Esfeld MetScience
Esfeld MetScience
Abstract
The paper argues that metaphysics depends upon science when it comes to claims about the
constitution of the real world. That thesis is illustrated by considering the examples of global
supervenience, the tenseless vs. the tensed theory of time and existence, events vs. substances,
and relations vs. intrinsic properties. An argument is sketched out for a metaphysics of a four-
dimensional block universe whose content are events and their sequences, events consisting in
physical properties instantiated at space-time points, these properties being relations rather than
intrinsic properties.
1. Introduction
Metaphysics used to be and again is the core discipline of philosophy. In the words of Frank
Jackson,
Metaphysics … is about what there is and what it is like. But of course it is concerned not with
any old shopping list of what there is and what it is like. Metaphysicians seek a comprehensive
account of some subject matter – the mind, the semantic, or, most ambitiously, everything – in
terms of a limited number of more or less basic notions. In doing this they are following the
good example of physicists. The methodology is not that of letting a thousand flowers bloom but
rather that of making do with as a meagre a diet as possible. (Jackson 1994, 25)
Metaphysics, thus conceived, seeks a comprehensive account of what there is in the real
world. How do we gain knowledge about the world? When it comes to explaining how the
manifest phenomena are connected, science tells us what there is in the world. As Wilfrid
Sellars once put it, “in the dimension of describing and explaining the world, science is the
measure of all things, of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not” (“Empiricism and
the Philosophy of Mind” (1956) in Sellars 1963, 173). There is no source of philosophical
knowledge about the world independent of science. In seeking a comprehensive account of
everything, metaphysics is continuous with science, going beyond particular scientific
theories. The thesis of this paper is that there is a mutual dependence between science and
philosophy: philosophy in the sense of metaphysics needs science to know about what there is
in the real world, and science needs philosophy in the sense of epistemology when it comes to
developing criteria for the interpretation of scientific theories – that is, criteria for the
assessment of knowledge claims contained in scientific theories.
It is common to distinguish between the epistemology and the metaphysics of science.
David Papineau, for one, draws this distinction in the following way:
Metaphysics of science between metaphysics and science 2
The philosophy of science can usefully be divided into two broad areas. The epistemology of
science deals with the justification of claims to scientific knowledge. The metaphysics of science
investigates philosophically puzzling features of the world described by science. In effect, the
epistemology of science asks whether scientific theories are true, whereas the metaphysics of
science considers what it would tell us about the world if they were. (Papineau 1996, 1)
Whereas the philosophy of science was dominated for decades by epistemological issues
under the influence of logical empiricism and its critics, the metaphysics of science has
gathered momentum in the last two decades or so. The type of metaphysics that is at issue is a
revisionary in contrast to a descriptive metaphysics, to use Peter Strawson’s terms (1959,
introduction). The justification for a revisionary metaphysics stems from science: our best
scientific theories suggest the conclusion that a number of our common sense beliefs about
the constituents of the world – as analysed by what Strawson calls descriptive metaphysics –
are false.
In the following, I shall sketch out four examples that illustrate the interplay between
science and metaphysics – examples that show how scientific results provide a content for
metaphysics, namely a content that results in a revisionary metaphysics. The examples are (1)
global supervenience, (2) tenseless vs. tensed theories of time and existence, (3) events vs.
substances, and (4) relations vs. intrinsic properties. In conclusion, I shall sum up the
resulting view of the fundamental ingredients of the world and mention the most important
open issues.
By contrast, chemical or biological theories, for instance, are not fundamental. It is not the
case that everything that there is in the world is a chemical system (such as a molecule) or a
biological system (such as an organism). The mentioned physical theories are fundamental
with respect to all the other current theories of science in the sense that these theories never
need to have recourse to concepts, laws and explanations from any other theories, whereas all
our other theories sometimes need to have recourse to concepts, laws and explanations from
general relativity or quantum field theory. Chemical or biological theories sometimes have to
invoke physical concepts and laws that are in the last resort concepts and laws of general
relativity or quantum field theory – for instance, in order to explain why a given chemical or
biological regularity has an exception in a particular situation. If there are laws in chemistry
or biology, these are ceteris paribus laws, whereas the laws of fundamental physics are strict
laws, admitting no exceptions.
One can sum up these considerations by putting forward a principle of the causal,
nomological and explanatory completeness of the fundamental level: for any fundamental
physical system p (i.e. instantiation of physical properties at a space-time point), insofar as p
has causes, comes under laws and admits of explanations, there are causes that are only
fundamental physical causes, there are laws that are only fundamental physical laws and
there are explanations that employ only concepts of fundamental physics. This principle does
not exclude that for any fundamental physical system p, there are other causes, laws, or
explanations. But such other causes, laws, or explanations, if they exist, do not contribute
anything that is not contributed by fundamental physical laws, causes, and explanations.
The principle of completeness does not occur within physics. It is a principle of the
metaphysics of science, belonging to a reasonable interpretation of what our fundamental
physical theories tell us about the world (for an extensive argument, see Papineau 2002,
appendix). If one did not endorse that principle, an unpalatable consequence would ensue: one
would be committed to saying that our fundamental physical theories are either inapplicable
to some phenomena in their domain (i.e. physical properties being instantiated at space-time
points), because these phenomena are covered by causes, laws and explanations of a higher-
level theory instead of fundamental physical causes, laws and explanations; or, if applicable,
these theories are false, because there are some phenomena in their domain for which the
predictions in terms of causes, laws and explanations of these theories yield the wrong results,
these phenomena being under the influence of causes, laws and explanations of a higher-level
theory instead (the recent criticism of the principle of completeness that Bishop 2006 voices
comes down to exploring that possibility).
To illustrate that point, consider the example of mental causes and brain states – putting in
brain states for fundamental physical phenomena, and mental causes for higher-level causes
that are distinct from physical causes. Assume that there are mental causes that are not
neurobiological causes and that bring about neurobiological effects that are caused only by
them, say produce certain brain states. In that case, as regards the brain states in question, the
relevant neurobiological theory would be either inapplicable, because these states are subject
to the influence of certain non-biological, mental causes; or it would be false, yielding the
wrong probabilities for the occurrence of the brain states in question. If, for instance, the
occurrences of a mental intention of the type raising one’s right arm were distinct from
neurobiological states and if these occurrences of mental intentions produced neurobiological
effects that are not produced by neurobiological causes, then any mental intention of that type
Metaphysics of science between metaphysics and science 4
would regularly raise the probability for brain states of certain types to occur – a probability
that would be different from the neurobiological probability that takes only biological factors
into account. However, there is not the slightest evidence that the physical or neurobiological
laws break down in one of these ways in some area of the brain when the mental is present.
Thus, in short, as far as the principle of completeness is concerned, the argument is a
philosophical one (as with any claim in the metaphysics of science) – but if the argument
were not true, a consequence unacceptable for science would ensue.
The principle of completeness does not imply global supervenience. It rules out causes,
laws and explanations that contribute something to fundamental physical phenomena that is
not provided by fundamental physical causes, laws and explanations; but it does not exclude
that there are emergent epiphenomena in our world that would not necessarily be duplicated if
one created a duplicate of the fundamental physical level of our world. However, admitting
such emergent epiphenomena would again lead to consequences that are unacceptable to
science: such emergent epiphenomena would be such that it would in principle be impossible
to find any explanation for them.
In order to strengthen that point, one can draw on another principle, namely the principle of
evolution: everything that there is in the real world apart from fundamental physical systems
developed out of fundamental physical systems. Given evolution, making a duplicate of the
fundamental physical level of the real world would amount to duplicating cosmic evolution. If
anything that there is in the real world were missing in the duplicate, everything that we know
from science would lead us to expect that there also is some difference in the distribution of
fundamental physical properties in that duplicate with respect to the real world – difference in
some spontaneous mutation, for instance (and there is no such biochemical difference without
there also being a fundamental physical difference). Consequently, such a possible world
would after all not be an exact duplicate of the fundamental physical level of the real world.
Completeness, if conjoined with evolution, therefore provides a strong reason for endorsing
global supervenience.
Note that, according to global supervenience, what there is on the fundamental level
determines everything that there is in the real world, but that the issue of determinism is a
different matter. Global supervenience considers the distribution of the fundamental physical
properties over the whole of space-time as the supervenience base. Determinism concerns the
question of whether or not the evolution in time is deterministic. If global supervenience is
valid and if the real world is deterministic, having, say, the big bang as initial condition, then
any duplicate of the big bang and the laws of nature would be sufficient to amount to a
duplicate of cosmic evolution. But this is a much stronger thesis than global supervenience.
Global supervenience says something about worlds that are a physical duplicate of our world
– that is, a duplicate of the distribution of fundamental physical properties over the whole of
space-time –, independently of whether or not there is physical determinism. If there is
quantum indeterminism and, say, two possible worlds w1 and w 2 agree until a certain time t in
the distribution of the fundamental properties and then diverge because of one radioactive
atom decaying in w1 but not in w2 , then w2 is not a minimal physical duplicate of w 1 .
3. Example 2: the tenseless vs. the tensed theory of time and existence
Let us have a closer look at the fundamental level, the distribution of physical properties at
space-time points over the whole of space-time. There are two rival theories of time as well as
Metaphysics of science between metaphysics and science 5
of existence. According to the tensed theory of existence, existence is relative to a time in the
sense that only that what is present – or only that what is present and what is past – exists.
What is in the future does not exist as yet, and, according to some versions of this theory,
what is past does not exist any more. The tensed theory of existence implies the tensed theory
of time according to which there is a flow of time; the past, the present and the future are
objective modes of time, being out there in the world. The tensed theory of time, however,
does not imply the tensed theory of existence.
Opposed to the tensed theory of time is the tenseless theory of time which claims that there
are only temporal relations of being earlier than, simultaneous with and later than among
events, but no objective modes of past, present and future. The tenseless theory of time
implies the tenseless theory of existence according to which existence is not relative to a
location in time in the same way as it is not relative to a location in space: everything that
there is in space and time simply exists. The tenseless theory of existence, however, does not
imply the tenseless theory of time.
There are philosophical arguments in favour of both these theories of time and existence.
The case can be settled by taking science into account. The relevant scientific theory is
special relativity. Special relativity shows that there is no objective simultaneity. Any event –
in the sense of physical properties occurring at a space-time point – that is supposed to be
simultaneous with other events is so only relative to a reference frame, and there is no
globally preferred reference frame. Thus, there is no objective “now” – in the same way as
there is no objective “here”. For any space-time point, it can be claimed that it is “present” in
the same way as it can be claimed that it is “here” (see, for instance, Dorato 1995, chapters 11
to 13, in particular pp. 186–187, 210). The reason is that, according to special relativity,
spatial as well as temporal distances between events are relative to a reference frame.
Invariant with respect to the choice of a reference frame is only the four-dimensional, spatio-
temporal distance between any two events (or points of space-time). That is the reason why
special relativity is taken to show that space and time are united in a four-dimensional entity,
space-time. General relativity – and notably its application in cosmology – goes beyond
special relativity; but it does not change anything with respect to what special relativity says
about the relativity of spatial and temporal distances.
Special relativity hence makes a case for the tenseless theories of time and existence. Since
spatial and temporal distances are relative to a reference frame, there is no basis in the
physical world for upholding a tensed theory of time or existence (see Saunders 2002). Again,
this claim belongs to the metaphysics of science. It is logically possible to rescue the idea of
an objective present by introducing the notion of one globally privileged reference frame.
That notion does not contradict special relativity. The point is that it is entirely ad hoc – so
that, rejecting the tenseless theories of time and existence as a claim of the metaphysics of
science again has consequences that are unacceptable for science.
Moreover, in recent years, arguments have been developed to the effect that admitting
three-dimensional substances with spatial, but no temporal parts is not consistent with special
relativity. According to special relativity, the spatial distances between points depend on a
reference frame. Consequently, if one subscribes to an ontology according to which there are
three-dimensional macroscopic substances, their spatial figure varies from one frame of
reference to another one, because the spatial distances between the points that the substance in
question occupies depend on a reference frame. If, by contrast, physical objects are four-
dimensional perdurants, their figure in four-dimensional space-time is not relative to a
reference frame (see Balashov 1999 as well as Hales & Johnson 2003). A further argument
makes the following point: since simultaneity is relative to a reference frame, a metaphysics
of enduring three-dimensional objects cannot come up with a convincing theory of the
coexistence (copresence) of objects. By contrast, a metaphysics of perduring four-
dimensional objects, which have temporal parts, can easily include a theory of coexistence:
any two four-dimensional objects coexist if and only if they have parts that are separated by a
space-like interval (see Balashov 2000 and the discussion between Gilmore 2002 and
Balashov 2005). If these arguments prove sound, they put the case against three-dimensional
substances on a par with the case against objective simultaneity based on special relativity.
6. Conclusion
Let us take stock. The examples discussed in the preceding sections suggest a view of the
fundamental level of the world according to which the world is a four-dimensional block
universe whose content are events and their sequences, events consisting in physical
properties instantiated at space-time points, these properties being – as far as quantum physics
is concerned – relations rather than intrinsic properties. This certainly is a revisionary
metaphysics, rejecting a tensed view of time and existence, admitting only events and
processes instead of substances (endurants) and giving priority to relations instead of intrinsic
properties. Everything else there is in the world supervenes on that fundamental level in the
sense of the mentioned thesis of global supervenience. The rationale for this metaphysics
stems from science. The claims sketched out in the preceding sections are a reasonable
interpretation of what science tells us about the world. Not endorsing them would lead to
consequences that are unacceptable for science.
Nonetheless, there are a number of open issues skipped in the preceding sections:
• the relationship between space-time and matter: In the preceding sections, I have used the
terminology of physical properties being instantiated at space-time points or regions. Are
the physical properties literally properties of space-time points or regions – so that matter
reduces to properties of space-time? Or is there a dualism between space-time and matter
fields being inserted in space-time? This is an open issue in the philosophy of general
relativity in the first place. On the one hand, the project of an outright reduction of matter
to space-time failed. (This is the project of Wheeler’s geometrodynamics; see Wheeler
1962 and for the acknowledgement of its failure Misner, Thorne & Wheeler 1973, §
44.3–4, in particular p. 1205). On the other hand, there is no clear distinction between
space-time and matter in general relativity: the metric field includes spatio-temporal
properties, such as the spatio-temporal distances between space-time points, as well as
material properties, namely gravitation. However, resolving this issue depends not only on
the philosophy of general relativity, but also on the open issue of the unification of
general relativity and quantum field theory.
Metaphysics of science between metaphysics and science 9
• the unification of general relativity and quantum field theory: For the time being, there are
two fundamental physical theories: quantum field theory and general relativity. The
relationship between these two theories is not clear. It is desirable to have one
fundamental physical theory. If the project of unifying quantum field theory and general
relativity succeeds, the resulting scientific theory may have important repercussions for
our view of the basic level of nature. To be more precise without engaging in as yet
premature speculations, quantum entanglement is independent of the spatio-temporal
distance of the quantum systems whose states are entangled. This may be taken as one
hint among others that space-time points are not the most fundamental level of nature. The
level of physical properties instantiated at space-time points is, of course, fundamental
with respect to all the other known levels – such as the levels of chemical, biological
properties, etc. But there may be a quantum level that is more fundamental than the level
of space-time points, space-time being somehow derived from that quantum level. If such
a view were to prove sound in the future, it would have important implications for the
metaphysics of the physical world (and, perhaps, the definition of “physical” itself).
Nonetheless, whatever may be the future fundamental physical theory that achieves a
unified treatment of the phenomena that are currently considered by two different
theories, it would be unreasonable to expect that future theory to go back behind the
unification of space and time as considered by general relativity or the holism that
quantum entanglement manifests. Even if we ignore as yet the content of that future
theory, the metaphysical direction seems clear: events instead of enduring substances, and
relations instead of intrinsic properties.
• the micro-macro relationship: This is what the famous measurement problem in the
interpretation of quantum physics is about. That problem is still unsolved. The point at
issue is the extension of quantum entanglement. Is there a physical process that leads to
the dissolution of quantum entanglement so that there really are macroscopic systems
having well-defined properties separately – such as cats being always either alive or dead,
their states not being entangled with the states of other systems (cf. the famous thought
experiment of Schrödinger’s cat (Schrödinger 1935, 812)? There is a physical proposal for
a further development of the formalism of quantum theory in that sense, going back to
Ghirardi, Rimini & Weber (1986). But that proposal faces a number of physical problems.
To my mind, this issue is rather an open physical one than a metaphysical one.
These open issues show that the metaphysics of science is an unfinished business. The
metaphysics of science depends on science and its progress. In a nutshell, the metaphysics of
science is as hypothetical as is science. However, since there is no source of philosophical
knowledge about the constitution of the world that is independent of science, this is all that
can be achieved in a metaphysics of the real world – and it is sufficient to turn the
metaphysics of science into an exciting business, worth engaging in.
References
Balashov, Yuri (1999): “Relativistic objects”. Noûs 33, pp. 644–662.
Balashov, Yuri (2000): “Enduring and perduring objects in Minkowski space–time”. Philosophical Studies 99,
pp. 129–166.
Balashov, Yuri (2005): “Special relativity, coexistence and temporal parts: a reply to Gilmore”. Philosophical
Studies 124, pp. 1–40.
Bell, John S. (1964): “On the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen-paradox”. Physics 1, pp. 195–200.
Metaphysics of science between metaphysics and science 10
Bishop, Robert C. (2006): “The hidden premiss in the causal argument for physicalism”. Analysis 66, pp. 44–52.
Bohm, David & Hiley, Basil (1993): The undivided universe. An ontological interpretation of quantum theory.
London: Routledge.
Dorato, Mauro (1995): Time and reality. Spacetime physics and the objectivity of temporal becoming. Bologna:
Cooperativa Libraria Universitaria Editrice Bologna.
Esfeld, Michael (2004): “Quantum entanglement and a metaphysics of relations”. Studies in History and
Philosophy of Modern Physics 35B, pp. 601–617.
French, Steven & Ladyman, James (2003): “Remodelling structural realism: quantum physics and the
metaphysics of structure”. Synthese 136, pp. 31–56.
Ghirardi, Giancarlo, Rimini, Alberto & Weber, Tullio (1986): “Unified dynamics for microscopic and
macroscopic systems”. Physical Review D34, pp. 470–491.
Gilmore, Cody S. (2002): “Balashov on special relativity and temporal parts”. Philosophical Studies 109, pp.
241–263.
Hales, Steven D. & Johnson, Timothy A. (2003): “Endurantism, perdurantism, and special relativity”.
Philosophical Quarterly 53, pp. 524–539.
Howard, Don (1989): “Holism, separability, and the metaphysical implications of the Bell experiments”. In: J. T.
Cushing & E. McMullin (eds.): Philosophical consequences of quantum theory. Reflections on Bell’s
theorem. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Pp. 224–253.
Jackson, Frank (1994): “Armchair metaphysics”. In: J. O’Leary-Hawthorne & M. Michael (eds.): Philosophy in
mind. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Pp. 23–42. Reprinted in Frank Jackson (1998): Mind, method and conditionals.
Selected essays. London: Routledge. Pp. 154–176.
Jackson, Frank (1998): From metaphysics to ethics. A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Langton, Rae & Lewis, David (1998): “Defining ‘intrinsic’”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58,
pp. 333–345. Reprinted in David Lewis (1999): Papers in metaphysics and epistemology. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. Pp. 116–132.
Lewis, David (2001): “Redefining ‘intrinsic’”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, pp. 381–398.
Misner, Charles W., Thorne, Kip S. & Wheeler, John A. (1973): Gravitation. San Francisco: Freeman.
Papineau, David (1996): “Introduction”. In: D. Papineau (ed.): The philosophy of science. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. Pp. 1–20.
Papineau, David (2002): Thinking about consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Saunders, Simon (2002): “How relativity contradicts presentism”. In: C. Callender (ed.): Time, reality &
experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pp. 277–292.
Schrödinger, Erwin (1935): “Die gegenwärtige Situation in der Quantenmechanik”. Naturwissenschaften 23, pp.
807–812, 823–828, 844–849.
Sellars, Wilfrid (1963): Science, perception and reality. London: Routledge.
Sider, Theodore R. (2001): Four-dimensionalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Strawson, Peter F. (1959): Individuals. An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Routledge.
Teller, Paul (1986): “Relational holism and quantum mechanics”. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
37, pp. 71–81.
Wheeler, John A. (1962): Geometrodynamics. New York: Academic Press.