Teaching History Master Narratives Fostering Imagi
Teaching History Master Narratives Fostering Imagi
Teaching History Master Narratives Fostering Imagi
net/publication/314463947
CITATIONS READS
35 907
1 author:
Mario Carretero
Universidad Autónoma de Madrid
162 PUBLICATIONS 3,383 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Mario Carretero on 09 May 2018.
Fostering Imaginations 3
Mario Carretero 4
History teachers everywhere are likely to present the past through a narrative 5
format while in classrooms students work with the class contents in differ- 6
ent ways. Traditionally, students received those stories rather passively: reading 7
them in books or repeating them in different ways. Fortunately, in the last 8
decades, these traditional practices and learning activities have changed. In this 9
Handbook, the contributions of several new approaches to history learning 10
and teaching can be found that consist of inquiry-based educational practices 11
(e.g. the chapters by Van Boxtel & Van Drie, Nokes, and Seixas). 12
Most of these proposals are related to the developments of seminal initia- 13
tives proposed by either British research (Dickinson, Lee, & Rogers, 1984) 14
or innovative German approaches (Retz, 2015; Rusen, 2004; Seixas, 2004, 15
AU1 2015a, 2015b) to History Education developed in the 1980s. All are based 16
on the purpose of developing historical thinking and historical consciousness 17
in school (Chapman & Wilschut, 2015). This is to say, to develop learning 18
activities around historical contents following the idea that History is a disci- 19
pline to think about and to reflect upon. These initiatives were partly motivated 20
by the research findings that history as a school subject was unable to capture 21
AU2 the interest of the students (Ravitch & Finn, 1988) and that students were 22
unable to understand historical contents properly (Beck & MacKeown, 1994). 23
This paper has been written with the support of Projects EDU2013-42531P and
EDU2015-65088-P from the DGICYT (Ministry of Education, Spain) and also the
Project PICT2012-1594 from the ANPCYT (Argentina) coordinated by the author.
Also this work was conducted within the framework of COST Action IS1205 “Social
psychological dynamics of historical representations in the enlarged European Union”.
M. Carretero (*)
Department of Psychology, Autonoma University, Madrid, Spain
myth, is labeled mythic. This stage extends from 2–3 years of age, until initiat- 67
ing literacy occurs around 6–8 years of age. Its central components consist of 68
binary structures (good–bad, rich–poor) and fantasy, a category that mediates 69
opposites: for example, ghosts as a mediating category between the dead and 70
the living. Therefore, small children are capable of understanding a story or 71
concept that is expressed in binary concepts. As such, they tend to understand 72
historic knowledge in school as a “tale” of “good and bad”, and the cen- 73
tral aspects of “time” and “space” (as historiographical categories) cannot be 74
understood except in a very basic sense. 75
Egan’s second stage of comprehension, called the romantic stage, is related 76
to the beginning of alphabetization and oriented toward the development of 77
rationality and takes place approximately between ages 9 and 12. The binary 78
structures decrease to make space for a more complicated reality. This stage’s 79
characteristics are associated with knowledge of the limits of reality and identity. 80
There persists, however, a desire to go beyond these limits, a desire embodied 81
by the figure of the hero. This is a stage situated between mythos and logos, in 82
which individuals and their emotions become relevant. These narrative abili- 83
ties permit an understanding of historic knowledge closer to historiography. 84
However, several limitations remain due to the tendency toward a heroic and 85
romantic nature of this cosmovision, in which characters and individual figures 86
have great importance in the causality of historic phenomena. 87
The third stage, the philosophic, is fundamentally characterized by the 88
search for relationships and can be reached by approximately age 12–15, after 89
having accumulated the abilities from the two previous stages. It involves going 90
beyond the romantic interest in details to searching the theory, law, and general 91
models. It is precisely this search for integrating and totalizing models that 92
makes youth vulnerable to dogmatism and unconditionally defensive of vari- 93
ous “absolute truths”. A risk that characterizes this stage is the rigidity of laws 94
and concepts that sustain general models, such as ignorance of the flexibility 95
and versatility of reality. Another characteristic of this stage is the transition 96
from heroes to the appearance of complex understanding of social agents, thus 97
passing from individual deeds to an abstract representation of social processes. 98
The last stage of narrative development consists of ironic comprehension, 99
which is characteristic of adult life. It is necessary to clarify that although it 100
is considered “last”, it is not a guaranteed stage of development. Rather, it is 101
reached as long as there is adequate cultural appropriation. Ironic comprehen- 102
sion is characterized by a high level of reflection on one’s own thoughts and 103
by sensitivity toward the limited nature of conceptual resources that can be 104
employed to understand the world. Therefore, the irony consists of having a 105
mind sufficiently open to recognize the insufficient flexibility of our minds. 106
One of the principle features of this stage consists of disregarding the concept 107
of a totalizing “truth”, while at the same time developing the capacity to rec- 108
ognize the multifaceted nature of the social world. 109
Egan’s theory of understanding narrative highlights the influence of the 110
first narrations over the later adult comprehension of the world. At the same 111
514 M. CARRETERO
112 time, this theory provides several guidelines regarding the goals that students
113 must achieve when understanding history, principally through its narrative
114 components. Therefore, as shown below, developing a vision that is critical,
115 flexible, and distanced from dogmatism, typical of the ironic stage, and also the
116 improvement of different restrictions from the mythic, romantic, and philo-
117 sophic stages, constitute cognitive achievements that can establish the base
118 of better historic literacy. But narrative and cognitive development in general
119 does not happen in a vacuum but in and educational context. The relations of
120 narrative development theories with historical contents representation will be
121 mentioned later on in this paper. For the moment, let us see some important
122 aspects of the educational context of historical narratives.
toward an ideal of progress and civilization continue to be the prototypical way 155
through which many historians and textbooks disseminate knowledge. This 156
observation demonstrates the predominate presence of these types of narratives 157
in the teaching of history. An analysis of its characteristics and its influence over 158
the students’ abilities when learning history can provide clues about some of 159
the skills those students need in this regard. 160
The individual narratives are those focused around the personal lives of rel- 161
evant historic figures, in comparison with those in which the focus is on more 162
abstract entities and events such as nations, economic systems, social change, 163
civilizations, and impersonal concepts of this nature. Frequently, these figures 164
are on the sidelines of other events and individuals that comprise the histori- 165
cal context, and the most controversial aspects of their lives are generally not 166
shown (Alridge, 2006). However, in the informal ambit, these narratives begin 167
to join other more anonymous narratives, above all those from novels and 168
movies. 169
The use of this type of individual narrative is justified, in part, due to the fact 170
that the more abstract accounts are identified as likely more difficult to under- 171
stand and as motivating students to a lesser degree. As Barton and Levstik 172
(2004) indicate, these individual narratives have the power to humanize his- 173
tory. Students may identify with these characters and put themselves in their 174
place in order to gain an idea of the feelings that guided them and even to 175
imagine how they might have acted in those situations. Through these nar- 176
ratives, students also learn to value the role that one individual can play in a 177
society and contemplate the possible impact of one individual. 178
Nevertheless, although these last narratives can be a highly motivating com- 179
ponent and more easily understood by students, they also produce a series of 180
characteristic biases that complicate the acquisition of a historic literacy. For 181
example, when narratives are exclusively for individual and personal use, there 182
is an absence of causal explanations of a structural nature based on social, polit- 183
ical, or economic factors. At the same time, the impact produced by collective 184
action is unknown. 185
In any case, there are negative effects for the type of causal explanations 186
that students employ when understanding history. When students face more 187
abstract texts that are more difficult for them to understand, they attempt to 188
use individual narratives as a tool for comprehension in order to give meaning 189
to the narration. From there, they search for individual motives or reasons that 190
will allow them to understand what occurred. As noted by Halldén (1986), in 191
an analysis of the explanations given by students about certain historical events, 192
these explanations focus on the actions and intentions of individuals. For these 193
students, the object of study in history is persons or personified phenomena. 194
To Halldén this personification of historical explanations can arise in various 195
aspects: 196
One aspect of personalization is connected with the view that the course 197
of history is directed by Great Men (Grever, 2009; Smith, 1998). A sec- 198
ond aspect concerns the personification of the state, political institutions, 199
516 M. CARRETERO
200 and other organizations. A third has to do with the tendency of students
201 to transform structural explanations into the kind of explanation where the
202 actions or needs of the people constitute the explanations (Halldén, 2000).
203 Riviere et al. in an interesting study (2000) showed similar results.
204 Therefore, a predominant use of these individual narratives can foster the
205 emergence of these biases in historical explanations, while they develop a vision
206 of history as a fragmented series of stories about celebrities. It seems evident
207 that the predominant use of these narratives can complicate students’ learning
208 of a contextualized history, in which there is space for important aspects such
209 as social, political, and economic factors and the role of different social groups.
210 History should provide these students with knowledge of the complexities,
211 contradictions, and nuances of that history, while this type of narrative pres-
212 ents simplistic and one-dimensional portraits (Alridge, 2006). This is to say, in
213 terms of Egan’s views these individual narratives and this personified under-
214 standing would prevent an understanding closer to philosophical and ironic
215 ways of narrative representations.
closed, unique, and true (Van Sledright, 2008). At this point, it is important to 243
take into account the ironic stage mentioned above by Egan´s ideas about the 244
development of narratives. 245
This type of narrative, however, not only diminishes the importance of 246
these “other histories”, but also influences the type of causal explanations stu- 247
dents give to specific historic events. Taking the term used by Wertsch (1998) 248
these national narratives become a kind of schematic narrative template –more 249
abstract and generic narratives that are socially shared—which influence is 250
fundamental when building specific historical narratives. For example, in the 251
case of the U.S., there are two present schematic narrative templates in the 252
vast majority of national narratives, the concept of progress and that of lib- 253
erty. Therefore, students use these schematic narrative templates to explain 254
past events. Consequently, the resistance of Native Americans facing waves of 255
European colonists is seen as an obstacle in achieving progress and the Vietnam 256
War is justified by the need to bring freedom to that country. Students, due 257
to excessive use of these national narratives, do not have access to the most 258
controversial aspects of history, complicating the development of a more criti- 259
cal perspective that will allow them to consider the difficulties, dilemmas, and, 260
in short, the reality of the democratic realities in which they live (Carretero & 261
Kriger, 2011; Epstein, 2009; Grever & Stuurman, 2007). 262
Interestingly enough Social Psychology studies have shown that national 263
narratives representations are not only mental states but they can be trans- 264
lated into political actions (Barreiro, Castorina and Van Alphen, this Hanbook; 265
Smeekes, 2014). For example, let us see some of our results in the present and 266
very complicated Greek context of both economic crisis and immigration. The 267
following cases come from data collected from the large pool of comments 268
published in the online forum created by the Greek Ministry of Internal Affairs 269
(http://www.opengov.gr/ypes/?p=327) following the announcement of the 270
legislation: “Current provisions for Greek citizenship, the political participa- 271
tion of repatriated Greeks and lawfully resident immigrants and other provi- 272
sions” (see Kadianaki, Andreouli, & Carretero, 2016 for details). Therefore, 273
they represent not just answers to a research questionnaire, but a real and 274
everyday use of historical ideas developed as political attempts to influence new 275
immigration regulations. More specifically, ideas about the past used with the 276
purpose of defending a particular view on citizenship. Thus, one of our com- 277
mentators says, 278
Even in ancient Athens at the time when it was an exemplar city-state (that we use 279
constantly as an example) there was a clear distinction between Athenian citizens 280
and those who came from other cities but concentrated in it [Athens], in order to 281
enjoy [its] glamour and economic development. The metrics as they called them, did 282
not originate from there [ancient Athens], they lived within the borders of the city- 283
state but they usually had limited or no political rights. Political rights in Athens 284
were given only in special circumstances but even in those cases they could become 285
PEOPLE WITH EQUAL DUTIES-, but not CITIZENS. This was the protection 286
518 M. CARRETERO
287 of the system, since the foreigner could not participate in the decisions of the City
288 Council or claim some sort of political power. With regards to financial assistance
289 on the part of the Athenian democracy towards non-citizens it was probably non-
290 existent, since they were not entitled to a wage. On the contrary, there existed eco-
291 nomic duties of the metics towards the city, like the metikion [type of taxation specific
292 to metics], which was part of the official revenues of the state or the theorika [type of
293 taxation], for the wealthy metics. And all this applied to Greeks of other cities, every-
294 one else was simply… “barbarian” (Filakismenos).
295 Through the analysis of several comments as this one, we identified four
296 themes in the ways that national history is represented to formulate argu-
297 ments about citizenship rights and boundaries in our data: (1) continuity of
298 the nation; (2) idealization of the past; (3) moral obligation toward the past;
299 (4) homogeneity or heterogeneity of the nation.
300 As Van Alphen and Carretero (2015) note, idealization of the past leads to
301 perceiving the past as a moral example to follow in the present. Thus, ideas
302 about idealization are complemented by ideas of moral obligation that we sub-
303 sequently examine. Thus morality is a recognized feature of historical narra-
304 tives. Gergen (2005) has suggested that historical narratives construct a moral
305 status for the actors involved in the story. Studies on history “consumption”
306 reveal that students’ historical narratives contain a positive moral judgment and
307 legitimization of the national group actions (Lopez, Carretero, & Rodriguez-
308 Moneo, 2015a). Interestingly enough in our previous studies, our coincident
309 results were found with high school and university students in both Spain
310 and Argentina (Carretero & Kriger, 2011; Carretero & Van Alphen, 2014).
311 Therefore, it looks like there is a clear coincidence between formal schooling
312 and informal uses and representations of history among citizens.
322 1. As is the case in the above example about Greek citizens internet com-
323 ments on Citizenship regulations, the historical subject is established in
324 terms of inclusion and exclusion, radically opposing it to others as a coher-
325 ent and homogeneous group. See above the distinction between the
326 “metekos” and the “Greek” where an imagined homogeneity of the
327 nation is defended and conceived as having very clear historical roots.
328 Therefore the establishment of the nation is based on a pre-existent and
TEACHING HISTORY MASTER NARRATIVES: FOSTERING IMAGINATIONS 519
everlasting historical subject. Of course this determines the main voice of 329
the narrative. As is well known, any narrative strongly depends on who its 330
subject is. Another important feature of this dimension is precisely that the 331
establishment of the narrative subject follows a nonhistorical process. This 332
is to say the historical subject is not seen as a result of a number of changes 333
across different times but as something prior to those historical transfor- 334
mations. This is to say this “historical subject” is in fact an “essentialist and 335
nonhistorical subject” based on a process of continuity between the past 336
and the present. Also besides this continuity citizens tend to see the his- 337
torical subject as homogenous instead of heterogeneous. This is to say all 338
the members of this imagined national community (Anderson, 1983) is 339
seen as a prototypical part of if instead of considering the possibility of 340
different and heterogeneous groups of nationals. As it can be easily seen 341
this is a very idealized conception of the nationals of any community. 342
2. The historical subject is referred to in the first person plural “us,” often 343
logically opposed to “them,” and valued more positively. The presence of 344
an identification process with the mentioned historical subject and its 345
political unit. Identification processes are at work in the narrative, attach- 346
ing personal affect and value judgments to the unification and opposition 347
mentioned above. A shared identity—a timeless national identity— 348
between the present storyteller and the past historical subject is estab- 349
lished. Of course the continuity feature mentioned earlier is also related 350
to this identification feature is adding very influential emotional ties. This 351
implies that the person not only has a historical misconception about her 352
national origin but also feels this misconception as an emotional content. 353
This process would be responsible for establishing the origins of the per- 354
sons (as nationals) who are learning the concept. These (national) origins 355
would be considered ontological instead of constructed through pre- 356
cisely a historical process. 357
3. The historical events are simplified around one common narrative 358
theme, such as the search for freedom or territory. This simplification is 359
based on rather simple causal relations. Basically it is a monocausal expla- 360
nation instead of being multicausal as most of sophisticated historical 361
explanations. In relation to previous two dimensions, this explanation 362
only considers the freedom of a specific group: the freedom of the his- 363
torical subject. The narrative tends to minimize, and avoids mentioning, 364
the right to freedom of additional and possible subjects, such as natives, 365
slaves, or women. Also, this particular freedom is considered in a teleo- 366
logical way, as the pre-established outcome of the historical processes. 367
The existence of a natural territory belonging “since ever” to the nation, 368
instead of a conception of the correspondence of nations and their ter- 369
ritories as the result of different complex political, social, and historical 370
processes. Needless to say this historical territory is precisely the same 371
territory than the present one. This is to say the present territory is con- 372
sidered as an ontological a priori. 373
520 M. CARRETERO
374 4. The application of moral features that legitimize the actions of the
375 nation and the nationals. Especially in relation to national territory
376 and all the actions related to its developments and changes. These
377 moral judgments provide a tautological legitimization for the nation’s
378 main acts. National historical narratives, both in and out school, play
379 an important role as moral vectors, because they are designed with
380 that goal in mind. This purpose is accomplished in at least two ways:
381 First, the master narrative establishes the distinction between “good”
382 and “bad” options, people, and decisions. Typically, the first one is
383 associated with the national “we”, and the second one is related to
384 “they”. Also master narratives offer living examples of civic virtue,
385 particularly of loyalty. As it can be easily inferred, this loyalty func-
386 tion was essential in the construction of the nation, and it can still be
387 found in many symbolic forms out of the school like sports for
388 example.
389 5. Essentialist concept of the nation and nationals. They are both pre-
390 sented as entities that predate the processes that led to their creation,
391 independent of historical development. Our empirical studies show that
392 historical concepts (e.g. nation, revolution, and independence) are
393 expressed within the framework of the general structures provided by
394 master narratives. Adolescents use a concept to construct a narrative and,
395 at the same time, that narrative expresses the concept itself. Therefore,
396 concepts play a double role in historical narratives. On a level of analysis,
397 they are tools for building narratives, giving them meaning and direc-
398 tion. At the same time, the characteristics of the concepts are defined
399 through the narratives, which contextualize and particularize them
400 (Carretero, Castorina, & Levinas, 2013).
401 Let us present some examples which illustrate these dimensions. In the case of
402 Spain, the selected task has been about the so called “Reconquest—a period AU4
403 in which the Spanish nation did not exist—began in 718 and ended in 1492
404 with the expulsion of Muslims from the Iberian Peninsula. This process was
405 reinterpreted through romantic historiography and became a master national
406 narrative based on the loss of Spain to the Muslims and its subsequent recovery.
407 Spanish national identity has been built upon this one (Alvarez Junco, 2011).
408 However as Ríos Saloma (2005) pointed out, the very term “Reconquest” just
409 appears in the late eighteenth century. In this sense, we can say that the very
410 idea of the Reconquest is an “invented” concept if we apply the essential idea
411 of Hobsbawm and Ranger (1983) that national traditions are invented solely
412 to give legitimacy to the national past. Similarly, one could also say that “the
413 Reconquest” is an “imagined” concept because it helps to imagine the nation,
414 as Anderson states (1983). However, the empirical facts of the 800 years of
415 Muslim presence on the Iberian Peninsula and the fighting between Christians
416 and Muslims during that time should instead be defined as successive con-
417 quests by different sides. Importantly, there was not a single struggle between
TEACHING HISTORY MASTER NARRATIVES: FOSTERING IMAGINATIONS 521
Christians and Muslims, but over 800 years, alliances varied among certain 418
Christian and Muslim factions, and there was also infighting among factions of 419
the same religion. 420
One important objective of our studies has been to comparatively look at 421
citizens’ representations about a similar narrative of another nation. Through 422
using a foreign historical event, we aim to analyze the student’s view on 423
national narratives once their identity connection and emotional link with the 424
content is minimized. For this reason, we presented Spanish university students 425
a task about the history of Greece. The period analyzed refers to the so-called 426
“Ottoman occupation of Greece” (1492–1850) and the nation’s subsequent 427
independence. Therefore, in both cases, students faced a historical task where 428
either Muslims or Turks remained several centuries in a country, which cur- 429
rently is a national state (Spain and Greece). As our students were Spanish we 430
hypothesized that they’d demonstrate different historical interpretations for 431
these two similar historical scenarios. This is to say, we predicted that the previ- 432
ously mentioned dimensions would be much more present in the task about 433
Spain than in the task about Greece (Lopez, Carretero, & Rodriguez-Moneo, 434
2015a, 2015b). In general terms, this was indeed the case. Let us see some 435
examples. 436
In both cases, the interview was very similar and focused on each period in 437
chronological order. For each period the participant was asked about: (1) who 438
the inhabitants of either the Iberian peninsula or the Balkan Peninsula at that 439
time were, (2) the legitimacy of the actions of one group against the other, and 440
(3) whether these were carried out by the inhabitants for the gain of territory. 441
Let us compare these two interview fragments. The first belongs to an inter- 442
view about the so-called Spanish Reconquest and the second to an interview 443
on the Greek independence process. 444
[And whom do you think that territory belonged to?] Well, at that moment it is 445
true that it would be dominated by Arabs, but it was still of the Spaniards…Even 446
though it had been taken by force, but sooner or later they had to expel the Arabs. 447
(…) [The conquests you have drawn (making reference to the further 448
Christian conquests in the year 1212), do you think they were legitimate?] 449
Conquests in the opposite way, to throw them out? Well, they seem to me more legiti- 450
mate. A bit more legitimate yes, because they are like recovering what was taken 451
from them. Well, wars are not alright, but I do think it could be slightly justified. 452
To recover their territory and customs and whatever they were not allowed to do by 453
the Arabs. (Sara, 22 years old). 454
[Does it seem to you that it legitimately belongs to (the Byzantines) at that 455
time?] Well, at that time, they had won it, right? So to speak. However, I also don’t 456
think that a territory belongs to anyone concretely … (…) it is not attached to 457
anyone. (…) [In that sense, does it seem to you that the territory (in the period 458
of the Ottoman Empire) legitimately belongs to the Ottomans or not?] No, as 459
with the Byzantines, it is a matter of ambition to have more territories but I do not 460
see that it has to belong to anyone as I said with the Byzantines… (…). It does not 461
belong permanently to anyone. (…) [In the period of Greek independence, does 462
522 M. CARRETERO
463 it seem to you that the territory legitimately belongs to the Greeks?] No, not to
464 them either. [Why?] Well, what I have said before, the territories are there, and an
465 empire that wants to have more territories, well they are going to conquer them, but
466 I don’t think that because of this it always owns this territory and that the territory
467 has always belonged to it, because it is not so. It is not going to be like this forever
468 (Belen, 17 years old).
469 As it can be seen in the case of the interview about Spain, the Spanish student
470 clearly legitimizes the actions of the Spaniards against the Arabs, applying
471 some of the dimensions presented above. But it is not the case for the Spanish
472 student interviewed about the presence of the Ottomans in Greek territory.
473 In both cases, the participants are university students, and therefore, their
474 historical knowledge in general is rather high. Considering this, the more
475 plausible explanation for the difference encountered would be based on the
476 relation of the interview’s main topic with the participant’s national identity.
477 Interestingly, this difference disappears when the interview deals with the
478 establishment of the historical subject.
479 But let us compare two more examples. The first is related to the Spanish
480 Reconquest and the second to the Greeks and the Ottomans. These examples
481 will show that there are also some similarities. In this case about the establish-
482 ment of the historical subject of the narratives.
483 The Arabs invade a territory, which is not theirs. During more than seven centuries
484 they keep trying to conquer what is the entire Spanish territory and, the Spaniards,
485 when it in fact was in essence their territory before the Arabs came in, hey recon-
486 quered it again to make it once again their own. (Juan, 25 years old).
487 [How long could the feeling of belonging to the Greek nation have been
488 present?]
489 I think since forever. (…) If we forget history … there has always been a feeling of
490 saying I belong to Greece, to ancient Greece (…). And then came a moment in which
491 you say, “So far and so further!” One after another spreads the word; (…) they create
492 that feeling until they say: “We have been invaded by the Romans, the Byzantines,
493 the Ottomans; now is our moment.” (…) “Now is the time for us to rebel and become
494 independent as Greeks” (Maria, 21 years old).
495 As it can be seen in both cases, the two Spanish students establish a rather
496 essentialist historical subject. Thus in both cases this historical subjects are
497 fundamentally based on present national subjects and not on historical
498 changes and developments. As mentioned above, Spain and Spaniards do
499 not exist properly speaking until the sixteenth century. The Kingdoms of
500 Castile, Aragon and other similar political entities of the Iberian Peninsula
501 carried out the fights against the Arabs. Similar arguments could be applied
502 to the Greek case. Therefore, it can be concluded that analyzing the nar-
503 ratives about these two topics as a whole a more historiographical view on
504 historical narratives is easier to apply when they have to do with nations
505 that are not our own. Nevertheless, a number of difficulties remain, like the
506 concept related to the establishment of the historical subject. This is likely
TEACHING HISTORY MASTER NARRATIVES: FOSTERING IMAGINATIONS 523
to be related to the issue of the possible origins of the dimensions described 507
above. This issue of origins is also related to the educational implications of 508
our research. 509
We could think of two possible origins for these dimensions of national nar- 512
ratives: cognitive, educational, and sociocultural. Firstly, in terms of cognitive 513
development, it is easy to see how the dimensions we have described are very 514
much related to the romantic stage studied by Egan and mentioned above. 515
Therefore, it seems that the features of the philosophical and ironic stages 516
are difficult to achieve. On the other hand, from an educational point of view 517
within both formal and informal contexts, as museums and similar environ- 518
ments, traditional instruction still dominates, with explicit or implicit con- 519
tent that is closer to the romantic ideals than to the renovated aims of history 520
education. Also, history, as an academic discipline, still has advocates for the 521
romantic approach (see Berger, this volume, about national historiographical 522
writings) and many school textbooks and programs (Seixas, 2010)—mainly 523
through master national narratives—emphasize that banal nationalism that 524
Billig (1995) described. 525
In addition, banal nationalism is still present on a day-to-day basis in most 526
nations, particularly in the informal context, through national celebrations 527
and rites, movies, novels, or mass media communication (Carretero, 2011; 528
Wineburg, Mosborg, Porat, & Duncan, 2007). All of these mechanisms are 529
related to the process of the production of a narrative around the concept of 530
the nation. This process has been postulated as one of the most influential in 531
the social sciences nowadays, and much theoretical work has been developed 532
about how nations are imagined (Anderson, 1983; Hobsbawm & Ranger, 533
1983). Also, as signaled by Billig, when nations are granted a monopoly over 534
the right to violence within their territory, historical conflicts become nation- 535
alized. These conflicts evolve into wars among nations instead of counties, 536
nobles, or royal lineages. This phenomenon undoubtedly is reflected in the 537
history of many nations today that nationalize territorial conflicts from epochs 538
much earlier than the birth of the nation itself. Thus, national narratives fol- 539
lowing the same general scheme of the so-called reconquest can be found in 540
many a nation’s interpretation of history (Carretero, 2011; Wertsch, 2002). As 541
a matter of fact, many more examples can be found all over the world (see for 542
example chapters by Millas and Maier in this Handbook). 543
Let’s just consider the changes in European territories and nations during 544
the so-called short century (Hobsbawm, 1990). This is to say, the First and 545
Second World Wars, plus the collapse of the Soviet Union, introducing fre- 546
quent and dramatic changes on the political map of the European continent. 547
It would be interesting to investigate whether students are able to understand 548
that those changes in the nations’ territories not only constitute geopolitical 549
524 M. CARRETERO
550 and historical consequences but also imply that nations are not essential and
551 immutable political entities. Thus, the possible cognitive origins of the studied
552 conceptions, we think, have to do with how the learning and teaching process
553 takes place. For this reason, these cognitive origins are considered in the con-
554 text of specific suggestions to improve those processes.
555 For example, teachers could emphasize that the concept of nation is embed-
556 ded in a particular national narrative, and this narrative usually has a histori-
557 cal subject, but that other possible subjects could also be taken into account.
558 Even though these new subjects could change the meaning of the narrative,
559 presenting alternative historical versions of the past could be a fruitful learn-
560 ing strategy. Concerning the second dimension discussed in this chapter, stu-
561 dents could learn the important distinction between the past and the present
562 in relation to possible identification, that is, to understand that the historical
563 “we” is not the same as the current “we.” In this research, we have found that
564 university students tend to confound the two “we’s,” but at younger ages this
565 tendency could be much greater. This teaching endeavor would likely need not
566 only specific contents but also a good deal of metacognitive ability which is a
567 related aspect of historical consciousness (Straub, 2005).
568 In relation to the territorial dimension of the concept of nation, we would
569 like to emphasize the need for and the convenience of introducing historical
570 maps to school teaching activities. This is because our studies show university
571 students tend to consider the present map both Spain and Portugal as the
572 map that better describes historical changes over the centuries on the Iberian
573 Peninsula. But definitely it is not the case because Spain and Portugal just
574 existed as political entities since fifteenth-sixteenth century. Therefore, histori-
575 cal maps are an essential part of historical literacy and research, because they
576 provide a clear and precise representation of how territories and nations have
577 changed over centuries. As mentioned above, they are probably the clearest
578 proof that nations are not essential entities. But some students might tend
579 to consider the present maps as either immutable or as cognitive anchors for
580 representing historical events and political changes. In relation to this, recent
581 historiographical research has showed that the so-called historical rights are
582 based on rather invented knowledge about historical boundaries (Herzog, this
583 Handbook). This is to say, many of the ancient historical limits never existed as
584 very precise borders. Therefore, it would be unjustified to use them to main-
585 tain territorial rights based on supposed past evidence. No doubt these findings
586 have clear implications for history teaching and learning.
587 Conclusion
588 Finally, the issue of legitimizing the pursuit of the national territory, as
589 an imagined entity through the master narrative, in its different historical
590 moments could be approached along the lines already described. This is to
591 say, students could be taught that historical events indeed have moral con-
592 notations but that these can only be properly understood in the context of
TEACHING HISTORY MASTER NARRATIVES: FOSTERING IMAGINATIONS 525
the historiographical understanding of that specific period. One of the most 593
common misconceptions in history learning is presentism, in the sense of 594
projecting the nation to earlier periods. These examples will allow to illus- 595
trate a very strong tendency in its moral form. Any teaching development 596
oriented at promoting historical thinking should try to improve this through 597
the modern representation of the concept of nation embedded in historical 598
narratives. A concept not associated with the need of legitimizing the actions 599
of present subjects is definitely different from legitimizing past historical 600
subjects’ actions. 601
Thus, students might benefit from the combination of these suggested 602
strategies in order to take into account this complexity. Elsewhere (Carretero 603
& Lee, 2014) we have pointed out how, on numerous occasions, learning to 604
think historically entails navigating counterintuitive ideas (Wineburg, 2001). 605
For this purpose, we believe that future investigations are necessary to delve 606
deeper into this concept, whose adequate understanding would prepare stu- 607
dents for understanding the past and present complexity of the societies in 608
which they live. Also, we would like to emphasize that, as present citizens of 609
a world experiencing an intense globalization process, clearly our learning 610
needs to be closer to a flexible and nuanced narrative of the nation. Migration 611
processes will be even more intense in the future, and as this is having an enor- 612
mous cultural impact, the learning of history in and out of school, particularly 613
when it concerns the nation, has to keep up. 614
References 615
Lopez., C., Carretero, M., & Rodriguez-Moneo, M. (2015a). Conquest or Reconquest? 686
Students’ Conceptions of Nation Embedded in a Historical Narrative. Journal of 687
the Learning Sciences, 24(2), 252–285. 688
Lopez, C., Carretero, M., & Rodríguez-Moneo, M. (2015b). Telling a National 689
Narrative That Is Not Your Own. Does It Enable Disciplinary Historical 690
Consumption? Culture & Psychology., 4, 547–571. 691
Mink, L. O. (1978). Narrative Form as a Cognitive Instrument. Historical 692
Understanding, 182–203, 197–198. 693
Penuel, W. R., & Wertsch, J. V. (2000). Historical Representation as Mediated Action: 694
Official History as a Tool. In J. F. Voss & M. Carretero (Eds.), Learning and 695
Reasoning in History (pp. 39–60). New York: Routledge. 696
Ravitch, D., & Finn Jr., C. E. F. (1988). What Do Our 17-Year Olds Know? A Report 697
on the First National Assessment of History and Literature. New York: Harper & Row. 698
AU6 Retz, T. (2015). At the Interface: Academic History, School History and the Philosophy 699
of History. Journal of Curriculum Studies. 700
Ricoeur, P. (2004). Memory, History, Forgetting. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago 701
Press. (Original work published 2003). 702
Rios Saloma, M. F. (2005). From the Restoration to the Reconquest: The Construction 703
of a National Myth (An Historiographical Review. 16th–19th Centuries). En la 704
España medieval [In medieval Spain], 28, 379–414. 705
Rivière, A., Nuñez, M., Barquero, B., & Fontela, F. (2000). Influence of Intentional 706
and Personal Factors in Recalling Historical Text. In J. F. Voss & M. Carretero 707
(Eds.), Learning and Reasoning in History. International Review of History 708
Education (Vol. 2, pp. 214–226). New York: Routledge. 709
Rüsen, J. (2004). Historical Consciousness: Narrative Structure, Moral Function, and 710
Ontogenetic Development. In P. Seixas (Ed.), Theorizing Historical Consciousness 711
(pp. 63–85). Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press. 712
Seixas, P. (Ed.). (2004). Theorizing Historical Consciousness. Toronto, Canada: 713
University of Toronto Press. 714
Seixas, P. (2010). National History and Beyond. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 41(6), 715
719–722. 716
Seixas, P. (2015a). A Model of Historical Thinking. Educational Philosophy and Theory. 717
doi:10.1080/00131857.2015.1101363. 718
AU7 Seixas, P. (2015b). Translation and Its Discontents: Key Concepts in English and 719
German History Education. Journal of Curriculum Studies 47(6) (October). 720
Smeekes, A.N. (2014). The Presence of the Past. Historical Rooting of National Identity 721
and Current Group Dynamics. Doctoral dissertation, Utrecht University. 722
Smith, B. G. (1998). The Gender of History. Men, Women, and Historical Practice. 723
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 724
Straub, J. (Ed.). (2005). Narration, Identity, and Historical Consciousness. New York: 725
Berghahn Books. 726
Van Alphen, F., & Carretero, M. (2015). The Construction of the Relation Between 727
National Past and Present in the Appropriation of Historical Master Narratives. 728
Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 49(3), 512–530. 729
Van Sledright, B. (2008). Narratives of Nation-State, Historical Knowledge and School 730
History Education. Review of Research in Education, 32(1), 109–146. 731
Wertsch, J. (1998). Mind as Action. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. 732
Wertsch, J. V. (2002). Voices of Collective Remembering. Cambridge: Cambridge 733
University Press. 734
528 M. CARRETERO
735 Wineburg, S. (2001). Historical Thinking and Other Unnatural Acts. Philadelphia:
736 Temple University Press.
737 Wineburg, S., Mosborg, S., Porat, D., & Duncan, A. (2007). Common Belief and the
738 Cultural Curriculum: An Intergenerational Study of Historical Consciousness.
739 American Educational Research Journal, 44, 40–76.
740 White, H. (1987). The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical
741 Representation. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press.
742 Zerubavel, E. (2003). Time Maps: Collective Memory and the Social Shape of the Past.
743 Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Author Queries
Chapter No.: 27 0002829103