Wiesing AbstractPhotography-2005
Wiesing AbstractPhotography-2005
Wiesing AbstractPhotography-2005
Lambert Wiesing
Translated by Nils F. Schott
STANFORD, CALIFORNIA
Stanford University Press
Stanford, California
The translation of this work was supported by a grant from the Goethe-lnstitut
which is funded by the German Ministry of Foreign Affairs.
Wiesing, Lambert.
[Artifizielle Prasenz. English]
Artificial pn:sence: philosophical studies in image theory/ Lambert Wiesing;
translated by Nils F. Schott.
p. cm. - (Cultural memory in the present)
"Originally published in German in 2005 under the title Artifizielle Priisenz:
j
1 Studien zur Philosophic des Bildes."
Includes bibliographical references.
ISBN 978-0-8047-5940-3 (cloth : alk. paper)
ISBN 978-0-8047-5941-o (pbk. : alk. paper)
r. Image (Philosophy) 2. Art-Philosophy. I. Title. II. Series: Cultural
memory in the present.
B105.l47W5413 2oro
m'.85-dc22
2009018393
Contents
Preface lX
Translator's Note Xt
Notes 135
Glossary 1 47
What Could ''Abstract
Photography" Be?
J
What Could "Abstract Photography" Be? 63
FIGURE 1. Alvin La ngd o n Cob urn (USA 1882- 1966 GB): Vottograph, 19 17. New
gela tin sil ve r print, 30.6 x 25.5 c m , ca. 1960. L. Fritz ,ruber Coll ection , Muse um
Ludwi g, Co logne. © Geo rge-Eas tm an- House, Rochester, NY.
visible form s und er normal li ght cond iti ons. The chemi gram practices a
techniqu e rhar raises rhe ques tion whether it docs nor absrracr from an
essenti al characteristi c of phorography, namely from des igning and form -
in g rhe li ght shining onto rhe paper. Gott fri ed Jage r, in any case, does nor
want ro do without this characreri sri c in a defi niti on of photography: " Ir is
j
What Could "Abstract Photography" Be? 67
th e princ ip le of rhe ana logy betwee n the cause and the effect of the li g ht.
Photos are brought about by electromagnetic radiation being cha nnel ed
a nd fi xed o n a material sensitive co rad iation. T hi s proposition applies for
simp le ca mera p hocographs, as we ll as for the most abst ract light co mposi -
tion s. Both are the direc t resu It of a physica l i ncerplay of ca uses and e ffects
char th ey p ic ture each in their own way." 1 H ere we see once again char rhe
a nswe r to the question What could "abstract photography" be? a lways de-
pends o n one's opinion about what phocography is as such. If phocographs
indeed "a re brought about by electromagnetic radi ation bein g c ha nn eled ,"
68 What Could "Abstrttct Photography" Be?
as we just saw, then the chemigram either crosses the boundary of what
can be abstracted or it constitutes an extreme kind of interpretation of this
characteristic. In this particular case the decision is particularly difficult
to make, for the chemicals themselves do indeed sit on the photo paper
like an object and act as a light-absorbent and thus light-channeling me-
dium, as is the case for the objects used in the photogram. Yet if this rest
of channeling of light were to be essential to a chemigram, we would not
be dealing with an autonomous form of abstract photography, just with a
variant of the photogram. Yet photograms and chemigrams can very well
be distinguished conceptually: the techniques of the photogram influence
the path oflight from the source onto the light-sensitive material, whereas
the techniques of the chemigram influence the effects oflight on the light-
sensitive material. In the case of the chemigram a photo is thus produced
because electromagnetic radiation is channeled and formed in its effect by
the photographer. Here, as in the case of every photo, we have the fixed
trace of a controlled cooperation of light and light-sensitive material. This
is exactly what we should not overlook: in the case of the chemigram
we precisely have not abstracted from an essential component of taking
photographs, namely from the fixation of a trace of light. It is very well
possible to think of dispensing with this fixation, as is the case for so-
called flux or fluid images. Differently disposed light-sensitive substances
arc exposed to nonformed light and lefr to this process; what we get is a
continuously developing, nonstopped chemigram. Where the light shows
what kind of effect might well have been influenced, yet if we demand-
as we have just said-that in a photo, channeled radiation is "fixed on a
material sensitive to radiation," we have to say that this fixation is missing.
Though flow images are conceivable and indeed familiar from Sigmar
Polke's work for the 1986 Venice Biennale, they do not fall under the con-
cept of abstract photography because they are no longer photographs at
all. In this extreme form of abstraction the photograph is reduced to the
mere sequence of a chemical process and is thus dissolved in a conceptual,
albeit not a chemical sense.
If we are to judge cameraless photography to be a form of abstract
photography, we are well advised to state precisely why this is to be the
case. We can think of two reasons. First, we could say that cameraless pho-
tography is abstract because it abstracts, during the taking of photographs,
What Could "Abstract Photography" Be? 69
L
70 What Could "Abstract Photography" Be?
bears only very vague and modest visible resemblance to real objects or
none at all. The abstract photo delivers no image object that-as is the
case in the so-called figurative picture-could be referred by means of its
resemblance to an existent or a fictitious object. Yet how does chis negative
description help? Saying what an abstract photo is not does not answer the
question What could abstract photographs be?The problem of abstract pho-
tography, remarkably, is not the simple statement that it does not display a
recognizable object, but the giving of reasons why and what for an abstract
photo abstracts from the depiction of a familiar object. The solution to
chis problem is related to the phenomenon, already presented above, that
every abstraction happens in order to direct attention to something that
is judged to be essential. When we abstract, we disregard something and
thereby show that we chink we can disregard it. Thereby, in turn, we show
that what we disregard, from our point of view, cannot be essential, since
essential things can, in principle, not be disregarded. That is why every
abstraction always leads to an exhibition of what is deemed essential; every
abstracting turn away is linked to a visualizing turn toward. This, howev-
er, means that abstract photography is only conceivable if its works forgo
picturing discernible objects in order to make something else all the more
clearly discernible. In the end the question What could "abstract photog-
raphy" be? is not answered by saying that it is nonfigurative photography.
This nondisplay can only be a necessary but not a sufficient characteristic
of abstract photography since photographs arc conceivable chat do not dis-
play any object and yet are not abstract photographs. On wrapping paper
that is produced with photographic means we might see pretty shapes but
not discern objects, yet the wrapping paper is not abstract photography
since this paper does not forgo displaying something for the sake of some-
thing else. Or let us imagine we developed and enlarged the unusable be-
ginning of a common film negative that has accidentally been exposed to
light: we would not get an abstract photo. We even have to go so far as to
say chat nondisplay cannot be the concern proper of abstract photography
but only a way of doing something else; if this something else-whatever
it is-is not actualized, nonfigurative photography is not abstract photog-
raphy. The question that stood at the beginning, What could "abstract pho-
tography" be?, has to be translated more precisely: What could be reasons for
producing photographs in which we cannot discern objects? Several answers
are conceivable; what follows is a presentation of three of them.
What Could "Abstract Photography" Be? 71
One answer to the question What could be reasons for producing pho-
tographs in which we cannot discern objects?that immediately presents itself
is the following: these photographs are meant to demonstrate that with
the medium of photography we can refer to something other than just ob-
jects and that this happens in figurative images as well. If abstract pho-
tography abstracts from picturing things for this reason, it is an emphatic
self-reflection in the medium of photography. With the means provided
by photography, abstract photography wants to answer the question of
what a photo is, and to this end it produces photographs that display what
in figurative images is an essential, albeit restricted, not independent, part.
This part is the "how" of the photo, the formal structures of a photograph
that make it possible for a figurative photograph to do what it does, name-
ly display an object. Every photograph comes about by means oflight trac-
es being developed into visible forms on a piece of paper. Yet these visible
forms, their figures and internal relations, serve a purpose: they exist not
for their own sake but to allow something to become visible, to display
what they themselves are not. When we look at a figurative picture, we
would not say we were looking at forms and colors. Even though the forms
are what we sec, our gaze, our intentional attention, is directed toward the
image object. Yet this image object is only visible because there arc forms
and colors, even though these do not as such enter the gaze of the normal
viewer. This does not, however, mean that they could not be made visible.
This is one reason for abstraction: the abstract picture can forgo display-
ing a thing in order thus to show how a photo displays an object. Looking
at the image object demands that we overlook the infrastructure. That is
why an abstract photo could be a photo that tries to display the otherwise
overlooked structures themselves. Something overlooked is being thema-
tized. If an abstract picture forgoes displaying a thing for this reason, the
forms and colors in the abstract photo are something fundamentally dif-
ferent from the forms and colors on a wallpaper: they are the forms and
colors that this medium can also use for the depiction of objects. Every
photo-that is, the figurative photo, too-comes about in a process of
structure formation. And precisely because this is the case for objective
photographs as well, abstraction from the objectivity of photographs is a
reduction of the picture to the very aspect that is essential to photography
L
72 What Could "Abstract Photography " Be?
A second a nswe r to the quest ion What could be reasons far produc-
ing photographs on which we cannot discern objects?, a n a nswe r th at doe
F I GU R E3. Carl Scr(.i we (D 1898- 1988): Ein Kristal! ist geb01n·1 (A C: rysrn l w~s
Born), 1946. Mi crophocograph . C rystals of asparagin e acid . Gelarin sil ver vin -
tage print, 54.7 x 43.8 cm. Kunsrha lle Bielefeld. © VG Bi ld-Kunst, Bonn/ Prof.
Go ttfried Jager, Bielefeld.
74 What Could "Abstract Photography" Be?
not present itself as immediately as the first, is the following: these pho:
tographs are meant to show that photographs can be images chat do no.
have to refer to anything at all. This thesis can be formulated differe nd Y·
. b · ages
ab stract Ph otograp h y ts meant to show chat photographs can e 11:1' c
th
that are not signs. Everything that is used for referring is a sign, and 10
fir st answer the structures indeed are used to refer to something: they e)(-
emplify the possibilities of photographic picturing [Abbilden]. The st nw
tura 1 f,ormattons
· · an a bstract photograph in the first answer are us ed as
m
signs: they stand for how something can become visible in a photo, Yet
does it have to be this way? We could think of an escalation: does the turf!
away from the object have to be a turn toward the "how" of photographic
displaying? It can be; that is not the question. But can the turn away fro~
the object not also be linked to a turn to something other than the "how
of displaying? This question concerns the sign character of abstract ph~-
tography. It is easily conceivable that an abstract photo also fulfill semi-
o t'1c purposes. Th'1s 1s
· not surpnsmg,
·· 1'f on Iy b ecause every o b'Ject a nd thus
also every image can be used as a sign. Yet, once more, the opposite, coo,
is at least conceivable, namely that an abstract photo forgoes displaying _a
familiar image object in order to consciously create an image object that is
not to be used as a sign at all. What is to be created is, as it were, an image
object that refuses the obvious use as a sign for a thing chat bears visib~c
resemblance to it because this image object docs not, at least not in chis
way, bear resemblance to any known real thing. .
In the case of a figurative image we construct an object whose vw
ibility we are familiar with, for example an exclusively visible house. In
the abstract photo, however, we are concerned with constructing objects
from pure visibility, objects that bear no resemblance to real things but arc
simply new, visibly determined objects, just as we are capable of construct-
ing both familiar and new objects outside of images. If we understand
abstract photography in this sense, then the medium of photography is
not used for picturing [abbilden] or visibly reproducing something but for
forming [bilden] and visibly producing something. The medium becomes
a tool for the generation of an artificial object. The concept of generative
photography aptly captures this understanding of the sense and purpose
of abstract photography: "It's not giving reality to a concept, it's presenting
a reality-that's photography." 6 Yet we have to be careful: the concepts
What Could "Abstract Photography" Be? 75
T hat thi s is almost always the case is beyond doubt ; almost eve rythin g
chat is produced photographica lly is an image. Yet here, too, the d ecisive
quest ion ca n only be Does it have to be this way, or can we also think of it
differently? Co uld it not be chat the use of photog raphy for th e product io n
of im ages is a contin genr- albeic w id espread- use? Could we not think
of photographs that are not im ages? We have here a qu est io n th at ta rgets
th e center of abstract photography. Abs tract photography makes it its pro-
gram to produ ce photographs that abstract from the contin ge nt pro perties
of the medium in ord er to emphasize its nonco ntin gent propert ies; thu s,
it mu st of course ask itse lf if not perh aps t he picto ri al cha racte r as a w ho le
is cont ingent fo r photography. A lvin Langdon Coburn, fittin g for a first
ancesto r, may have been the first to suspect thi s, sin ce he citi ed hi s 1916
programm atic essay on abstract ph otography The Future of Pictorial Pho-
j
What Could "Abstract Photography" Be? 77
5.
F IGU R E orcfricd Jager (D 1937): Cmukeil (Grays ale), 1983. Ph oto object.
Uniqu e gelatin sil ver paper, 25 x 25 cm. Co ll ection of rh e arri sr © 2007 by V
Bild-Kunst, Bonn/ Prof. Gottfried Jager, Bi elefeld .
Yet we mu st also sec t hat th e co ncept here acquires a mea ning different
from the one we o utlined above. For now it is no longer th e produc tion
of a co ncrete object in th e im age, that is, the ge nerat io n of a thing from
pure visibility, we a re dealin g with; it is the produ c tion of a thing that , like
a ny norm al thin g, ca n be to uched a nd smelt. T he exa mpl es for such an
understanding of abstract photography a re num erous, bur o ne must suf-
fi ce: Gorrfr ied Jage r's 1983 GraukeiL[G ray Ca rd] (fig. 5). In rhis work no
picturing [Abbi/den] of a nythin g ta kes pl ace; it is no t abo ut the pi ctoria l
produ ction of a purely pic toria l vis ibili ty but exclus ively about rh e u se of
the photograph in the materi al se nse as part of a n in sta ll ati o n. In GraukeiL
the photo paper, w hich in objec tive photography usua lly di spl ays three-
dimensiona l things, beco mes three-dim ensio na l itself: th e m ate ri al th at
displays takes th e pl ace of w hat is pictori a ll y di spl ayed . T he photo paper
What Could "Abstract Photography" Be? 79
as a rea l obj ect ousts the im agin a ry image obj ect- a nd t hus ousts the im -
age from a work of a rt.