perspective informed by the oppressive
nature of authority, the iron cage of rationality and bureaucracy that will
imprison us all. Analysis of the micro-management exerted by all systems of
authority has been most fully explored by Foucault, with particular atten-
tion to marginal groups such as prisoners, the ‘mad’ and homosexuals.
Conversly, postmodern theory inspired by Levinas offers an approach to
rights based on unconditional responsibility towards the ‘other’: a radical
justice of alterity. The feminist critique of false universals can also be viewed
in this light, as can proposals for a feminist jurisprudence that challenges
claims to gender neutral legal thought.
The main problem for sociological approaches to liberal penal policy, as
sketched out in Chapter 10, is that a focus on individual rights and responsi-
bilties ignores the social conditions producing criminality and is challenged
by the justice of alterity. This position condemns the demonisation of
offenders and embraces unconditional responsibility towards them, thus
highlighting the importance of human rights as a system of protection for
those beyond empathy. In contrast to these sentiments, the chapter high-
lights the continuing legacy of ‘civil death’ for prisoners, and the fact that
prisons themselves have operated as ‘lawless agencies’, with prisoners sub-
ject to the exclusive control of the authorities. The chapter then documents
some challenges to this arrangement, including the 1975 ruling that deemed
prisoners to fall under the purview of the European Convention on Human
Rights, and the eventual acknowledgement that prison authorities must act
188 The clash of rights
within legally defined powers. The impact on prisoners is argued to be slight
thus far, and their protections against damage or ill-treatment remain weak,
rendering them a classic case of vulnerability that requires protection but
evokes little sympathy: candidates for the ‘justice of alterity’. A movement is
now under way to ensure that the conditions of imprisonment conform to
human rights standards.
Chapter 11 considers the related case of human rights issues raised in the
treatment of mental disorder, reviewing the traditional denial of rights to
this group, their gradual but incomplete acquisition and the question of how
far denial of rights can itself induce mental disorder. The chapter draws on
the work of Foucault to chart changing characterisations of ‘madness’ from
the language of lunacy to the language of illness, the latter being accom-
panied by an expansion of recognised conditions such that mental disorder
today cannot be equated with eighteenth-century ideas of madness as
‘unreason’. The chapter then considers Marshall’s model of citizenship as
community membership, noting his acknowledgement that full equality had
not been achieved, his (often ignored) recognition of the role of struggle in
the accretion of rights and the role of social class in mediating their realis-
ation (or otherwise). This then provides the context for a consideration of
the traditional denial of liberty to those deemed mad, the ‘civil death’
referred to in Chapter 10, though here a majority of those detained had
committed no offence.
Despite the gradual change in the nature of treatment from forcible
restraint to moral management the denial of rights continued, though
with an accompanying tension between restraint and therapy. The mid-
nineteenth century saw the introduction of clear procedures for admission to
an institution that was a first step in clarifying the rights of those who
might be subject to detention, though the principle concern was to protect
the rights of the sane rather than assert the rights of the ‘mad’. Certification
was, of course, hugely stigmatising and the introduction of voluntary
admission in the twentieth century was thus a step forward. However,
the chapter goes on to document a number of perverse effects of the reduc-
tion of institutionalised treatment for mental disorder, including ‘trans-
institutionalisation’, whereby the patients rotate through different forms of
residential care or detention. Alternatively, where provision for alternative
care and treatment is inadequate we find the patient facing a series of prac-
tical difficulties, often rooted in class inequality. Thus, the chapter argues, a
vicious circle may be established whereby the lack of rights to adequate
provision exacerbates the original problem.
Chapter 12 addresses a fundamental liberal dilemma of how to weigh
freedom of expression against freedom from discrimination. This can also
be construed as another instance of universalism versus particularism;
how far should the universal freedom of expression be constrained in favour
of the protection of vulnerable minorities? The chapter starts by document-
ing New Labour’s specific concern with racially aggravated offences –
The clash of rights 189
influenced to some degree by legislation and debate in the USA – and details
a gradual expansion of British law in this field, from race to religion, and
also to sexuality and disability. Through this account we see the dilemmas
surrounding such legislation: from the supporting arguments that crimes
motivated by hate cause damage to the victim beyond the crime itself, that
this additionally infects a wider community with fear and trauma, and
constitutes an assault on the dominant values of society; to the opposing
view that legislating against ‘hate’ crime is totalitarian, punishes thought
and bad values and treats equal crimes unequally. The chapter shows how
sociological evidence can be brought to bear in evaluating these positions.
Holocaust denial is then addressed as a special case of ‘hate speech’, which
has not yet been outlawed in Britain, though there is such legislation in a
number of other European countries – part of a movement against the trivi-
alisation of crimes against humanity. Some of the hesitation in Britain has
been related to the problem of offering singular protection to a particular
group in the context of an ethnically and religiously diverse society. The
issue of freedom of expression arises again in this debate, and to date,
incitement to racial hatred has been addressed only in the context of public
order. Again the chapter considers the problems of appropriate evidence, but
also outlines the difficulties of addressing holocaust denial under this legisla-
tion, and provides a background to current plans for a new offence of
incitement to religious hatred. Proposed legislation in this area is considered
to be especially relevant to Muslim groups, who fall outside of laws framed
in terms of racial hatred, and are potentially vulnerable to discrimination via
anti-terrorist measures. The fear of eroding freedom of expression has arisen
again in this context, and the symbolic force of legislation is a key factor in
attempts to strike a balance between fundamental freedoms and acceptable
norms of personal conduct.
10 Punishment, rights and justice
Eamonn Carrabine
Continuing controversies
The current penal problems can be regarded as simply too many offenders in
too few prison places, which give rise to overcrowding, understaffing and
Punishment, rights and justice 205
decrepit conditions. The striking increase in Britain’s prison population,
which rose from 42,000 in 1991 to 74,023 in 2003, is due to the courts
sending more people to prison and sending them there for longer. For
instance, the proportion of adults convicted in the crown courts who were
sent to prison increased from 45 per cent in 1992 to 64 per cent in 2001
(Kennedy, 2004: 281–2). Although the country lies some way behind the
global leaders in imprisonment – Russia, the USA, China and South Africa –
this should not detract from the fact that England and Wales consistently
uses imprisonment to a greater extent than practically every country in
Western Europe (Carrabine et al., 2004: 290). The expanding prison system
was initially fuelled by the infamous insistence of the then Conservative
Home Secretary, Michael Howard, in 1993 that ‘prison works’ and the
introduction of a range of austere policies that subjected prisoners to grim
regimes. The Labour government has continued to rely on expanding the
prison system, but by ‘making prisons work’, in the words of the new Home
Secretary Jack Straw in 1998, through rescuing rehabilitative programmes.
As the prison population has spiralled so has the problem of overcrowd-
ing, especially in local prisons. It has been estimated that by June 2003,
85 out of 138 prisons were overcrowded, as were 9 of the 13 new prisons
built since 1993 (NACRO, 2003: 6). The problems generated by over-
crowding have to be located in the material context of dilapidated physical
conditions in which many prisoners are contained, combined with poor
sanitation, scarcely edible food, decaying cramped cells, clothing shortages
and brief, inadequate family visits.5 Compounding this deprivation are the
severely restricted and oppressive regimes that are imposed in the absence of
space, facilities and resources to provide prisoners with a range of training,
work and educational opportunities. Hence, conditions of almost total
‘lock-down’ prevail.
Over the past decade the number of women in prison has trebled.
Although women make up only 6 per cent of the prison population, 20 per
cent of prison suicides from January to August 2004 were women, with
nearly half of all self-harm incidents involving women (Scraton and Moore,
2004: 35–6). Half of all women in prison are on prescribed medication such
as anti-depressants or anti-psychotics, with two-thirds having children
under the age of 16, which has been estimated at 24,000 children (Kennedy,
2004: 285). The government’s own Strategy for Women Offenders, pub-
lished in 2000, recognizes that the ‘current system does impact differently on
women and men’ (cited in Scraton and Moore, 2004: 36), which echoes
longstanding feminist criticisms, discussed above, that treating women the
same as men only compounds inequality. For instance, Carlen (1998: 10)
has argued that women’s imprisonment ‘incorporates and amplifies all the
anti-social modes of control that oppress women outside the prison’, and
that the rationales for reducing the imprisonment of women have been sub-
verted and are now used to lock up more women through processes of
‘carceral clawback’ (Carlen, 2002).
206 The clash of rights
The controversies surrounding deaths in custody raise fundamental
questions over the state’s responsibility to protect prisoner’s lives and pre-
vent death. The Strasbourg court has consistently held that the state’s article
2 positive obligation of the ECHR to protect life extends to prisoners. In
Keenan v. United Kingdom (2001) the ECtHR held that this obligation
included a duty to prevent suicides when authorities were aware of a
‘real and immediate risk’. This positive obligation was further clarified in
Edwards v. United Kingdom (2002), where the court held that the author-
ities had failed to appreciate the vulnerability of Christopher Edwards, who
was murdered by his cell-mate at Chelmsford prison, as both prisoners
suffered from mental illness (Scott, 2004: 20). The Prison Service is still
under scrutiny following the murder of an Asian teenager, Zahid Mubarek,
at Feltham Young Offenders Institution in 2000, who was put in a cell with a
known racist who had openly fantasized about committing a racist murder.
It has also been argued that the brutal deaths of ethnic minorities while in
prison custody is similar to the deaths of African/Caribbeans in police cus-
tody, as there is ‘a tendency for prison staff to overreact to disruptive
behaviour by African/Caribbean prisoners, whereby the stereotype of “Big,
Black and Dangerous” seems to predominate in determining their response’
(Bowling and Phillips, 2002: 208). This view is confirmed in the BBC docu-
mentary Death on Camera (2004), which broadcast CCTV footage of the
death in police custody of Christopher Alder, who had been left to die on the
floor of a Hull police station in 1998. The fact that black people are six times
more likely to be imprisoned than whites, even if it is their first offence,
combined with the substantial evidence of racial discrimination in the
police, courts and prisons, confirms that there is systematic injustice in the
criminal justice system.
The United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child (2002) has
formally raised a range of concerns over youth justice policy and practice in
England and Wales, not least since the country imprisons twice as many
children as the rest of Western Europe combined. Critics of Labour’s youth
justice policy are especially concerned with the government’s continuing
reliance on custodial sentences for young offenders, with campaigners argu-
ing ‘that the Government’s “obsession” with teenagers on street corners had
contributed to the sharp rise in the number of young people in prison’. In
particular, there has been ‘a ninefold rise in the number of children under 15
being sentenced to custody’ (Bright, 2003: 9). It has been estimated that
40 per cent of young people in prison have been in local authority care,
while a staggering 90 per cent have mental health or substance abuse prob-
lems. Nearly a quarter have literacy and numeracy skills below those of
an average seven-year-old and a significant proportion have suffered phys-
ical and sexual abuse (Kennedy, 2004: 292). This punitive direction in
youth justice is as inhumane in its violation of rights as it is ineffective in
preventing crime.
Punishment, rights and justice 207
Conclusion
This is by no means an exhaustive discussion of the current controversies in
prisons, yet what it does illustrate is that ‘democratic states with strong legal
institutions and rights traditions can and do abuse the human rights of their
citizens’ and that they ‘can do so with perfect legality’ (Ignatieff, 2000: 37–8).
Human rights are social inventions. They are not intrinsic to individuals but
are attached, created and removed by external forces. As Arendt (1973) has
shown, human rights depend on strong political arrangement to enforce and
protect them. Her account of how the Nazis dehumanized Jews highlights
how fragile are appeals to common humanity in defending the vulnerable
and marginalized. The importance of human rights legislation is that it
mandates ‘an obligation to respect human agency’ (Ignatieff, 2000: 39).
What this brief discussion of prison conditions has shown is that the com-
bination of structural disadvantages and demonizing media representations
masks the grim realities of many prisoners’ lives. It is these social injustices
that demand recognition and their human rights that need defending. Of
course, this is not to deny that crimes need to be censured, but the material
covered in this chapter should be seen as advancing a fuller acknowledgement
of social wrongs and a fuller protection of the human rights of all.
Notes
1 There are certain affinities here with Turner’s (1993: 506) appeal to ‘collective
sympathy’ as a means of generating moral intersubjectivity through Durkheimian
compassion rather than Kantian duty.
2 Portia is the female character in Shakespeare’s Merchant of Venice who tricks
the money-lender Shylock out of his pound of flesh, while Persephone was a
goddess in Greek mythology who spent part of each year with her husband Hades
in the underworld and then returned to the upper world for part of the year with
her mother. The myth is seen as explaining the changing seasons and fertility
cycles, with the world grieving her absence in winter and blossoming on her return
in spring. This solution is seen as exemplifying the virtues of relational justice, as it
is acceptable to all involved, rather than distinguishing between right and wrong.
3 Sentencing is often used as an example to illustrate how the two elements are
combined, as there is a formal element that involves dealing with offenders in a
procedurally consistent fashion to ensure fairness and a substantive element of
doing what is the most appropriate in the particular case. Not only can this result
in an individualized and paternalistic form of justice for female offenders
(Edwards, 1984), but the balance between the two shifts over time and has in
recent years moved in a logic of justice direction over the ethic of care (Hudson,
1993).
4 Since 1966 individuals have been able to take their cases to the European Court of
Human Rights in Strasbourg (Schone, 2001: 73) and in Britain the Human Rights
Act now provides domestic remedy (as of 2000).
5 The domestic courts and Strasbourg institutions have been reluctant to intervene
in these routine conditions of neglect. The ECtHR has taken the view that article 3
of the convention, which prohibits torture, inhuman or degrading treatment or
punishment, was not intended to find the inevitable deprivations of imprisonment
as human rights violations. For instance, in Reed v. United Kingdom (1983)
208 The clash of rights
‘spending three weeks in a cockroach-infested cell was held not to be enough’, but
in a more recent case, Tekin v. Turkey (1998), the court found a breach of article 3
‘where the applicant was held for four days in a police cell in freezing conditions
and with little food and water’; but the fact that the prisoner also received regular
beatings means that ‘the decision leaves it unclear whether the neglect or physical
mistreatment alone might amount to inhuman or degrading treatment’ (Living-
stone, 2000: 314–15). In contrast, the European Committee for the Prevention of
Torture and Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment (CPT) has used the
terms ‘inhuman’ and ‘degrading’ to describe custodial living conditions, but has
taken a cumulative view so that ‘the combination of overcrowding, lack of inte-
gral sanitation, almost unalleviated cellular confinement and/or lack of outdoor
exercise have on several occasions been judged to amount to inhuman and degrad-
ing treatment’ (Morgan, 2001: 728). However, the CPT has no judicial function.
The distinction is that the ECtHR aims at ‘ “conflict solution” on the legal level,
the CPT’s activities aim at “conflict avoidance” on the practical level . . . to
strengthen the “cordon sanitaire” that separates acceptable and unacceptable
treatment or behaviour’ (Evans and Morgan, 1999: 6). The more important point
is that international human rights standards lay a floor (i.e. the minimum an
individual should expect) rather than set a ceiling (i.e. aspiration) of obligations
(Scraton and Moore, 2004: 22).
11 Mental disorder and
human rights
Joan Busfield
Theoretical underpinnings
Theorising rights
I now turn to consider sociological theorising about human rights. Probably
the best-known discussion is to be found in T. H. Marshall’s influential essay
‘Citizenship and social class’ (1963), based on a lecture given in 1949.10 In
this essay Marshall does two things. First, he provides a categorisation of the
rights of citizenship – that is, being a member of a community – into civil,
political and social rights; second, he offers an account of the factors under-
pinning the acquisition of citizenship rights and their relation to social class.
Both the categorisation and his theoretical analysis are useful when con-
sidering the linkages between mental disorder and human rights. Marshall
defines civil rights as the set of rights relating to individual freedom embed-
ded in the law: ‘liberty of the person, freedom of speech, thought and faith,
the right to own property and to conclude valid contracts, and the right to
justice’ (ibid.: 74). These rights include the right to work and are, he con-
tends, the rights necessary for capitalism, a system that requires people to
engage as individuals in the market. At the institutional level, these rights are
supported by the civil courts. They tend, he argues, to be achieved earliest,
suggesting that they were formally achieved as universal rights in Britain in
the eighteenth century; the same was true in the USA, where they were
incorporated into the 1776 Declaration of Independence, and in France,
where they were the basis of the 1789 Declaration of the Rights of Man.
Political rights refer to ‘the right to participate in the exercise of political
power, as a member of a body invested with political authority or as an
elector of the members of such a body’ (ibid.: 74). The institutions here are
the national and local governing bodies. In Britain political rights were
secured for many members of the population in the nineteenth century after
considerable political struggle, although universal suffrage was not fully
achieved until the twentieth century. Again, the speed and timing of their
introduction varied across Europe and the USA. However, unlike civil rights,
political rights are, Marshall contends, a threat to capitalism, since they
include not only the right to vote (and so potentially the power to get rid of
governments) but also the right to collective bargaining through trade
unions.
Social rights are the third type of right identified by Marshall and include
‘the right to a modicum of economic welfare and security and the right to
share to the full in the social heritage and to live the life of a civilized being
according to the standards prevailing in society’ (ibid.). The corresponding
institutions are the educational system and welfare services, such as health
Mental disorder and human rights 213
services, and social security benefits covering unemployment, retirement and
sickness. Marshall contends that social rights, like political rights, are a
threat to capitalism because of the way they modify market arrangements
(an example is unemployment benefit, which may affect an individual’s will-
ingness to work as well as rates of pay), and again they have only been
achieved (to the extent that they have) after considerable political struggle.
Social rights were not included in the eighteenth-century codification of
rights such as the US Declaration of Independence or the French Declaration
of the Rights of Man, and were largely secured in the twentieth century.
Article 25 (1) of the 1948 United Nations Universal Declaration of Human
Rights asserts:
Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for the health
and well-being of himself and of his family, including food, clothing,
housing and medical care and necessary social services, and the right to
security in the event of unemployment, sickness, disability, widowhood,
old age or other lack of livelihood in circumstances beyond his control.
Madness borrowed its face from the mask of the beast. Those chained
to the cell walls were no longer men whose minds had wandered, but
beasts preyed upon by a natural frenzy: as if madness, at its extreme
point, freed from that moral unreason in which its most attenuated
forms are enclosed, managed to rejoin, by a paroxysm of strength, the
immediate violence of animality. This model of animality prevailed in
the asylums, and gave them their cage-like aspect, their look of the
menagerie.
(Foucault, 1967: 72)
While there is evidence that such a conception of insanity was not entirely
new (a more humane view of those with melancholia, often individuals
from the upper classes, had existed prior to this), important changes in
conceptions of madness did occur during this period and did so at precisely
the same time that an emphasis on the liberty of the subject was develop-
ing and civil rights were being acquired by most of the population. How-
ever, the changes in conceptions of madness did not free mad people from
the possibility of confinement and the attendant loss of rights – civic exclu-
sion in Lockwood’s terms. In law, for instance, lunatics had in effect the
status of children and contracts they made were not enforceable. This
denial of rights occurred even though the majority had not committed any
criminal offence that might justify their detention. Confinement of mad
people and the attendant loss of rights were justified in terms of their
irrationality (albeit often partial) and the potential power of the asylum to
correct it. The aim, though frequently over-optimistic, was to restore the
person to rationality so that they could return to the community and share
the same rights that others were acquiring.12 Indeed, the confinement of
mad people increased across Europe in the nineteenth century, in part
because of a new therapeutic optimism, itself encouraged by the increasing
claims by medical men of their power to cure insanity (which would
reduce the burden of dependency), but also because, once established, the
asylums rapidly filled up with those persons (often only a relatively small
Mental disorder and human rights 217
proportion of those admitted) whose problems were long term and could
not easily be remedied. None the less, while it did not secure the rights
of those detained during the nineteenth century, the changed conception of
madness did start to lay the foundations for the subsequent acquisition
of rights by those deemed mad or disordered in mind, which I consider in the
next section.
One important area of change during the nineteenth and twentieth centur-
ies was the formulation of clearer legal procedures for admitting someone to
an institution because of the loss of liberty that resulted and the public’s
fears of arbitrary incarceration.13 These procedures required certificates to
be signed if a person were to be admitted to an asylum – a medical certificate
becoming necessary in most cases. In France, for instance, the 1838 Lunacy
Act, widely regarded as a piece of pioneering legislation that became a model
for many other countries, required a petition by a relative or friend and a
medical certificate for admission in non-emergency cases. Admission in
emergency cases, where there was a threat to public order or the safety of
others, required a signature from a prefect, followed by a clinical assessment
within 24 hours of admission and then again within 14 days, with a report
to the prefect on each occasion.
Certification procedures provided some regulation of admission to the
asylum, even though they did not prevent the admission of some individuals
who were not severely disturbed. The procedures were, however, largely
designed to protect the civil rights of those who were not mad – to prevent
wrongful detention. They did not ensure any rights to inmates: those admit-
ted continued largely to be denied their civil rights, especially if they ended
up as long-stay patients, and they were also excluded from the emerging
political rights being secured by key groups in the population. Moreover,
for all the therapeutic optimism that had facilitated the development of
asylums, certification served as a reminder of the legal compulsion under-
pinning asylum use and became highly stigmatising, since it required clear
evidence of insanity. Indeed, there was an ongoing tension between cus-
todial models of the asylum symbolised by certification and compulsory
detention, and therapeutic models symbolised by the presence of medical
men. This tension has continued to the present, since the legal powers to
detain on grounds of severe mental disorder (along frequently with the per-
ceived dangers to the public) remain.14 However, the use of these powers is
now more regulated and restricted and the rights of those so detained have
generally increased. In the section that follows I look at the acquisition of
rights by those confined on grounds of severe mental disorder.
The enjoyment of the rights and freedoms set forth in this convention
shall be secured without discrimination on any grounds such as sex,
220 The clash of rights
race, colour, language, political or other opinion, national or social
origin, association with a national minority, property, birth or other
status.
This clause provides a potential basis for claims by those with mental dis-
order or other marginal groups whose rights are denied. Certainly during
this period there were increasing efforts in a number of countries to
strengthen the rights of those detained on a compulsory basis, and mental
health pressure groups were also set up.15 In Britain the 1959 Mental Health
Act gave patients the right to contest their admission by seeking to be
discharged through the framework of mental health review tribunals, and
the 1983 Mental Health Act further strengthened patients’ rights vis-à-vis
‘exceptional’ treatments such as ECT and psychosurgery. In the USA the
laws governing compulsory detention varied between states, but many states
began to strengthen patients’ rights. In addition to the impact of studies such
as Asylums on awareness of conditions in mental hospitals, the focus on civil
rights in the USA and Europe in the 1960s undoubtedly increased con-
sciousness of issues surrounding the rights of mental hospital patients. For
instance, the American psychiatrist and libertarian Thomas Szasz, in his
book Law, Liberty and Psychiatry (1963), argued that compulsory deten-
tion of those with mental illness was a form of imprisonment and an attack
on human rights.16 Increasingly, too, a range of authors and activists
emphasised the importance of listening to patients and new campaign
groups were formed, some exclusively for patients, calling for improvements
in the care and support of those with mental illness.
The second change of key importance was the policy of community care,
which began to be introduced at varying speed and intensity across Europe
and the USA from the mid-1950s. Narrowly defined, this was a policy of
providing facilities outside the hospital – small residential and rehabilitation
units – for those with more severe problems who were previously long-term
inmates in mental hospitals or might otherwise have ended up as long-term
inmates. More broadly it was a policy of providing mental health facilities
away from the old mental hospitals, not only for long-stay patients, but also
services such as outpatient clinics, drop-in centres, and acute and emergency
services (whether in units attached to general hospitals or in community
mental health centres – the US model) for those with less severe or acute
problems. Consequently, the policy of community care became associated
with plans to close down the old mental hospitals altogether, relocating
former inmates into smaller units or trying, where possible, to help indi-
viduals with mental health problems to manage in their existing environ-
ments. In the USA the mental hospital population reduced very rapidly
(from a 1955 peak of 559,000 state hospital inpatients to 137,180 in 1980
(Brown, 1985: 5)), new community mental health centres were opened and
state mental hospitals began to be closed. In Italy the policy changes were
even more sudden, with legislation passed in 1978 to close down all mental
hospitals. In Britain after a slow decline in inpatients from the mid-1950s,
Mental disorder and human rights 221
a growing number of mental hospitals were closed from the 1980s
onwards.
A number of factors underpinned the development of community care,
including changing welfare regimes, the undermining of the pro-institutional
ideologies on which the asylum system had been founded, as well as belief in
the value of new drug treatments to control symptoms. However, instead of
the deinstitutionalisation envisaged by community care policies there has
frequently been a process of ‘trans-institutionalisation’, with those who
might formerly have stayed in mental hospitals ending up in nursing homes,
old people’s homes, secure units for patients considered dangerous and even
prisons. Significantly, much of this residential provision, where it exists, is
now increasingly owned and administered by the private sector rather than
the state. In the case of old people’s homes and nursing homes, legal powers
of detention may not be involved, but admission may be constrained by the
lack of alternative provision and residents may be subject to treatment
regimes that are in practice difficult to contest. In the case of secure units or
prisons, compulsory detention is involved and the individual’s rights are
curtailed, not only the right to liberty but also frequently the right to vote.
Not surprisingly, as the number of psychiatric beds has declined the propor-
tion detained on a compulsory basis has increased and frequently there has
been a shift to a higher proportion of male inmates.17 Moreover, even where
a patient is not compulsorily detained they may be subject to compulsory
treatment in the community. This is currently possible, for instance, in some
US states and in Australia and is under discussion in Britain.
There is also evidence that mental hospitals have been closed down with-
out adequate provision of alternative services, with the consequence that
those with severe mental health problems have faced neglect and some have
ended up on the streets (Dear and Wolch, 1987; Knowles, 2000). This
raises the wider issue of the extent to which those with mental health prob-
lems have adequate access to care and support in dealing with their prob-
lems. This, of course, is a matter of the social rights of those with such
problems, not their civil or political rights. There is considerable evidence
that such rights have been neglected and that there have often been
inadequate services (mental health services are frequently the Cinderella
services within welfare provision). One aspect of this neglect is the heavy
reliance on psychiatric drugs to deal with mental health problems and
the absence of much in the way of alternatives – for instance, psychotherapy
or various forms of social support. This absence is an especial problem
given that many psychiatric problems have their underlying causes in the
conditions and circumstances people face in their everyday lives.
In this context it is important to note that mental health problems are not
evenly distributed across the population but vary according to social class,
ethnicity and gender. Numerous studies have shown, for instance, a clear
link between social class (measured in various ways) and mental ill-health in
a wide range of societies (see, for instance, Hollingshead and Redlich, 1958;
Robins and Regier, 1991; Meltzer et al., 1995), and it is interesting that the
222 The clash of rights
links with social class even apply to forms of cognitive brain impairment
such as Alzheimer’s disease (Evans et al., 2003). Studies also show that these
associations are typically the product of psycho-social processes, including
the uneven distribution of long-term difficulties, adverse situations and
personal circumstances (see, for instance, the classic study by Brown and
Harris, 1978) – a point recognised in the reference in UN article 25 (1) to the
right to a standard of living adequate for health and well-being.18
We also need to note that the infringement of other human rights, such as
the right not to be ‘subject to torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading
treatment or punishment’ (UN Declaration: article 5), is usually highly
traumatic for the individual and can generate severe psychological prob-
lems. Although not specifically mentioned in article 5, sexual violence and
abuse, such as rape, is one form of infringement of an individual’s rights that
needs to be included in any listing of inhuman and degrading treatment.
There is now, for instance, a wide range of evidence of the adverse impact of
child sexual abuse, which may be long term (Browne and Finkelhor, 1986;
Beitchman et al., 1992). Significantly, the impact of extreme events on psy-
chological health is recognised through older illness categories such as shell-
shock, as well as newer ones such as post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD),
although the range of mental disorders generated by traumas like these is far
wider.19
Such issues return us to Marshall’s and Lockwood’s interest in the inter-
section of citizenship and social stratification. On the one hand, individuals
with severe mental disorder may face a loss of rights, especially if they need
residential treatment. On the other hand, their disorder may itself be partly
generated or sustained by the denial of moral and material resources for
adequate conditions of living or by inhuman and degrading treatment, as
well as lack of adequate and appropriate mental health services. In that
respect those with severe mental health problems can face a dual disadvan-
tage: adverse circumstances may underpin their mental disorder and then, as
a result of their disorder, they may be denied specific human rights.
Conclusion
Individuals with severe mental health problems have long faced poor treat-
ment, have often been confined on the grounds of public protection and have
usually been excluded from the human rights that most other groups have
gradually acquired. Irrationality and unreason, which have been at the heart
of lay and professional judgements of madness and severe mental disorder,
have been seen as denying full humanity to the individual and have legiti-
mated the denial of well-established rights. Instead, those with severe mental
disorders have frequently been stigmatised, marginalised and treated as
social outcasts and subject to discrimination.
To some extent the wider acquisition of human rights in Western societies
has over time helped to improve the rights of those with severe disorders.
Mental disorder and human rights 223
Their powers to contest detention and to challenge extreme forms of treat-
ment have been enhanced, and some have been allowed the right to vote.
Overall, however, services for those with mental health problems have often
been neglected and their social rights downplayed. Moreover, severe mental
health problems may themselves result from the infringement of human
rights. While human rights are supposedly universal rights, in practice this is
often not the case, and those with severe mental disorder all too frequently
face exclusion from many human rights prior to, and during, their disorder.
Notes
1 R. D. Laing (1967) sought to argue that although the behaviour of individuals
might be judged irrational, in fact it was intelligible if the situation was carefully
examined from the point of the individual concerned.
2 Discussing the concept of psychosis, the DSM-IV comments ‘Finally, the term
has been defined conceptually as a loss of ego boundaries or a gross impairment
in reality testing’ (American Psychiatric Association, 1994: 273).
3 The term mental disease is an older one; it is linked with the earliest involvement
of doctors and can be traced back to ancient Greece.
4 While the term mopish is now more or less archaic we do still use the verb to
mope and talk of people ‘moping’ and ‘moping around’.
5 It is possible to argue, however, that some irrationality is still involved (see
Busfield, 1996: 69–75).
6 In Britain the formal change was made in the 1930 Mental Treatment Act.
7 Lay understandings already incorporated a wide range of ‘psychological’
problems, such as being ‘troubled in mind’, which was clearly differentiated
from madness.
8 Along with the International Classification of Diseases’ section on mental
disorders, this is a very widely used official psychiatric classification.
9 The problem with this argument is that ‘normal’ reactions can still be
dysfunctional.
10 It is interesting that this lecture followed the year after the 1948 publication of
the UN Universal Declaration of Human Rights.
11 William Cullen, First Lines in the Practice of Physic, 4th edn, 1784 (Hunter and
MacAlpine, 1963: 473–8).
12 In fact many of those admitted were discharged relatively quickly.
13 Daniel Defoe, writing in 1728, attacked private madhouses because of the
dangers of wrongful detention (Hunter and MacAlpine, 1963: 266–7).
14 Dangerousness is not a criterion for compulsory detention in all European coun-
tries (European Commission, 2002)
15 In Britain the National Association for Mental Health (later MIND) was formed
in 1946 (Crossley, 1998).
16 He later used the phrase ‘a crime against humanity’ (Szasz, 1970).
17 This is partly linked to issues around dangerousness, which more typically
involve men, but also because of the use of such units for those with severe
problems with alcohol or drugs.
18 Biological factors play a part in the causal mechanisms linking psycho-social
stress and mental disorder, and part of the dispute about biological and
psycho-social explanations of mental disorder is about what counts as an
adequate causal account.
19 The presence of PTSD in current psychiatric classifications is significant, given
the explicit desire to eschew aetiological assumptions in these classifications.
12 Free to speak, free to hate?
Paul Iganski
The fact that racial crime is being taken so seriously may assist in
rebuilding confidence in the criminal justice system on the part of mem-
bers of ethnic minority communities. However, the extent to which that
is achieved will also depend heavily on how those involved in the crim-
inal justice system implement and respond to the spirit and intention of
the legislation, and are seen to take it seriously.
(Iganski, 1999: 391)
lack of protection that is afforded to the Muslim community per se. The
lack of legislation protecting followers of multi-ethnic faiths such as
Islam and the failure to outlaw incitement to religious hatred exposes one
of the most vulnerable and marginalized minorities in the UK to further
harm and contributes to the ensemble of factors that lead many to
conclude that Muslims are discriminated and victimized by the current
spate of anti-terror measures. Our democracy is deficient for its want of
protection for a minority actively discriminated against and mainstream
legislation is clearly its proper place . . . it is important that all minorities
are equally protected, not least the one that is most disaffected.
I don’t doubt the sincerity of those who are seeking this legislation but I
do question the government’s enthusiasm for it so close to a General
Election, an enthusiasm that must be rooted in their belief that this
measure could help their cause in some marginal constituencies with
large religious populations, many of whom are critical of the govern-
ment’s prosecution of the war in Iraq. It seems a shame we have to be
robbed permanently of one of the pillars of freedom of expression
because it’s needed temporarily to shore up a wobbling edifice elsewhere.
I question also the ease with which the existing race hatred legislation is
going to be extended simply by the scoring out of the word ‘racial’ and
the insertion of ‘racial or religious hatred’ as if race and religion are very
similar ideas and we can just bundle them together in one big lump.
When it seems clear to me and to most people that race and religion are
fundamentally different concepts, requiring completely different treat-
ment under the law. To criticise people for their race is manifestly
irrational but to criticise their religion, that is a right. That is a freedom.
The freedom to criticise ideas – any ideas – even if they are sincerely held
Free to speak, free to hate? 237
beliefs – is one of the fundamental freedoms of society and a law which
attempts to say you can criticise or ridicule ideas as long as they are not
religious ideas is a very peculiar law indeed. It promotes the idea that
there should be a right not to be offended, when in my view, the right to
offend is far more important than any right not to be offended, simply
because one represents openness, the other represents oppression.
Concerns that criticism and ridicule of a religion will fall foul of the new
provisions against incitement to religious hatred were fuelled by some
advocates of the new law, who were indeed expecting it to provide blanket
protection against those who are offensive or rude about Islam.11 However,
such expectations, and also the concerns about the law eroding rights to
freedom of expression, are unfounded once the application of the provisions
against incitement to racial hatred are appreciated, as discussed above. The
new provisions against incitement to religious hatred will be subject to simi-
lar constraints and applied to only the most egregious expressions that
threaten public order.
Notes
1 The prevalence and characteristics of Holocaust denial in Western Europe and
the USA have been well documented (see Seidel, 1986; Lipstadt, 1994; Shermer
and Grobman, 2000). Before the defeat of the Third Reich, denials of atrocities
committed were heard well before the genocide had reached its full conclusion.
Some Nazi sympathisers outside Germany dismissed claims of atrocities as
‘mostly Jew invention’ (Aronsfeld, 1979). In the years immediately following the
Second World War, in the early 1950s, neo-Nazis in Germany claimed that ‘the
fairy tale of the six million’ had been invented by the Allies to divert attention
away from the atrocities they had committed. The view was also propagated that
the atrocities against Jews were carried out secretly by fanatics – in one variant of
this claim, under special orders from Himmler – ‘behind the back of the German
people, German soldiers, even behind the back of the National Socialists and the
hundreds of thousands of SS men fighting on all fronts’ (Aronsfeld, 1979). Hitler,
it was claimed, was unaware of their activities. Doubts were cast on the number
of Jews murdered. It was even claimed that Zionists – who had allegedly infil-
trated the German authorities – were involved in orchestrating the genocide.
Variants of all these claims persist within Holocaust denial material today. In the
late 1960s and in the 1970s a number of publications were distributed that have
since become seminal works of Holocaust denial. Today, a number of them can
be read on the Internet by following links from the websites of extreme right
groups. The material published during this period is characterised by a pseudo-
scholarly guise in their presentation and referencing of sources. But they are also
characterised by distortion and falsification of the sources used. In his publica-
tion Die Auschwitz Luge (1973), Thies Christophersen claimed that Auschwitz
was just a gigantic armanents factory. Richard Harwood, in his publication Did
Six Million Really Die?, claimed that the ‘myth’ ‘that no less than six million
Jews were exterminated’ was designed to ‘arouse sympathy’ for the state of Israel
and to extract financial reparation from Germany. Harwood drew extensively
from an earlier booklet, The Myth of the Six Million, published anonymously in
the United States in 1969. The pseudo-scholarly guise of Holocaust deniers is
epitomised by the Institute for Historical Review – established in the United
States in the late 1970s – and its journal, the Journal of Historical Review, which
have provided the core of the more contemporary Holocaust denial movement
(Stern, 1995). The ‘Institute’ believes that dissemination of its material is pro-
tected under the First Amendment to the United States Constitution, and by
article 19 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights.
2 Early day motion no. 99, ‘David Irving and Holocaust denial’, House of
Commons, 20 June 1989, Session 1988–9.
3 In outlawing ‘incitement to racial hatred’ in the UK the Public Order Act 1986
makes it an offence for a person to publish or distribute ‘written matter which is
threatening, abusive or insulting’ or use ‘in any public place or at any public
Free to speak, free to hate? 239
meeting words which are threatening, abusive or insulting’ with an intent to
stir up racial hatred or, alternatively, ‘in a case where having regard to all the
circumstances, hatred is likely to be stirred up against any racial group in Great
Britain by the matter or the words in question’ (Public Order Act 1986, Part III,
Section 18).
4 UK House of Commons 1997, Standing Committee C, Holocaust Denial Bill,
col. 22.
5 UK 1975, Cmnd 6234, Racial Discrimination, para. 125.
6 UK Home Office, Scottish Office 1985, Cmnd 9510, Review of Public Order
Law, London: HMSO.
7 UK House of Commons 1997, Standing Committee C, Holocaust Denial Bill,
cols 8–9.
8 David Irving, Introduction to the Leuchter Report (www.fpp.co.uk/Auschwitz/
Leuchter/ReportIntro.html), accessed 5 December 2005. The full section from
which this quote has been drawn reads: ‘Nobody likes to be swindled, still less
where considerable sums of money are involved. (Since 1949 the State of Israel
has received over 90 billion Deutschmarks in voluntary reparations from West
Germany, essentially in atonement for the “gas chambers of Auschwitz”.) And
this myth will not die easily: Too many hundreds of millions of honest, intelligent
people have been duped by the well-financed and brilliantly successful post-war
publicity campaign which followed on from the original ingenious plan of the
British Psychological Warfare Executive (PWE) in 1942 to spread to the propa-
ganda story that the Germans were using “gas chambers” to kill millions of Jews
and other “undesirables”. As late as August 1943 the head of the PWE minuted
the Cabinet secretly that despite the stories they were putting out, there was not
the slightest evidence that such contraptions existed, and he continued with a
warning that stories from Jewish sources in this connection were particularly
suspect.’
9 Mick Hume in the online magazine Spiked 19 July 2005 argued: ‘every govern-
ment minister or official spokesman has emphasised their commitment to defend
“tolerance” – which, in the Newspeak of New Labour, means that they will not
tolerate anything that they deem to be intolerant of Islam or Muslims.’
10 Rowan Atkinson speaks to the Lords, 25 January 2005 (www.secularism.org.
uk/31964.html), accessed 5 December 2005.
11 In evidence to the House of Commons Home Affairs Committee, Session 2004–5,
the Director of Public Prosecutions stated: ‘I think the main issue around that is
managing expectations. . . . One of the dangers around incitement to religious
hatred is that communities – and indeed representatives of the Muslim com-
munities have said this to me – believe somehow this is going to protect them
from people being offensive or rude about Islam. It is not going to do that. You
are perfectly free to be offensive or rude about any religion, there is no law
against it. The danger is that if people think it is going to protect them from that
and it does not they feel very let down by us, by the police, by the Government
and by everybody else, and we get accused of being racist or incompetent, or a
combination of the two, when in fact we are just applying the law. So it is very
important that people understand what that offence will achieve: it will stop the
grossest sort of conduct, but it is not going to stop people being rude about
Islam.’ See also the memorandum submitted by the National Secular Society
(House of Commons Home Affairs Committee, Session 2004–5, House of
Commons Paper No. 165, Memorandum 29).
A foundation for rights or
theories of practice?
Lydia Morris
Classical themes
Sociology has something to offer on each of these analytical levels, as we
discover from the material reviewed in the introduction, and from the struc-
turing of the chapters that followed. In what remains of this conclusion, I
first identify the key themes and issues that emerged from the introduction
and the way in which they have been engaged or advanced by the various
chapters, before briefly reviewing the four different parts, or approaches,
into which the contributions to the volume have been grouped. As we saw, a
consideration of classical works yielded several contrasting but not necessar-
ily mutually exclusive perspectives on the issue of rights, from which a num-
ber of substantive themes emerge. My focus now is less on these perspectives
per se, but more on their scope for application to the study of rights,
especially as taken up in the various contributions to this volume.
We have seen that Durkheim was principally interested in the bases of
social cohesion, especially under conditions of fragmentation and anomie.
Although an adherent of moral individualism, he also stressed the role of
beliefs in providing a foundation both for identity and for a communal bond
between members of society. He offered a view of rights as social facts, in
the gift of society but representing a recognition and sanctification of human
potential. This potential he thought best realised through the freedoms and
protections of liberalism, but in the context of a communion with others.
Chapter 1 takes up these issues to argue that no fully human life is possible
without some connection with the life of society and the meaning that this
provides, and here we have a view of the individual situated within a system
of beliefs and values that gives meaning to their social relations and inter-
actions. For Benton, a reasonable expectation of a system of rights is that it
should acknowledge and enable this interconnectedness. Similar ideas are
explored in Chapter 7, through a view of rights as rooted in society, its
values and institutions, while ideas about the meaning of commonality
and the way in which it might structure our thinking about rights are also
present in Chapters 2 and 3, which respectively consider pensions rights and
the right to care as being variously embedded in the pattern of both familial
and societal responsibilities across the generations.
The introduction shows how Weber, like Durkheim, was interested in
the disenchantment of modern life, which he argued to result from an
unremitting drive towards rationality. This process was, in part, built on the
efficient administration of state and society through the elaboration of law
and bureaucracy, yielding a set of rationally objective rules and procedures
for governing and regulating individuals. For Weber, this is the context in
which a regime of rights must operate, and he gives us a key to understand-
ing how such a system may also be bound up with the struggle for power
246 A foundation for rights or theories of practice?
and resources, shaped by techniques of social closure. These struggles are
manifest in what Lockwood (1996) terms a system of civic stratification,
illustrated in Chapter 4 through a discussion of welfare, immigration and
asylum, while Chapter 5 shows how women’s claim to full human rights
was built explicitly on a claim to equal status, which was also in part a claim
for resources. This approach is also apparent, though less central, in the
account of the struggle for gay rights in Chapter 8 and the discussion of
indigenous rights in Chapter 9, both of which document struggles for status
and recognition. Chapter 6 discusses the importance of advocacy coalitions
in the pursuit of rights, but shows how this may also involve a collision or
compromise over strategy and competition over resources.
In Marx’s work we have a view of rights as functioning in service to the
economic system and the ruling powers of capitalism, and a critique of any
conception of rights based on self-sufficient and egoistic individuals, whose
social existence is premised on personal autonomy and the right to property,
without regard for other social bonds. However, Chapter 1 offers an
account of Marx’s position that differs from some of his critics, noting in
particular that civil and political rights could be the basis for actions that
challenge the status quo, in the name of human emancipation. The argument
opens up further debate about the possible future of rights once such liber-
ation has been achieved, and this Benton believes must be rooted in social
belonging, embodiment and environmental integrity. Such a ‘systems’ based
approach to rights is also present in different ways in Chapter 2, which
considers pension rights in the context not only of intergenerational justice,
but also the tension between public and private schemes, and the different
questions of responsibility and liability each raises. Chapter 3 adopts a
related approach in considering the culturally variable patterns of exchange,
reciprocity and obligation that underpin different systems of care.
I include in this section on classical themes the work of T. H. Marshall
(1950), as the first sociologist to place the issue of rights at the centre of
analysis. His essay on citizenship and social class is informed by some of the
ideas discussed above, and indeed places the tension between citizenship and
capitalism at its core. The work is also a recognition of the significance of
status in modern capitalist society, and considers rights as a possible source
of social cohesion and integration, while also being a potential source of
inequality. A number of chapters in this collection take Marshall’s work as a
starting point for their own discussion. Chapter 4 sees in Marshall a devel-
opment of the Weberian tradition through a status based approach to rights,
which considers both formal standing and informal prestige factors in the
struggle for recognition and resources. Chapter 8 also considers the way in
which a Marshallian model of citizenship has underpinned some of the
claims of the gay and lesbian movement, while Chapter 11 uses Marshall’s
analysis to consider the linkages between mental disorder and human rights,
making the point that his argument is more complex than critics have
recognised, especially his recognition of rights as a terrain of struggle.
A foundation for rights or theories of practice? 247
Particularism versus universalism
Struggle and movement have been at the centre of much critical comment on
Marshall, and this is the area from which the more recent work on the
dynamic nature of rights has emerged. The most trenchant criticisms hinge
on the universalist/particularist opposition and stem from an argument that
the rights guaranteed by citizenship, and even more so by universal human
rights, elevate a particularist model of social life to the level of the universal.
This argument has been adopted in relation to the exclusion of a variety of
specific groups from entitlement to the full range of rights, and each in its
turn has fuelled a related social movement for establishing a claim to
the rights at issue. Many of these critiques are expressed as critiques of
Marshallian citizenship, and while some may envisage universal human
rights as a solution, often the same criticisms will also have a salience at that
level.
For example, the feminist critique of Marshall (e.g. Phillips, 1992; Lister,
1997) notes his neglect of the gendered assumptions structuring citizenship.
As a status of the public sphere, citizenship is argued to ignore the public/
private divisions that inform the concept of rights, and that systematically
disadvantage women. Feminism has therefore entailed a claim to sameness
(that is, to be treated as equal to men) and a claim to be different (that is, to
have their particularity recognised and accommodated). These arguments,
and some of their attendant difficulties, are addressed in Chapter 5, which
documents the struggle of the women’s movement for full recognition on the
international stage, demonstrating the way in which dilemmas generated at
the level of citizenship may be writ large at the level of human rights. The
feminist movement itself, however, has generated its own particularities, as
Elson makes clear, and has led to the charge that the concerns of black and
‘Third World’ women have been submerged in the agendas of ‘First World’
feminism. Arguments such as these have fuelled the deconstructive strand
of feminism (Nash, 2002), which seeks to challenge all classification and
categorisation that tends to essentialism.
We noted in the introduction that the feminist critique of ‘false universals’
is closely associated with an interest in the embodiment of rights, which
emphasises the lived experience of difference, and hence applies not only to
gender difference but to sexuality, race, ethnicity, disability and age. Each of
these sources of difference can lead to demands that are perhaps best seen in
terms of claims for particularist inclusions, or Lister’s differentiated univer-
salism, which seeks an incorporation of these varied perspectives in the
granting and delivery of rights. Chapter 8 provides an example by means of
a narrative of the gay rights movement, revealing the sameness/difference
dilemma in another guise. Part of the movement may seek the right to be the
same as the heterosexual population: to marry, found families and claim the
recognition and entitlements that accompany this. Others seek the right to
be different: to establish a way of living that does not approximate to the
248 A foundation for rights or theories of practice?
recognised patterns of conventional intimate life, a claim that is closely
associated with ‘queer theory’. In Chapter 6 we see how the sameness/
difference dilemma arises again in the context of anti-racism, and in
Chapter 12 we find a discussion of the clash between a universal right to
free expression and particular needs for protection.
Some particularist positions have criticised the neglect of cultural rights in
Marshallian notions of citizenship, and also at the level of universal human
rights more generally. Their arguments are rooted in a communitarian cri-
tique of liberalism, apparent in Chapter 1, and also informing the arguments
of Chapter 7. The former, as we have seen, challenges the construction of
rights around a model of the isolated and autonomous individual, conceived
as unencumbered and unsupported by intimate social relations. The latter
attempts an interpretation of moral dilemmas in their social and cultural
context, to illustrate the socially embedded nature of rights and consider
the alternative expressions of morality within which they may operate.
Chapter 9 considers the case of indigenous rights, to illustrate the ethno-
centric assumptions of universalist frameworks of rights that deny the legit-
imacy of indigenous systems and offer compensation in the context of a
citizenship and sovereignty they do not recognise.
An associated criticism of Marshallian citizenship challenges the taken-
for-granted status of the nation state in his conception of rights; his failure to
deal with national boundary drawing and the position of non-citizens.
Chapter 4 considers this issue, weighing the arguments that see citizenship
as a form of social closure against the view that national citizenship has been
superseded by universal personhood. The chapter seeks a path between the
two positions by using the notion of civic stratification to illustrate the way
in which rights can be a means of constructing inequalities. The debate is,
however, indicative of a more general tendency to look to the development
of transnational institutions for the assertion and protection of rights, as
discussed in Chapters 5 and 6. In particular, there has been a tendency to
expand Marshallian conceptions of national citizenship to embrace the uni-
versal (e.g. Parry, 1991; Soysal, 1994; Meyer et al., 1997), though this pos-
ition is also open to criticism, by virtue of the limited purchase of many
human rights guarantees, and the danger of continuing the evolutionary
mind-set for which Marshall has been (somewhat unfairly) criticised.
There is one other treatment of particularism considered in this volume
and noted in the introduction, which has classically drawn on Foucauldian
discourse analysis of the construction and management of marginal groups
such as prisoners, the mad and homosexuals. Foucault’s work provides a
conception of disciplinary discourse and regimes of power that might appear
as the converse of rights, but that can often function through their adminis-
tration and implementation (Woodiwiss, 2005). He also emphasises the
force of subjugated knowledges, awakened by the application of disciplinary
discourses to challenge the power and authority they embody. This work is
drawn on by Chapter 11, which discusses the tradition of denying rights to
A foundation for rights or theories of practice? 249
those held in detention for mental disorder, before documenting the process
that led to a change in this tradition, in part through changed conceptions of
‘madness’. Chapter 10 similarly considers the denial of prisoners’ rights,
but moves on to engage with a ‘justice of alterity’, which asserts the rights
of those for whom there is no empathy, and to document the slow but
significant recognition of prisoners’ claims to human rights.
In many cases, the particularist positions reported in this volume seem to
stake a claim for recognition in terms of equal status and worth, but not
necessarily in terms of the conventions of established rights. We are thus
faced with the question of how to respond to scepticism about claims to
universalism, and whether proliferation of diversity and increasing fragmen-
tation is the inevitable outcome. As we noted above, the implementation of
rights and adjudication of claims will almost always involve an element of
interpretation, and a central issue here is the use of ‘rights talk’: the way in
which a particularist claim is expressed, perhaps in a manner translatable
into universalist guarantees, albeit in revised form. These claims often pro-
vide the momentum that fuels changes in the law and in conceptions of
rights, as referred to in earlier discussion. We have already noted another
element of interpretation that could be brought into play in the assertion and
understanding of rights: that of the broader context of structures, values and
relationships in which people live their lives. A truly enabling system of
rights would build these considerations into its design and implementation,
and sociological analysis can help to provide the background understanding
that might make this possible.
Adam, B., Duyvendak, J. W. and Krouwel, A. (eds) (1998) The Global Emergence of
Gay and Lesbian Politics. Phildelphia: Temple University Press.
Adams, D. W. (1995) Education for Extinction: American Indians and the Boarding
School Experience, 1875–1928. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.
Adelmann, L. and Moorshead, P. (1995) Bad laws make hard cases: hate crime laws
and the Supreme Court’s opinion in Wisconsin v. Mitchell. Gonzaga Law Review,
30: 1–27.
Albrow, M. (1996) The Global Age. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Alfred, T. (1999) Peace, Power, Righteousness: An Indigenous Manifesto. Don
Mills, Ontario: Oxford University Press.
Alink, F., Boin, A. et al. (2001) Institutional crises and reforms in policy sectors:
the case of asylum policy in Europe. Journal of European Public Policy, 8:
286–306.
Altman, D. (1997) Global gays/global gaze. Gay and Lesbian Quarterly, 3:
417–36.
Altman, D. (2001) Global Sex. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
American Psychiatric Association (1994) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of
Mental Disorders, 4th edn. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.
Anaya, S. J. (1996) Indigenous Peoples in International Law. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Anthias, F. and Yuval-Davis, N. (1992) Racialised Boundaries. London: Routledge.
Aoyama, K. (2005) Becoming someone else: Thai sex workers from modernization
to globalization. PhD thesis, University of Essex.
Arendt, H. (1973) The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt and Brace.
Ariès, P. (1979) Centuries of Childhood. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Aronsfeld, C. C. (1979) After the Murders – the Lies. Denials of the Holocaust.
London: Institute for Jewish Affairs.
Assembly of First Nations (1994) Breaking the Silence: An Interpretive Study of
Residential School Impact and Healing as Illustrated by the Stories of First Nation
Individuals. Ottawa: Assembly of First Nations.
Assies, W. (1998) Indigenous peoples and reform of the state in Latin America. In
W. Assies, G. van der Haar and A. Hoekema (eds), The Challenge of Diversity:
Indigenous Peoples and Reform of the State in Latin America. Amsterdam: Thela
Thesis.
Atkinson, P. and Housley, W. (2003) Interactionism: An Essay in Sociological
Amnesia. London: Sage.
254 Bibliography
Australian Bureau of Statistics (2002) Australian Social Trends 2002. Health –
Mortality and Morbidity: Mortality of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander
Peoples. Canberra: AGPS.
Aye Maung, C. and Mirrlees-Black, C. (1994) Racially Motivated Crime: A British
Crime Survey Analysis. London: Home Office.
Badiou, A. (2002) Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil. London: Verso.
Baird, V. (2001) No Nonsense Guide to Sexual Diversity. London: New
Internationalist.
Baird, V. (2004) Sex, Love and Homophobia. London: Amnesty International.
Baker, D. and Wiesbrot, M. (2000) Social Security. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Bal, P. (1996) Discourse ethics and human rights in criminal procedure. In M. Deflem
(ed.), Habermas, Modernity and the Law. London: Sage.
Bane, M. J. (1988) Politics and policies of the feminization of poverty. In M. Weir,
A. S. Orloff and T. Skocpol (eds), The Politics of Social Policy in the United States.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Barbalet, J. M. (1988) Citizenship. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Barry, B. (1989) A Treatise on Social Justice. Volume 1, Theories of Justice. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Barton, R. (1959) Institutional Neurosis. Bristol: John Wright.
Bauman, Z. (1993) Postmodern Ethics. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bauman, Z. (1995) Life in Fragments: Towards a Postmodern Morality. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Baxi, U. (2002) The Future of Human Rights. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Bechhofer, F. (1996) Comment on Lockwood. British Journal of Sociology, 47:
551–5.
Beck, U. (1992) Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: Sage.
Beck, U. and Beck-Gernsheim, E. (2002) Individualisation: Institutionalized Indi-
vidualism and Its Social and Political Consequences. London: Sage.
Beger, Nico J. (2004) Tensions in the Struggle for Sexual Minority Rights in Europe:
Que(e)rying Political Practices. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Beiner, R. (ed.) (1995) Theorising Citizenship. Albany: State University of New York
Press.
Beitchman, J. H., Zucker, K. J., Hood, J. E., Dacosta, G. A., Ackman, D. and
Cassavia, E. (1992) A review of the long-term effects of child sexual abuse. Child
Abuse and Neglect, 16: 101–18.
Bell, D. (1993) Communitarianism and Its Critics. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Bell, D. and Binnie, J. (2000) The Sexual Citizen: Queer Politics and Beyond.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bellah, R., Madsen, R., Sullivan, W. M., Swidler, A. and Tipton, S. (1985) Habits of
the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
Bellamy, R. (1999) Liberalism and Pluralism: Towards a Politics of Compromise.
London: Routledge.
Benhabib, S. (1992) Situating the Self. London: Routledge.
Benton, T. (1993) Natural Relations: Ecology, Animal Rights and Social Justice.
London: Verso.
Ben-Tovim, G. (1997) Why ‘positive action’ is ‘politically correct’. In T. Modood and
Bibliography 255
P. Werbner (eds), The Politics of Multiculturalism in the New Europe: Racism,
Identity and Community. London: Zed Books.
Berger, P. and Luckmann, T. L. (1967) The Social Construction of Reality.
Harmondsworth: Allen Lane.
Bernstein, R. J. (1986) Philosophical Profiles: Essays in a Pragmatic Mode.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Berridge, V. (1996) AIDS in the UK: The Making of Policy 1981–1994. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Best, J. (1990) Threatened Children: Rhetoric and Concern about Child Victims.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Best, J. (2001) How Claims Spread: Cross National Diffusion of Social Problems.
New York: de Gruyter.
Bhabha, J. (1996) Embodied rights. Public Culture, 9: 3–32.
Bhabha, J. and Shutter, S. (1994) Women’s Movement. Stoke-on-Trent: Trentham
Books.
Bidney, D. (1996) Theoretical Anthropology, 2nd edn. New Brunswick, NJ:
Transaction Books.
Binnie, J. (2004) The Globalization of Sex. London: Sage.
Bishop, R. and Robinson, L. (1998) Night Market: Sexual Cultures and the Thai
Economic Miracle. London: Routledge.
Blackburn, R. (2002) Banking on Death or Investing in Life: The History and Future
of Pensions. London: Verso.
Blackburn, R. (2003) Eurodenial. New Left Review, 18.
Blackburn, R. (2004a) The pension crisis and how to tackle it. Challenge: The
Magazine of Economic Affairs, July/August: 95–111.
Blackburn, R. (2004b) How to rescue a failing pension regime: the British case.
New Political Economy, December: 559–81.
Blair, T. (2000) Values and the power of community. Presentation to the Global
Ethics Foundation, Tübingen University, 30 June.
Bloch, A. and Schuster, L. (2002) Asylum and welfare: contemporary debates.
Critical Social Policy, 22: 392–414.
Blumer, H. (1969) Symbolic Interactionism: Perspective and Method. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Board of Deputies of British Jews (1992) Group Defamation. Report of a Working
Party of the Law, Parliamentary and General Purposes Committee. London:
Board of Deputies of British Jews.
Bobbio, N. (1995) The Age of Rights. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Boje, T. and Leira, A. (2000) Gender, Welfare State and Market: Towards a
New Division of Labour. London: Routledge.
Bolderson, H. and Roberts, S. (1995) New restrictions on benefits for migrants.
Benefits, January: 11–15.
Boli, J. and Thomas, G. M. (eds) (1999) Constructing World Culture: International
Nongovernmental Organizations since 1875. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Bonnett, A. (2000) Anti-Racism. London: Routledge.
Borradori, G. (2003) Deconstructing terrorism – Derrida. In G. Borradori (ed.),
Philosophy in a Time of Terror. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Boswell, J. (1995) The Marriage of Likeness: Same-Sex Unions in Pre-Modern
Europe. London: Fontana.
256 Bibliography
Bottomore, T. (1992) Citizenship and social class forty years on. In T. H. Marshall
and T. Bottomore, Citizenship and Social Class. London: Pluto Press.
Bourdieu, P. (1977) Outline of a Theory of Practice (trans. R. Nice). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Bourne, R. (2003) Invisible Lives: Indigenous Peoples in the Commonwealth.
London: Commonwealth Policy Studies Unit.
Bower, B. (1993) A Place at the Table. New York: Poseidon Press.
Bowling, B. and Phillips, C. (2002) Racism, Crime and Justice. Harlow: Longman.
Boyer, R. (1997) The variety and unequal performance of really existing markets:
farewell to Doctor Pangloss. In J. R. Hollingsworth and R. Boyer (eds), Con-
temporary Capitalism. The Embeddedness of Institutions. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Bright, M. (2003) Youth hit hardest by wave of new laws. Observer, 13 April: 9.
Bristow, J. (2000) Who’s afraid of Holocaust denial? LM Archives, 19 June
(www.informinc.co.uk/LM/LM97/LM97_Denial.htm).
Bristow, J. and Wilson, A. R. (eds) (1993) Activating Theory: Lesbians, Gay,
Bisexual Politics. London: Lawrence and Wishhart.
Brody, H. (1981) Maps and Dreams. New York: Pantheon.
Brown, G. and Harris, T. (1978) Social Origins of Depression. London: Tavistock.
Brown, P. (1985) The Transfer of Care: Psychiatric Deinstitutionalization and Its
Aftermath. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Browne, A. and Finkelhor, D. (1986) Impact of child sexual abuse: a review of
research. Psychological Bulletin, 99: 66–77.
Brubaker, W. R. (1989) Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and
America. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Bruce, T. (2001) The New Thought Police. New York: Three Rivers Press.
Bunch, C. (1990) Women’s rights as human rights: toward a re-vision of human
rights. Human Rights Quarterly, 12: 486–98.
Burchell, G., Gordon, C. and Miller, P. (eds) (1991) The Foucault Effect: Studies in
Governmentality. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Burger, A. and Dekker, P. (2001) The Nonprofit Sector in the Netherlands. Working
Document 70. The Hague: Social and Cultural Planning Office.
Busfield, J. (1986) Managing Madness: Changing Ideas and Practice. London:
Unwin Hyman.
Busfield, J. (1996) Men, Women and Madness: Understanding Gender and Mental
Disorder. London: Macmillan.
Busfield, J. (2002) The archaeology of psychiatric disorder. In G. Bendelow,
M. Carpenter, C. Vautier and S. William (eds), Gender, Health and Healing.
London: Routledge.
Buss, D. and Herman, D. (2003) Globalizing Family Values: The Christian Right in
International Politics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Butler, J. (1990) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity.
New York: Routledge.
Canadian Centre for Justice (2001) Aboriginal Peoples in Canada. Statistics Profile
Series. Ottawa: Statistics Canada.
Canadian Institute for Health Information (2004) Improving the Health of Canadi-
ans. Ottawa: Canadian Institute for Health Information.
Cantarella, E. (2001) Private revenge and public justice: the settlement of disputes in
Homer’s Iliad. Punishment and Society, 3: 473–83.
Bibliography 257
Caramagno, T. C. (2002) Irreconcilable Differences: Intellectual Statements in the
Gay Rights Debate. London: Greenwood.
Carlen, P. (1980) Radical criminology, penal politics and the rule of law. In P. Carlen
and M. Collison (eds), Radical Issues in Criminology. Oxford: Martin Robertson.
Carlen, P. (1990) Alternatives to Women’s Imprisonment. Buckingham: Open
University Press.
Carlen, P. (1998) Sledgehammer: Women’s Imprisonment at the Millennium. London:
Macmillan.
Carlen, P. (2002) Carceral clawback: the case of women’s imprisonment in Canada.
Punishment and Society, 4: 115–21.
Carrabine, E., Iganski, P., Lee, M., Plummer, K. and South, N. (2004) Criminology:
A Sociological Introduction. London: Routledge.
Chambers, S. (1996) Reasonable Democracy: Jürgen Habermas and the Politics of
Discourse. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Charlesworth, H. (1995) Human rights as men’s rights. In J. Peters and A. Wolper
(eds), Women’s Rights, Human Rights: International Feminist Perspectives.
New York: Routledge.
Cheal, D. (1988) The Gift Economy. London: Routledge.
Checkel, J. (1999) Norms, institutions and national identity in contemporary
Europe. International Studies Quarterly, March: 83–114.
Christophersen, T. (1973) Die Auschwitz-Luge. Mohrkirch: KritikVerlag.
Churchill, W. (1983) Introduction: journeying towards a debate. In W. Churchill
(ed.), Marxism and Native Americans. Boston: South End Press.
Churchill, W. (1999) The tragedy and the travesty: the subversion of indigenous
sovereignty in North America. In T. Johnson (ed.), Contemporary Native
American Political Issues. Walnut Creek, CA: Alta Mira Press.
Cladis, M. S. (1992) A Communitarian Defence of Liberalism: Emile Durkheim and
Contemporary Social Theory. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Cobo, J. M. (1987) Study of the Problem of Discrimination against Indigenous
Populations, Volume 5. UN doc. E/CN.4/Sub. 2/1986–7/Add. 4.
Cohen, I. (1989) Structuration Theory: Anthony Giddens and the Constitution of
Social Life. London: Macmillan.
Cohen, S. (1988) Against Criminology. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books.
Commission of the European Communities (1993) Legal Instruments to Combat
Racism and Xenophobia. Luxembourg: Office for Official Publications of the
European Communities.
Commonwealth Policy Studies Unit (2003) Recognising and Protecting Indigenous
Peoples’ Rights in the Commonwealth. Memorandum to the Commonwealth
Heads of Government attending the Commonwealth Heads of Government Meet-
ing (CHOGM) Abuja, Nigeria, 1–7 December. London: Commonwealth Policy
Studies Unit.
Cook, R. J. (1993) Women’s international human rights law: the way forward.
Human Rights Quarterly, 15: 230–61.
Cornell, D. (1992) The Philosophy of the Limit. New York: Routledge.
Cornell, D. (1995) What is ethical feminism? In S. Benhabib, J. Butler, D. Cornell and
N. Fraser, Feminist Contentions. London: Routledge.
Cornell, S. (1988) The Return of the Native: American Indian Political Resurgence.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Crisp, R. and Slote, M. (eds) (1997) Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
258 Bibliography
Critchley, S. (1999) The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas, 2nd edn.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Crossley, N. (1998) Transforming the mental health field: the early history of
the National Association for Mental Health. Sociology of Health and Illness, 20:
458–88.
Cruz, A. (1995) Shifting Responsibility. Stoke-on-Trent: Trentham Books.
D’Emilio, J. (1983) Sexual Politics, Sexual Communities. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Daly, K. (1989) Criminal justice ideologies and practices in different voices: some
feminist questions about justice. International Journal of the Sociology of Law,
17: 1–18.
Daly, M. (2002) Care as a good for social policy. Journal of Social Policy, 31:
251–70.
Daly, M. (2003) Governance and social policy. Journal of Social Policy, 32: 113–28.
Daly, M. and Lewis, J. (1999) Introduction: conceptualising social care in the
context of welfare state restructuring. In J. Lewis (ed.), Gender, Social Care and
Welfare State Restructuring in Europe. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Daly, M. and Lewis, J. (2000) The concept of social care and the analysis of
contemporary society. British Journal of Sociology, 51: 281–99.
Davidson, B. (1992), The Black Man’s Burden: Africa and the Curse of the Nation
State. New York: Times Books.
Davies, P., Hickson, F., Weatherburn, P. and Hunt, A. (1993) Sex, Gay Men and
AIDS. London: Falmer Press.
de Beauvoir, S. (1949) Le Deuxième Sexe. Paris: Gallimard.
Dean, H. (1998) Popular paradigms and welfare values. Critical Social Policy, 18:
131–56.
Dear, M. and Wolch, J. (1987) Landscapes of Despair. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Deloria, V. (1985) Behind the Trail of Broken Treaties: An Indian Declaration of
Independence. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Dent, J. A. (1998) Research Paper on the Social and Economic Rights of
Non-Nationals in Europe. London: ECRE.
Department of Social Security (1998) New Ambitions for Our Country: A New
Contract for Welfare, Cm 3805. London: HMSO.
Derrida, J. (1990) Force of law: the ‘mystical foundations of authority’. Cardozo
Law Review, 11: 919–1045.
Derrida, J. (1992) Force of law: the mystical foundations of authority. In D. Cornell,
M. Rosenfeld and D. G. Carlson (eds), Deconstruction and the Possibility of
Justice. London: Routledge.
Derrida, J. (1996) The Gift of Death. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Derrida, J. (2001) On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. London: Routledge.
Derrida, J. (2003) Autoimmunity: real and symbolic suicides. In G. Borradori (ed.),
Philosophy in a Time of Terror. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Devlin (1959) The Enforcement of Morals: The Second Maccabean Lecture to the
British Academy. London: Oxford University Press.
Dickens, R. (2001) Is welfare to work sustainable? Benefits, 34: 88–91.
DiMaggio, P. and Powell, W. (1991) The iron cage revisited: institutional isomorph-
ism and collective rationality. In P. DiMaggio and W. Powell (eds), The New
Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bibliography 259
Directorate General of Economic and Financial Affairs (2002) European Commis-
sion, Economic Paper 170, May. Brussels: EU.
Donnelly, J. (2003) Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.
Donnelly, M. (1983) Managing the Mind. London: Tavistock.
Dorr Legg, W. (ed.) (1994) Homophile Studies in Theory and Practice. San Francisco:
One Inc GLB Publications.
Douglas, L. (1988) Policing the past: Holocaust denial and the law. In R. C. Post
(ed.), Censorship and Silencing: Practices of Cultural Regulation. Los Angeles:
The Getty Research Institute for the History of Art and the Humanities.
Dryzek, J. (1996) Democracy in Capitalist Times: Ideals, Limits, and Struggles.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dryzek, J. (2000) Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contesta-
tions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Duff, R. (1996) Penal communications: recent work in the philosophy of
punishment. Crime and Justice: A Review of Research, 20: 1–97.
Duff, R. (2001) Punishment, Communication, and Community. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Duff, R. and Garland, D. (1994) Introduction: thinking about punishment. In
R. Duff and D. Garland (eds), A Reader on Punishment. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Durkheim, E. (1933) The Division of Labor in Society (trans. W. D. Hall). New
York: Free Press (first published 1893).
Durkheim, E. (1938) The Rules of Sociological Method. New York: Free Press (first
published 1895).
Durkheim, E. (1951) Suicide: A Study in Sociology (trans. J. Spaulding and
G. Simpson). Glencoe, IL: Free Press (first published 1897).
Durkheim, E. (1961) The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. London: Allen and
Unwin (first published 1912).
Durkheim, E. (1964) The Division of Labor in Society (trans. G. Simpson). Glencoe,
IL: Free Press.
Durkheim, E. (1974) The determination of moral facts. In Sociology and Philosophy.
New York: Free Press (first published in 1906).
Durkheim, E. (1975) Individualism and the intellectuals. In W. S. F. Pickering (ed.),
Durkheim on Religion. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul (first published 1898).
Dworkin, R. (1978) Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Dworkin, R. (1985) A Matter of Principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Edwards, S. (1984) Women on Trial. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Ehrenreich, B. and Hochschild, A. R. (eds) (2003) Global Woman: Nannies, Maids
and Sex Workers in the New Economy. London: Granta.
Ellison, N. (1997) Towards a new social politics: citizenship and reflexivity in late
modernity. Sociology, 31: 697–717.
Elson, D. (2002) Gender justice, human rights and neo-liberal economics. In
M. Molyneuz and S. Razavi (eds), Gender Justice, Development and Rights.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Elson, D. and Gideon, J. (2004) Organising for women’s economic and social rights:
how useful is the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural
Rights? Journal of Interdisciplinary Gender Studies, 8: 133–52.
260 Bibliography
England, C. (2004) A look at the Indian Health Service policy of sterilization,
1972–1976 (www.diskshovel.com/IHSSterPol.html).
Esping-Andersen, G. (1990) The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1999) Social Foundations of Postindustrial Economies.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Etzioni, A. (2000) The Third Way to a Good Society. London: Demos.
European Commission, Health and Consumer Protection Directorate-General
(2002) Compulsory Admission and Involuntary Treatment of Mentally Ill
Patients: Legislation and Practice in EU-Member States. Brussels: European
Commission.
European Parliament (2000) Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union.
Official Journal of the European Communities.
Evans, D. (1993) Sexual Citizenship. London: Routledge.
Evans, M. and Morgan, R. (1999) The CPT: an introduction. In R. Morgan and
M. Evans, Protecting Prisoners: The Standards of the European Committee for
the Prevention of Torture in Context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Evans, O., Singleton, N., Meltzer, H., Stewart, R. and Prince, M. (2003) The Mental
Health of Older People. London: The Stationery Office.
Ewijk, H. van, Hens, H. and Lammersen, G. (2002) Mapping of Care Services and
the Care Workforce. Consolidated Report. WP3 of Care Work in Europe Current
Understandings and Future Directions (www.ioe.ac.uk./tcru/carework.htm).
Farrelly, C. (2004) An Introduction to Contemporary Political Theory. London:
Sage.
Feldman, D. (2002) Civil Liberties and Human Rights in England and Wales,
2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Felice, W. F. (1996) Taking Suffering Seriously: The Importance of Collective Human
Rights. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Ferguson, J. (1990) The Anti-Politics Machine. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Ferreira, M. (ed.) (2005) Indigenous Peoples and Diabetes. Durham, NC: Carolina
Academic Press.
Field, F. (1989) Losing Out. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Finch, J. and Groves, D. (1983) Labour and Love: Women, Work and Caring.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Fink, J. (ed.) (2004) Care: Personal Lives and Social Policy. Bristol: Policy Press.
Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (1998) International norm dynamics and political
change. International Organization, 52: 887–917.
Flanagan, K. and Jupp, P. C. (2001) Virtue Ethics and Sociology: Issues of Modernity
and Religion. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Fligstein, N. (2001) The Architecture of Markets. An Economic Sociology of
Twenty-First Century Capitalist Societies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Flynn, D. (2004) Tough as Old Boots: Asylum, Immigration and the Paradox of
New Labour Policy. JCWI Discussion Paper. London: JCWI.
Ford, G. (1992) Fascist Europe: The Rise of Racism and Xenophobia. London:
Pluto Press.
Forero, J. (2004) In a land torn by violence, too many troubling deaths. New York
Times, 23 November.
Bibliography 261
Foucault, M. (1967) Madness and Civilisation. A History of Insanity in the Age of
Reason. London: Tavistock Publications.
Foucault, M. (1977) Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Harmonds-
worth: Penguin.
Fraser, A. (1999) Becoming human: the origins and development of women’s human
rights. Human Rights Quarterly, 21: 853–906.
Fraser, N. (1995) From redistribution to recognition? Dilemmas of justice in a
‘post-socialist’ age. New Left Review, 212: 68–93.
Fraser, N. (1997) Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the Post-Socialist
Condition. New York: Routledge.
Fraser, N. (2003) Social justice in the age of identity politics. In N. Fraser and
A. Honneth (eds), Redistribution or Recognition? London: Verso.
Freeden, M. (1996) Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Freeman, G. P. (1986) Migration and the political economy of the welfare state.
Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 485 (May): 51–63.
Freeman, G. P. (1995) Modes of immigration politics in liberal democratic states.
International Migration Review, 29: 881–902.
Freeman, M. (1995) Are there collective human rights? Political Studies, 43: 25.
Freeman, M. (2002) Human Rights: An Interdisciplinary Approach, Key Concepts.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Friedman, E. (1995) Women’s human rights: the emergence of a movement. In
J. Peters and A. Wolper (eds), Women’s Rights, Human Rights: International
Feminist Perspectives. New York: Routledge.
Fultz, E. (2004) Pension privatisation in Poland and Hungary. In G. Hughes and
J. Stewart (eds), Pension Reform in Europe. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Garland, D. (1990) Punishment and Modern Society: A Study in Social Theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gerth, H. H. and Wright Mills, C. (eds) (1948) From Max Weber: Essays in
Sociology. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Gey, S. G. (1997) What if Wisconsin v. Mitchell had involved Martin Luther
King Jnr? The constitutional flaws of hate crime enhancement statutes. George
Washington Law Review, 65: 1014–70.
Giddens, A. (1984) The Constitution of Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Giddens, A. (1985) The Nation State and Violence. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Giddens, A. (1990) The Consequences of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Giddens, A. (1991) Modernity and Self Identity. Cambridge: Polity.
Giddens, A. (1994) Beyond Left and Right. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Giddens, A. (1998) The Third Way. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Giddens, A. (2001) Sociology, 4th edn. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Gilbert, K. (1977) Living Black: Blacks Talk to Kevin Gilbert. Ringwood, Victoria:
Allen Lane.
Gilbert, K. (1994) Because a White Man’ll Never Do It, 4th edn. Sydney: Angus and
Robertson.
Gilbert, N. (2004) The Transformation of the Welfare State: The Silent Surrender of
Public Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gilligan, C. (1982) In a Different Voice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Gilroy, P. (1990) The end of anti-racism. In W. Ball and J. Solomos (eds), Race and
Local Politics. London: Macmillan.
262 Bibliography
Glennerster, H. (2003) Understanding the Finance of Welfare. Bristol: Policy Press.
Glucksmann, M. (2000) Cottons and Casuals: The Gendered Organisation of
Labour in Time and Space. Durham: Sociology Press.
Goffman, E. (1961) Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and
Other Inmates. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Graham, H. (1991) The concept of caring in feminist research: the case of domestic
service. Sociology, 25(1): 61–78.
Green, D. G. (1999) An End to Welfare Rights. London: Institute of Economic
Affairs.
Greenberg, D. (1988) The Construction of Homosexuality. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Greenberg, D. and Stender, F. (1972) The prison as a lawless agency. Buffalo Law
Review, 21: 799–839.
Guardian (2000) Ministers agree voucher review. Guardian, 28 September.
Guardian (2003) Judges saving asylum seekers from starvation. Guardian, 4
November.
Guardian (2004) Woolf leads judges’ attack on ministers. Guardian, 14 March.
Guardian (2005) Plans to overhaul incapacity benefit. Guardian, 27 January.
Guardian Weekly (2004) Extra 1000 places planned for asylum detention. Guardian
Weekly, 24 September.
Guiraudon, V. (1998) Citizenship rights for non-citizens: France, Germany and the
Netherlands. In C. Joppke (ed.), Challenge to the Nation State. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Gullette, M. M. (2003) Aged by Culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gupta, A. and Ferguson, J. (1997) Culture, power, place: ethnography at the end of
an era. In A. Gupta and J. Ferguson (eds), Culture, Power, Place: Explorations in
Critical Anthropology. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Gutierrez, M. and Palomo, N. (2000) A woman’s eye view of autonomy. In
A. Mayor (ed.), Indigenous Autonomy in Mexico. Copenhagen: International
Work Group for Indigenous Affairs.
Gutmann, A. (1992) Multiculturalism and the Politics of Recognition. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Habermas, J. (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 1. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Habermas, J. (1987a) The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 2. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Habermas, J. (1987b) The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Hacker, J. (2002) The Divided Welfare State: The Battle over Public and Private
Social Benefits in the United States. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haebich, A. (2001) Broken Circles: Fragmenting Indigenous Families 1800–2000.
Fremantle: Fremantle Arts Centre Press.
Hale, C. (1994) Resistance and Contradiction: Miskitu Indians and the Nicaraguan
State, 1894–1987. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Hale, S. (2004) Community by contract? Paper presented at the Political Studies
Association conference.
Halévy, E. (1955) The Growth of Philosophical Radicalism (trans. M. Morris).
Boston: Beacon Press.
Hall, S. (1979) The great moving right show. Marxism Today, January: 14–20.
Bibliography 263
Hall, S. (1980) Reformism and the legislation of consent. In National Deviancy
Conference (eds), Permissiveness and Control: The Fate of the Sixties Legislation.
London: Macmillan.
Hameso, S. (1997) Ethnicity and Nationalism in Africa. Commack, NY: Nova
Science Publishers.
Harrington Meyer, M. (ed.) (2000) Care Work: Gender, Class and the Welfare State.
New York: Routledge.
Hasenclever, A., Mayer, P. and Rittberger, V. (1997) Theories of International
Regimes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Healey, D. (1997) The Anti-Depressant Era. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Health Canada (2003) Statistical Profile on the Health of First Nations in Canada.
Ottawa: Health Canada.
Heidensohn, F. (1986) Models of justice: Portia or Persephone? Some thoughts on
equality, fairness and gender in the field of criminal justice. International Journal
of the Sociology of Law, 14: 287–98.
Heise, L. (1989) International dimensions of violence against women. Response,
12(1).
Herek, G. M., Gillis, J. R. and Cogan, J. C. (1999) Psychological sequelae of hate-
crime victimization among lesbian, gay, and bisexual adults. Journal of Consulting
and Clinical Psychology, 67: 945–51.
Heritage, J. (1984) Garfinkel and Ethnomethodology. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Hernandez Castillo, R. (1997) Between hope and adversity: the struggle of organized
women in Chiapas since the Zapatista rebellion. Journal of Latin American
Anthropology, 3: 102–20.
Hills, J. (2001) What rights? Whose responsibilities? In A. Park, J. Curtice,
K. Thomson, L. Jarvis and C. Bromley (eds), British Social Attitudes: The 18th
Report. London: Sage.
Hindley, J. (1996) Towards a pluricultural nation: the limits of indigenismo and
article 4. In R. Aitken et al. (eds), Dismantling the Mexican State. Basingstoke:
Macmillan.
Hobhouse, L. T. (1922) The Elements of Social Justice. London: George Allen and
Unwin.
Holden, K. (2001) Family, caring and unpaid work. In I. Zweiniger-Bargielowska
(ed.), Women in Twentieth Century Britain. Harlow: Longman.
Holden, K. (2004) Personal costs and personal pleasures: care and the unmarried
woman in interwar England. In J. Fink (ed.), Care: Personal Lives and Social
Policy. Bristol: Policy Press.
Hollifield, J. F. (1992) Immigrants Markets and States. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Hollingshead, A. B. and Redlich, F. C. (1958) Social Class and Mental Illness.
New York: John Wiley.
Home Office (2000) Statistics on Race and the Criminal Justice System, 2000.
London: Home Office Research, Development and Statistics Directorate.
Honneth, A. (1995) The other of justice: Habermas and the ethical challenge of
postmodernism. In S. White (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Habermas.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hooks, G. and Smith, C. (2004) The treadmill of destruction: national sacrifice areas
and Native Americans. American Sociological Review, 69(4): 558–75.
264 Bibliography
Horwitz, A. V. (2002) Creating Mental Illness. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
HREOC (1997) Bringing Them Home: Report of the National Inquiry into the
Separation of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Children from Their Families.
Canberra: AGPS.
Hudson, A. (2001) NGOs’ transnational advocacy networks: from ‘legitimacy’ to
‘political responsibility’? Global Networks, 1: 331–52.
Hudson, B. (1993) Penal Policy and Social Justice. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Hudson, B. (2001) Punishment, rights and difference: defending justice in the risk
society. In K. Stenson and R. Sullivan (eds), Crime, Risk and Justice: The Politics of
Crime Control in Liberal Democracies. Cullompton: Willan.
Hudson, B. (2003) Justice in the Risk Society. London: Sage.
Hughes, B., McKie, L., Hopkins, D. and Watson, N. (2005) Love’s labour lost?
Feminism, the disabled people’s movement and an ethic of care. Sociology, 39:
259–75.
Hughes, G. and Sinfield, A. (2004) Financing pensions by stealth. In G. Hughes and
J. Stewart (eds), Reforming Pensions in Europe. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Humphrey, C. and Sneath, D. (1999) The End of Nomadism? Society, State and the
Environment in Inner Asia. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Hunter, R. and MacAlpine, I. (eds) (1963) Three Hundred Years of Psychiatry,
1535–1860. Hartsdale, NY: Carlisle.
Hurd, H. (2001) Why liberals should hate ‘hate crime legislation’. Law and
Philosophy, 20: 215–32.
Ibhawoh, B. (1999) Between culture and constitution: evaluating the cultural
legitimacy of human rights in the African state. Paper presented to the Conference
on Reconstructing Human Rights: A Critical Project for the 21st Century?,
University of Sussex.
Iganski, P. (1999) Why make hate a crime? Critical Social Policy, 19: 385–94.
Iganski, P. (2001) Hate crimes hurt more. American Behavioral Scientist, 4: 626–38.
Ignatieff, M. (2000) The Rights Revolution. Toronto: House of Anansi Press.
Illich, I. (1975) The Limits to Medicine. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Inglehart, R. (1977) The Silent Revolution: Changing Values and Political Styles
among Western Publics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Inglehart, R. (1989) Cultural Change. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Inglehart, R. and Norris, P. (2003) Rising Tide: Gender Equality and Cultural
Change around the World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Institute for Jewish Policy Research (2000) Combating Holocaust Denial through
Law in the United Kingdom. London: Institute for Jewish Policy Research.
Irigaray, L. (1985) Speculum of the Other Woman. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Irwin, S. (1996) Age related distributive justice and claims on resources. British
Journal of Sociology, 47: 69–82.
Ishay, M. (ed.) (1997) The Human Rights Reader. New York: Routledge.
Ishay, M. (2004) The History of Human Rights. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Jacobs, J. B. and Potter, K. A. (1997) Hate crimes: a critical perspective. Crime and
Justice, 22: 1–50.
Jacobs, J. B. and Potter, K. A. (1998) Hate Crimes: Criminal Law and Identity
Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bibliography 265
Jacoby, J. (2002) Punish crime, not thought crime. In P. Iganski (ed.), The Hate
Debate. Should Hate Be Punished as a Crime? London: Profile.
Jaffe, A. J. (1992) The First Immigrants from Asia: A Population History of North
American Indians. New York: Plenum.
Janzen, L. (2004) Better housing a right, says First Nation. Winnipeg Free Press,
16 December: A5.
Jeffery-Poulter, S. (1991) Peers, Queers and Commons: The Struggle for Gay Law
Reform from 1950 to the Present. London: Routledge.
Jenness, V. and Grattet, R. (2001) Making Hate a Crime. New York: Russell Sage
Foundation.
Jennings, F. (1975) The Invasion of America: Indians, Colonialism and the Cant of
Conquest. New York: W. W. Norton.
Joas, H. (2000) The Genesis of Values. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Joint Council for the Welfare of Immigrants (1987) Out of Sight. London: JCWI.
Jones, G. S. (2004) The End of Poverty. London: Profile.
Jordan, B., James, S., Kay, H. and Redley, M. (1992) Trapped in Poverty. London:
Routledge.
Kahan, D. M. (2001) Two liberal fallacies in the hate crimes debate. Law and
Philosophy, 20: 175–93.
Kaufman, N. and Lindquist, S. (1995) Critiquing gender-neutral treaty language: the
Convention on the Elimination of All Discrimination against Women. In J. Peters
and A. Wolper (eds), Women’s Rights, Human Rights: International Feminist
Perspectives. New York: Routledge.
Keal, P. (2003) European Conquest and the Rights of Indigenous Peoples: The Moral
Backwardness of International Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Keck, M. E. and Sikkink, K. (1998) Activism Beyond Borders. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Kennedy, H. (2004) Just Law. London: Chatto & Windus.
Kenrick, J. and Lewis, J. (2004) Indigenous peoples’ rights and the politics of the
term ‘indigenous’. Anthropology Today, 20(2): 4–9.
Kleiss, K. (2004) Peru’s government forced sterilization on 300,000 women.
Edmonton Journal, 12 November.
Klug, F. (2003) Values for a Godless Age. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Knijn, T. (2000) Marketization and the struggling logics of (home) care in the
Netherlands. In M. Harrington Meyer (ed.), Care Work: Gender, Class and the
Welfare State. New York: Routledge.
Knijn, T. and Kremer, M. (1997) Gender and the caring dimension of welfare states:
toward inclusive citizenship. Social Politics: International Studies in Gender State
and Society, 4: 328–61.
Knijn, T., Jonsson, I. and Klammer, U. (2003) Care packaging: minding the children
and/or work. In U. Gerhardt and T. Knijn (eds), Working and Mothering: Social
Practices and Social Policies. Frankfurt am Main: Beck Verlag.
Knowles, C. (2000) Bedlam on the Streets. London: Routledge.
Kotlikoff, L. and Burns, S. (2005) The Coming Generational Storm. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Kukathas, C. (1992) Are there any cultural rights? Political Theory, 20(1): 105–39.
Kymlicka, W. (1989) Liberalism, Community and Culture. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kymlicka, W. (1995) Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority
Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
266 Bibliography
Kymlicka, W. (2000) American multiculturalism and the ‘nations within’. In
D. Ivison, P. Patton and W. Sanders (eds), Political Theory and the Rights of
Indigenous Peoples. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kymlicka, W. (2004) Dworkin on freedom and culture. In J. Burley (ed.), Dworkin
and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lacey, N. (2003) Penal theory and penal practice: a communitarian approach. In
S. McConville (ed.), The Use of Punishment. Cullompton: Willan.
Laclau, E. (1996) Emancipation(s). London: Verso.
Laing, R. D. (1967) The Politics of Experience and the Bird of Paradise. Harmonds-
worth: Penguin.
Lam, M. (2000) At the Edge of the State: Indigenous Peoples and Self-
Determination. New York: Transnational.
Lan, P.-C. (2003) Among women: Filipina domestics and their Taiwanese
employers across generations. In B. Ehrenreich and A. R. Hochschild (eds), Global
Woman: Nannies, Maids and Sex Workers in the New Economy. London:
Granta.
Landsberg-Lewis, I. (ed.) (1998) Bringing Equality Home: Implementing the
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women.
New York: United Nations Development Fund for Women.
Laslett, P. (1989) A Fresh Map of Life: The Emergence of the Third Age. London:
Weidenfeld and Nicholson.
Laslett, P. (1996) The New Map of Life, 2nd edn. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Latouche, S. (1996) The Westernization of the World: The Significance, Scope and
Limits of the Drive towards Global Uniformity (trans. R. Morris). Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Lauritsen, J. and Thorstad, D. (1974) The Early Homosexual Rights Movement
(1864–1935). New York: Times Change Press.
Lawrence, F. M. (1994) The punishment of hate: towards a normative theory of
bias-motivated crimes. Michigan Law Review, 93: 320–81.
Lawrence, F. M. (1999) Punishing Hate. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lazarus, L. (2004) Contrasting Prisoners’ Rights: A Comparative Examination of
Germany and England. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lazreg, M. (1990) Feminism and difference: the perils of writing as a woman on
women in Algeria. In M. Hirsch and E. Fox Keller (eds), Conflicts in Feminism.
London: Routledge.
Leacock, E. B. (1981) Introduction to L. H. Morgan, Ancient Society, Parts I, II, III,
IV. In E. B. Leacock (ed.), Myths of Male Dominance: Collected Articles on
Women Cross-Culturally. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Lee, Y. J., Parish, W. L. and Willis, R. J. (1994) Sons, daughters and intergenerational
support in Taiwan. American Journal of Sociology, 99(4): 1010–41.
Lehmann, J. (1994) Durkheim and Women. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Leinberger, P. and Tucker, B. (1991) The New Individualists: The Generation after
the Organization Man. New York: HarperCollins.
Leira, A. and Saraceno, C. (2002) Care, actors, relationships and contexts. In B.
Hobson, J. Lewis and B. Siim (eds), Contested Concepts in Gender and Social
Politics. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Lester, A. and Bindman, G. (1972) Race and Law. London: Longman.
Levin, B. (1999) Hate crimes. Worse by definition. Journal of Contemporary
Criminal Justice, 15: 6–21.
Bibliography 267
Levin, J. and McDevitt, J. (1995) Landmark study reveals hate crimes vary
significantly by offender motivation. Klanwatch Intelligence Report (Southern
Poverty Law Center), August.
Levinas, E. (1969) Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press.
Levinas, E. (1987) Language and proximity. In Collected Philosophical Papers
(trans. A. Lingis). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Levinas, E. (1993) Outside the Subject. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Lewis, J. (1992) Gender and the development of welfare regimes. Journal of
European Social Policy, 2: 159–73.
Lewis, J. (ed.) (1999) Gender, Social Care and Welfare State Restructuring in
Europe. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Lewis, J. (2001) The decline of the male breadwinner model: implications for work
and care. Social Politics, 8: 152–69.
Lillard, L. A. and Willis, R. J. (1997) Motives for intergenerational transfers:
evidence from Malaysia. Demography, 34(1): 115–34.
Lin, C. J. (1999) Filipina Domestic Workers in Taiwan: Structural Constraints and
Personal Resistance. Taipei: Taiwan Grassroots Women’s Center.
Lin, C. J. (2003) Transforming patriarchal kinship relations: four generations of
‘modern women’ in Taiwan, 1900–99. Unpublished PhD thesis, University of
Essex.
Lipstadt, D. (1994) Denying the Holocaust: The Growing Assault on Truth and
Memory. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Lister, R. (1997) Citizenship: Feminist Perspectives. London: Macmillan.
Lister, R. (2000) To Rio via the Third Way: New Labour’s ‘welfare’ reform agenda.
Renewal, 8: 9–20.
Lister, R. (2003) Citizenship: Feminist Perspectives, 2nd edn. London: Palgrave.
Livingstone, S. (2000) Prisoners’ rights in the context of the European Convention
on Human Rights. Punishment and Society, 2: 309–24.
Livingstone, S., Owen, T. and MacDonald, A. (2003) Prison Law, 3rd edn. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Lockwood, D. (1996) Civic integration and class formation. British Journal of
Sociology, 47: 531–50.
Loffreda, B. (2000) Losing Matt Shepard: Life and Politics in the Aftermath of
Anti-Gay Murder. New York: Columbia University Press.
Loseke, D. (2003) Thinking about Social Problems: An Introduction to
Constructionist Perspectives, 2nd edn. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Lukes, S. (1973) Emile Durkheim: His Life and Work. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Lukes, S. (1985) Marxism and Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lukes, S. (1991) Moral Conflict and Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Lunbeck, E. (1994) The Psychiatric Persuasion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Lyon, D. (2005) The organisation of care work in Europe: gender and migrant
labour in the new economy. Paper presented at the 13th annual conference of the
Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies, Globalization and the New Politics of
Labor, Indiana University School of Law, Bloomington.
McConville, S. (ed.) (2003) The Use of Punishment. Cullompton: Willan.
MacDonald, M. (1981) Mystical Bedlam: Madness, Anxiety and Healing in
Seventeenth Century England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
268 Bibliography
McDowell, L. (2003) Redundant Masculinities. Blackwell: Oxford.
MacIntyre, A. (1981) After Virtue. London: Duckworth.
Macionis, J. (2004) Society: The Basics. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
MacKinnon, C. (1987) Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Maines, D. (2001) The Faultline of Consciousness: A View of Interactionism in
Sociology. New York: Alison de Gruyter.
Majone, G. (ed.) (1996) Regulating Europe. London: Routledge.
Malloch, M. and Stanley, E. (2005) The detention of asylum seekers in the UK:
representing risk, managing the dangerous. Punishment and Society, 7: 53–71.
Mann, M. (1986) The Sources of Social Power. Volume 1, A History of Power from
the Beginning to AD 1760. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mann, M. (1987) Ruling class strategies and citizenship. Sociology, 21: 339–54.
Mann, M. (1993) The Sources of Social Power. Volume 2, The Rise of Classes and
Nation-States 1760–1914. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Manne, R. (1998) Stolen generations. In P. Craven (ed.), Best Australian Essays.
Melbourne: Black Inc Books.
Manne, R. (2001) In denial: the stolen generations and the right. Australian
Quarterly Essay, 27: 1.
March, J. G. and Olson, J. P. (1989) Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational
Basis of Politics. New York: Free Press.
Marks, G. and McAdam, D. (1996) Social movements and the changing structure
of political opportunity in the European Union. In G. Marks, F. W. Scharpf, P. C.
Schmitter and W. Streeck (eds), Governance in the European Union. London: Sage.
Marotta, T. (1981) The Politics of Homosexuality. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Marshall, T. H. (1950) Citizenship and Social Class and Other Essays. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Marshall, T. H. (1963) Citizenship and social class. In Sociology at the Crossroads
and Other Essays. London: Heinemann.
Marshall, T. H. (1977) Class, Citizenship and Social Development. Chicago:
Chicago University Press.
Marshall, T. H. and Bottomore, T. (1992) Citizenship and Social Class. London:
Pluto Press.
Marx, K. (1975) On the Jewish question. In Karl Marx and Frederick Engels:
Collected Works, Volume 3. New York: International Publishers.
Marx, K. (1978a) The German ideology, Part 1. In R. Tucker (ed.), The Marx–Engels
Reader. New York: W. W. Norton.
Marx, K. (1978b) On imperialism in India. In R. Tucker (ed.), The Marx–Engels
Reader. New York: W. W. Norton.
Math, A. (2004) The impact of pension reforms on older people’s incomes. In
G. Hughes and J. Stewart (eds), Reforming Pensions in Europe. Cheltenham:
Edward Elgar
Mead, L. M. (1986) Beyond Entitlement. New York: Free Press.
Medhurst, A. and Munt, S. R. (eds) (1997) Lesbian and Gay Studies: A Critical
Introduction. London: Cassell.
Meidner, R. (1978) Employee Investment Funds. London: Allen and Unwin.
Meltzer, H., Gill, B., Petticrew, M. and Hinds, K. (1995) The Prevalence of Psychi-
atric Morbidity amongst Adults Living in Private Households. London: Office of
Population Censuses and Surveys.
Bibliography 269
Menon, N. (1995) The impossibility of ‘justice’: female foeticide and feminist
discourse on abortion. Contributions to Indian Sociology, 29: 369–92.
Meyer, J. (1980) The world polity and the authority of the nation state. In
A. Bergesen (ed.), Studies of the Modern World System. New York: Academic
Press.
Meyer, J., Boli, J., Thomas, G. M., and Ramirez, F. O. (1997) World society and the
nation state. American Journal of Sociology, 103: 144–81.
Mill, J. S. (1982) On Liberty (ed. G. Himmelfarb). Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Miller, A. M. (2000) Sexual but not reproductive: exploring the junctions and dis-
junction of sexual and reproductive rights. Health and Human Rights, 4: 68–109.
Miller, B. G. (2003) Invisible Indigenes: The Politics of Nonrecognition. Lincoln:
University of Nebraska Press.
Miller, J. R. (1996) Shingwauk’s Vision: A History of Native Residential Schools.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Miller, R. B. (1991) Casuistry and Modern Ethics: A Poetics of Practical Reasoning.
Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Modood, T., Berthoud, R., Lakey, J., Nazroo, J., Smith, P., Virdee, S. and Beishon,
S. (eds) (1997) Ethnic Minorities in Britain. Diversity and Disadvantage. London:
Policy Studies Institute.
Mohanty, C. (1991) Under Western eyes: feminist scholarship and colonial dis-
courses. In C. Mohanty, A. Russo and L. Torres (eds), Third World Women and
the Politics of Feminism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Molyneux, M. and Razavi, S. (2002) Introduction. In M. Molyneux and S. Razavi
(eds), Gender Justice, Development and Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Momaday, N. S. (1976) The Names: A Memoir. Tucson: University of Arizona Press.
Montgomery, H. (2001) Imposing rights? A case study of child prostitution in
Thailand. In J. K. Cowan, M.-B. Dembour and R. Wilson (eds), Culture and
Rights: Anthropological Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Morgan, R. (2000) The utilitarian justification of torture: denial, desert and dis-
information. Punishment and Society, 2: 181–96.
Morgan, R. (2001) The European Committee for the Prevention of Torture and
Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment. In D. van Zyl Smit and
F. Dünkel (eds), Imprisonment Today and Tomorrow: International Perspectives
on Prisoners’ Right and Prison Conditions. Hague: Kluwer.
Morgan, R. (2004) Advancing indigenous rights at the United Nations: strategic
framing and its impact on the normative development of international law. Social
and Legal Studies, 13(4): 481–500.
Morris, G. (1992) International law and politics: toward a right to self-
determination for indigenous peoples. In M. A. Jaimes (ed.), The State of Native
America: Genocide, Colonization and Resistance. Boston: South End Press.
Morris, L. D. (1994) Dangerous Classes. London: Routledge.
Morris, L. D. (1996) Researching living standards. Journal of Social Policy, 25:
459–83.
Morris, L. D. (1998) Governing at a distance: rights and controls in British
immigration. International Migration Review, 32: 949–73.
Morris, L. D. (2002a) Managing Migration: Civic Stratification and Migrants’
Rights. London: Routledge.
Morris, L. D. (2002b) The shifting contours of rights: Britain’s asylum and immigra-
tion regime. Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 28: 409–25.
270 Bibliography
Morrison, D. (2004) New Labour, citizenship and the discourse of the Third
Way. In S. Hale, W. Leggett and L. Martell (eds), The Third Way and Beyond.
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Mouzelis, N. (1991) Back to Sociological Theory: The Construction of Social
Orders. London: Macmillan.
Mouzelis, N. (1995) Sociological Theory: What Went Wrong? Diagnosis and
Remedies. London: Routledge.
Mouzelis, N. (2000) The subjectivist–objectivist divide: against transcendence.
Sociology, 34: 741–62.
Mudrooroo (1995) Us Mob, History, Culture, Struggle: An Introduction to Indigen-
ous Australia. Sydney: Angus and Robertson.
Mulhall, S. and Swift, A. (1992) Liberals and Communitarians. Oxford: Blackwell.
Murphy, J. G. (1994) Marxism and retribution. In R. Duff and D. Garland (eds),
A Reader on Punishment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Murphy, J. G. (2000) Two cheers for vindictiveness. Punishment and Society, 2:
131–43.
Murray, C. (1984) Losing Ground. New York: Basic Books.
Murray, C. (1990) The Emerging British Underclass. Choice in Welfare Series No. 2.
London: Health and Welfare Unit, Institute of Economic Affairs.
NACRO (2003) Overcrowded jails aren’t working. Safer Society Magazine,
Autumn: 6–7.
Nadasdy, P. (2003) Hunters and Bureaucrats: Power, Knowledge and Aboriginal–
State Relations in the Southwest Yukon. Vancouver: University of British Columbia
Press.
Naffine, N. (1990) Law and the Sexes. London: Allen and Unwin.
Nagel, J. (1996) American Indian Ethnic Renewal: Red Power and the Resurgence of
Identity and Culture. New York: Oxford University Press.
Narayan, U. (1997) Dislocating Cultures: Identities, Traditions and Third World
Feminism. London: Routledge.
Nash, K. (2002) Human rights for women: an argument for ‘deconstructive equality’.
Economy and Society, 31: 414–33.
National Association of Citizens Advice Bureaux (1996) Failing the Test. London:
NACAB.
National Association of Citizens Advice Bureaux (2000) A Person Before the Law.
London: NACAB.
Nelson, R. R. (2002) On the complexities and limits of market organisation. In
S. M. Metcalfe and A. Warde (eds), Market Relations and the Competitive
Process. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Nietzsche, F. (1996) On the Genealogy of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press
(originally published 1887).
Niezen, R. (2000) Spirit Wars: Native North American Religions in the Age of
Nation Building. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Norval, A. (2004) Democratic decisions and the question of universality: rethinking
recent approaches. In S. Critchley and O. Marchart (eds), Laclau: A Critical
Reader. London: Routledge.
Nozick, R. (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia. Oxford: Blackwell.
Nussbaum, M. (1997) Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of Reform in
Liberal Education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Nussbaum, M. (1999) Sex and Social Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bibliography 271
Nussbaum, M. (2000) Women and Human Development: The Capabilities
Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
O’Brian, R., Goetz, A. et al. (2000) Contesting Global Governance. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Observer (2000) Nowhere left to run to. Observer, 31 December: 17.
O’Connor, J. (1993) Gender, class and citizenship in the comparative analysis of
welfare state regimes: theoretical and methodological issues. British Journal of
Sociology, 44: 501–18.
O’Connor, J., Orloff, A. and Shaver, S. (1999) States, Markets, Families: Gender,
Liberalism and Social Policy in Australia, Canada, Great Britain and the US.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Omni Television (2004) The Mushuau Innu: Surviving Canada, documentary film
directed by Ed Martin.
O’Neill, O. (2002) A Question of Trust: The BBC Reith Lectures 2002. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Oosterhuis, H. (2000) Stepchildren of Nature: Krafft-Ebing, Psychiatry, and the
Making of Sexual Identity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Orkin, A. (2003) When the law breaks down: aboriginal peoples in Canada and
governmental defiance of the rule of law. Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 41(2/3):
445–62.
Orloff, A. (1993) Gender and the social rights of citizenship: the comparative
analysis of gender relations and welfare states. American Sociological Review, 58:
303–28.
Orloff, A. (1996) Gender in the welfare state. Annual Review of Sociology, 22:
51–78.
Ostner, I. (1999) The politics of care policies in Germany. In J. Lewis (ed.), Gender,
Social Care and Welfare State Restructuring in Europe. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Owers, A. (2003) BIHR Human Rights Lecture: Prison inspection and the protection
of human rights (www.homeoffice.gov.uk/docs2/bihrlecture.html), accessed 19
September 2004. Reprinted in European Human Rights Law Review, 2 (2004).
Pagden, A. (1995) Lords of All the World: Ideologies of Empire in Spain, Britain and
France c.1500–c.1800. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Pahl, R. (2000) On Friendship. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Pahl, R. and Spencer, L. (2004) Personal communities: not simply families of fate or
choice. Current Sociology, 52: 99–221.
Parekh, B. (1998) Superior people: the narrowness of liberalism from Mill to Rawls.
Times Literary Supplement, 25 February: 11–13.
Parekh, B. (2000) Rethinking Multiculturalism: Cultural Diversity and Political
Theory. London: Palgrave Macmillan
Parkin, F. (1992) Durkheim. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Parkin, F. (2002) Weber. London: Routledge.
Parry, G. (1991) Conclusion: paths to citizenship. In U. Vogel and M. Moran (eds),
The Frontiers of Citizenship. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Pashukanis, E. (1978) Law and Marxism: A General Theory. London: Ink Links
(originally published 1924).
Pasuk Phongpaichit (1982) From Peasant Girls to Bangkok Masseuses. Geneva:
International Labour Organization.
Patterson, O. (1991) Freedom: Freedom in the Making of Western Culture.
New York: Basic Books.
272 Bibliography
Peach, L. J. (2001) Are women human? The promise and perils of ‘women’s rights as
human rights’. In L. S. Bell, A. J. Nathan and I. Peleg (eds), Negotiating Culture
and Human Rights. New York: Columbia University Press.
Pensions Commission (2004) Pensions: Challenges and Choices, the First Report of
the Pensions Commission. London: TSO.
Percy, A. (1998) Ethnicity and victimization: findings from the 1996 British Crime
Survey. Home Office Statistical Bulletin, 6/98. London: Home Office.
Petchesky, R. P. (2000) Sexual rights: inventing a concept, mapping an international
practice. In Richard Parker et al. (eds), Framing the Sexual Subject: The Politics of
Gender, Sexuality and Power. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Petchesky, R. P. (2003) Global Prescriptions: Gendering Health and Human Rights.
London: Zed Books.
Peters, B. G. (1992) Bureaucratic politics and the institutions of the European
Community. In A. Sbragia (ed.), Euro-Politics. Washington, DC: The Brookings
Institution.
Peters, B. G. (2000) Institutional Theory in Political Science: The ‘New Institutional-
ism’ in Political Science. London: Continuum International.
Peterson, V. S. and Parisi, L. (1998) Are women human? It’s not an academic ques-
tion. In T. Evans (ed.), Human Rights Fifty Years On, A Re-appraisal. Manchester:
Manchester University Press.
Phelan, S. (2001) Sexual Strangers: Gays, Lesbians and Dilemmas of Citizenship.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Phillips, A. (1992) Universalist pretentions in political thought. In M. Barrett and
A. Phillips (eds), Destabilising Theory. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Phillips, M. (2002) Hate crime: the Orwellian response to prejudice. In P. Iganski
(ed.), The Hate Debate. Should Hate Be Punished as a Crime? London: Profile.
Pickering, W. S. F. (ed.) (1975) Durkheim on Religion. London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Pickering, W. S. F. and Watts Miller, W. (1993) Individualism and Human Rights in
the Durkheimian Tradition. Occasional Papers No. 1. Oxford: British Centre for
Durkheimian Studies.
Pierson, P. (1997) Dismantling the Welfare State? Reagan, Thatcher and the Politics
of Retrenchment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Plender, R. (1999) Basic Documents on International Migration Law. The Hague:
Kluwer Law International.
Plummer, K. (ed.) (1981) The Making of the Modern Homosexual. London:
Hutchinson.
Plummer, K. (1995) Telling Sexual Stories: Power, Change and Social Worlds.
London: Routledge.
Plummer, K. (1999) The lesbian and gay movement in the UK 1965–1995: schisms,
solidarities and social worlds. In A. Barry, J. W. Duyvendak and A. Krouwel (eds),
Gay and Lesbian Movements since the 1960s. Philadelphia: Temple University
Press.
Plummer, K. (2003) Intimate Citizenship: Private Decisions and Public Dialogues.
Seattle: University of Washington Press.
Plummer, K. (2005) Critical humanism and queer theory. In Y. Lincoln and N. Denzin
(eds), Handbook of Qualitative Research, 3rd edn. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Pontusson, J. (1994) Sweden: the people’s home in danger. In P. Anderson and
P. Camiller (eds), Mapping the Left in Western Europe. London: Verso.
Bibliography 273
Povinelli, E. A. (1998) The state of shame: Australian multiculturalism and the crisis
of indigenous citizenship. Critical Inquiry, 24: 575–610.
Povinelli, E. A. (2002) The Cunning of Recognition: Indigenous Alterities and the
Making of Australian Multiculturalism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Powell, W. P. and DiMaggio, P. (eds) (1991) The New Institutionalism in Organiza-
tional Analysis. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Power, L. (1995) No Bath but Plenty of Bubbles. London: Cassell.
Prins, N. (2004) Other People’s Money: The Corporate Mugging of America.
New York: The New Press.
Pritchard, S. (1998) Indigenous Peoples the United Nations and Human Rights.
Sydney: Federation Press.
Putnam, R. D. (2000) Bowling Alone. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Rao, A. (1995) The politics of gender and culture in international human rights
discourse. In J. Peters and A. Wolper (eds), Women’s Rights, Human Rights:
International Feminist Perspectives. New York: Routledge.
Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, J. (1993) Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
RCIADIC (1991) National Report. Canberra: Royal Commission on Aboriginal
Deaths in Custody.
Red–Green Study Group (1992) What on Earth Is to Be Done? Manchester: RGSG.
Rex, J. (1986) Race and Ethnicity. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Reynolds, H. (1996) Aboriginal Sovereignty: Three Nations, One Australia. Sydney:
Allen and Unwin.
Rheinstein, M. (ed.) (1954) Max Weber on Law in Economy and Society. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Richardson, D. (1998) Sexuality and citizenship. Sociology, 32: 83–100.
Richardson, D. (2000) Claiming citizenship? Sexuality, citizenship and lesbian
feminist theory. Sexualities, 3: 255–72.
Richardson, D. (2002) Theorising Heterosexuality. London: Sage.
Richardson, G. (1985) The case for prisoners’ rights. In M. Maguire, J. Vagg and
R. Morgan (eds), Accountability and Prisons: Opening Up a Closed World.
London: Tavistock.
Richardson, G. (1995) Prisoners and the law: beyond rights. In C. McCrudden and
G. Chambers (eds) (1994), Individual Rights and the Law in Britain. Oxford:
Clarendon.
Risse, T., Ropp, S. et al. (eds) (1999) The Power of Human Rights. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Risse Kappen, T. (1994) Ideas do not float freely: transnational coalitions, domestic
structures, and the end of the Cold War. International Organization, 48: 185–214.
Risse Kappen, T. (1995) Bringing Transnational Relations Back In: Non-State
Actors, Domestic Structures and International Institutions. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Roberston, R. (1992) Globalization: Social Theory and Global Culture. London: Sage.
Robertson, G. (1999) Crimes Against Humanity: The Struggle for Global Justice.
London: Allen Lane.
Robertson, G. (2002) The great socialist shame: left-wing thinkers backed policies
that tore aborigine girls from their mothers. New Statesman, 11 November.
Robins, L. N. and Regier, D. A. (eds) (1991) Psychiatric Disorders in America.
New York: Free Press.
274 Bibliography
Robinson, F. (1998) The limits of a rights-based approach to international ethics.
In T. Evans (ed.), Human Rights Fifty Years On, A Re-appraisal. Manchester:
Manchester University Press.
Robinson, M. (2004) Public sociologies and human rights: finding common
ground. Paper presented at the American Sociological Association conference,
San Francisco, 14 August.
Rogin, M. P. (1987) Ronald Reagan, The Movie and Other Episodes in Political
Demonology. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Rorty, R. (1989) Contingency, Irony and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Rorty, R. (1993) Human rights, rationality and sentimentality. In S. Shute
and S. Hurley (eds) On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993.
New York: Basic Books.
Royal Commission on Lunacy and Mental Disorder (1926) Report. London: HMSO.
Rusche, G. and Kirchheimer, O. (1968) Punishment and Social Structure. New York:
Russell and Russell (originally published 1939).
Ruzza, C. (2002) ‘Frame bridging’ and the new politics of persuasion, advocacy
and influence. In A. Warleigh and J. Fairbrass (eds), Influence and Interests in the
European Union: The New Politics of Persuasion and Advocacy. London: Europa
Press.
Ruzza, C. (2004) Europe and Civil Society: Movement Coalitions and European
Governance. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Ruzza, C. (2006) European institutions and the policy discourse of organised civil
society. In S. Smismans (ed.), Civil Society and Legitimate European Governance.
London: Elgar.
Sainsbury, D. (ed.) (1999) Gender and Welfare State Regimes. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Samson, C. (1999) The dispossession of the Innu and the colonial magic of Canadian
liberalism. Citizenship Studies, 3(1): 5–26.
Samson, C. (2001) Sameness as a requirement for the recognition of the rights of the
Innu of Canada: the colonial context. In J. Cowan, M.-B. Dembour and R. Wilson
(eds), Culture and Rights: Anthropological Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Samson, C. (2003) A Way of Life that Does Not Exist: Canada and the Extinguish-
ment of the Innu. London: Verso Press.
Samson, C. (2004) The dis-ease over Native North American drinking: experiences
of the Innu of Northern Labrador. In R. Coomber and N. South (eds), Drug Use
and Cultural Contexts: Beyond the West. London: Free Association Books.
Samuelson, P. (1958) An exact consumption-loan model of interest with or without
the social contrivance of money. Journal of Political Economy, December.
Sandel, M. (1982) Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Sassen, S. (1996) Losing Control. New York: Colombia University Press.
Sassen, S. (1998) Globalisation and Its Discontents. New York: The New Press.
Schone, J. (2001) The short life and painful death of prisoners’ rights. Howard
Journal of Criminal Justice, 40: 70–82.
Scott, D. (2004) The politics of prisoners’ rights: the potential and limitations of legal
discourses. Paper presented to the European Deviance Group conference, Bristol,
September.
Bibliography 275
Scott, J. W. (1988) Gender and the Politics of History. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Scraton, P. (2002) Defining ‘power’ and challenging ‘knowledge’: critical analysis as
resistance in the UK. In K. Carrington and R. Hogg (eds), Critical Criminology:
Issues, Debates, Challenges. Cullompton: Willan.
Scraton, P. and Moore, L. (2004) The Hurt Inside: The Imprisonment of Women and
Girls in Northern Ireland. Belfast: Northern Ireland Human Rights Commission.
Sedgwick, E. K. (1990) Epistemology of the Closet. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Seed, P. (2001) American Pentimento: The Invention of Indians and the Pursuit of
Riches. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Seidel, G. (1986) The Holocaust Denial. Antisemitism, Racism and the New Right.
Leeds: Beyond the Pale Collective.
Sen, A. (1999) Commodities and Capabilities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sen, A. (2005) Mary, Mary, quite contrary. Feminist Economics, 11: 1–9.
Sevenhuijsen, S. (1998) Citizenship and the Ethics of Care. London: Routledge.
Shermer, M. and Grobman, A. (2000) Denying History. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Short, D. (2003a) Australian ‘aboriginal’ reconciliation: the latest phase in the
colonial project. Citizenship Studies, 7(3): 291–392.
Short, D. (2003b) Reconciliation, assimilation and the indigenous peoples of
Australia. International Political Science Review, 24(4): 491–513.
Sierra, M. (2002) The Challenge to Diversity in Mexico: Human Rights, Gender and
Ethnicity. Working Paper No. 49. Halle: Max Planck Institute for Social
Anthropology.
Slezkine, Y. (1994) Arctic Mirrors: Russia and the Small Peoples of the North.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Smart, C. (1989) Feminism and the Power of Law. London: Routledge.
Smith, A. (1891) An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations.
London: T. Nelson and Sons.
Smith, A. (1995) Nations and Nationalism in a Global Era. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Smith, A. M. (1992) Resisting the erasure of lesbian sexuality: a challenge for queer
activism. In K. Plummer (ed.), Modern Homosexualities. London: Routledge.
Smith, A. M. (1994) New Right Discourse on Race and Sexuality: Britain, 1968–
1990. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Smith, J., Chatfield, C. and Pagnucco, R. (eds) (1997) Transnational Social Move-
ments and Global Politics: Solidarity Beyond the State. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse
University Press.
Smith, R. R. and Windes, R. R. (2000) Progay/Antigay: The Rhetorical War over
Sexuality. London: Sage.
Smyth, C. (1992) Lesbians Talk Queer Notions. London: Scarlett Press.
Soysal, Y. (1994) Limits of Citizenship. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Stamatopoulou, E. (1995) Women’s rights and the United Nations. In J. Peters and
A. Wolper (eds), Women’s Rights, Human Rights: International Feminist Perspec-
tives. New York: Routledge.
Stanton, A. and Schwartz, M. (1954) The Mental Hospital. New York: Basic Books.
Stark, A. and Regner, A. (2002) In Whose Hands? Work, Gender, Ageing and Care in
Three EU Countries. Linkopings: Linkopings Universitet, Tema genus report No. 2.
Steiker, C. S. (1999) Punishing hateful motives: old wine in a new bottle calls for
prohibition. Michigan Law Review, 97: 1863–70.
276 Bibliography
Steiner, H. J. and Alston, P. (1996) International Human Rights in Context. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Stephen, L. (2003) The gendered dynamics of agrarian counter-reform and indigen-
ous rights in southern Mexico. Paper presented at a conference at the Institute of
Latin American Studies, University of London.
Stern, K. (1995) Denial of the Holocaust: an anti-Semitic political assault. In J. R.
Chanes (ed.), Antisemitism in America Today. New York: Birch Lane Press.
Stivens, M. (2000) Introduction: gender politics and the reimagining of human rights
in the Asia-Pacific. In A.-M. Hilsdon, M. Macintyre, V. Mackie and M. Stivens,
Human Rights and Gender Politics: Asia-Pacific Perspectives. London: Routledge.
Stones, R. (1996) Sociological Reasoning: Towards a Post-Modern Sociology.
London: Macmillan.
Stones, R. (2002) Social theory, documentary film and distant others: simplicity and
subversion in The Good Woman of Bangkok. European Journal of Cultural
Studies, 5: 217–37.
Stones, R. (2005) Structuration Theory. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Stout, J. (1990) Ethics after Babel: The Languages of Morals and Their Discontents.
Cambridge: James Clark & Co.
Strauss, L. (1953) Natural Right and History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Supperstone, M. (1981) Brownlie’s Law of Public Order and National Security,
2nd edn. London: Butterworths.
Szasz, T. S. (1963) Law, Liberty and Psychiatry. New York: Macmillan.
Szasz, T. S. (1970) Involuntary mental hospitalisation: a crime against humanity.
In Ideology and Insanity. New York: Doubleday.
Tanner, V. (1947) Outlines of the Geography, Life and Customs of Newfoundland-
Labrador (The Eastern Part of the Labrador Peninsula), two volumes. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Tappan, P. (1954) The legal rights of prisoners. The Annals, 293: 99–111.
Tatchell, P. (2002) Some people are more equal than others. In P. Iganski (ed.), The
Hate Debate: Should Hate Be Punished as a Crime? London: Profile.
Tatz, C. (1999) Aboriginal suicide is different: aboriginal youth suicide in New
South Wales, the Australian Capital Territory and New Zealand: towards a
model of explanation and alleviation. Criminology Research Council Report
(www.aic.gov.au/crc/reports/tatz; accessed December 2005).
Taylor, C. (1979) Hegel and Modern Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Taylor, C. (1994) Multiculturalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Taylor, C. (1995) Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Taylor, L. (1980) Bringing power to particular account: Peter Rajah and the
Hull Board of Visitors. In P. Carlen and M. Collison (eds), Radical Issues in
Criminology. Oxford: Martin Robertson.
Therborn, G. (2004) Between Sex and Power: Family in the World, 1900–2000.
London: Routledge.
Thomas, C. (1993) De-constructing concepts of care. Sociology, 27: 649–69.
Thompson, E. P. (1977) Whigs and Hunters: The Origin of the Black Act.
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Thornton, R. (1987) American Indian Holocaust and Survival: A Population
History since 1492. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.
Bibliography 277
Thornton, R. (2002) Health, disease and demography. In P. Deloria and N. Salisbury
(eds), A Companion to American Indian History. Oxford: Blackwell.
Thornton, R. and Grasnick, M. (1980) Sociology of American Indians: A Critical
Bibliography. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Titmuss, R. M. (1970) The Gift Relationship: From Human Blood to Social Blood.
London: Allen and Unwin.
Travis, A. (1999) Delay on Holocaust denial law. Guardian, 19 October.
Tronto, J. (1993) Moral Boundaries. A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care.
London: Routledge.
Tuke, S. (1813) A Description of the Retreat. York: W. Alexander.
Tully, J. (1995) Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in the Age of Diversity.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tully, J. (2000) The struggles of indigenous peoples for and of freedom. In D. Ivison,
P. Patton and W. Sanders (eds), Political Theory and the Rights of Indigenous
Peoples. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Turner, B. S. (1986) Citizenship and Capitalism: The Debate over Reformism.
London: Allen and Unwin.
Turner, B. S. (1988) Status. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Turner, B. S. (1989) Ageing, status politics and sociological theory. British Journal
of Sociology, 40: 588–60.
Turner, B. S. (1990) Outline of a theory of citizenship. Sociology, 24: 189–214.
Turner, B. S. (1993) Outline of a theory of human rights. Sociology, 27: 485–512.
Turner, B. S. (1997) A neo-Hobbesian theory of human rights: a reply to Malcolm
Waters. Sociology, 31(1): 565–71.
Turner, B. S. and Rojek, C. (2001) Society and Culture: Principles of Scarcity and
Solidarity. London: Sage.
Turner, L. (1979) Ethnology of the Ungava District and Hudson Bay Territory:
Indians and Eskimos in the Quebec-Labrador Peninsula. Quebec City: Presses
Comeditex (first published 1889).
UN (1999) Report of the Working Group on Indigenous Populations. Seventeenth
Session, Geneva, 26–30 July, Chairperson-Rapporteur E.-I. A. Daes. Geneva:
United Nations.
UN Committee on the Rights of the Child (2002) Concluding Observations on the
Committee on the Rights of the Child: United Kingdom of Great Britain and
Northern Ireland. Geneva: United Nations.
UN Economic and Social Council (2005) Economic, Social and Cultural Rights:
Report of the Special Rapporteur on the Right of Everyone to the Enjoyment of
the Highest Attainable Standard of Physical and Mental Health. New York:
United Nations.
UN Population Division (2000) World Population Prospects: The 1998 Revision.
Volume III, Analytic Report. New York: United Nations.
UN Population Division (2001) Replacement Migration: Is It a Solution to Declining
and Ageing Populations? New York: United Nations.
Ungerson, C. (ed.) (1990) Gender and Caring: Work and Welfare in Britain and
Scandinavia. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Union of British Columbia Indian Chiefs (2004) Certainty: Canada’s struggle to
extinguish aboriginal title (www.ubcic.bc.ca/certainty.htm).
US Department of Justice, Bureau of Justice Assistance (1997) A Policymaker’s
278 Bibliography
Guide to Hate Crimes. Washington, DC: US Department of Justice, Bureau of
Justice Assistance.
Useem, M. (1996) Investor Capitalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Van Reenan, J. (2001) No more skivvy schemes? In D. Card and R. Freeman (eds),
Seeking a Premier League Economy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Vanstone, J. W. (1974) Athapaskan Adventures. Hunters and Fishermen of the
Subarctic Forests. Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company.
Virdee, V. (1997) Racial harassment. In T. Modood, R. Berthoud, J. Lakey, J.
Nazroo, P. Smith, S. Virdee and S. Beishon (eds), Ethnic Minorities in Britain.
Diversity and Disadvantage. London: Policy Studies Institute.
Vitoria, F. de (1991) Political Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Vizenor, G. (1984) The People Named the Chippewa: Narrative Histories.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Vizenor, G. and Lee, A. R. (1999) Postindian Conversations. Lincoln: University of
Nebraska Press.
Vogel, U. (1997) Emancipatory politics between universalism and difference:
gender perspectives on European citizenship. In P. Lehning and A. Weale (eds),
Citizenship, Democracy and Justice in the New Europe. London: Routledge.
Waerness, K. (1984) Caring as women’s work in the welfare state. In H. Holter (ed.),
Patriarchy in a Welfare Society. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.
Walby, S. (2002) Feminism in a global era. Economy and Society, 31: 533–57.
Walker, N. (1991) Why Punish? Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Walklate, S. (2001) Gender, Crime and Criminal Justice. Cullompton: Willan.
Walters, A. (ed.) (1980) Come Together: The Years of Gay Liberation (1970–1973).
London: GMP.
Waters, M. (1996) Human rights and the universalization of interests. Sociology, 30:
593–600.
Weaver, J. (1997) That the People Might Live: Native American Literature and
Native American Community. New York: Oxford University Press.
Webber, F. (2004) Asylum – from deterrence to destitution. Race and Class, 45: 77–85.
Weber, K. E. M. (1948) Class, status and party. In H. H. Gerth and C. W. Mills (eds),
Essays in Sociology. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Weber, K. E. M. (1949) The Methodology of the Social Sciences. New York: Free
Press.
Weber, K. E. M. (1976) The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (trans.
T. Parsons). New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Weber, K. E. M. (1978) The nature of charismatic domination. In W. G. Runciman
(ed.), Weber: Selections in Translation (trans. E. Matthews). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Weeks, J. (1990) Coming Out: Homosexual Politics in Britain from the Nineteenth
Century to the Present, 2nd edn. London: Quartet Books.
Weeks, J. (1995) Invented Moralities. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Weeks, J. (1998) The sexual citizen. Theory, Culture and Society, 15: 35–52.
Weinstein, J. (1992) First Amendment challenges to hate crime legislation: where’s
the speech? Criminal Justice Ethics, 11: 6–20.
Weston, K. (1991) Families We Choose. New York: Columbia University Press.
Westwood, G. (1952) Society and the Homosexual. London: Gollancz.
Westwood, G. (1960) A Minority: A Report on the Life of the Male Homosexual in
Britain. London: Longman.
Bibliography 279
White, S. (2000) Review article: Social rights and the social contract – political
theory and the new welfare politics. British Journal of Political Science, 30:
507–32.
Whittaker, A. (2000) Intimate Knowledge: Women and Their Health in North-East
Thailand. Sydney: Allen and Unwin.
Wiener, C. (1981) The Politics of Alcoholism. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers.
Willetts, P. (ed.) (1982) Pressure Groups in the Global System: The Transnational
Relations of Issue-Oriented Non-Governmental Organizations. London: Frances
Pinter.
Williams, D. G. T. (1970) Protest and public order. Cambridge Law Journal, 108:
96–121.
Williams, F. (2001) In and beyond New Labour: towards a new political ethics of
care. Critical Social Policy, 21: 467–93.
Williams, F. (2004) Rethinking Families. London: Calouste Gulbenkian Foundation.
Williams, R. A. (1990) The American Indian in Western Legal Thought: The
Discourses of Conquest. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wilson, A. R. (ed.) (1995) A Simple Matter of Justice: Theorising Lesbian and Gay
Politics. London: Cassell.
Wilson, R. A. (ed.) (1987) Human Rights Culture and Context. London: Pluto
Press.
Wilson, R. A. (2001) The Politics of Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa: Legit-
imising the Post Apartheid State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wolfe, A. (1992) Democracy versus sociology: boundaries and their consequences.
In M. Lamont and M. Fournier (eds), Cultivating Differences. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Wolfenden, Lord (1957) Report of the Departmental Committee on Homosexual
Offences and Prostitution. London: HMSO, Cmnd 247.
Wolffe, W. J. (1987) Values in conflict: incitement to racial hatred and the Public
Order Act 1986. Public Law, 85: 345.
Wood, E. M. (2003) The Empire of Capital. London: Verso.
Woodburn, J. (2001) The political status of hunter-gatherers in present-day and
future Africa. In A. Bernard and J. Kenrick (eds), Africa’s Indigenous Peoples:
‘First Peoples’ or ‘Marginalized Minorities?’ Edinburgh: Centre for African
Studies, University of Edinburgh.
Woodhouse, D. (1998) The judiciary in the 1990s. Policy and Politics, 26: 458–70.
Woodiwiss, A. (2005) Human Rights. London: Routledge.
Wunder, J. (1994) ‘Retained by the People’: A History of American Indians and the
Bill of Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zellick, G. (1974) Prisoners’ rights in England. University of Toronto Law Review,
24: 334–9.
Zerilli, L. (2004) This universal which is not one. In S. Critchley and O. Marchart
(eds), Laclau: A Critical Reader. London: Routledge.
Zola, I. K. (1972) Medicine as an institution of social control. Sociological Review,
20: 487–504.
Zwingel, S. (forthcoming) From intergovernmental negotiations to (sub)national
change: a transnational perspective on the impact of the CEDAW Convention.
International Journal of Feminist Politics.
Index