Essentials of Cognitive Neuroscience 2nd Edition
Essentials of Cognitive Neuroscience 2nd Edition
Essentials of Cognitive Neuroscience 2nd Edition
CLICK HERE
INTRODUCTION TO SECTION I THE NEUROBIOLOGY
OF THINKING
Anyone who can read these words, including you,
experiences conscious awareness. What explains
this? Is the conscious experience of other people “the
same” as my own? Is our conscious experience
qualitatively different from what may or may not be
experienced by nonhuman animals? These and similar
questions have fascinated some of humankind’s most
celebrated thinkers for as long as humans have been
leaving records of their cogitation. They are among the
most profound that a human being can ask. Not
surprising, then, is the fact that questions that relate
either directly or indirectly to the phenomenon
consciousness and the related construct of cognition
(i.e., thinking) have been taken up by many different
scholarly disciplines, including philosophy,
evolutionary biology, anthropology, economics,
linguistics, computer science, and psychology. What
distinguishes cognitive neuroscience, the focus of this
book, from these and other disciplines, is its
grounding in the methods and traditions of
neuroscience, and the primacy that it places on
understanding the biological bases of mental
phenomena. Now it bears noting that cognitive
neuroscience doesn’t concern itself only with
consciousness and conscious awareness. Indeed, I
feel confident asserting that the vast majority of
articles that have been published in, say, the Journal
of Cognitive Neuroscience (one of many scientific
journals publishing peer-reviewed reports of research
in the field) don’t even explicitly address the idea of
consciousness, much less use the word.
Nonetheless, it is also true that it can be difficult to
entertain detailed thoughts about human behavior
and the principles that govern it without straying into
ideas such as those that opened this paragraph. This
clear relationship to profound philosophical questions
is one of the qualities that differentiates cognitive
neuroscience from other physical and biological
sciences, including many other domains of
neuroscience. Like other physical and biological
scientists, cognitive neuroscientists design and carry
out rigorously controlled experiments that yield
objective, measurable data, and seek to relate these
data to mechanistic models of how a natural system
works. And, as suggested above, the system studied
by cognitive neuroscientists is one that is also of
direct interest to scholars who study it from a very
different perspective (e.g., from philosophy, from
anthropology, and from cognitive psychology). This
overlap turns out to be both a blessing and a curse.
It’s a blessing in that the cognitive neuroscientist can
draw on ideas and observations from a vast array of
rich intellectual traditions. And because they are
studying questions that are fundamental to the human
condition, almost any thinking person that a cognitive
neuroscientist encounters is likely to be interested in
what they do for a living. (Much easier, in the humble
opinion of the author, to be a cognitive neuroscientist
attending a social function full of strangers than, say,
an economist, or a cell biologist, or a particle
physicist.) The curse is found on the flip side of this
coin. Because scholars in different fields are often
interested in the same object of study (whether it be
visual perception, or aesthetics, or antisocial
behavior), cognitive neuroscience research can often
be characterized by people working in other fields as
asking the wrong question, or asking it in the wrong
way, or of generating findings that are fundamentally
irrelevant for understanding the question at hand.
Being aware of this sociological context surrounding
cognitive neuroscience is INTRODUCTION TO
SECTION I 3 just one piece of knowledge that can be
helpful in evaluating the implications and importance
of any particular set of facts and ideas that will be
described in this book. COGNITIVE NEUROSCIENCE?
OR “HUMAN NEUROSCIENCE”? OR
“NEUROSCIENCE-WITHDIRECT-IMPLICATIONSFOR-
UNDERSTANDINGHUMAN-BEHAVIOR”? How were
the topics to be covered in this book selected? More
importantly, when teaching cognitive neuroscience,
where does one draw the line that defines the
boundaries of the discipline? This is a difficult
question that doesn’t have a definitive answer. It’s
really just an accident of history that the confluence of
neuroscientific methods and studies of human
behavior happened first, or, at least, influentially, with
domains of behavior and function that are studied by
cognitive psychology (e.g., visual perception, language
function, memory), as opposed to, for example, social
behavior, personality, emotion, or psychopathology.
As a result, one sees the label “cognitive
neuroscience” appearing earlier in the literature than,
for example, affective neuroscience or, certainly,
social cognitive neuroscience. As a consequence, the
term “cognitive neuroscience” has come to be used in
many contexts, and not always with precisely the
same meaning. In one context, “cognitive
neuroscience” can be used to refer to the tools and
methods used to study the neural bases of human
behavior (e.g., brain scans, recording electrical
potentials at the scalp, brain stimulation). This might
seem like a misnomer, however, if the behavior being
studied doesn’t directly relate to cognition (e.g., the
study of sleep or of the maturation of various brain
systems during adolescence). The label “cognitive
neuroscience” can also seem like a bad fit for
research that spans multiple traditional categories of
brain and/or behavior. To pick one real-world
example, let’s consider the study of how neural
systems measured with brain scans relate to
performance on an economic decision-making task by
high trait-anxiety vs. low traitanxiety prisoners (all
classified as “psychopaths”), and the comparison of
these data with data from neurological patients with
frank damage to the ventromedial prefrontal cortex.
Should this be classified as cognitive neuroscience
research? On one level, I hope that the answer is
“yes,” because we will be considering this research in
Chapter 17! However, to do so is to not explicitly
acknowledge the equally important contributions to
this research from clinical psychology, from affective
neuroscience, from neuroeconomics, and from
neuropsychology. In view of the above, to capture the
interdisciplinary breadth of much of what we’ll be
considering in this book, might it perhaps have been
better to entitle it “Essentials of Human
Neuroscience”? Here the answer is an unequivocal
“no,” because to do so would be to exclude the fact
that understanding the neural bases of almost all
domains of human behavior requires a thorough
knowledge of analogous neural functioning in
nonhuman animals. This is because, as we shall see
in almost every chapter of this book, technical and
ethical limitations of what we can measure in humans
require us to draw heavily on the results of research
performed with nonhuman animals. Hence, the idea,
implied in the title of this section, that the most
precise title for this book might be “Essentials of
Neuroscience with Direct Implications for
Understanding Human Behavior.” Now I’m no expert
in academic publishing, but I’m fairly confident that,
were I to have actually proposed this title, my editor
would have rejected it. If nothing else, there probably
aren’t many universities where one can find a course
that’s called “Introduction to Neuroscience with
Direct Implications for Understanding Human
Behavior.” Nonetheless, this is probably as good a
summary, in 10 words or less, of what this book hopes
to cover. And so, with these considerations in mind,
we’ll stick with the label “cognitive neuroscience.” It’s
not perfect, but if one is comfortable with a
reasonably broad definition of cognition as thinking,
behaving, and the factors on which these depend,
then this label will serve us reasonably well. CHAPTER
1 KEY THEMES ● Although the phenomenon of
consciousness and the related construct of cognition
(i.e., thinking) are the focus of many different scholarly
disciplines, what distinguishes cognitive
neuroscience is its grounding in the methods and
traditions of neuroscience, and the primacy that it
places on understanding the neurobiological bases of
mental phenomena. ● There are two levels at which
the term “cognitive neuroscience” is used: broadly, it
has come to refer to the neuroscientific study of most
domains of human behavior; narrowly, it refers to the
study of neural bases of thinking – what influences it,
what it consists of, and how it is controlled. ● The
roots of cognitive neuroscience can be traced back to
a nineteenth-century debate over two ways of thinking
about brain function that both remain relevant today:
localization of function vs. mass action. ● Mid-to-late
nineteenth-century research, and the vigorous debate
that accompanied it, led to models of localization of
three functions: motor control (localized to posterior
frontal lobes); vision (localized to occipital lobes); and
speech production (localized to the left posterior
inferior frontal gyrus). ● Motor control research
introduced the principle of topographic
representation, that is, adjacent parts of the body can
be represented on adjacent parts of the cerebral
cortex. ● Studying an aspect of cognition requires
careful thought about the validity of the function to be
studied; and not all aspects of human behavior can be
studied with the same sets of assumptions, or even
with the same methods. ● The discipline of cognitive
neuroscience could not exist without discoveries
yielded by research with nonhuman animals. ● At the
dawn of the twentieth century, scientists were
studying the brain and behavior from three related, but
distinct, perspectives that would eventually give rise
to cognitive neuroscience as we know it today:
systems neuroscience, behavioral
neurology/neuropsychology, and experimental
psychology. INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY
INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY 5 CONTENTS KEY
THEMES A BRIEF (AND SELECTIVE) HISTORY
Construct validity in models of cognition Localization
of function vs. mass action The first scientifically
rigorous demonstrations of localization of function
The localization of motor functions The localization of
visual perception The localization of speech WHAT IS
A BRAIN AND WHAT DOES IT DO? LOOKING AHEAD
TO THE DEVELOPMENT OF COGNITIVE
NEUROSCIENCE END-OF-CHAPTER QUESTIONS
REFERENCES OTHER SOURCES USED FURTHER
READING 6 SECTION I: THE NEUROBIOLOGY OF
THINKING A BRIEF (AND SELECTIVE) HISTORY
Although the term “cognitive neuroscience” as a
moniker for a scientific discipline has only been with
us for a few decades, the field has roots that extend
back thousands of years. Ancient Egyptians, Greeks,
and Romans all had ideas about the corporeal bases
of human thoughts and emotions, although many of
these did not specify a role for the brain. In preparing
the bodies of deceased nobles for the afterlife, for
example, ancient Egyptians removed and discarded
the brain as an early step in the mummification
process. The internal organs that were deemed to be
important were preserved in urns that were entombed
along with the body. In most ancient civilizations for
which there are records, up through and including
Roman civilization, the heart was believed to be the
organ of thought. By the time we get to Enlightenment–
era Europe, however, the central importance of
“neuro” for cognition was widely accepted. One highly
influential (and, more recently, ridiculed) example was
that of German anatomists Franz Josef Gall (1758–
1828) and Johann Gaspar Spurzheim (1776–1832),
who developed a highly detailed scheme, known as
phrenology, for how they thought that the shape of
different parts of the skull related to one’s personality
and mental capacities. The underlying premise was
that the relative bigness or smallness of various parts
of the brain would produce convexities or concavities
in the overlying skull. A skilled phrenologist, then,
could learn something about an individual by
palpating that person’s skull. A bulge in the eye socket
(inferred from “bulgy eyes”) would mean a
predilection toward language, whereas an indentation
near the left ear would correspond to a relative
absence of the trait of “destructiveness” (Figure 1.1).
One can see how such a scheme, if it had any validity,
would have obvious utility for diagnosing maladies of
the brain, as well as for assessing personality and
aptitude. (Indeed, for a period during the 1800s it was
[mis] used in this way quite extensively, particularly in
England and in the United States.) Construct validity in
models of cognition For at least the past 100 years,
the psychology and neuroscience communities have
viewed virtually all tenets of the phrenological
enterprise as being scientifically invalid. For starters,
the very “functions” that phrenologists assigned to
different parts of the scalp were derived from Gall’s
intuition rather than from a principled theoretical
framework. Let’s consider, for example,
conscientiousness. Now it is true, of course, that an
organism without a brain cannot exhibit
conscientiousness, and, therefore, the phenomenon
could not exist without a brain. However, might it not
be the case that “conscientiousness” is just a label
that we, as denizens of highly organized societies,
have given to a certain collection of attributes
characteristic of some peoples’ behavior and
personality? This can be illustrated from two
perspectives. The first is a caveat about inferring the
existence of a discrete neural correspondence to
every describable aspect of behavior. For example,
when a student sends me a thank-you note for having
written a letter of recommendation for her, I will
consider her to have displayed conscientiousness.
But could it not be that this reflects the fact that she
was conditioned during her upbringing to seek positive
reinforcement from her parents (“You’re such a good
girl for writing those thank-you notes!”), and that her
note to me is “merely” the product of an association
that she has formed between writing a thank-you note
and this reinforcement? Were this the case, it
wouldn’t make sense to think of conscientiousness as
a discrete mental faculty. (And if there’s no such
faculty, then there’s no “thing” to localize to a part of
the brain.) The second perspective is that, as it turns
out, there is a branch of psychology in which
conscientiousness is a valid construct, but it is as one
of the so-called “big-5” personality traits. But because
each of these five traits (openness-toexperiences,
conscientiousness, extraversion, agreeableness, and
neuroticism) is a statistical composite derived from
multiple measurements (such as responses to many-
morethan-five questions on personality assessment
questionnaire), none of them can be construed as a
unitary entity that might be localized to one brain
system. And so, from this perspective, because
conscientiousness isn’t any one thing, it doesn’t seem
reasonable to expect it to localize to one part of the
brain.
CLICK HERE