Philo
Philo
Philo
www.continuumbooks.com
Preface viii
Introduction 1
1. Studying philosophy 3
What is philosophy? 3
What philosophers think about 5
Why study philosophy? 8
What does studying philosophy involve? 10
Summary 13
2. Reading philosophy 15
What to read 15
The reading list 15
How to read 27
Reading philosophically 27
What makes reading philosophy challenging? 48
Summary 66
3. Taking notes 69
Why is note-taking important? 69
Recording what you have learned 69
Engaging with the material 70
Content – what should I write down? 70
Summarizing material 70
Evaluating material 71
Recording your sources 72
Method – how should I go about taking notes? 72
Use your own words 73
Use quotations carefully 73
Leave plenty of room on the page 74
Distinguish between different types of information 74
vi CONTENTS
Index 181
Preface
Once you have decided that philosophy is for you and obtained a
place at university, probably the first thing you will be asked to do is
to read some philosophy. You may well be sent a reading list before
you even arrive in the department, and this can help you to prepare
for the coming year. So, in Chapter 2, ‘Reading philosophy’, we set
out what to do when faced with a reading list, and how to go about
analysing various texts.
While reading and in lectures and tutorials you will need to take
notes, and we set out strategies for doing so in Chapter 3, ‘Taking
notes’.
You will usually be asked to prepare reading and notes before
attending philosophy classes, and Chapter 4, ‘Discussion’, concerns
seminars and tutorials. We suggest ways in which you can get the
most out of your time spent discussing philosophy, both in and out
of class.
The culmination of reading and talking about philosophy is
usually an essay or paper, so we move on to look at the topic of
writing philosophy. In Chapter 5, ‘Writing philosophy’, we set out
the different kinds of questions you might face, and work through
example essay questions to help you get a better idea of what you
need to be thinking about when you write your own essays.
Chapter 6, ‘Resources’, contains information about books and
articles mentioned in the preceding chapters, resources you might
find useful during your course of study, and advice about how to
find and use them effectively. It also features a short glossary of
terms that should help you as you begin your studies.
We hope that in focusing on the different sorts of activity
involved in a philosophy degree, and going through them in the
same order that most students will face them, you will be well
prepared for what lies ahead. This book can be used by people
thinking about whether they want to study philosophy, in order to
get a better idea of what is involved. It is mainly aimed at the first
year undergraduate student, regardless of background or prior
educational experience. We hope that the information and advice
on making the transition to degree-level study of philosophy will
be useful throughout your course.
1 Studying philosophy
What is philosophy?
Philosophy is not quite like any other subject. Even professional
philosophers find it notoriously difficult to define philosophy, and
often shy away from stating what ‘philosophy is’ in favour of giving
examples of the sorts of things that philosophers do. The dictionary
definition of ‘philosophy’ (and the literal translation of the Greek
origins of the word) is ‘the love of wisdom’, which covers just about
everything; and indeed philosophy encompasses the study of
science, and art, and language – for just about any subject you can
think of, there will be a ‘philosophy of’ that subject.
So, what sets philosophy apart from other disciplines? Although
philosophy does have its own unique areas of enquiry, one of its
most distinctive features is not so much what you study as how you
study it – and it is this which makes the experience of studying
philosophy quite different from that of any other subject. In
philosophy, we learn to identify, and think carefully about, our
most basic ideas and theories – those that support all the questing
for knowledge we do in other subject areas. It has been charac-
terized as ‘conceptual plumbing’ or ‘conceptual engineering’.1 We
look behind our everyday concerns to examine the systems and
structures which support our thinking (and which ordinarily we
take for granted), and to test their soundness.
Because of this distinctive approach it is often easier to capture
the nature of philosophy by providing examples of ‘doing
philosophy’ rather than defining its field of study. This helps us to
appreciate more fully how – even when the object of our study is
common to more than one discipline – philosophy has a distinctive
contribution to make to our knowledge and understanding of the
world.
4 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Case study
Liz has been caught shoplifting from her local department store,
for the third time in as many weeks. The police are called;
she is arrested and charged with theft. When her case
comes to court, her lawyer argues in her defence that Liz is a
kleptomaniac.
human freedom and responsibility for our actions, and the connec-
tion between these two notions.
It is from the philosophical perspective that we might ask (for
example): ‘If I am genetically predisposed towards risk-taking,
aggressive behaviour, should I be held responsible for this?’ – or,
at the limit: ‘If science will ultimately be able to provide a complete
explanation of all my behaviour, then am I truly free?’
These philosophical questions are also crucial for us to address in
order to provide a basis for tackling the practical issues raised within
our other investigations. We need to develop our understanding of
what it is to be responsible for our actions before we can make
informed judgements about many issues – for example, regarding
who is able to make autonomous decisions: children, adults with
learning disabilities, those under the influence of drugs?
So this case study helps us to capture how philosophy is not just
concerned with grand abstract theories; it also has real implications
for everyday living.
What is there?
This is the basis of a branch of philosophy called metaphysics.
While a physicist could tell us something about the nature of
physical reality, and a sociologist about the nature of human
6 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Summary
This chapter has introduced the kinds of enquiries that form the
basis of the study of philosophy as a discipline, and the skills you
will be required to develop as you learn how to be a philosopher.
Looking more deeply at these skills, and presenting various
strategies to practise and improve them, will be the focus of the rest
of this book.
Notes
1 The analogy of philosophy as plumbing is developed by Mary
Midgley; the definition of philosophy as ‘conceptual engineering’ is
Simon Blackburn’s. Both provide very readable and engaging intro-
ductions to philosophy:
Midgley, Mary (1992), ‘Philosophical plumbing’, in A. Phillips Griffiths (ed.)
(1992), The Impulse to Philosophise. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
pp. 139–152.
Blackburn, Simon (1999), Think: A Compelling Introduction to Philosophy.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
(See also Chapter 3 for further discussion of Midgley’s argument.)
2 This quotation is taken from the Subject Benchmark Statement for
Philosophy, which outlines what you can expect from a philosophy
degree at any UK university – including the skills and personal attrib-
utes that a student should develop through their degree programme:
Quality Assurance Agency for Higher Education (2000), Philosophy Subject
Benchmark Statement. Gloucester: Quality Assurance Agency for Higher
Education.
The full text can be found on-line at the following URL:
www.qaa.ac.uk/academicinfrastructure/benchmark/honours/
philosophy.asp
3 Further details of what qualities employers are looking for in their
graduate recruits, and how a philosophy degree equips you to meet
such demands, can be found in:
Employability: Where next? Unlocking the Potential of your Philosophy Degree,
(2007), Leeds: Subject Centre for Philosophical and Religious Studies,
available for download at http://prs.heacademy.ac.uk/publications/
emp_guides.html
14 DOING PHILOSOPHY
What to read
You may be given specific guidance on what to read each week in
order to prepare for lectures and tutorials. Often, such reading is
detailed in a course handout. This makes the job of deciding what
to read seem easy. However, this may not be everyone’s experience
of starting a philosophy course. Guidance given varies hugely across
different institutions.
Even if you are given directed reading for the semester ahead, it is
likely that at some stage, particularly when you are preparing your
assessed work, you will need to take control over your own reading,
and make judgements about what to read.
What do you do next? Surely you are not supposed to buy and
read all these texts – but how do you know where to start?
In your reading list, the order and format in which this infor-
mation is presented may vary. However, it should provide you
with all the key information you need to find the right book.
18 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Foot, P. (1985),
‘Utilitarianism and the
virtues’. Mind 94,
196–209. Repr. in S.
Scheffler (ed.) (1988),
Consequentialism and its
Critics. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
McDowell, J. (1979),
‘Virtue and reason’. The
Monist 62, 331–350.
READING PHILOSOPHY 19
Types of texts
Let us look at these different types of text in a bit more detail.
Textbooks
Often, and especially on introductory level courses, textbooks will
be included on the reading list. They are usually written with a
student audience in mind, with the aim of providing an overview
of the area of philosophy being discussed. They draw on the work
of other philosophers to outline the background, and major philo-
sophical problems, of the topic under discussion. A good text-
book can be a great way into a difficult subject area, and if you
cannot afford to buy many books, getting hold of a recommended
textbook can be a valuable initial investment.
Primary texts
Where the work of a particular philosopher is going to be dis-
cussed in detail in your course, the original text by that philosopher
is likely to be included. Original texts are often called primary
texts.
These may well be historical texts, written several centuries ago,
and quite possibly in a different language. Where the text is written
in antiquated English, or has been translated, the edition you use
can be very important as you try to get to grips with the content.
Particular translations may be controversial. Because of this, your
lecturer is likely to recommend a particular edition or English
translation of the work, and it is a good idea to stick to this. For
instance, our sample reading list specifies Roger Crisp’s translation
of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.1
20 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Secondary texts
Secondary texts may also be included on your reading list. These
are texts which other thinkers have written about the primary
texts in question. Typically these provide a detailed analysis of the
original text, and of its impact on subsequent thinking. Secondary
texts can be a very good way of helping you to get to grips with a
difficult primary text, but should be read in conjunction with the
original, rather than instead of it, not least because a secondary text
only offers one person’s interpretation of the material.
Note that the terms primary and secondary texts do not mean the
same as essential and optional reading.
Anthologies
Another type of book you may come across is the anthology. These
are collections of writings on a particular topic, and may consist of
(more or less) short extracts from primary texts; essays or discrete
articles on the subject; or a combination of both. Reading a
recommended anthology can be a good way of familiarizing your-
self with the breadth of opinion about a particular subject without
spending hours trawling the library catalogue.
Journals
Journals are publications made up of collections of articles, often
referred to as papers, written by university researchers, and pub-
lished in serial volumes once or several times a year. Journal papers
are the format in which much academic research is first published,
and philosophy is no exception.
Journals are a distinctive feature of academic life. They are one of
the principal means by which academics across the world discuss
and develop their ideas. As such, they are an important way of
finding out the latest developments in your subject. Many journals
specialize in particular areas of philosophy, so if you are studying
ethics, for example, it may be that one or more of the specialist
ethics journals will be included on your reading list, as several of the
articles found in the various volumes of this journal may be relevant
to your course.
There are also journals aimed at specific levels of philosophical
study, including those written by and for undergraduates. See
Chapter 6, ‘Resources’, for more details.
READING PHILOSOPHY 21
Articles
Philosophy articles, whether published in an anthology or a journal,
may well be more challenging to read than a textbook. This is because
they are often (although not always) written for an audience of
philosophy academics rather than students; they are typically
focused on a very specific issue, and may be very densely argued.
When reading a journal article, you should not be intimidated if
you do not understand everything on your first, or even second,
reading. Even professional philosophers will often need to read such
an article several times in order to tackle it thoroughly; this is what
it is like to read philosophy.
In your first year, you are unlikely to be required to read many
articles at the cutting edge of philosophical research, but as you
progress and develop your own areas of interest and specialization,
you may find that journal articles provide you with a depth of
understanding of specific issues that you come to value.
text, but in order to provide you with, for example, further reading
on particular topics that will be useful if you choose to write an
assignment in that area; or a range of different textbooks in case one
or more prove difficult to obtain.
In this case, it is likely that further guidance will be given within
this list, highlighting which texts are essential. It goes without
saying that you ignore this at your peril; these are the texts that are
likely to form the core of your classroom discussions, and of your
assessment, so you will be at a disadvantage if you have neglected
them.
Electronic resources. You may have noticed that very little has been
said so far about anything other than printed texts. It is notoriously
difficult to provide detailed guidance on good web-based resources,
as these can become out of date very quickly. There are some
excellent philosophy resources on-line, such as internet encyclo-
paedias and gateways to other resources on various topics. However,
there are also many of very dubious quality, so it is important to be
very careful and critical in your use of information you find on the
web.
Again, your library should be your first port of call – they are
likely to offer a variety of useful internet resources, such as:
• On-line reading lists.
• e-texts; many core texts, and reference texts such as encyclo-
paedias, are now available on-line, so you do not need to rely
on tracking down a hard copy.
• Recommended websites; these will have been assessed to
ensure that they are of suitable academic quality, so are a much
more reliable means of accessing on-line information than a
general internet search.
See Chapter 6, ‘Resources’ for more detailed advice on using the
library and internet.
essay for this module. However, most tutors would say that quality is
far more important than quantity.
How to read
So now you have worked out what you need to prioritize, trawled
the shelves for your selected readings, and are at your desk with a
stack of books and articles – what next?
Reading will form a significant part of your study time, so it is
important that you approach it with some idea of what to expect
and some strategies for getting to grips with the texts.
Some philosophers have gone out of their way to make their
arguments clear and engaging for the reader, so there are some
philosophy texts that are paradigms of clarity and expression.
Others are more challenging. One thing is certainly true of the
majority of philosophy texts – they are difficult to skim-read, and
require effort, thought and time. But they will pay off with rich
rewards and give you an intellectual workout you cannot easily
forget.
It is up to you to get the best out of the reading you do.
Philosophy encourages direct engagement. This means working
towards really understanding what is going on so that you feel
confident enough to create and defend your own interpretations,
which may well be different from (and potentially better than) the
ones that you might be offered by a lecturer or a textbook. There is
a great deal to be gained by thinking about what else a text could
mean and trying out your own ideas, as long as you fairly represent
what the text says and provide good evidence and arguments for
your views.
In the rest of this chapter we will look at how to begin reading
and then finding, analysing and evaluating arguments when reading
philosophy. This is only a first taste of how you can use analysis
of arguments to understand philosophy, but it should give you a
flavour of the way it can be used.
Reading philosophically
The process of reading philosophically could be seen as consisting
of three main activities:
• Getting an overview of the text, its structure and the philo-
sophical problem under discussion.
• Understanding the arguments used and the conclusions
reached – that is, analysing the details of the structure.
28 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Structured reading
Here are some strategies that might seem obvious, but which might
help you to approach your reading in a structured way, in order to
get more from it:
1. Get a good overview of the text:
• What is its title? Does this tell you what it is about?
• How long is it? How much time do you need to put aside
to read it?
• Is there anything particular about how the text is set out
on the page?
• Does it have an introduction that sets up the problem or
argument addressed?
• Is there a conclusion that sums up the argument and
points the way forward to other ideas?
• What are the section or chapter headings? Can you see a
pattern or structure?
2. Think about what you want from the text: a good grasp
of the arguments? A framework for understanding some-
READING PHILOSOPHY 29
In this case, the title of the paper seems to give a clear state-
ment of the question to be addressed; but it is not clear why
this is a philosophical question. Why does it matter what it is
like to be a bat, and what do we learn from exploring this
question?
The first sentence of the paper itself gives us a clearer statement
of the philosophical problem to be addressed:
Spotting the conclusion is not always easy and you will need to
think carefully: there are compound arguments in which the con-
clusion of one minor argument becomes the premise of another.
However, in doing so you are beginning the process of making
the text your own and engaging with the ideas at more than a
superficial level. Further strategies are needed to take us deeper.
Analysing arguments
Let us consider arguments in a little more detail to get a better
understanding of what makes them work, and how we could
determine their worth or value. So far we know that, in reading
philosophy, we are looking among other things for arguments to
assess. We have observed that what distinguishes an argument from
a mere statement of opinion, fact or belief is that it brings together
a set of statements, using some rational principles, to give a con-
clusion. A strategic approach towards analysing arguments at this
stage might be to ask:
1. What is the point the author is trying to make? What is the
conclusion of the argument(s) presented? Is it clear that there is
one?
2. What are the premises of the argument? What material does
the author use to reach the conclusion?
3. What is the structure of the argument? How does it ‘hang
together’? Is there one long argument or many smaller
ones with conclusions at one point becoming premises at
another?
This helps us to understand how we might begin to assess three
things:
1. the truth of the premises;
2. the logic of the way the conclusion has been reached from
the premises, that is, the form of the argument;
3. the truth of the conclusion.
When the conclusion of an argument must logically follow from
the premises, we call this a valid argument. However, this does not
necessarily mean that the conclusion is true, as the premises might
not be true. Where the argument is valid, and the premises are true,
this means the conclusion is true. This is called a sound argument.
38 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Let us suppose that we accept the second premise and see what
happens. Does the conclusion then follow from the premises? Read
the sentences again and see what your own answer is. Be careful to
think why you would answer as you do and be prepared to defend
your answer with arguments of your own. What is said below is
only one interpretation and open to challenge.
If you answered ‘no’ you probably thought that since the argu-
ment does not immediately follow it can be dismissed. Not
necessarily so. As noted above, Descartes assumed that his readers
shared a lot of knowledge with him: what appears to be a jump
from the premises to the conclusion, might simply be that other
parts of the argument are elsewhere in the text, or that the assump-
tions he draws on are considered common knowledge and not
worth stating at all.
If you are tempted to answer ‘yes’ then you will have given
Descartes the benefit of reading a lot into how he uses certain
words and will have assumed a series of other premises that are not
explicitly stated. The idea of ‘true knowledge’ is not given in either
of the premises, but is a significant point in the conclusion. One of
the hidden premises might be:
Only judgements about sensible things based on fully developed
reason give true knowledge.
Another might be:
Speech is required for the formation of reason.
And there is a point in the conclusion that we have ‘preconcep-
tions’ that we continue to employ even now, which we have picked
up from our early years, even though we have reason on our side. So
we could also add:
Judgements from earlier experience continue to act as the basis for
current assumptions about what we sensibly experience.
If we add these to our first starting premises we can begin to see
how we might answer ‘yes’ if asked whether the conclusion follows.
The argument looks like this now:
even if on only one occasion. The second reason is that in our dreams we
regularly seem to sense or imagine many things which are completely non-
existent, and there are no obvious signs which would enable someone having
such doubts to distinguish between sleeping and waking with any certainty.7
This also has an argument in it, with apparently two independent
supporting claims or premises for the conclusion. He notes that we
are going to test those ideas (and only those ideas) which we take to
be true by doubting them or assuming them to be false and seeing
if we can find reasons for supposing this to be wrongheaded. He
decides to start with sensible (experienced through the senses) and
even imaginary things. They can be doubted, he says. We can see
that this claim is the conclusion of another argument because he
goes on to give us reasons or premises in support of it. He says there
are two, but each can be broken down into simpler statements. So
we have:
1. We sometimes notice that our senses deceive us.
2. It is wise never to put too much trust in what has let us
down, even if on only one occasion.
3. In our dreams we regularly seem to sense or imagine
many things which are completely non-existent.
4. There are no obvious signs [in dreams] which would
enable someone having such doubts to distinguish
between sleeping and waking with any certainty.
therefore
It can be doubted whether any sensible or imaginable
things exist.
Analyse this argument further yourself. First, check to see whether
you agree with how the premises have been presented. Then
work through the premises checking their initial plausibility or
acceptability. Bear in mind what Descartes has already said and
that there may be things assumed here that are not stated. Do the
premises draw on facts we could challenge? Are they based on
generally accepted experience? Then ask yourself, if we were to
accept the conclusion as true, what else do we need to make this
argument work?
If we were to read the rest of the chapter from The Principles
of Philosophy, we would see that Descartes is building up a series of
READING PHILOSOPHY 43
attention to the arguments at the core of the text. You can expose
concepts and logical failings with this general strategy.
Using logic
Some philosophers use logical symbolism to express arguments or
make them clearer. This is an important and lively part of con-
temporary philosophy. You might be required to study formal
logic as a module in itself and there you will be taught how to read
and write logical notation. Additionally, you might encounter logic
in the context of other reading – especially in contemporary
philosophy of mind, language or metaphysics. We do not intend to
go into the details of formal logic here, but rather to show you
how you can use the basic principles of logic to clarify arguments to
yourself and back up your analysis of texts.
There is nothing to fear in logic, even if you feel you lack skills
at a mathematical level. In fact, it presents us, as readers, with an
opportunity to achieve a level of understanding of the relationship
between concepts and arguments that is not always available in
other contexts. It means we can find very fine-grained differences
in authors’ positions, and discover precisely where an argument
fails, or is ambiguous. It is rather like exposing the skeleton of an
argument; finding a broken bone can be a very good explanation
for why a limb does not work in the way we think it should.
Logic, when used appropriately, is powerful and something that
can improve your grasp of many aspects of current philosophical
writing considerably.
We have already noted that finding the arguments in a text is the
key to assessing the convincingness of the philosophical points
being made. We have seen that in order to spot arguments we have
to isolate the conclusion and the premises that are being employed.
Logic is simply a way of showing how the premises are related to
the conclusion. It allows you to look beyond the words and con-
cepts used in specific cases to the structure of the argument itself,
and so test the argument. Look at the following argument:
All dogs wag their tails when happy.
Santa’s Little Helper is a dog.
therefore
Santa’s Little Helper wags his tail when happy.
READING PHILOSOPHY 45
D is inside T because all the things that are dogs (D) are claimed to
be things that wag their tails when happy (T). There could be other
things that wag their tails when happy, but all dogs do, so no part
of D is outside of T. Also, s is inside D because Santa’s Little
Helper is a dog. From the picture we can see that it is impossible for
Santa’s Little Helper not to be inside T as well: if we accept the
premises it must be the case that Santa’s Little Helper wags his tail
when he is happy. So we can see that the argument is structurally
valid. The diagram we have used here is a form of Venn diagram.
Venn diagrams are a powerful tool for checking arguments.
Using pictures and diagrams can be a quick way of making
arguments clearer to yourself. In a similar way, logic uses a set of
established rules to construct and examine arguments. Consider the
following:
If Martin is taller than Natasha,
and Natasha is taller than Ozzie,
and Ozzie is the same height as Polly,
then Martin is taller than Polly
Let us look again at the idea of validity. It says that an argument is
valid when the conclusion cannot be false if the premises are true.
46 DOING PHILOSOPHY
As the line diagrams show, we are concerned with the way things
are related in terms of their height, so the names themselves could
be anything. In fact, when considering height alone we could be
talking about lines, plant pots or ostriches as much as humans, so we
could replace the names with letters:
If m is taller than n,
and n is taller than o,
and o is the same height as p,
then m is taller than p
Next let us look at the relationships between these objects, what-
ever they are. We have two different ways of relating these things,
‘being taller than’ and ‘being the same height as’. All logic does is
look at these relationships and generalizes them so that we can look
at all arguments that have the same form. Supposing I say:
Martin is older than Polly
This is logically similar in form to:
Martin is taller than Polly
This is because if they are true then the reverse is false. It simply
cannot be the case that Martin is older than Polly and at the same
READING PHILOSOPHY 47
time Polly is older than Martin. The same is true of ‘being taller
than’. The relationship has a direction and an order – the relation-
ship works in a particular direction so therefore the order in which
Martin and Polly are considered is important.
But look at ‘is the same height as’ or ‘being the same age as’:
these work either way. If Ozzie is the same height as Polly then it is
obviously true that Polly is the same height as Ozzie.
So ‘being older than’ and ‘being the same age as’ are different
properties and are true under different conditions. Logic reveals this
in terms of the direction in which the properties work and shows
that the ordering of the object names really matters. When we
think about the meaning of the relations we are considering the truth
conditions (what would make the statements true) as they are passed
from one sentence to another. See what happens if you replace ‘is
taller than’ with ‘is older than’ and ‘is the same height as’ with ‘is
the same age as’ in the argument above. The argument remains
intact in terms of the way the individuals are related to each other,
although its meaning changes. Its logical form is unaltered because
the objects are represented by the same letters and the relation-
ships have not been changed in terms of the direction and order of
their operation. So the argument will remain valid, although not
necessarily sound.
So using logic allows us to make the jump to expressing an
argument’s form in a purely logical way based on relation rather
than specific properties. Whether we are talking in terms of height
or age, the argument has the structure:
If m > n,
and n > o,
and o = p,
then m > p
So if you are reading a text and you spot this argument form, you
know that regardless of the truth of the premises, the argument is
valid.
Logic is about the structure of relationships that can operate
between sentences, concepts, ideas or things. That is where its
power lies. It can be generalized across all sorts of different contexts
where logically similar ideas are used.
This is the crucial point. If we are dealing with very abstract and
48 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Technical language
The philosophers that we study do not tend to be
run-of-the-mill thinkers. Where contributions to philosophy go
beyond clarifying and developing existing ideas, and present
revolutionary concepts and theories that transform the way sub-
sequent philosophers think, new concepts require new language.
Because of this, much philosophy uses technical terms to find ways
of expressing new ways of thinking about things, and to show
relationships between concepts that cannot be expressed easily in
ordinary language.
There are two main ways in which philosophers use technical
language:
1. they use everyday words in ways that are perhaps unusual
and often much more precise than we normally expect;
and
2. they invent new terms and expressions for ideas and argu-
ments that have not been named before.
We will deal with each of these in turn.
‘Reason is the journey; method is the road to science; and the goal of
science is the good of humanity’ – but no-one would expect you to
know this.
One more problem which you might well miss is that Hobbes
does not use the word ‘science’ in the modern sense of natural
science, which came into use only in the late nineteenth century.
Instead, he means any systematic body of knowledge known
demonstratively (as the OED2 will tell you).
The second sentence is much easier, apart from the bit of Latin:
ignes fatui. This is the plural of ignis fatuus, which occurred so often
in older English that it is actually in the OED2, meaning a will-o’-
the-wisp – a flash of light appearing above marshy ground, which
was alleged to lead travellers astray. As Hobbes argues throughout
the Leviathan, one of the causes of civil war is the way in which
various sectors of society (especially university professors and
Catholic priests) use meaningless language to gain power over
ordinary people, and lead them astray.
Translation problems
Reading a text in translation can also present difficulties. Even at
the level of everyday experience, one language is not always exactly
translatable into another, because things are classified differently.
For example, there is no Greek word corresponding to the English
words ‘melon’ or ‘peach’, because in Greek you have to specify
what kind of melon or peach you are referring to, and the more
general term does not exist. The problem becomes much more
acute when dealing with abstractions, because abstract concepts
have evolved in different ways in different cultures.
There are a number of ways in which translation difficulties
bring about loss of meaning or ambiguity, and can bring specific
problems to the reading of texts. We will look at them in turn.
Untranslatable terms
A word or phrase in the original language may have no equivalent
at all in English. In such cases, it is common to leave the word in the
original language, just as in ordinary speech we use foreign words
like Schadenfreude for ‘taking pleasure in the misfortunes of other
people’, or encore for ‘a piece of music, not on the programme,
played at the end of a concert’. So, in philosophical writings, you are
READING PHILOSOPHY 57
Untranslatable ambiguities
Philosophical words and sentences are often ambiguous, and it is
rarely possible to reproduce the ambiguity in English – the trans-
lator is forced to opt for one interpretation rather than another. A
good example of this is the passage from Descartes we quoted pre-
viously. According to our translation, Descartes said that we were
‘born without speech’, whereas other translations simply refer to us
being ‘infants’. The truth of the matter is that the Latin word infans
means a baby too young to speak, and we simply do not know if
Descartes was primarily thinking of our being babies, or of our lack
of speech. It is possible that our interpretation lays more stress than
Descartes intended on the relation between speech and reason,
unlike his opponent Hobbes who, in the extract we have quoted
from Leviathan, explicitly maintained that speech and reason are
completely inseparable.
Untranslatable distinctions
The third case is when there are more words in the original
language than there are in English. For example, Kant has two
words which can only be translated as ‘object’, namely Objekt and
Gegenstand. There is clearly a difference between the two, in that
an Objekt is abstract, and contrasted with a subject, whereas a
Gegenstand is a physical object with which one can be confronted in
experience. It is a moot point how far this distinction affects the
interpretation of Kant, since the meaning is usually obvious from
the context. But most translations alert the reader to which term is
being used by a footnote. Generally, if an untranslatable distinction
58 DOING PHILOSOPHY
It may seem that you are being set an impossible task in reading a
philosophical text in translation, but do not worry. There are many
levels of understanding of philosophical ideas. At undergraduate
level, no-one expects you to be able to argue about what a
philosopher meant in the original language. Your course will have
been designed in such a way that you can get a first-class mark by
engaging with the translation available to you. The materials you
are given may or may not alert you to translation problems, because
some teachers are more concerned with historical facts about what
philosophers actually believed, whereas others are more concerned
with the broad ideas themselves, but it is a good idea to bear these
difficulties in mind, especially if you find yourself struggling with
a particular concept.
Here is an example of how language differences can affect the
plausibility of a philosophical argument. In Principles I.14 (written
in Latin), Descartes says:
Next, the mind considers the various ideas it has within itself; and one
stands out far above the rest, namely that of a being which is totally intelli-
gent, totally powerful, and totally perfect. It discerns that this idea includes
existence – not merely possible and contingent existence (as in the ideas of
all the other things of which it has a distinct conception), but unlimited
necessary and eternal existence.
This is what was later known as the ‘ontological’ argument for the
existence of God. Descartes is claiming that we have in our minds
an idea of what God is – namely an intelligent, omnipotent and
perfect being. He argues that such an idea includes existence,
that is, in order for a being to be totally perfect it must exist. If it
existed only as an idea it would not be perfect, so given this, God
necessarily exists.
Most English-language readers find the argument implausible,
because even if we accept that we can imagine a perfect and
omnipotent being, we do not see why this idea of perfection has
to include existence. However, the scope of the word perfectus
in Latin is different from the scope of the word ‘perfect’ in English.
We tend to think of ‘perfect’ as covering no more than moral or
aesthetic perfection, whereas in Latin perfectus also includes a con-
cept that can be understood as ‘fulness of being’. So the concept
that Descartes is talking about (originally in Latin) does have a
60 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Handling ambiguity
Even the most clearly written of texts are capable of different inter-
pretations. As well as the use and invention of technical terms,
which we have already looked at, philosophers often use
metaphors, analogies and examples to get their new ideas across,
and it is ambiguous how they are to be interpreted. Ultimately, the
meanings of terms are determined by their place in a philosophical
system as a whole, and there is the catch-22 that you can grasp
the system as a whole only if you understand the terms it consists of.
READING PHILOSOPHY 61
• Which interpretation fits best with what the author says else-
where? Are there other passages in which the author is clearer
and more explicit about what they mean?
• With regard to historical texts, is there any supplementary
evidence in the secondary literature about what people
believed at the time, for example, which makes one interpret-
ation more likely than the others?
• Again, for historical texts, do any of the interpretations
READING PHILOSOPHY 63
• Make the primary text the main focus of your reading and
note-taking. You will not be learning to become a philosopher
unless you use secondary literature as an aid to your own
thinking rather than as a substitute for it. And when you come
to be assessed, you will not get high marks for showing the
ability to summarize interpretations by recent writers, instead
of arguing about the text itself.
• When you make a note of your interpretation of a passage,
do not just note the interpretation, but also your reasons for
it. Again, when it comes to assessment, it is showing the
evidence of your independent thought as you engage
with primary and secondary texts that will get you a good
mark.
Let us take as an example Kant’s famous claim that he was bringing
about a Copernican revolution in philosophy. This illustrates not
only the sorts of reasons you might use for and against different
interpretations, but also the fact that philosophers do not always
mean what they actually say, and it is often necessary to dig below
the surface in order to come up with a plausible interpretation.
What Kant says in the Preface to the second edition of the Critique
of Pure Reason is:
Here it is the same as with the first thoughts of Copernicus. He made little
progress in explaining the motions of the heavenly bodies on the assumption
that they all revolved round the observer. So he wondered if he might not
make better progress if he let the observer revolve, and left the stars at rest. In
metaphysics, you can make a similar thought experiment about the intuition
of objects. If intuition must accommodate itself to the nature of the object,
I do not see how you can know anything about it a priori. But if the object
(as object of the senses) accommodates itself to the nature of our faculty of
intuition, then I can easily conceive that such knowledge is possible.15
64 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Summary
By now you should have a good idea of what it means to read
philosophically, rather than simply to read philosophy. Reading
philosophically means engaging with the texts, identifying and
analysing arguments, creating and refining your own interpretations
and being prepared to criticize what others think in a structured
way. The techniques suggested here should give you the tools to
take your reading further, to increase your understanding of the
topics at hand, and to use your reading to prepare you for engage-
ment in other philosophical activities, which we will examine in
more detail in the rest of this book.
Notes
1 Aristotle (384–322 BCE) was an ancient Greek thinker; and, along
with Plato (who was his teacher), arguably one of the most influential
figures in the history of western philosophy. His Nicomachean Ethics
remains a core text in ethical theory today.
2 Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) was a German philosopher, famous
(amongst other things) for synthesizing the competing philosophies of
the Enlightenment era – his work remains hugely influential through-
out western philosophy today, not least in the field of ethics.
3 Kantianism is the approach to ethics associated with Kant (see previous
note), which places emphasis on the individual’s motivations for
action. Virtue theory can be traced back to Aristotle (see note 1),
and focuses its morality on the character of the individual rather
than his/her particular actions. Utilitarianism is principally associated
with the nineteenth-century thinkers Jeremy Bentham and John
Stuart Mill; according to this theory, the moral status of an action
is determined by the extent to which its consequences maximize
happiness.
4 Thomas Nagel (1937–) is an American philosopher. His work focuses
mainly on issues in moral and political theory; but he is also well-
known for his paper ‘What is it like to be a bat?’, which became one
of the most discussed papers in twentieth-century philosophy of
mind:
• Nagel, Thomas (1974), ‘What is it like to be a bat?’ Philosophical
Review vol. 83, no. 4, 435–450.
This famous paper has also been reprinted in a number of other books,
for example:
READING PHILOSOPHY 67
leeds.ac.uk/GMR/hmp/texts/modern/kant/preface2.html (accessed
04.06.07).
16 This is the interpretation of Sandra LaFave. See http://instruct.west
valley.edu/lafave/KANT.HTM (accessed 02.06.07).
17 This is the interpretation of Stephen Palmquist. See www.hkbu.
edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1/KSP3.html (accessed 02.06.07).
18 This is the interpretation of George MacDonald Ross. The whole
of this discussion is adapted from an interactive exercise at www.
philosophy.leeds.ac.uk/GMR/hmp/modules/kantmcq/p19/
p19frame.html (accessed 02.06.07).
3 Taking notes
Summarizing material
Identifying all (and only) the key points in a lecture or text is a
philosophical skill which takes practice, and requires you to think
carefully about what is being said. When looking at what it
means to read philosophically, that is, to gain an understanding of a
philosophical text, we broke down the process into:
TAKING NOTES 71
Evaluating material
Accurately capturing the essence of the author’s or lecturer’s
original argument is, however, only one dimension of effective
note-taking. You should also seek to capture your own engagement
with the ideas discussed. Do you agree with the claims being made,
or can you think of counter-examples? Does the conclusion follow
from the premises, or is the author relying on unspoken assump-
tions? (Can you identify what these are? Do you think they are
acceptable?) If you accept the author’s argument, can you envisage
any other consequences which you might be committed to as well
– and are these acceptable?
Critical analysis and evaluation of this kind is at the heart of
doing philosophy, so it is important to include these reflections in
your note-taking. When you read philosophy, take time to pause
and ask yourself not only whether you understand the argument,
but also how you think it holds up; and make a note of your
thoughts, as well as those of the author. This should include making
a note of any issues you do not understand; so that you can follow
these up later, by asking for clarification in class or doing some
further reading.
72 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Lecture slides
. . . So, the problem remains: we need to account for how mental states
can cause physical events – which is something that behaviourism fails
to explain – without resorting to dualism. And we want to avoid dualism
because we have good scientific reasons to accept physicalism – which is
the thesis that everything can be explained in physical terms. A key
argument of this type is the causal closure argument for physicalism, which
goes something like this:
At every time at which a physical state has a cause, it has a fully sufficient
physical cause. This scientific principle is known as ‘the causal closure of
the physical’, and it underpins all our assumptions about how the world
works – for any given event in the physical world, it should be possible to
tell a complete story about how that event came to happen, in terms of
other physical things and events. Even if we don’t know this complete
story (for instance, if science isn’t yet sufficiently advanced), we believe
that some such physical explanation exists, and that is sufficient to explain
the cause of the event in question.
But some physical states have mental states among their causes – what is
known as psychophysical causation. This also seems uncontroversial if you
think of everyday examples – for instance, how might I explain what caused
me to eat a bar of chocolate just before this lecture? I would say that I felt
hungry; I wanted to rid myself of these hunger pangs before the lecture so
that I could concentrate; and I believed that raiding the vending machine
for a bar of chocolate to eat would achieve this. Each of these explanatory
steps involves appealing to a mental state of mine – a feeling, a desire, and
a belief, respectively.
But then we seem to be left with the conclusion that my consumption of the
chocolate has both a complete physical cause, and a mental cause too –
that is, that this event is causally overdetermined . . .
Sample notes [If you have a copy of your lecturer’s slides, you can annotate these
rather than repeating their content in your own notes.]
Phil Mind: ID Theory – Prof Bloggs – 31 Nov
M causation – theory of mind needs to explain; behaviourism doesn’t
Avoid dualism – why? Science ✔ physicalism = all explained in p terms
Do we have to accept the science? Check notes from dualism lecture.
later date. It will also give you the opportunity to identify any
action points – Is there anything in your notes which you sign-
posted ‘don’t understand this’? If so, what will you do to rectify
this? Ask about it in your next seminar, or consult a philosophy
encyclopaedia, for example?
This activity will also help to do more than ensure the accuracy
and comprehensiveness of your notes – it will also prompt you to
think again about the ideas discussed, while they are still fresh in
your mind; and give you the opportunity to come up with further
critical reflections of your own. In looking back over the argument
as a whole, you may well spot difficulties that were not immediately
apparent to you when you were immersed in the details of the
lecture or text. This can help you to pinpoint your confusion, or
disagreement, over any points which originally made you think
‘that doesn’t seem quite right, but I’m not sure what’s wrong with
it’. Reviewing your notes should help you to practise your skills of
philosophical analysis, which will be a key advantage when it comes
to discussing the issues in class or writing philosophy for assessment.
Separate notes
notes on key thinkers and /or theories which you may revisit at a
later stage in your philosophical studies. You may well be expected
to read, for instance, Plato’s Republic more than once during your
degree – perhaps first as part of your ‘Introduction to Philosophy’
course, and then again in a level three Political Philosophy module.
In the third year, your first-year notes may come in useful, but you
are also likely to wish to add to them – reflecting the different focus
of your level three studies, and also your more highly developed
skills of philosophical analysis – and it will be helpful for you to be
able readily to distinguish between the two sets of notes on the
same text.
Summary
This chapter has given you an overview of how note-taking can be
a valuable philosophical activity in its own right, as well as pre-
senting you with various strategies that you can use to make sure
that your notes are suited to the context of their further use, and
continue to be a valuable resource as you progress. Being able to
take pertinent and concise notes is a vital philosophical skill to
develop, and will stand you in good stead as you go on to pursue
other philosophical activities, described in the rest of this book.
4 Discussion
Active learning
It is widely accepted that active learning is more effective than
passive learning. You learn more and in greater depth by doing
things, reflecting on what you are doing, and receiving timely
and helpful feedback on what you have done, than by passively
memorizing what you are told in lectures, and regurgitating it in
exams.
Discussion groups are an ideal means for learning in this way,
because you are active while listening to and seeking to understand
the contributions of others; thinking what contribution you
might make; and when you actually make a contribution. You also
obtain feedback from your fellow students and your tutor, and you
receive it instantly (whereas you may have to wait weeks to receive
feedback on your written work).
Contested subjects
The ability to discuss well is even more valuable in humanities
subjects than it is in other subjects. This is because they are contested
– that is to say, there are fundamental disagreements about the
nature of the subject, and even when two people agree on overall
aims, they may still disagree about the interpretation and evaluation
of particular texts. A well designed course will reflect the diversity
of opinions, and lectures and reading lists should enable you to
explore a range of different approaches and interpretations. How-
ever, your lecturers are human, and they may weight the evidence
in favour of their own opinions. Discussion groups provide an
opportunity to explore competing views.
More importantly, when you write essays or exams, you are
expected to show your ability to give arguments for and against
different possible interpretations of a text, and for and against the
doctrines you extract from the text. This is extremely difficult to do
if you are working by yourself, because your own judgement tends
to banish alternatives from your mind. If you have spent a lot of
hard mental effort trying to work out what a text means, one of
your criteria for success will be that your interpretation is plausible.
But if you find it plausible, you will have empathized with it, and
you will find it very hard to think up arguments against it. There are
ways round the problem if you are working in isolation, such as
using your intellectual imagination to think of the different ways in
DISCUSSION 89
Roots of philosophy
By this stage, it should be obvious why discussion is considered to
be crucial in philosophy, with its emphasis on critical engagement,
argument and counter-argument. Philosophy is a special case
because dialogue has been essential to its practice almost from its
earliest beginnings. Socrates was not the first philosopher, but he
was the first philosopher we know of who insisted, as we do now,
that any claim to truth must be subject to rational debate. He was a
brilliant teacher who never gave any lectures and never wrote any
books, but confined his teaching to conducting dialogues (recorded
by his pupil Plato). Nowadays, in modern academic culture, while
philosophers do discuss their ideas informally with their colleagues
and friends, as well as at more formal seminars and conferences, the
written word tends to be the primary method of disseminating
one’s thoughts.
We are, in effect, confronted with different models of what doing
philosophy consists in. On the Socratic model, it is a group activity,
in which the outcome depends on the contributions of the dif-
ferent members. Socrates could not achieve what he did without
the participants, any more than a conductor can play a symphony
without an orchestra. And ancient Athens was not the only place
and time where the Socratic model was practised. When university
learning was re-established in mediaeval Europe after the Dark
Ages, a key part of the syllabus was the ‘disputation’, in which
students had to defend a controversial thesis in a public debate.
On an alternative model (which was actually the preferred model
of Plato as he grew older), philosophers are soloists, who think
by themselves, and then deliver the outcomes of their thinking
through lectures or books. Discussion still has its place, but
unlike the Socratic dialogue, an individual comes to a seminar or
90 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Discussion seminars
One of the reasons your classes are likely to follow the Platonic
model is that the modern university is a very different setting from
DISCUSSION 91
the market place of ancient Athens. For a start, groups will necessar-
ily be much more formal than the chance discussions involving
Socrates. They will be part of a syllabus, with topics specified in
advance; they will take place at fixed times of the week and have a
fixed length; you may have no control over which group you
join; and you may be penalized for non-attendance, or graded for
the quality of your contributions. Discussions which succeed in
recapturing the spontaneity and originality of the early dialogues of
Socrates will be lively, engaging and memorable, and are something
to aim for when participating in your classes.
Groups will also vary in size and structure, and will be given
different names in different universities – what might be called a
seminar in one place might be called a tutorial in another. The
most common format is a group of perhaps five to twenty students,
meeting regularly under the supervision of a tutor to discuss issues
arising in a course of lectures, which we have called a discussion
seminar.
Preparation
As we have already said, most of the time you spend learning
to become a philosopher takes place outside the classroom, and
preparing for discussion is a big part of this.
Why prepare?
We cannot stress too much that discussion seminars are likely to be
your main opportunity to philosophize actively, and to develop
your ability to argue effectively. Preparation is key to getting the
most out of your discussions. If you come poorly prepared and do
not contribute actively, it entirely negates the purpose of having
discussion groups. It is very frustrating for your teachers because
they are likely to end up doing most of the talking. What is more,
failing to prepare also detracts from your learning experience, and
that of your fellow students. So it is ultimately your responsibility to
make sure the discussion is a success.
Apart from writing essays, it is in discussion that you have the
chance to demonstrate that you have read and understood the
required reading, and it is an invaluable opportunity for you to
fine-tune your understanding and criticism of what you have read.
So you should set aside plenty of time for preparation.
92 DOING PHILOSOPHY
How to prepare
Solo preparation
You will almost certainly have been given instructions on what to
do before the discussion. Most module or course handbooks will
tell you what reading is required, week by week, in order for you to
prepare for what will be discussed in seminars, and your tutors will
give you further guidance. Sometimes this might seem to be a
dauntingly large amount of reading, and you will be required to
make intelligent decisions yourself over what is practically possible
for you to achieve in the time available. We have already given
advice on how to decide what to read, in Chapter 2, and the key
here is to remember that depth is more important than breadth.
If you are presented with a variety of texts to read for a particular
topic, it may be better to choose a few that form a representative
sample of viewpoints and analyse them in depth, than to attempt to
read them all and achieve no more than a surface understanding.
It is also likely that you will be given a series of questions to
inform your reading, to which you should prepare answers to bring
to the seminar. Again, the extent to which your reading is directed
in this way will vary from course to course, and where little
guidance is given, you can analyse the texts you read in ways we
have already discussed, to ensure that the arguments are clear to
you.
We have already given you general advice on reading and note-
taking, and here we are concerned only with what you need to
produce in preparation for a discussion, as contrasted with writing
a whole essay. The rule is to keep it brief, and stick closely to the
questions actually set (or what you consider to be the fundamental
points, if you have not been given specific questions). The main
reason for bringing anything you have written with you to the
discussion is to remind you of salient points that emerged during
your reading. So keep your notes concise and make important
points that you want to raise, or questions that you might have, clear
to yourself within your notes so that you can find them easily as the
discussion progresses.
There is another reason for having notes with you, and this is that
you may be shy or nervous about saying anything, especially if the
topic is a difficult one, and the numbers in the group are large.
DISCUSSION 93
Collaborative preparation
So far we have assumed that you will prepare for the discussion
alone. But it is possible, and highly effective, to work collaboratively
with fellow students. One common reason for not speaking in dis-
cussions is the fear of seeming stupid. This is often the case for new
students who are not used to learning in this way. But, as often as
not, if there is something you have in mind but do not dare to say
out loud, many other people will have the same thought too. It is
also the case that intelligent questions are at least as valuable to
discussion as the presentation of complete answers.
It can help to overcome potential shyness if you talk to others in
a more casual environment before you come to the official dis-
cussion. Some departments will organize less formal meetings of
students, where first-year students feel able to talk more freely
and ask questions of each other that they might feel embarrassed
about raising in a tutorial. If your department or teacher have not
organized such informal meetings you could consider doing so
yourself. If you compare what you do when preparing for a dis-
cussion by yourself with what you do when preparing for it col-
laboratively, the biggest difference is that the skills you exercise
by yourself (reading and writing) do not feature in a discussion;
whereas those involved in collaborating with friends are exactly the
skills that discussion groups are about (listening, talking, arguing
and so on). So any such informal discussion gives you practice at the
abilities you need to demonstrate in seminars.
94 DOING PHILOSOPHY
• Make sure you are seated so that you can see the face of
everyone else in the room.
• Do your best to empathize with different points of view: a
good philosopher can handle the fact that there may be
irresolvable differences between people, but that they can still
co-operate.
• See a discussion as a co-operative enterprise in which every-
one is seeking for the truth, rather than a competitive exercise
in which there are winners and losers.
• Address your fellow students rather than your teacher, and do
your best to establish eye contact with all of them. If you
address only your teacher, the session is likely to degenerate
into a question-and-answer session with the teacher as an
authority figure, at the expense of a genuine dialogue.
Keeping a record
It is tempting to take notes in discussion groups, so that you do not
forget valuable points that are made. But the trouble is, that if you
concentrate on taking notes, you will miss some of what is said
when you are writing down what went before, and you will not
have time to think of contributions you could make yourself.
Some teachers might appoint a single minute-taker each time, who
will post the minutes on a website to which you all have access. This
has a number of advantages:
and philosophical skills, and you will get the most out of it if you
participate actively. Do not let this opportunity pass you by.
Electronic discussion
Most philosophy teachers would like students to spend more time
in discussion than they usually do. The main constraint is staff time.
If discussion is to be led by a member of staff, there is a limit to the
number of groups an individual teacher can be responsible for,
and group sizes have tended to get larger and larger, to a point
where it becomes difficult for everyone to join in. An increasingly
popular way of providing greater scope for discussion is by making
electronic discussion lists available.
Most universities have a virtual learning environment, or VLE,
which allows teachers to set up a discussion list which can be
accessed only by students registered for a particular course, or by
sub-groups. There are also public discussion lists where you can
join in philosophical debate with other students, and /or philo-
sophers, of various academic levels. These can be valuable in
widening your perspectives, and might be particularly useful if
you are studying in a very small department where your pool of
collaborators for philosophical discussion is small. Some examples
of these are given in Chapter 6, ‘Resources’.
There are both advantages and disadvantages to electronic
discussion. Advantages are:
• If you are shy about speaking in class, you may find the ability
to make a written contribution to discussion liberating.
• You do not have to travel to a classroom.
• There is a permanent record of the discussion.
Disadvantages are:
Summary
This chapter has focused on the vital nature of discussion, both
in the development of philosophy as a discipline, and in your own
philosophical development. It has broken down what constitutes
good practice in philosophical debate, and outlined some strategies
for making the most of the various opportunities for discussion that
you may be given.
Although discussion can initially seem daunting, it is intrinsic to
becoming a philosopher, and as your philosophical skills develop, it
is an activity that you will come to relish.
5 Writing philosophy
There are many times that writing will be required during your
course, ranging from writing emails to writing a dissertation. Some
of this will be assessed, and some of it will not. But you will find
yourself writing philosophy in diverse forms for many different
purposes.
This chapter focuses on writing essays and papers. It remains the
case in most universities and colleges that essays, whether course-
work essays or those written in exams, are the principal forms used
to assess your progress and achievement. So looking at the writing
of essays will be how we explore and demonstrate the best ways
to write philosophy. However, the central points about argument
structure and clarity that we shall be discussing apply across all
contexts when you are thinking about the presentation of philo-
sophical ideas.
Having said that, you may well find it useful to look at guidance
for other forms of writing to build on the advice given here – short
communications need a different style and very succinct expression,
and dissertations present the opportunity for exploration of greater
detail and more creative work. Increasingly, philosophy under-
graduates are asked to produce a variety of types of written work,
from presentations to participating in blogs, and all of these require
specialized writing skills. Chapter 6, ‘Resources’, provides some
pointers.
What to write
In your first year, you are likely to be given a lot of guidance in
what to write. Then the level of support will probably decrease as
you continue your course; and if and when you write a dissertation,
you will choose your own philosophical question to answer. This
102 DOING PHILOSOPHY
as a whole hangs together is done for you, but this means you have
to pay particular attention to arguing concisely and logically in each
part of the question. Often critical thinking or logic tests and essays
will be of this form.
Descriptive questions
Questions of this type are usually indicated by words like ‘describe’,
‘show how’, ‘demonstrate’, ‘explain why’; for example ‘Describe
how Descartes reaches the conclusion that the only clear and dis-
tinct idea initially available to him is the cogito’. Here you are being
asked to explain, in your own words, how the arguments of others
work. Simply stating an opinion of your own, or only giving the
conclusion of the argument, will not be enough; you need to show
how premises and conclusion(s) work in an argument, which is
another reason why spotting arguments in your reading can be so
important.
Evaluative questions
Essays of this sort ask you to do more than just describe the argu-
ments of other philosophers. You need to make a critical assessment
of the arguments and ideas being proposed, and indeed questions
like this are often introduced by words such as ‘discuss’, ‘evaluate’,
‘critically examine’, or ‘assess’. Crucially, you are expected to form
an opinion – importantly, one that is supported by evidence from
what others have said, or by what you can argue yourself. You need
to do more than recapitulate the arguments in the piece – you also
need to show where they are weak, or where they have been
criticized by others, and demonstrate how your analysis feeds in to
your thoughts on the issue.
Comparative questions
In comparative questions, you are asked to take two or more
positions and look at them alongside one another. You may be asked
to ‘compare and contrast’ two positions or to argue for one over
another. In all cases you are being asked to show how the arguments
differ and are similar, so you need to show that you understand the
point and workings of both, and are capable of formulating
reasoned opinions on which view is the more defensible.
WRITING PHILOSOPHY 107
Preparing to write
As we have discovered, choosing your essay title means looking
carefully at what you are being asked to discuss. Do you have a
good grounding in the topic under discussion? What is the basis of
knowledge and understanding that you have to build on? If the
answers to these questions are ‘no’ and ‘very low’, this does not
necessarily mean you should not choose that particular question,
if it interests you, but obviously it will require a lot more pre-
liminary work than another on a topic with which you are more
familiar.
Preparing for writing an essay involves a certain amount of the
philosophical activities we have already discussed, namely selecting
your resources, reading them and engaging with them and taking
notes on this engagement, as well as hopefully being able to use
what you have learned, and the opinions you have formed, through
attending lectures and seminars, tutorials or discussion groups.
How much new work you undertake at the point when you are
beginning your assignment will depend on which question you
choose, and how much background work you have already done
on the subject. It is likely that even if you have kept up well with
your course reading, when it comes to preparing for an essay you
will want to expand your knowledge a bit further using the philo-
sophical skills and techniques you have been developing.
In taking part in all these activities, you have been ‘doing
philosophy’. Although starting to write your essays may feel like a
bit of a milestone, it is simply the next step towards becoming
a successful philosophy student. The skills of critical thinking and
argument analysis that you have been practising in reading, note-
taking and discussion will serve you well when it comes to writing
– it is now a question of demonstrating them in your written
assignments.
How to write
What is philosophical writing?
At its most basic, writing philosophically means getting down your
own ideas and arguments using your own words. Philosophical
writing – using the written word to express ideas clearly and
logically, and to convey new concepts, and relationships between
108 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Format
There is a word limit to stick to: indeed, to aim at. (Your department
may give further specific advice on whether, and if so to what
extent, it is acceptable for you to deviate from any recommended
word limit.) We also know the format and that the tutor expects the
essay to be word-processed.
Question analysis
As we saw earlier, this question is a common type in philosophy
essays, in that it provides you with a statement, and asks you to
respond to it. At first glance the initial question might not seem
to fit any of the specific types of essay we described, but you can see
110 DOING PHILOSOPHY
from the second part that you are being asked to use an evaluative
approach to the question, with particular regard to utilitarianism.
(As we noted, most questions will be a combination or variation of
the basic types outlined.) You need to get to the end of the essay
with an answer to the question set. An open-ended discussion of
utilitarianism will not do this, so you need to take up a position and
argue for it, demonstrating along the way that you understand the
various nuances of the argument.
Time management
How long will it take to write a 1,500 word essay? This very much
depends on your own individual experience of writing. Your
department or tutor may give you more advice on how long a
particular assignment may take you. You need to factor in time for
doing the preparation described above. Consider how long it would
take you to write this amount of text from scratch. Then add in
time to re-read and rewrite and to check that you have correctly
referenced all the books and papers you have used.
It is also worth saying that philosophical ideas, like intellectual
concepts of any kind, take time to develop fully. If you have kept up
with your reading plan you should be on top of the required basic
WRITING PHILOSOPHY 111
materials for writing and you now have the opportunity to explore
an idea in more depth. It can be a good idea to leave sufficient time
to have a first attempt at writing the essay, leave it for a while, and
then return to it – you will probably find that you have gained
additional insight into the topic in the meantime. What is more,
you are more likely to be able to spot any mistakes or weaknesses
with a bit of distance. Of course, this means starting to write your
essay well before the submission date.
Marking criteria
Your department should provide you with information about the
marking criteria that your tutor will be using to assess your essay. In
the example assignment list above, it is stated that they are published
in the Philosophy Student Handbook – and you should make sure
that you have a copy of this to hand, or other documentation where
the criteria appear, and look at it carefully before tackling your
assignments, so that you can ensure your work meets the criteria
against which it will be marked.
The following is an example of the marking criteria used at one
UK institution for assessing undergraduate philosophy essays.1 It
sets out the basic requirements which your essay must meet in order
to be awarded a first, 2.1 and so on.
First (70+): The essay meets at least one of the following descrip-
tions: (i) faultless exposition, which is clearly structured around a
central thesis; (ii) essay which shows deep understanding, in which
there are clear signs of creative engagement with the issues.
Fail (39 and below): At best, shows some sign of familiarity with
course topics, but nothing else.
Essay structure
Let us now turn to the structure of the essay. We will return to our
earlier example to look at how the different parts of an essay should
work. There are other requirements, but the central components
are:
• An introduction, that spells out the basis of what will be
argued for.
• The body of the essay that carries the main arguments.
• A conclusion that summarizes the argument, recapitulates the
position and points to further considerations beyond the
scope of the essay.
How much of your word count is given over to each of these
sections may be suggested by your tutor or in general style guides,
but as a rule of thumb the introduction and conclusion should
each not exceed ten per cent of your total. In the example we have
been looking at this would mean your introduction will be no
more than 150 words. Bearing in mind that undergraduate essays
may often be even shorter, for example 1,000 words, you need to
limit the word count of the introduction and conclusion to make
sure that there is enough room for you to express your arguments
clearly. Often 50 words may suffice for an introduction that
adequately and succinctly expresses what you will be arguing in the
main body of the essay.
It is always a good idea to prepare an essay outline for philosophy
assignments, because this will help you to clarify the structure of
your argument – and, as we have emphasized throughout this book,
this is a crucial component of doing good philosophy. People differ,
however, on how early in your essay preparation this should be
done. See the other examples in this chapter and experiment with
different approaches, in order to find out what works best for you.
The introduction
An introduction should set the stage in a concise and clear way.
Try to avoid re-stating material that is already in the title; but it is
perfectly acceptable to state what you will argue for, for example,
‘In this essay I argue that killing another human being is sometimes
justified.’ You also need to say a little bit about the context of the
discussion and something about its history if this is appropriate.
114 DOING PHILOSOPHY
You may also want to give the reader pointers as to the kind
of arguments you will be using, or the evidence you intend to use,
for example, ‘I will draw on the work of J.S. Mill and consider
whether a time traveller would be justified in killing Hitler as a
baby.’
Because you need to outline what you will be arguing for in this
way, it is often advised that you should leave writing the intro-
duction until last, as it is often only after the rest of the essay is
written that you will have a clear idea about what to say.
The conclusion
The conclusion should wrap up your essay by summarizing what
has been said without repetition and suggesting ways that the
argument may go forward in the future. It should not state anything
new. The main body of your essay should carry all the main logical
structure of the argument you are presenting. In some literary
traditions, and in other cultures, the conclusion of the essay (rather
than the argument) is the point at which you reveal the dénoue-
ment of your narrative. On the whole this is bad practice in
philosophy. If the essay’s conclusion contains material that could
not have been known already there is something awry with
your structure. The reader should not be presented with a stated
opinion that they could not have anticipated from the rest of your
essay.
As with the introduction, you may, or may not, know what will
feature in your conclusion before you start writing. It is worth
keeping an open mind, as the detailed argument development and
analysis you engage in as you write may present new possibilities or
lines of enquiry which you wish to develop further.
Referencing
We do not give detailed advice about how to give references here,
because there are various systems, and different departments have
different preferences. Indeed, if you are studying another subject in
addition to philosophy, you may well find that the two departments
require different referencing systems. See Chapter 6 for more
information on referencing. The important point is to check
whether a particular style is required in the student handbook, and
if so, to stick to it rigorously.
If no particular style is required, then the golden rule is to give
sufficient information for the reader to be able to check that the
author referred to did actually write what you attribute to them.
At a minimum, the reader needs to know what edition of a work
you have used, and what page the quotation comes from (or some-
times a section or paragraph number, if the work is numbered
that way). So as a guide, you need to state the author, the name of
the work, the translator (where appropriate), the editor (where
appropriate), the publisher, the place of publication and year of
publication, and the number of the page where the quotation or
idea comes from. This is illustrated by this example taken from our
earlier reading list:
Kant, I. (1993), Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans.
and ed. M. Gregor. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press, p. 29.
118 DOING PHILOSOPHY
use such texts as material for comment. You might give reasons for
agreeing or disagreeing with what is said, or you might identify
two or more secondary texts which disagree with each other, and
say which you prefer and why. This way, your essay will be argu-
mentative through and through, and it will be evident to the reader
that it is all your own work.
Let us look at an example. Suppose you included the following in
an essay on Leibniz:
Leibniz defined a ‘necessary’ truth as one which could not have been
otherwise, in that its opposite would imply a contradiction. So, it is necessary
that a triangle has three sides, since the idea of a non-three-sided, three-sided
figure is self-contradictory. By a ‘contingent’ truth, he meant one that could
have been otherwise, in that its opposite would be non-contradictory, or
logically possible.
This would be plagiarism, since it is an unacknowledged, word-
for-word copy of a paragraph on p. 59 of G. MacDonald Ross
(1984), Leibniz. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Suppose then that
you add a reference:
Leibniz defined a ‘necessary’ truth as one which could not have been
otherwise, in that its opposite would imply a contradiction. So, it is necessary
that a triangle has three sides, since the idea of a non-three-sided, three-sided
figure is self-contradictory. By a ‘contingent’ truth, he meant one that could
have been otherwise, in that its opposite would be non-contradictory, or
logically possible. (MacDonald Ross (1984), p.59).
This is still inadequate, since you have not specified which are
MacDonald Ross’s actual words. Suppose you paraphrased the
passage:
Leibniz’s definition of a ‘necessary’ proposition was one which could not
have been false, because its negation would involve a logical impossibility. So
it is a necessary proposition that a triangle has three angles, because the
concept of a three-angled figure which doesn’t have three angles is a logical
impossibility. By a ‘contingent’ proposition Leibniz meant one that could
have been false, since its falsehood wouldn’t involve a contradiction or logical
impossibility.
This would be no better, because unacknowledged paraphrasing
still counts as plagiarism. What you need to do is to specify precisely
122 DOING PHILOSOPHY
• Philosophers use the first person singular, ‘I’, ‘me’, ‘my’ etc.
much more than in other disciplines, where it is often
frowned upon. Do not be afraid to use it yourself.
• Philosophers use active verbs more often than other dis-
ciplines, where passive forms tend to be preferred. For
example, use ‘I believe that’ rather than ‘it is believed that’.
Again, writing in this way is encouraged and gives a more
direct and concise turn of phrase.
• In some philosophical writing, you will find fewer direct quo-
tations than in other disciplines, or other areas of philosophy.
This is because arguments can be summarized rather than
having to be quoted. However, we have already noted
that literary considerations are also a factor in European phil-
osophy, in which texts and quotations are more prevalent.
Pay attention to materials you are reading to determine the
best practice for your course.
If you have been studying logic, or there is a logic component in
your module, you may feel that use of symbolism to support your
WRITING PHILOSOPHY 123
argument can be helpful. Take care to ensure that the use of logic
is appropriate and to ensure that it does indeed add clarity. There is
no point in labouring to get this aspect of your work right if it does
not aid your argument. On the other hand, it can sometimes go a
long way to making your main line of thought crystal clear for the
reader, where a paragraph of prose does not.
Writing clearly is very important because you want your tutor
to be able to understand what your arguments are and how they
fit together to support your conclusion. Do not use long words or
convoluted sentence structure just because you think it will make
you sound more like a professional philosopher. While some classic
texts in philosophy you read will be hard to understand and have
very complicated syntax, remember that they are classics in spite of
their lack of clarity, not because of it. Reading your essay aloud can
help you to identify any passages that sound awkward, so that you
can rewrite them.
It is also worth noting that because philosophers are very specific
in terms of how language is used, you should take particular care
over your grammar and spelling. There are many good essay
writing guides for the humanities that will help you with general
issues over spelling, grammar and general style. See Chapter 6 for
some suggestions.
Content
To begin with, it is important to make it clear that you understand
the meaning of key terms, and to clear up any ambiguities about
how you will be using them in your essay. You may hear philo-
sophers say at the start of a discussion or paper, ‘We must define our
terms’, and this is an important point. If you study any philosophy
of language you will come across different ideas about meaning and
reference, and philosophers often question what people mean when
they use a particular term, or how we can know that we refer to the
same thing as someone else when we use a word.
Having said this, it can be tempting to start an essay with a
dictionary definition of the key term in the question. However,
you should be wary of starting all your essays with the phrase, ‘The
Oxford English Dictionary defines [insert relevant term] as . . .’.
Rather than demonstrate your understanding of the issues at hand
and your critical engagement with them, this merely demonstrates
124 DOING PHILOSOPHY
that you know how to use a dictionary. Striving for clarity and a
shared understanding of the meaning of specific terms is very dif-
ferent from dusting off the OED every time you start writing an
essay.
If you have done your planning carefully, the central body of the
essay should involve your putting some flesh on your skeleton
argument. The work of demonstrating your own philosophical skill
goes on here. This is demonstrated in more depth in the essay
writing examples further on in this chapter. The philosophical tools
of argument construction and analysis do not differ from those we
have already explored.
Establishing what counts as ‘sufficient depth’ of analysis is per-
haps one of the key challenges in writing philosophy. As a rule of
thumb, seek to explain the ideas in enough detail for them to be
comprehensible to someone who has no previous knowledge of
the subject. This will become easier to judge as you practise your
skills of philosophical argument.
You will always need to be selective in your discussion, focusing
only on relevant issues; but your assignment should be designed so
that you can tackle the topic adequately within the time and word
limit available. If word limits prevent you from discussing additional
issues, then ‘signpost’ these if you wish. This shows that you are
aware of wider considerations, but have differentiated between
major and minor points for the purposes of the essay question being
addressed.
Once you have outlined the initial argument that you consider
to form the basis of your discussion of the topic, you can then
look at arguments against this position, then think of more ways to
defend the original position against this attack, and so on. Playing
devil’s advocate in this way is a key to writing a good philosophy
essay. The ability to make a point, to give reasons why that point is
relevant and why it backs up your main argument, then to look at
counter-arguments, and so on, is very important. When you are
writing your essay, think about what someone who disagreed with
your argument would say, and then what you would say in response
to them. Good philosophical arguing is like an extended rally in a
tennis match.
WRITING PHILOSOPHY 125
Example essay A
Background knowledge
The reading list for a course in which euthanasia is covered might
include the following texts:
1,500 words are not very many for a large topic such as eutha-
nasia. This means you will need not only to be concise, but to
decide which parts of the issue to concentrate on. It is inevitable
with large topics and small word limits that some issues will have
to be left out, but as long as you justify your choices for inclusion
and exclusion it is perfectly legitimate to focus in depth on one
particular issue, and this is often preferable to a broad but shallow
discussion of a topic. Perhaps you decide that you are particularly
interested in the distinction between active and passive euthanasia,
and this is what you will focus on in your essay. This is fine, but
make sure you explain your reasons for choosing to focus on one
area rather than another, and acknowledge that there are potentially
relevant issues that you will be putting aside because of the word
limit.
Having read the relevant literature and thought about your own
views on the topic, you can begin to plan your essay. Let us assume
that you have chosen to focus on the distinction between active
and passive euthanasia, and have decided that you want to argue that
euthanasia is not morally wrong.
An essay plan for the question above might look something like
this:
• Define euthanasia
• Focus will be on active/passive euthanasia (explain choice)
• Will be arguing euthanasia is not morally wrong
Body:
Conclusion:
As you can see, you may have less detail at the end of your plan
than the beginning, but you can develop your line of argument
as you write. Having a basic outline means that you can start
expanding your plan into a full essay – you could think about
writing your essay as filling in the gaps of your essay plan.
130 DOING PHILOSOPHY
For example, the acts and omissions doctrine offers great scope for
discussing the idea that passive euthanasia is morally acceptable, but
active euthanasia is not. However, this can also be criticized with
further counter-arguments. Ideally, your evidence of critical
thought should be several layers deep.
While there are many examples of philosophers arguing for and
against the acts and omissions doctrine, this is a prime opportunity
for you to express your own opinion, backed up with reasons of
course. You might think that you have nothing new to add to the
debate. After all, professional philosophers have been writing about
and discussing these issues for thousands of years, so what could
you say that has not been said before? While it is true that you may
find it hard to come up with an entirely new argument for (or
against) the acts and omissions doctrine, there are many ways that
you can demonstrate originality in your writing. For example, an
essay about euthanasia provides an opportunity to create your own
examples and scenarios. So, just as Philippa Foot makes up an
example about Rescue 1 and Rescue 2 in an attempt to demon-
strate that killing and letting die are morally distinct, you could
embellish her examples to argue that they are not distinct after all,
or make up a completely new scenario.
So you should now have ‘filled in’ quite a lot of the gaps in
your original essay plan, and expanded on the points you wanted
to make. Keeping the points above in mind when expanding
your initial thoughts should help you to write critically and
clearly.
When you have expanded all the points in your original essay
plan you can write the conclusion. Remember that the conclusion
should be a brief recapitulation of the main points you have made
in the body of your essay, and how they back up your main thesis.
There should be nothing in your conclusion that would surprise
the reader – your arguments in the essay body should all support
and lead up to your conclusion.
Example essay B
Let us look at a slightly more difficult example. There is a great deal
of discussion in all areas of our lives about the kinds of responsi-
bilities we have towards the environment, so here is a question that
has direct relevance to our thinking about these issues.
132 DOING PHILOSOPHY
This is a real problem for us now. How should we think about the
moral or political interests of all people in relation to their needs
and wants? And how should we consider the interests of those
who do not yet exist when we have our current real needs and
environment to consider? It would be easy to answer a question like
this with opinion that appealed to emotive factors about future
children; or to base our response on news reports about globaliza-
tion and multinationals, biodiversity and conservation, and the
interests of the developing world. However, a good philosophical
essay will require clear analysis of the issues and questions that
underpin this quotation and question. This essay requires you to
show your skill in analysing the philosophical problems that are
present in these current political debates.
It would be inappropriate to begin with just your opinions, for
instance:
not been asked what pollution is. We can say something about what
the author means by something being an evil, in a short sentence.
Second, the point about governmental responsibility is also not a
key concern, but we should make the reader of our essay aware that
we know it is a component or premise of the argument and needs to
be recognized. Third, in noting that governments have to balance
interests we are beginning to touch on the key topics to be
addressed, so we also need to show awareness of this as an important
part of the discussion.
Examine the following paragraph and see how some of the other
lesser points have been addressed and how the focus has been
shifted to the main topic:
issues. Next we would need to look in more detail at the three issues
already alluded to: can non-existent people have any interests? What
interests can we assume for people whose needs are unknown?
And, even if they have interests, what are our obligations to them?
Each of these needs to be addressed as a separate issue. At this stage,
you will need to look at the reading for the course in which this
question is embedded. How are interests to be measured and
determined? Are there already existent criteria you can appeal to
in the literature of your course that can be quoted (with correct
references)?
What you should see with this essay example is how important it
can be to break down the different questions that could be part of
the main question. Writing out as many of the questions as you can
in the form of notes, before beginning, is a good way of showing
yourself that you need to keep each line of argument clear and to
treat each point as needing support and analysis in some way.
Remember that each of the main points you identify will be acting
as a premise in the argument which forms your essay, leading to the
final conclusion. If the premises are not strong, the conclusion you
reach will not be strong either.
Example essay C
Innate ideas
How can we be sure that what we believe is true? Philosophers
of the seventeenth century were particularly concerned with this
question – seeking to move beyond unquestioning trust in the
education provided by the church of the time, to provide an inde-
pendently secure foundation for human knowledge. Descartes, in
particular, grappled with sceptical doubts: that nothing could be
known for certain.
Let us now take stock of progress so far. How does this informa-
tion help us to answer the essay question? Do we have enough to
complete the assignment, or does more work need to be done?
At this point, it may be helpful to draft an outline of our essay. Let
us go back to the essay title, sketch out the different sections of our
argument, and identify where the information we have gathered so
far will fit – and whether there are any gaps remaining:
Describe L’s account. What are the similarities & diffs cf. D’s?
• L rejects D’s account [So what are the similarities? Are there
any?]
• Diffs: no innate ideas.
• This is because counter-examples can be provided for all so-
called innate ideas:
Maths, logic – infants & learning disabled don’t have these
ideas
God, moral rights/wrongs – different societies have different
ideas about these
• And L rejects suggestion that we can have innate ideas
unconsciously
• → mind is ‘blank slate’. We have innate capacities, e.g. reason,
but all ideas are built on experience
Conclusion
matter whether ideas are innate or not?’ So far we have tackled the
first two, but largely ignored the third.
If we consult our notes about this bigger question, then we will
readily discover that Descartes and Locke shared concerns about
the status of knowledge, and the need to provide justification for
what counts as true knowledge. It is in the context of this common
enquiry that both thinkers explore the concept of innate ideas to
see whether, and how, these might contribute to knowledge. So
we could argue that they share common ground regarding why
the question of innate ideas is important. (There may be other
similarities too – are there common assumptions which underlie
both accounts, for example?)
Now we need to apply our skills of critical analysis to the task of
evaluating the two accounts in more depth. Are there supporting
arguments for every claim that Descartes and Locke make? How
strong are these? What objections could be raised against each view
– and what arguments could be offered in response to these? Many
of Locke’s arguments present objections to Descartes’ account –
but if our essay is to present a balanced account, we need also to
explore possible objections to Locke’s own view.
Let us look again at our summary of Locke’s account. He
criticizes, in turn, many of the ideas which have been proposed as
‘innate’, providing opposing evidence in each case: for example,
infants and people with learning disabilities have no innate idea of
logical or mathematical principles; different cultures do not share
our ‘innate’ sense of what counts as right and wrong, or our idea of
God. He concludes that there are no innate ideas. But is this con-
clusion too hasty? It relies on Locke’s assertion of the impossibility
of holding innate ideas unconsciously – otherwise, his opponents
could argue that (for example) infants do have the innate idea of the
logical principle of non-contradiction; they simply are not in a
position to bring that notion to consciousness. But what is Locke’s
argument for rejecting the notion of unconscious knowledge? Can
you spot any other problems with his line of reasoning?
We also need to establish what we conclude from our arguments.
Perhaps we are convinced by Locke’s criticisms of Descartes, and
therefore wish to argue that his account is to be preferred – if so, we
need to be able to offer a defence of his account against objections
such as the one we have just raised; or at least to provide reasoned
142 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Example essay D
Skeleton argument
1. What does the quotation mean?
a. What are the key ideas discussed (provide definitions if
necessary)?
b. How do they relate to each other – what is the structure of
the argument?
2. What are the reasons for saying this?
a. What are the supporting arguments (if they are not included
in the quotation itself)?
b. Why is this question important?
3. What follows from it?
a. Is this position successful? Are the premises true? Does the
conclusion follow?
b. What are the consequences of this view?
c. Does it raise any problems?
d. Can these problems be overcome? How?
will – statements (1a) and (2a) above refer explicitly to the absence
of necessity and ‘free acts’. The rest of Leibniz’s argument is
more difficult – what does it mean to ‘incline our soul’ (1)? to be
‘admitted to existence’ (3)? for something to be ‘contained in one’s
notion’ (2a)? – and we probably need to go back to our notes, or do
some more research, to understand these fully. Here we can begin
to see that the first two sections of our skeleton argument – ‘what
does the quotation mean?’ and ‘what are the reasons for saying it?’ –
may blur into one another: we need to discover some of Leibniz’s
supporting claims in order to analyse the details of the quotation
itself.
With the aid of some research, we can establish other relevant
principles of Leibniz’s thought – for instance, that each human
being is a unity who has a complete concept, a ‘script’ of all that can
be said to be true of him/her.4 This helps us to interpret statement
(2) – Judas’s actions (including his sin) are part of this ‘script’ and
thus are ‘contained in his notion’; and so it makes no sense to
‘ask why Judas sins’ because, for Leibniz, this is part of who he is. If
he did not commit his sin, then he would not be Judas. We also
discover that Leibniz believed God to be the creator of the best of
all possible worlds – which helps us to interpret statement (3) as:
it makes sense to ask why God allows Judas (given his nature as a
sinner) to exist as part of such a world.
We could say more about the meaning of this quotation – but
we already have enough material to anticipate some of the issues
that will need tackling in the third section of our essay, where we
critically evaluate the implications of the quotation. On the one
hand, Leibniz talks of ‘free acts’; on the other, he claims that such
acts are ‘contained in [the] notion’ of Judas (or any other individual)
– which implies that he would not be Judas if he had done other-
wise. How do we reconcile these claims? How can Judas’s act be
free if he could not have done otherwise? How could he have done
otherwise if this act is ‘contained in his notion’? It is implausible to
suggest that Leibniz is advancing an obviously self-contradictory
claim (if this were the case, we would not still be studying his
arguments three centuries later), so we need to do some more
precise analysis of these ideas in order to establish how Leibniz seeks
to resolve this tension – and whether he is successful.
This is a good example of how philosophical argument can
148 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Example essay E
(a) What does the author mean by ‘the problem of evil’ in this
context? (5)
(b) What is a ‘sound valid argument’? Use examples to illus-
trate your answer. (10)
(c) Construct an argument of the kind described explaining
why each premise is needed and how the argument works.
(15)
(d) Give reasons for why an argument of this kind can be
questioned. (20)
To set the stage for those not familiar with the philosophical issue
here, there is a traditional form to the problem of evil, which is
being questioned by Yandell.
The premises, derived from mainstream thinking about God, are
that God is:
• all-knowing
• all-powerful
• all-loving
• perfect in all ways
WRITING PHILOSOPHY 151
this counts against the existence of God, since the existence of evil
is incompatible with his existence and his having the properties he
is supposed to. (99 words)
This might seem reasonably good as an answer, but let us look more
closely. Have we answered the question? Arguably not, because the
question made reference to the author, Yandell, and even asked us
to look at the context: we have not done so. As always, we do need
to address the question. We need to go back to the source. In
particular, think about why the paragraph of text has been given.
It suggests that we need to pay as much attention to the way the
author goes about looking at the problem of evil as we do to the
details. As the given text indicates, he is concerned to find philo-
sophically robust ways of expressing the problem. Additionally, if
we look at the source, we discover that he makes a distinction
between what he calls the pastoral problem of evil, that is, the
problem of what we should do in the face of evil; the theological
construction of a theodicy, that is, an account of why God permits
there to be evil; and the philosophical problem of God’s very
existence, given a supposed contradiction between his nature and a
world containing evil. He also goes on to argue that there are some
possible solutions to the problem that involve limiting God’s
powers, that are not available to us if we wish to deal with a god that
fulfils the criteria set out in traditional accounts of his nature. As
the chapter from which the given text is taken proceeds, the author
explores different forms of argument with alternative premises and
conclusions, exploring the strengths and weaknesses of each.
Having said all that, let us try our answer again:
Even if you did not start out seeing the bigger picture, by now
you should appreciate the general trend of our answers. Yandell
wants to explore the problem of evil in a clear and logical way. We
have answered (a) and (b) and have begun to explore the problem
itself and what the form of the problem could be for Yandell. We
now turn to (c) which asks us to apply ideas from (a) and (b) to
make up good arguments that fulfil Yandell’s criteria. We shall not
present a sample answer here. It is good for you to think about how
you would do so for yourself. Again, the basic rules apply. Some-
thing a little more in-depth is needed compared with what we have
written so far, since there are more marks available. We also need to
check back on our reading and notes to see what we have already
encountered that can be helpful. So what might you write? It is
worth bearing in mind that you are asked to critique the argument
you construct in (c) as your answer in (d); what you say in (c) must
be capable of further analysis, but you do not want to write any of
the critical side of the argument yet.
(d) asks you to assess critically the success of your work in (c).
Effectively you are being asked to present the pros and cons of a
form of the problem of evil argument, using the ideas already
explored.
We have seen that there is a skill to getting the right kind of
information in a short structured series of answers. They are not
straightforward, but often offer an opportunity to focus on specific
WRITING PHILOSOPHY 157
It is tempting just to read the grade you have been awarded, and
then cast the essay aside. After all, that piece of work is finished –
what more is needed? Surely there is little point in re-reading the
essay – especially if your grade is lower than you had hoped.
This is a common, but misguided, response. It overlooks the fact
that your completed and assessed assignments are, in turn, another
resource you can use for your future study. As well as grading your
essay, your tutor will have provided written comments to give
you feedback on how to improve your work in the future. If you
disregard these, you are wasting your tutor’s time and missing a
valuable source of guidance for your own learning. It is foolish to
tackle your next assignment without having learnt as much as you
can from your previous experience – especially if your grade is lower
than you had hoped.
Even so, you might think there is little to be learned from your
previous assignment – it was probably on a completely different
topic from your next essay, and what help is feedback on your
interpretation of Descartes’ theory of the mind when you are try-
ing to prepare a critique of Kant’s ethics? Admittedly, a better
understanding of Descartes’ theory may not be of direct assistance,
but it may benefit you in your end of year exams, or in future
philosophy courses. Furthermore, as we emphasize throughout this
book, philosophy is not only about understanding important theor-
ies; it is also about developing your own skills of critical analysis –
and these can be applied equally well to any area of philosophy. So
you may have much to learn from your tutor’s feedback on your
philosophical skills, which can be applied in your next assignment.
It is worthwhile to obtain as much feedback as you can on the
strengths and weaknesses of your philosophical efforts to date, so
that you can learn from this to continue to improve in the future.
In the next sections, we will consider how you can obtain useful
feedback on your work, and how to make best use of what you
discover from it.
Sources of feedback
Perhaps the most obvious source of feedback is your tutor’s com-
ment on your written work; and we will focus our attention on
this, as it is expressly designed for the purpose of providing you
with formative feedback. It also has the advantage of being a formal,
WRITING PHILOSOPHY 159
Who?
Tutors Students
Summary
This chapter has given an overview of what it means to write
philosophically, building on the skills you have already been practis-
ing through reading, taking notes and engaging in discussion. It has
shown you how you can build your own arguments and create
your own philosophical work that sits within the context of an
established body of philosophical writing.
You have also been presented with various example methods for
the task of writing essays and papers, and for applying the tech-
niques of philosophical criticism and argument analysis to your
own writing, so that you can improve your philosophical skills
incrementally with every assignment that you complete. In taking
part in this continuous learning process, you are well on the way to
becoming a philosopher.
Notes
1 www.leeds.ac.uk/arts/studyskills/learningandteachingatuniversity/
media/AssCode%20Marking%20criteria%20%20descriptors.doc
2 Gower, Barry S., ‘The environment and justice for future generations’
in Cooper, David E. and Palmer, Joy A. (eds) (1995), Just Environments,
Intergenerational, International and Interspecies Issues. London: Routledge,
p. 49
3 ‘Exegesis’ is a technical academic term which you are likely to
encounter – it means, roughly, the interpretation and explanation of a
text.
4 This is inevitably a very incomplete account of Leibniz’s theory. As
always, you will need to do your own research to augment your under-
standing – this is a sketch for an essay, not a fully developed argument.
5 Yandell, Keith E. (1999), Philosophy of Religion. London: Routledge,
p. 125.
6 This is a direct quotation from a first-year student, cited in Burke,
Deirdre (2007), ‘Engaging students in personal development planning:
profiles, skills development and acting on feedback’. Discourse vol. 6,
no. 2, p. 124.
6 Resources
Library resources
Your university’s libraries will host a wide range of resources, both
hard-copy books and journals, and electronic resources such as
CD-ROMs, subscriber-only databases and on-line material. The
library website will probably give you a good idea of what is avail-
able. It is likely that there will also be specialist librarians dedicated
to your subject, who will be able to point you to the most appro-
priate resources for whichever topic you are researching, and could
save you hours in searching for specific resources.
It is a good idea to familiarize yourself with the library as soon
as you arrive at university, as you will need to spend a fair amount
of time there if you are to do well in your degree. Most libraries
will run induction courses for new students, explaining how to use
the catalogue and where books and journals for your subject are
held, and we advise that you attend any such sessions offered at your
institution.
RESOURCES 167
Books
The library will probably hold a good selection of philosophy
books, and it is very unlikely that there will be texts on your reading
lists that are not stocked; your lecturers will have checked that the
library holds the relevant texts before recommending them, and if
they anticipate that there will be high demand for a particular book,
it is likely that it will be placed in a short-loan or high-demand
section, so that all students will have access to it.
If you do have trouble getting hold of a particular book, most
libraries offer a document supply service. This means that if you
have the reference details of a particular book or article, but your
university library does not stock it, they will often be able to order a
copy of it for you. This can be expensive, and while most libraries
will subsidize the cost of obtaining such items you may be required
to pay a small fee.
An alternative approach is to find out if there are other university
libraries you can visit (near your own university, or perhaps near
your home), and if so, to enquire whether you are able to use their
facilities – many university libraries offer reciprocal arrangements
which enable students and staff from other institutions to access
their resources. Your university librarians will be able to offer more
detailed advice about this.
Apart from the books on your reading lists, we recommend the
books below as useful, no matter which specific philosophers and
topics your course covers.
Journals
The library will probably subscribe to various philosophy journals.
This means that when a new edition of a particular journal is pub-
lished they will receive a hard copy, or if the journal is electronic,
on-line access will be granted, usually through a username and pass-
word system.
Many of the items on your reading lists are likely to be journal
articles, and some may have been reprinted in anthologies. If you
have trouble getting hold of an anthology containing an article
you need, try finding the journal in which it was originally
published.
As mentioned above, some journals are available on-line as well
as in hard copy, and your library will be able to give you more
information about which on-line services they subscribe to and
how to access them. Again, if there is an item that your library does
not hold you may be able to request it through the document
supply service.
Some journals aimed specifically at undergraduates are:
• The Richmond Journal of Philosophy: www.rutc.ac.uk/rjp/
• The British Journal of Undergraduate Philosophy: www.bups.org/
pages/bjup.shtml
There are many journals in philosophy published each year, and
you may be wondering how you should go about finding articles
170 DOING PHILOSOPHY
that are relevant to your topic if they are not already on your
reading list. One way is to look through the contents pages (either
hard copy or on-line) of journals relevant to the topic you are
researching. If you are not sure which journals to look at in the first
place, there are several databases that can help you to find what you
need. Consult your university library about how to access these.
Databases
With so many books, journals and articles about philosophy
available, databases are an essential tool. Listed here are the major
databases used by those working in philosophy.
Copyright
As a student, you have an interest in copyright from two points
of view: the copyright of the authors you read, and the copyright of
your own work. Copyright means the right of the owner of a text
to prevent anyone else from reproducing it. Copyright laws
came into being to protect authors who lost money because
unscrupulous publishers would print pirate editions of their works
without paying them any royalties.
Infringing the copyright of an author may seem like plagiarism,
RESOURCES 171
Referencing
Different lecturers and departments have different referencing
requirements. If information about which referencing system to use
is not provided in your course or module documentation, you
should check with your lecturer or tutor which system they prefer.
Below are details about how to use the main types of referencing.
Harvard referencing
When using Harvard referencing you should list all the sources you
cite in your essay alphabetically by author in the bibliography.
When you use a quotation or refer to one of your sources in the
main body of the essay you make a note just after it in brackets of
the author’s surname, year the source was published, and the page
you refer to.
For example, in an essay on moral theory the following sentence
might appear:
Simon Blackburn claims that ‘we should not theorize about morality and
ethics as if they are in the business of describing aspects of the world’
(Blackburn, 1996, 83).
In the bibliography the full reference would look like this:
172 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Footnote referencing
With this system, footnotes contain the full reference information.
So, the example above would look like this:
Simon Blackburn claims that ‘we should not theorize about morality and
ethics as if they are in the business of describing aspects of the world’.1
1
Blackburn, Simon, ‘Securing the nots: moral epistemology for the quasi-realist’,
in Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter and Timmons, Mark, Moral Knowledge: New Readings
in Moral Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996, p. 83.
When using this system of referencing, once you have given the
first full reference, and if you quote from no other source by the
same author in your essay, you can use just the author’s surname
and the relevant page for any further references from that text. For
example, a reference later in the same essay would look like this:
As Blackburn points out, the correct response to the relativistic threat is
to consider the external standpoint that the objector asks us to occupy
(Blackburn, p. 89).
If you do use more than one source by the same author in your
essay, you should also include the title of the work (although this
can be in a shortened form when the reference is repeated if the
title is a long one, as long as it is obvious which source you are
referring to).
If you access a journal on-line that is also printed in hard copy
you should reference it as you would the hard copy. If the journal is
only published on-line you should reference it as you would for a
hard-copy journal article but ensure you add the URL and date
you accessed the article.
Internet resources
The internet contains a vast amount of freely accessible informa-
tion. (There are other on-line resources such as databases and
RESOURCES 173
on-line journals, but these are not usually free to members of the
public, and often require you to log in using your university or
library username and password. These are covered in the section on
library resources.) New students may not know where to start look-
ing for useful, high quality philosophy resources. You may be
tempted to use general resources such as Wikipedia, and while the
articles written for this type of site can be informative, you should
not rely on them as definitive sources. It can be difficult to know
which sites contain reliable information, and which are of less high
quality. If you use a search engine to find resources on a particular
topic there are several checks you can make to ensure that the sites
you use are reliable:
• Does it tell you when the page was created, by whom, and
the last time it was updated?
• If an individual has created the page,
do they have relevant qualifications or experience that
make them an expert in the particular field?
Do they work for a Higher Education Institution (HEI), or
other reputable educational organization?
• If there is no individual author listed, but the page is owned by
an organization, what sort of organization is it?
Is it a university or other educational institution? If so,
look at their web page; is it a reputable institution? For
example, are they funded by the government or by some
other means? If you use a search engine to find informa-
tion about them does their website come near the top of
the list of results?
If the page owner is not an HEI, are they:
• a government organization?
• a commercial organization?
• a non-profit organization?
• a charity?
• an individual?
• What qualifies the author or owner of the source as expert in
the field you are researching?
• Is the information presented in a balanced way?
• Is the content of the page grammatically correct?
• Are any sources used cited and referenced properly?
174 DOING PHILOSOPHY
Support systems
Student centres
Many HEIs have centres that support students in their study skills,
frequently called student centres, study skills centres, skills centres
and various other names. Such centres typically offer short courses,
documentation and one-to-one help with aspects of study that you
find problematic. They often have websites with information about
how to improve your study skills, and where to get more help.
Careers centres
Your university will almost certainly have a careers centre, where
you can access a range of services. Most careers centres will offer
events, modules, workshops, talks, advice and guidance around all
aspects of deciding on and starting out in the career you want.
There will be information available about career development
and planning, for example, resources covering what is involved in
different jobs, and workshops on CV-writing or how to do well
in interviews. There will be information about work experience
opportunities, and talks by businesses and other employers in the
region. The careers centre will also run graduate recruitment fairs
at various points during the year.
Disability services
If you have a specific disability, for example, you are dyslexic, visu-
ally- or hearing- or mobility-impaired, your university disability
service will be able to provide information, guidance and support.
These can include specialist software, extra exam time, note-taking,
transcription (for example, lecture notes in Braille) and audio
services. While some people are disinclined to use support services
because of some perceived stigma attached to needing ‘help’, they
176 DOING PHILOSOPHY
are there to be used, and you should make the most of the services
your institution offers. You should contact the disability service at
your institution to find out more about the specific support offered.
Philosophy societies
Many departments have student philosophy societies. These are
groups run by and for students, and can be a good way to get to
know fellow philosophers. They often run social events, lectures
and even conferences, and provide a focus for those particularly
interested in the subject to meet like-minded people.
Subject associations
The British Undergraduate Philosophy Society www.bups.org
This society was founded in 2005 to provide a link for philosophy
students studying at different institutions. It runs quarterly con-
ferences, publishes a journal of undergraduate essays and papers
presented at the conferences, and provides support for philosophy
societies in institutions. It is run by and for students, and maintains
email discussion lists for philosophy students across the UK.
Metaphysical terms
These are words that are used to say something about the way
the world is, or could possibly be, as opposed to what we may
know about the world or how we may use language to refer to that
world.
Epistemological terms
These are words and terms that are used to help us to understand
something about knowledge – what knowledge is and what the
limits of our knowledge might be.
Semantic/logical terms
These terms are about a third way of looking at the relationship
between the world and ourselves that is concerned with the
language we use to talk about the world. So far we have discussed
how the world is or could be and how we could know about it.
These are words about how language and meaning work.
it just is how things are. What we say about the world can be true or
false: it is the case that Christopher Eccleston has played the Doctor
in Doctor Who, which makes the sentence ‘Christopher Eccleston has
played the Doctor in Doctor Who’ true.
Analytic truths are ones that we can say are true based purely on
the meaning of the words. The classic example used in many texts is
‘all bachelors are unmarried men’ – the truth of this statement rests
in the fact that ‘bachelor’ means ‘unmarried man’. Synthetic truths
(remember this is about language not the world) have that status
because they match the way the world is, not just the way words
have meaning. For example, ‘David Tennant has played the Doctor
in Doctor Who’ is also true because it matches the world: it is a
synthetic truth. Just like the a priori/a posteriori distinction there is
a great deal of discussion and debate about this. Can you think of
ambiguous statements that could be hard to place as either analytic
or synthetic?
Index
dialogue 31, 79, 89–90, 91, 96, see also Virtual Learning
163 Environment
dictionary 52, 58, 123–4 interpreting
list of dictionaries 167–8 texts 28, 62
Dostoyevsky, Fyodor 103–4 essay questions 145–6