Hegel and The Arts 1st Edition Stephen Houlgate
Hegel and The Arts 1st Edition Stephen Houlgate
Hegel and The Arts 1st Edition Stephen Houlgate
com
https://ebookgate.com/product/hegel-and-the-
arts-1st-edition-stephen-houlgate/
https://ebookgate.com/product/a-companion-to-hegel-1st-edition-
stephen-houlgate/
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-orthodox-hegel-development-
further-developed-stephen-theron/
https://ebookgate.com/product/pevsner-the-bbc-years-listening-to-
the-visual-arts-stephen-games/
https://ebookgate.com/product/information-arts-intersections-of-
art-science-and-technology-1st-edition-stephen-wilson/
Hegel s introduction to the System encyclopaedia
phenomenology and psychology 1st Edition Georg Wilhelm
Friedrich Hegel
https://ebookgate.com/product/hegel-s-introduction-to-the-system-
encyclopaedia-phenomenology-and-psychology-1st-edition-georg-
wilhelm-friedrich-hegel/
https://ebookgate.com/product/hegel-1st-edition-raymond-plant/
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-communist-ideal-in-hegel-and-
marx-1st-edition-david-macgregor/
https://ebookgate.com/product/communications-and-the-arts-1st-
edition-claire-wyckoff/
https://ebookgate.com/product/proust-and-the-arts-1st-edition-
christie-mcdonald/
HEGEL AND THE ARTS
Topics in Historical Philosophy
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
o The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the
American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper
for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1992.
In memory of Salim Kemal (1948–1999)
Contents
List of Abbreviations ix
Hegel’s Architecture 29
David Kolb
Art and History: Hegel on the End, the Beginning, and the
Future of Art 179
Martin Donougho
What Was Abstract Art? (From the Point of View of Hegel) 244
Robert B. Pippin
Art, Religion, and the Modernity of Hegel 271
John Walker
Index 337
Contributors 351
Abbreviations
The following abbreviations have been used in the essays in this collection.
ix
x
ABBREVIATIONS
xi
xii
INTRODUCTION
ings, they need to see and hear truth and freedom given concrete sensu-
ous expression; and he contends that they need art because they need to
encounter beauty that has itself been freely created by human beings.
This is not to say that art necessarily originated in some primordial desire
for beauty pulsating within primitive mankind. It is to insist, however, that
whatever its origin may have been and whatever other uses it may be put
to, art’s true purpose is to grant us the occasion to contemplate, dwell
with, and mold our minds to the contours of beauty. (Note, by the way,
that although beautiful art addresses the senses, specifically the eyes and
the ears, it does not address the senses alone. It speaks to the mind through
the senses by showing the mind its own freedom in a sensuous form
[VA 1:57/A 1:35].)
In an age when many artists regard beauty as peripheral and prefer
to concern themselves with aesthetic innovation, the unfettered explo-
ration of their chosen medium, or simply breaking taboos, Hegel’s beauty-
centered aesthetics might well seem hopelessly old-fashioned.20 It is im-
portant to recognize, however, that Hegel gives pride of place to beauty
not out of any personal conservatism, but because he regards beauty as
essential to a life lived in the full and multidimensional consciousness of
human freedom. Art and beauty are not luxuries for Hegel, but necessi-
ties. Hegel does not deny that art can do many other things apart from
present us with beauty. He recognizes that art can be decorative and en-
tertaining, that it can promote aims that are principally moral and politi-
cal rather than aesthetic, and that it can serve to refine our wilder emo-
tions (VA 1:20, 72–76/A 1:7, 47–50). It can also explore the possibilities of
the artistic medium itself or simply display the skill of the artist (VA 2:227–
28/A 1:599). If, however, besides doing these things art fails to present us
with beauty, it deprives us not just of some superfluous adornment to our
lives but of an indispensable way of bringing our own freedom and vital-
ity into view.
In the first half of his Critique of Judgment, Kant is primarily con-
cerned with the character of aesthetic judgment. He argues that we judge
an object to be beautiful when it stimulates the free play of our under-
standing and imagination. This free play leads to no definite cognition of
the object but is the source of a feeling of pleasure in the subject. “With-
out relation to the feeling of the subject,” Kant writes, “beauty is nothing
by itself.”21 Beauty is not, therefore, an independent property of the ob-
ject. Hegel, by contrast, thinks that beauty is a property of objects—in par-
ticular, of works of art—and he is interested in the objective character of
such beauty (VA 1:67/A 1:44).
It has been said that Hegel’s aesthetic theory marks a “turn from a
formal aesthetics to one of content.”22 This is true insofar as Hegel claims
xvii
INTRODUCTION
that beauty requires the content of art to be the “divine” (whether envis-
aged in the form of the Greek gods or of Christ), to be human freedom,
liveliness, and spirit, or to be aspects of nature, such as landscapes and
animals, in which we see something of our own freedom and vitality re-
flected. Beauty, however, is not just a matter of content: it is the appropri-
ate content expressed in the appropriate sensuous form. Hegel is thus
every bit as engaged as the aesthetic formalist by the formal features of an
artwork, especially in the more obviously “formal” arts of architecture and
music but also in sculpture, painting, and poetry. (Hence his interest in
the shape of the most beautiful profile in sculpture or in the beauty cre-
ated by the play of colors in painting.)23
The important thing, for Hegel, is that beauty is not just in the eye
(or taste or judgment) of the beholder, but in the object itself—in its own
content and form. This means that our taste need not always coincide with
objective beauty. Many beautiful works of art may speak to us directly. We
may need to learn to appreciate others, however, by discovering more
about the historical context in which they were produced (VA 1:30/
A 1:14). In the case of the sculptures of fifth-century Greece—works that
for Hegel are objectively the most beautiful and “ideal”—some in moder-
nity may find it impossible to take unalloyed delight in their beauty be-
cause they lack the inner depth of character and emotion that we have
come to expect of a work of art.24 Of course, if taste and beauty can diverge
in this way, it is possible that human beings could lose the taste for beauty
altogether (as they could lose interest in religion). But to do so, if we are
to believe Hegel, would be like losing our taste for the very food that sus-
tains and nourishes us. It would not constitute any “liberation” or “eman-
cipation” of art or of human beings.
Hegel notes that not every conception of the divine and the human is ca-
pable of giving rise to beauty. This is because only certain conceptions of
the divine and the human can be given clear sensuous expression in art.
To be capable of such expression, Hegel argues, divine reason and human
freedom must themselves be conceived as taking the shape of concrete,
embodied individuality (VA 1:104/A 1:73). If the divine is conceived too ab-
stractly as “simply one, the supreme being as such” (as Hegel thinks occurs
in Judaism and Islam [VA 1:101/A 1:70]), art will not be able to present it
in the form of visible individuals and thereby bring it directly before our
eyes and minds. Art will thus be “sublime” (erhaben) rather than beautiful,
xviii
INTRODUCTION
since it will point beyond itself to a God who remains invisible: “The inner
does not appear in it but so transcends it that nothing comes into the
representation except as this transcendence and transcending” (VA 1:479/
A 1:372).
Hegel includes sublime art under the general category of “symbolic”
art. The quintessential symbolic art, he tells us, was created by the ancient
Egyptians. Unlike the Jews, the Egyptians conceived of the divine as dif-
ferentiated into individual gods. Yet these gods were shadowy figures as-
sociated with death and mystery and so remained elusive. Consequently,
for the Egyptians, “the individual shape, as this individual animal, or this
human personification, or event, or action, cannot bring before contem-
plation an immediate adequate existence of the Absolute” (VA 1:451/
A 1:349). The visible images of the gods in Egyptian art thus do no more
than symbolize gods who can never come fully into view. Since such sym-
bolic art is not the clear sensuous manifestation of the divine, it lacks gen-
uine beauty just as sublime art does.
Hegel’s aesthetic theory will no doubt be regarded by many as nar-
rowly “Eurocentric,” since it clearly gives pride of place to the art and
poetry of Greece, Italy, England, the Netherlands, and Germany. In fact,
however, Hegel was one of the first to acknowledge and appreciate the art
of non-European cultures, such as India and Egypt. He draws special
attention to the fact that the “abandonment and distortion of natural for-
mations” found in such art stems not from “unintentional lack of techni-
cal skill or practice, but intentional alteration which proceeds from and is
demanded by what is in the artist’s mind” (VA 1:106/A 1:74). Neverthe-
less, Hegel argues that symbolic art clearly falls short of objective beauty.
This, in his view, is because the underlying conception of the divine is still
too indeterminate or abstract: the divine is not understood to be fully
incarnated in the concrete gestures, expressions, and actions of individu-
als. “The Chinese, Indians, and Egyptians,” he argues, “in their artistic
shapes, images of gods, and idols, never get beyond formlessness or a bad
and untrue definiteness of form.” He continues: “They could not master
true beauty because their mythological ideas, the content and thought of
their works of art, were still indeterminate, or determined badly, and so
did not consist of the content which is absolute in itself” (VA 1:105/A 1:74).
Hegel’s aesthetic objection to symbolic art is thus based on a more funda-
mental religious objection.
Hegel goes on to note that “works of art are all the more excellent
in expressing true beauty, the deeper is the inner truth of their content
and thought.” That deeper truth, he claims, is first to be found in the
religion and art of the ancient Greeks. The Greek gods, for Hegel, are
neither abstract nor mysterious and elusive, but are concrete, self-
xix
INTRODUCTION
when art was the servant of religion and mythology. Such art was not
merely decorative or entertaining but gave expression to “the Divine, the
deepest interests of mankind, and the most comprehensive truths of
the spirit” (VA 1:21/A 1:7). In so doing it fulfilled what Hegel regarded as
the highest vocation of which art is capable: for art cannot be any more im-
portant in our lives than when it brings directly before our minds the reli-
gious (and associated ethical) principles and values that we hold most dear.
In contrast to Greek polytheism, Christianity conceives of the divine
as pure “spirit,” as the single, invisible God whose Holy Spirit inwardly an-
imates and transforms believers and through such believers is at work in
history. This God, according to Hegel, does not need to be given aesthetic
expression in order to become determinate and intelligible for us, but can
be fully comprehended within religious feeling and faith (VA 1:112–13/
A 1:80). Christianity is thus independent of art in a way that Greek reli-
gion is not. Yet Christianity also holds that God’s love is incarnated and
made visible to believers in the life and death of Christ (and of the Virgin
Mary and the other saints). Christian love and spirituality thus remain
capable of being given sensuous, visible expression in art.
In Greek art—in particular, sculpture—spiritual freedom is wholly
immersed in and identical with visible bodily shape. In Christian or “ro-
mantic” art, by contrast, what must be presented in the sensuous medium
of stone, color, or language is a spirituality that has withdrawn from the
externality of the body into the profound inwardness of love. Romantic
beauty will thus take the form not just of idealized bodily shape as such
but of harmonious human form that is clearly suffused with inner feeling
and love. Such beauty is not pure beauty, but the “beauty of inwardness
[Schönheit der Innigkeit]” (VA 2:144/A 1:531). It is found supremely in the
painted images of the Virgin and Child and of Christ and his disciples
created by artists such as Jan van Eyck, Raphael, and Correggio. In the
“golden age of the later Middle Ages” (VA 1:24/A 1:10) and in the Re-
naissance, art thus continues to give expression to the divine and to “the
most comprehensive truths of the spirit,” and so continues to fulfill its
highest vocation.
With the Reformation the relation between art and religion alters
and the possibilities for art itself change. The defining characteristic of
the Reformation for Hegel is that divine love is understood to be fully
present only within faith. The implications for art are clear: for if God is
fully present only within the inwardness of faith, he cannot be regarded
as fully present in the human artifacts we see before us. As Hegel puts it,
“to the Lutherans truth is not a made object.”25 Through the Reformation,
“religious ideas were [thus] drawn away from their wrapping in the ele-
ment of sense and brought back to the inwardness of heart and thinking”
(VA 1:142/A 1:103). This does not mean that Protestantism abandons all
xxi
INTRODUCTION
from Greek and medieval art as did their original audiences: “No matter
how excellent we find the statues of the Greek gods, no matter how we see
God the Father, Christ, and Mary so estimably and perfectly portrayed, it
is no help: we bow the knee no longer [before these artistic portrayals]”
(VA 1:142/A 1:103). This does not prevent us from appreciating the beauty
of those older works of art: we can still see in them the magnificent and
moving sensuous expression of human freedom or of Christian love. We
(modern Protestants) do not, however, look upon those works with true
religious veneration and worship the divine in them, because we know
that they are “only” works of art and that divine freedom and love are truly
present in faith alone.
Hegel is sometimes said to have claimed that art comes to an end or “dies”
in the modern world.27 In fact, however, he never makes any such claim.
He declares that the modern world witnesses the end or “dissolution” of
the romantic form of art, and he notes that the epic has died out to be re-
placed by the novel and the short story.28 He also proclaims, as we have
just seen, that art for us is no longer able to fulfill its highest—that is,
aesthetico-religious—vocation. Nowhere, however, does he say that art as
such comes to an end. On the contrary, he insists that art remains a fun-
damental (though not the supreme) need in the modern world and will
always continue to do so. Indeed, he expresses the “hope that art will al-
ways rise higher and come to perfection” (VA 1:142/A 1:103). For Hegel,
then, art clearly had a future. This future—which in Hegel’s own time was
already becoming a reality—would be one in which artists are no longer
restricted to a particular style or content but can draw freely on all styles,
from the classical, romantic, or even symbolic art forms, to present what
engages their interest:
The Essays
Notes
volumes 13, 14, and 15 of G. W. F. Hegel, Werke in zwanzig Bänden, ed. E. Molden-
hauer and K. M. Michel, 20 vols. [Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1969–70]).
9. See G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesung über Ästhetik: Berlin 1820/21, ed. H. Schneider
(Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 1995); G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen über die Philoso-
phie der Kunst (1823), ed. A. Gethmann-Siefert (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 2003);
G. W. F. Hegel, Philosophie der Kunst (1826), ed. A. Gethmann-Siefert, J. I. Kwon,
and K. Berr (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2004); and G. W. F. Hegel, Philoso-
phie der Kunst oder Ästhetik (1826), ed. A. Gethmann-Siefert and B. Collenberg-
Plotnikov (Munich: Wilhelm Fink, 2004).
10. B. Wyss, Hegel’s Art History and the Critique of Modernity (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1999), 106.
11. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, 334.
12. K. Hammermeister, The German Aesthetic Tradition (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 2002), 21, 24.
13. O. Pöggeler, ed., Hegel in Berlin: Preussische Kulturpolitik und idealistische
Ästhetik: Zum 150. Todestag des Philosophen (Berlin: Staatsbibliothek Preussischer
Kulturbesitz, 1981), 247.
14. Hegel in Berlin, 87–88, 91.
15. See G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel: The Letters, trans. C. Butler and C. Seiler (Bloom-
ington: Indiana University Press, 1984), 654; and S. Houlgate, “Hegel and the Art
of Painting,” in Hegel and Aesthetics, 62, 77–78.
16. G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of
the Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon, 1970), 11
(section 246 Addition).
17. G. W. F. Hegel, Introduction to the Lectures on the History of Philosophy, trans.
T. M. Knox and A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon, 1985), 133.
18. G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of World History: Introduction: Rea-
son in History, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975),
105, 108.
19. F. Schiller, “Kallias, or Concerning Beauty: Letters to Gottfried Körner”
(1793), in Classical and Romantic German Aesthetics, ed. J. M. Bernstein (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2003), 160 (February 23, 1793). Schiller’s phrase neatly
encapsulates Hegel’s conception of beauty. Strictly speaking, however, Schiller’s
conception of beauty in the “Kallias” letters is somewhat different from that of
Hegel. For Schiller, beauty is sensible form that is merely analogous to freedom,
that merely appears to be free, whereas for Hegel beauty is the sensuous expression
or manifestation of freedom itself.
20. See A. Julius, Transgressions: The Offences of Art (London: Thames and
Hudson, 2002), 102.
21. I. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. P. Guyer and E. Matthews
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 103 (section 9).
22. Hammermeister, German Aesthetic Tradition, 88. See also Hegel, VA 1:28/
A 1:13.
23. Hegel, VA 2:228, 383–96/A 1:599–600, 2:727–38.
24. Hegel, VA 2:86, 92/A 1:485, 490. On the relativity of personal and national
taste in art, see Hegel, VA 1:68/A 1:44–45.
xxviii
INTRODUCTION
25. G. W. F. Hegel, The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree (New York: Dover,
1956), 416 (translation altered).
26. Hegel, VA 2:159, 3:211, 459/A 1:542–43, 2:949–50, 1145. Even after the
Reformation, of course, Catholic religious art also continues to be produced (for
example, by Rubens).
27. See S. Houlgate, “Hegel and the ‘End’ of Art,” Owl of Minerva 29, no. 1
(fall 1997): 1.
28. Hegel, VA 2:220, 231, 3:415, 457/A 1:593, 602, 2:1110, 1143.
29. Hegel, VA 2:237/A 1:607. See J. W. Goethe, “Die Geheimnisse,” in Goethe’s
Gedichte, ed. F. Strehlke, 2 vols. (Berlin: F. Dümmler, 1887), 2:48 (line 245: “Hu-
manus heisst der Heilige, der Weise”).
30. Hegel, VA 2:238/A 1:607. Later in the lectures on aesthetics, Hegel also
adds that art should never lack “reconciliation”; see Hegel, VA 3:494/A 2:1173.
31. See Houlgate, “Hegel and the ‘End’ of Art,” 15–19; and “Hegel and the
Art of Painting,” 71–75.
HEGEL AND THE ARTS
Symbolic, Classical, and
Romantic Art
Terry Pinkard
3
4
TERRY PINKARD
present “the divine,” the truth (and sometimes the “genuinely true,” or
perhaps “the real,” both of which are connoted by Hegel’s use of the term
das Wahrhaftige), the “deepest” and “highest” interests of mankind, the
“most comprehensive truths of spirit,” our “highest needs,” mankind’s
“true interests,” and so forth.4 Likewise, Hegel is often portrayed as hav-
ing proclaimed the “end of art” in the third, romantic form of art. Finally,
Hegel claims that art (like philosophy and Christian religion) seeks to of-
fer us a kind of “reconciliation” in its intimations that it can heal a kind
of self-inflicted alienation of Geist, spirit, from itself, or at least to point to
the way that religion and philosophy, if not art itself, can perform that
healing function.
It is hard enough to sort out these claims (and from the standpoint
of modern philology, to see which of them Hegel actually entertained),
and it is equally difficult to come to some sort of evaluation of what is
really being claimed. Hegel’s own statements about Geist bring out the very
basic tension already at work in his theory. Over and over again, he tells
us that Geist makes itself, gives itself its reality, that it is only what it makes
of itself, and so forth; yet if there were no Geist already there, as it were,
how could it “give itself” reality or be a product of itself? Hegel’s own state-
ment to this effect near the beginning of his lectures on aesthetics brings
out this puzzling feature:
The universal and absolute need from which art . . . springs has its origin
in the fact that man is a thinking consciousness, i.e., that man makes out
of himself for-himself what he is and what in general is. Things in nature
are only immediate and single, while man as spirit duplicates himself, in
that he exists in the way the things of nature exist, but he is to the same
extent for-himself; he intuits himself, represents himself to himself,
thinks, and only by means of this active being-for-self is he spirit.5
The typical Hegelian points of emphasis are all in play here, partic-
ularly the emphasis on the agent’s self-relation—his “being-for-self”—as
crucial to his agency. An agent is a “thing in nature” that is “immediate
and single,” that is, an organism making its way around in its environment.
An agent is also a self-conscious life whose nature as an agent is constituted
by his self-relation, by how he “takes” himself to be; or to put it another
way, as agents humans are, in Charles Taylor’s phrase, “self-interpreting
animals.” To have such a self-relation as “subjectivity” is to be Geist, or, as
we say now, to be an agent. Who we are as agents therefore depends on our
sustaining a certain interpretation of ourselves over time. Animals, as
Hegel says, live in peace with their surroundings in that no matter how
intelligent or complexly social they may be, who they are is not an issue for
5
SYMBOLIC, CLASSICAL, AND ROMANTIC ART
keeping faith with the law because of certain types of contradiction or ten-
sion in that conception of law. In fact, it is part and parcel of such an ac-
count that a type of agency could be said to fail—in that it cannot achieve
what it is seeking to achieve—even though the agents themselves are un-
aware of their failure and are perhaps even happy (although nonetheless
ignorant of their failure) while being in that state.
Speculative Problems
Clearly much is packed into such a conception, and it is perhaps not sur-
prising that Hegel’s attempts to work that idea out in all its proper quali-
fications and with all the arguments necessary to sustain such a view
amount to one of the largest and densest sets of works in the history of phi-
losophy. Part of the density is powered by Hegel’s own insistence on a
“speculative” approach to these issues that supposedly avoids the dilem-
mas contained within more “one-sided” comprehensive accounts offered
by what he always called the “understanding.” The idea of such a “specu-
lative” approach rests on Hegel’s generalization of a certain “Kantian
paradox” into a more inclusive conception of normative authority.8 The
problem arises first in Kant’s practical philosophy, where he argues that
norms cannot be practically and unconditionally binding on us unless we
can regard ourselves as having instituted those norms themselves. In the
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant says: “The will is therefore
not merely subject to the law, but is so subject that it must be considered
as also giving the law to itself and precisely on this account as first of all sub-
ject to the law (which it can regard itself as instituting).”9 Indeed, as is well
known, Kant attributes the failure of all prior moral philosophy to a fail-
ure to recognize this truth.10
However, as Kant came to see when he was writing the Critique of
Practical Reason, that conception landed him in a paradoxical situation
which resulted from two commitments on his part: first, that an arbitrary
will (Willkür) could not obligate us, since only a principled, rational will
could actually bind us to its requirements; and second, that only a self-
legislated principle (or “law”) could obligate us. The paradox arises out of
the realization that prior to such self-legislation, we would have no
principles, hence we would have only “arbitrary” (willkürlich) wills whose
legislation could not therefore bind us; but if we had some rational prin-
ciple in place prior to such legislation, then since it was not itself self-
legislated, we could also not be bound by it.
In the Critique of Practical Reason Kant called this the “fact of reason,”
7
SYMBOLIC, CLASSICAL, AND ROMANTIC ART
How to sort through the issues that come up for this kind of dialectical,
speculative, and “phenomenological” aesthetic theory is difficult to state
in any economical way. The problem that Hegel sees art, religion, and phi-
losophy as trying to come to terms with is that of comprehending what it
would be to express freedom in the natural, material world (and, as part
of his developmental story, in the modern developed social world of com-
plex market economies and state bureaucracies). What drives Hegel’s
type of developmental story is a self-incurred dissatisfaction with the types
of agency constituted by collective attempts at living out particular kinds
of self-conception (in his own language, by particular shapes and con-
cretizations of the Idea). Art, like religion and philosophy, is a collective
practice of self-education about this, a way of collectively reflecting on
what it means to be human.
9
SYMBOLIC, CLASSICAL, AND ROMANTIC ART
The idea that art “strives for truth” is linked with its being the Idea
in its “sensuous showing-forth.” For Hegel, truth is neither a relation of co-
herence among concepts nor is it primarily a correspondence between
representations and things external to them, and it is also not equivalent
to “warranted assertibility.” For Hegel, truth functions as a kind of “prim-
itive” which cannot be defined in terms of anything more fundamental
than itself but which nonetheless is capable of a full unfolding (an Ent-
faltung) within the proper kind of reflective activity (such as Hegel’s
own Phenomenology or Logic). Hegel’s initially puzzling statements about
truth—that truth does not have to do with the concept’s corresponding
to the object but with the object’s corresponding to the concept—is his
own provocative way of phrasing his view about normativity in general;
namely that, to use Robert Brandom’s phrase, the difference between the
normative and the nonnormative (or factual) is itself a normative dis-
tinction, a matter of how we ought to treat things, and that what seems
like the inevitable choice between correspondence, coherence, and war-
ranted assertibility conceptions of truth is itself only motivated by the ul-
timately untenable view of there being some kind of metaphysical line
that separates mind and world.16 In Hegel’s view, our concepts of ourselves
and the world embody an “ought,” a conception of what it would mean for
something to be the best exemplification of what it is. Although at the same
time both Aristotelian and Kantian in inspiration (like so many of Hegel’s
views), this view eschews any teleological conception of nature. For “we
moderns” nature is meaningless, dedivinized, devoid of spirit (geistlos, as
Hegel calls it); there is no better and worse in it.17 Indeed, that is the prob-
lem with nature; properly explained by the means of modern natural
science, nature displays itself to reflection as simply incapable on its
own of organizing itself into “better exemplifications.” (Hegel calls this
the “impotence [Ohnmacht] of nature.”)18 It is only when life appears in
nature that it makes sense to speak of “better” and “worse,” since only or-
ganisms display the kind of self-directing, functional teleological struc-
ture that makes the application of such terms meaningful. This is made
clearer when one reflects on the application of the concept of disease; it
makes sense to speak of an organism as diseased when it is in some kind
of state that is incompatible with its being the best exemplification of its
sort that it can be (when it is prevented from achieving goals proper to the
internal teleology of that organism); but it makes no sense to speak of a
diseased planetary system, a diseased mountain range, and so on. Al-
though life displays the kind of structure that makes the range of terms
having to do with “better” and “worse” applicable, as “life” nature is none-
theless still incapable of reflecting on that structure or of bringing it
about as a goal; even at the stage of life, nature is still “impotent.” When
11
SYMBOLIC, CLASSICAL, AND ROMANTIC ART
we arrive at human beings, though, this changes, and the very idea of the
“best” human life ceases to be fixed by nature itself and comes to be com-
prehended, in Hegel’s very complex phenomenology of our own mind-
edness, by the history of our collective self-conceptions; a history grasped
in terms of how the very determinate failures of earlier self-conceptions
have led, unavoidably, to the modern self-conception not only as required
by those failures but also as having “revealed” itself as the truth.
As striving for such truth, art is always committing itself to display
what Hegel (using the terms of his day) calls the “Ideal,” that is, “the truly
concrete Idea [that] produces its true configuration [Gestalt ].”19 To say
therefore that art strives after the “Ideal” is, to put it more prosaically, to
say that it strives for a kind of embodied norm, a kind of singular sensuous
presentation in the form of beauty of what it means to be a “minded,”
geistig, spiritual agent in its most exemplary form.20 Art does not seek to
formulate universal principles (as philosophy does) but rather to display
such norms in singular works of beauty. Since art seeks to display what it
means to be “minded,” Hegel dismisses the idea that natural beauty has
any real significance for us however much “attraction” it may otherwise
have. Beauty has a meaning for us to the extent that it “shows” us some-
thing about what it means to be human; natural beauty therefore can
show us little about this, except only insofar as we can be brought to see
various natural forms as intimating our own lives or offering some fore-
shadowing of them. Thus, from the standpoint of art, certain natural
organic forms (particularly those of animals) may display to us what it is
like, for example, to be self-moving, to be seeking one’s and one’s group’s
good, or perhaps to reveal some very general and very abstract truth about
our finite, material embodiment (such as the brevity of the flower’s life
showing us something about the contingency and brevity of our own
lives—a very abstract truth indeed).
Since the Ideal is that which shows us in aesthetic form what it would
mean to exemplify humanity in a particular way, art displays the Ideal as
a unity of universal and particular, that is, the way in which the demands
of the “law” on humans are carried out by particular humans in a natural
and social world in such a way that their actions are “their own,” reflective
of them as individuals. Part of Hegel’s remarkable claim about art is that
only Greek art can manifest the Ideal in this sense, and that all modern
art necessarily falls short of the Ideal—that the “Ideal” is fundamentally
unsatisfactory for us as real flesh-and-blood humans and that the self-
incurred dissatisfaction with the “Ideal” pushes us on to a mode of art that
is, peculiarly, less like art the more modern it becomes.
This helps to understand just why Hegel would insist on the initially
implausible claim that there are only three art forms that develop out of
12
TERRY PINKARD
each other and succeed each other historically. The meaning of agency as
self-determining is itself a historical achievement, not a metaphysical or
empirical fact about us. The historical origins of this self-conception be-
gin with our simply finding ourselves already oriented to some kind of
“whole” of which we are parts and which we take to be the “origin” of our
humanity and which thereby sustains us. Thought about this “whole” is
thus always mythical at its outset; it seeks to give an account and reassur-
ance of what might otherwise look like a purely self-bootstrapping ap-
pearance of agency, in terms of some kind of mythic origin of humanity
(of mythic origins of freedom, language, or of this or that way of life). We
begin reflection on what it means to be human by finding ourselves to be
a mystery to ourselves, and in their origins, therefore, both art and reli-
gion are mixed together in the way each offers a mythic origin for human
freedom. Art is therefore at first “symbolic” art in which the space of
reasons in terms of which we justify ourselves to each other remains rela-
tively abstract (that is, the Idea is only abstractly worked out).21 Symbols,
in this Hegelian sense, “hint at” something else that the symbol itself can-
not quite fully express, and what is being hinted at is the mythically con-
ceived origin of human freedom, the divine “whole” that brings about the
existence and sustains the continued lives of the “minded” creatures we
are. Since this origin remains a “mystery,” symbolic art is necessarily ab-
stract, sometimes possessing great technical beauty, but always hinting at
more than it can actually express, and it thus tends to be an art of the sub-
lime; that is, of seeking natural phenomena that serve to remind us of
our own mindedness. And from being an art of the sublime, symbolic art
tends to become the art of pantheism, of the attempt to say the unsayable
and represent the unrepresentable, as it seeks to show the unitary divine
substance that is the one in everything.
For Hegel’s overall narrative to work, symbolic art—the art of the
ancient Egyptians, Persians, Hindus, and Jews—must be unsatisfying not
because it makes us unhappy in any sense but because the pictures of
being human which it offers cannot sustain themselves. The appeal to the
“unsayable” and the “unrepresentable” (or even to the “sublime”) is itself
so abstract that the content (what is being said) and the form, the mode
of “saying it” (through parables, poems, sculptures, or anything else),
connect with each other in only fairly arbitrary ways. Hegel often ex-
presses this as its lacking some kind of proper fit between an inner, sub-
jective sense of things and an outer, material expression of that interior-
ity; his point, though, is that symbolic art incurs a dissatisfaction with
itself, since it cannot give us the kind of comprehension of the “Idea” we
are seeking in art. The problem with symbolic art lies, in Hegel’s terms, in
its “finitude,” its conception of the intelligibility of our meaning-giving
13
SYMBOLIC, CLASSICAL, AND ROMANTIC ART
unity of universality and particularity. In its ideal form, the free agent
relies on himself alone, is the law unto himself, and is thus in “repose”
(Ruhe).25 This “Ideal,” of course, is expressed paradigmatically by the
Greek gods (as given human form) and then derivatively by mythical
“heroes” (who have some type of connection to divinity), and it offers the
“classical” meaning of freedom as a form of “self-sufficiency.” To be
human is thus taken to be (ideally) self-sufficient, which in turn is taken
to consist of a kind of self-containment.26 (One thinks, of course, of Aris-
totle’s notion of human flourishing as involving “self-sufficiency,” such
that a life of eudaimonia, “flourishing,” would be lacking in nothing, as the
most dialectically sophisticated and final expression of that Greek ideal.)
The deficiency of classical art has to do with the problems contained
in such self-sufficiency, and Hegel’s arguments for this are laid out in the
section of the Phenomenology of Spirit on “Freedom and Self-Sufficiency”
(Selbständigkeit) from which the dialectic of mastery and servitude results.
Such self-sufficiency cannot survive its confrontation with other putatively
self-sufficient agents—unless the agents in question are gods. Hegel
thought that such a “classical” conception of freedom as “repose” and self-
sufficiency was best expressed in sculpture, since the statue in particular
expresses aesthetically what it means to be in such “repose,” to be self-
contained, in that way.
The problem for Greek life (and thus for classical art) is whether
such a meaning of freedom can be lived out for humans, not just for their
gods, and, at an even deeper level, whether such an aesthetic version of
the meaning of freedom can be sustained even for the gods themselves.
The Greek gods are only projections, Hegel argues, of our own need for
an exhibition, a Darstellung, of what a distinctively free human life would
be, and although for the Greeks the gods seemed to be more alive than
even the humans who worshipped them, they turned out to be only stone
idols, lacking any effective reality.27 In an evocative passage, Hegel notes
that those statues of the gods seem to have a kind of mourning to them,
as if they already had some intimation of their fate.28 It is thus not sur-
prising that Hegel thought that such a view of what life might be like at its
highest could only be sustained with a view of nature that saw it as teleo-
logically structured and fundamentally in harmony with human desires
and needs. (Such a view seems to be front and center in a large part of
Aristotle’s writings—or at least a view that nature is neither intrinsically
hostile nor simply indifferent to human needs and desires, even if from
time to time bad fortune may befall an otherwise good, self-sufficient per-
son, whose virtue will nonetheless enable him to bear up under those cir-
cumstances and to realize that his life is nonetheless a good one.) For
actual individuals, the problems with such an aesthetic presentation of
16
TERRY PINKARD
doing and what I really did and a shift therefore in the conception of that
to which I can be held responsible—opens up in a way that is both re-
quired in Greek life (and classical art) and impossible to sustain within it.
In Hegel’s telling, the origins of Greek civilization are aesthetic, not
doctrinal; Homer and Hesiod are its founders. As it develops itself, its
conception of the whole (the Greek “Idea”), originally formulated aes-
thetically, becomes more philosophical, and as it does, the strains within
this originally aesthetic “Idea” begin to reveal themselves more clearly to
the participants in that form of life. As the intelligibility of that form of life
begins to dissolve under those pressures, it becomes clear that the transi-
tion from the dissolution of classical art to that of modern, “romantic” art
cannot therefore be itself made aesthetically. As it were, telling new and
more beautiful stories about the gods and heroes simply cannot overcome
the experienced dissatisfaction with the ancient way of life, at least as that
dissatisfaction was lived through by generations of people. Whereas the
Greeks were able to tell themselves a mythical, aesthetically satisfying story
about how their gods triumphed over the titans (and thus told themselves
an aesthetically satisfying story about what it might mean to achieve a lib-
eration from the purely natural—so that the Greeks gave themselves their
gods in a purely aesthetic manner), no such purely aesthetic story, no new
mythic tales of a “war of the gods,” can resolve the problems inherent in
Greek life itself. Hegel’s thesis is thus fairly stark: what it means for a finite,
embodied human to be free cannot be given an adequate aesthetic pres-
entation; and art, as attempting to provide a reflection on what it means
to be human, necessarily fails in its task and this failure is expressed within
art itself, not through an external reflection on art.
The internal failure of classical art on its own terms historically sig-
naled a profound shift in the meaning and social status of art itself. Hav-
ing come to a self-consciousness about itself as incapable of adequately
embodying the “Ideal,” art subordinated itself to something “beyond” it-
self, something that, metaphorically speaking, sits on the other side of the
supposed metaphysical line dividing the artistic consciousness from the
truth; namely, Christian religion, in which the inwardness and subjectiv-
ity that the failure of classical civilization itself provoked comes into its
own as a claim about the truth about humanity.
Romantic art thus begins with the conviction that what we mean by our
actions is not completely disclosed by what we do and that there is there-
fore an “inwardness” which must be discovered or uncovered if we are to
19
SYMBOLIC, CLASSICAL, AND ROMANTIC ART
find out who we really are. Hegel’s more or less phenomenological treat-
ment of the development of romantic art rests on his view, not so much ar-
gued in the lectures on aesthetics as simply put into play there, that reli-
gion goes through a kind of dissolution similar to art’s own dissolution.
Christian religion “reveals” the meaning of humanity to be “infinite sub-
jectivity,” self-determining freedom, which itself can only be given what
Hegel calls a “representational” (relying on the term Vorstellung) treat-
ment; the mythical lawgiver at the origin of freedom is God-become-man,
who therefore mythically moves over from one side of the metaphysical
line separating consciousness from the true (what exists in-itself) and puts
himself into human form, revealing to us in the world that our “vocation”
is freedom. Christian religion, however, still remains metaphysical in that
God is represented as both immanent and transcendent at the same time;
we achieve the truth of the matter only, first, in the philosophical com-
prehension of what religion is about (itself provoked by Christian reli-
gion’s recognition that it requires a theology, which in turn provokes the
development of a modern, independent philosophy) and, second, in the
philosophical comprehension that the picture of a metaphysical line sep-
arating mind and world (or consciousness and the in-itself) itself dissolves
under the pressures it puts on itself, leaving us finally with a not only post-
Cartesian but also post-Kantian picture of ourselves as fully capable of
grasping what is in-itself—in short, capable of grasping the truth of the
world before us.
Thus romantic art begins as religious art, as the aesthetic exhibition
of religious (and eventually theological) truths; but its own dynamic
drives it to develop out of itself a conception of the truth of humanity as
individuality, as each person having a rich inner life, an “infinite subjec-
tivity” that eventually detaches itself from its religious origins and comes
to be concerned with itself in its prosaic, mundane world. Romantic art
thus becomes fully modern art—secular, fractured, in which “man wants
to see the present itself as it is—even at the cost of sacrificing beauty and
ideality of content and appearance—as a live presence recreated by art, as
his own human and spiritual work.”32
Thus, modern art is driven to a different sense of the dramatic from
that of the classical. In modern, “romantic” (and especially post-Christian)
dramatic art, the characters are not so much stating a pathos that they em-
body and then firmly setting out on their paths (as they do in classical art),
but rather are engaged in a kind of social dance in which they not only
worry about what they in fact feel, but also worry if what they feel is real,
worry about how they should feel, and constantly offer explanations to
each other about all these things in an effort to determine what it is that
is going on “within” themselves. (So many modern dramas involve lovers
who don’t know at first that they are in love, or who deny that they are, or
20
TERRY PINKARD
who are tricked into recognizing that they are, or who believe that they
love one person when they really love another, and so on. Hegel even
makes a quip about those moderns who “do not suppose themselves to ac-
tually be in love until they encounter in and around themselves the very
same feelings and situations [as those described in the romances].”)33
Although modern art at first understands itself as having cut itself
free from the limits set by religion, it soon discovers within its own devel-
opment the impossibility of a fully aesthetic comprehension of the “infi-
nite subjectivity” opened by Christianity. Shakespeare’s success at portray-
ing this, Hegel thinks, is only partial, and he accomplishes what he does
only by placing his ideal figures in civil wars, where their “self-sufficiency”
can be made plausible in modern terms. Goethe and Schiller, Hegel also
notes, attempted the same thing but were much less successful.34 Indeed,
the lack of such ideal heroes in modern, prosaic life is not something to
be lamented: “It would be inappropriate,” Hegel notes, “to set up, for our
time too, ideal figures, e.g., of judges or monarchs,” since such figures
would in fact be direct attacks on the hard-fought and still fragile achieve-
ments of the rule of law and the constitutional order.35 (One wonders what
Hegel would have made of the contemporary American “Western” film,
with its heroic lone cowboys bringing justice to town, or John Ford’s ironic
deconstructions of that myth.)
Romantic art as modern art thus loses its “vocation” as art for us, for
although it remains crucial and irreplaceable in human experience, it
cannot satisfy us on its own since it seeks something—namely, a compre-
hensive aesthetic exhibition of the meaning of freedom—that it cannot
in principle provide. This is hardly the “end of art,” at least in any sense of
finality—as if no new artworks would be created, art would become unim-
portant, or there could be no innovation in art. In an often-quoted and
memorable passage, Hegel says:
descent into his own breast, whereby art strips away from itself all fixed
restriction to a specific range of content and treatment, and makes Hu-
manus its new holy of holies.”37 In making these two claims together, it is
clear that Hegel is shifting the meaning of “divine” from its normal usage
and redescribing it in terms of his view of the absolute as Geist, as self-
determination, as mankind’s “true” or “highest interests.” What is “divine”
in humans is exhibited or “shown” aesthetically in art, is represented
mythically in religion, and is only conceptually comprehended in thought
(that is, philosophy).38 Hegel’s bluntness about the role of religion in this
collective endeavor is quite striking: the proper understanding of free-
dom as self-determination is philosophical and conceptual, not “repre-
sentational” or mythical, as it must be for religion. Whereas art seeks to
locate the origin of freedom in aesthetically complete individuals (who
simply embody the right, or the “universal,” and the particular as unified
in themselves), and religion seeks to locate the origin of freedom in some
kind of relation to an external divinity or a revelation of some sort, the
conceptual approach to freedom seeks to understand it as a “speculative
truth” (the Kantian paradox), in which our own individual and collective
practices of self-determination are to be comprehended as social and his-
torical achievements, not as metaphysical structures. The inadequacy of art
to capture this self-understanding for us is, paradoxically, not the meta-
physical inadequacy of art itself to get at a deeper truth, but a change in
the status of “we moderns” who find it inadequate to ourselves as we have
come to be.
However, making Humanus the new “holy of holies” effectively frees
art from all particular content, since what is at stake now are the lives of
individuals, with their own passions, loves, ends, and accidental circum-
stances surrounding them.39 This itself puts into motion the dissolution
of modern art, which itself then becomes the topic of modern art, so that
“it is the effect and the progress of art itself which . . . at every step along
this road makes its own contribution to freeing art from the content rep-
resented.”40 The progress of art therefore is toward increasing reflection,
incorporation of theory into itself, and, in short, to greater abstraction.41
Moreover, if what it means to be human is to be free, and freedom is to
be understood socially and historically, then there is no longer a meta-
physical secret to freedom or to the world, no basic enigma, that only art
can hint at or intimate; art therefore loses its power to say the unsayable
or represent the unrepresentable, since what was supposedly “unrepre-
sentable” has turned out to be conceptually comprehensible, namely, the
“Kantian paradox” as involving the sociality and historicity of agency and
reason. What it means to be human, Hegel says in his lectures on the phi-
losophy of religion, has been fully revealed: its origins do not lie on some
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
richement et mis sur le maistre autel de la dicte abbaie. Fos 234 vo et
235.
P. 224, l. 1: d’Armençon.—Mss. A 1 à 6, 18, 19: de Mouson. Fo 243
vo.
P. 224, l. 2: Tonnoire.—Mss. B 3, A 1 à 6, 8, 9: Tonnerre. Fo 232.—
Mss. A 18, 19: Tonneurre. Fo 251 vo.
P. 224, l. 5: plus de.—Mss. A 23 à 29: bien. Fo 256 vo.
P. 224, l. 5: trois mil.—Mss. A 20 à 22: trois cens. Fo 232.—Mss. A
30 à 33: bien trois cens. Fo 241.
Et li prince se desloga,
A chivacher se chimina,
Car celui jour ne quidoit pas
Combatre, je ne vous mente pas (v. 1268 à 1271).
Aussi, le héraut Chandos a bien soin de faire remarquer que ce fut l’arrière-
garde, placée sous les ordres du comte de Salisbury, qui eut à soutenir le
choc des maréchaux de France et de leurs 300 chevaliers d’élite et qui les mit
en déroute. Il ajoute que cette déconfiture eut lieu:
CHAPITRE LXXIX.
[44] Cf. Jean le Bel, Chroniques, t. II, p. 205 à 213.
[45] Ces sentiments se font jour dans une complainte en vers conservée au
deuxième registre capitulaire de Notre-Dame de Paris, commençant en
septembre 1356, finissant en janvier 1361 (Archives nationales, sect. hist.,
fonds de Notre-Dame, LL 209 A, fo 183). Entre les séances du 4 et du 7
octobre 1359 ont été transcrites plusieurs pièces plus anciennes et entre
autres la complainte dont nous parlons, relative à la bataille de Poitiers, qui
doit avoir été composée à la fin de 1356 ou au commencement de 1357 et qui
paraît être l’œuvre d’un chanoine ou d’un clerc de la cathédrale (voir dans la
Bibliothèque de l’École des Chartes 3e série, t. II, p. 257 à 263, un article de
M. Charles de Beaurepaire qui le premier a publié ce curieux document).
L’auteur de ce petit poëme attribue la déroute de l’armée française à la
trahison de la noblesse dont il flétrit énergiquement le luxe et les vices; il fait
des vœux pour la délivrance du roi Jean dont il célèbre la vaillance, et il
espère que le souverain, avec l’aide du peuple, désigné sous le sobriquet de
Jacques Bonhomme, parviendra à triompher de ses ennemis. V. un fac-simile
du document original dans le Musée des Archives nationales, Paris, 1872, in-
4o, p. 212 et 213.
[46] Dès leur première réunion à Paris le 17 octobre 1356, les États avaient
demandé: 1o la délivrance du roi de Navarre; 2o la destitution des principaux
membres du conseil du roi et du dauphin; 3o l’établissement d’un nouveau
conseil entièrement pris dans le sein des États eux-mêmes. Licenciés le 2
novembre suivant par le dauphin, puis rappelés le 5 février 1357, ils réclament
de nouveau, dans la séance du 3 mars, par l’organe de Robert le Coq, évêque
de Laon, en même temps que la destitution de vingt-deux hauts
fonctionnaires et la suspension de tous les officiers du royaume, la création
d’un grand conseil de réformateurs généraux nommés par les États qui
ordonneront souverainement de la guerre et des finances; dès le vendredi 10
mars, ils organisent ce grand conseil tiré de leur sein et qui concentre en ses
mains tous les pouvoirs. Ce conseil n’était pas composé de 36 membres,
comme le dit Froissart, mais seulement de 34 dont 11 appartenaient au
clergé, 6 à la noblesse et dont 17 représentaient la bourgeoisie. M. Douet
d’Arcq a publié leurs noms (Bibl. de l’École des Chartes, t. II, p. 382 et 383)
qui se trouvent au dos d’un rouleau conservé au dép. des mss. de la
Bibliothèque nationale. Par acte daté du Louvre lez Paris le 8 mars 1357 (n.
st.), Charles, lieutenant du roi, nomma réformateurs généraux par tout le
royaume ses amés les évêques de Nevers (Bertrand de Fumel), de Meaux
(Philippe de Vitry, le traducteur d’Ovide, mort en juin 1361), et de Thérouanne
(Gilles Aycelin de Montagu), maître Jean de Gonnelieu, doyen de Cambrai,
maître Robert de Corbie; messire Mahieu, sire de Moucy, messire Jean de
Conflans, maréchal de Champagne, chevaliers; Colard le Caucheteur,
bourgeois d’Abbeville, Jean Godart, bourgeois de Paris (JJ89, no 150). Ces
réformateurs se contentèrent d’imposer aux fonctionnaires convaincus de
concussion des amendes pécuniaires (JJ89, nos 150, 319).
[47] Le combat où périt Godefroi de Harcourt eut lieu au mois de
novembre 1356. M. Delisle a établi le premier, d’après une chronique inédite
(Bibl. nat., mss., fonds français, no 4987, fo 61), que l’action, engagée sur la
chaussée qui traverse les marais de Brévands (Manche, arr. Saint-Lô, c.
Carentan, entre les embouchures de la Taute et de la Vire), en un lieu dit
Cocbour, se termina près des gués de Saint-Clément (Calvados, arr. Bayeux,
c. Isigny), non loin de l’endroit où Amauri de Meulan, lieutenant du dauphin
Charles en Normandie, avait été battu et fait prisonnier peu de temps
auparavant (JJ84, no 710). Le même savant a prouvé aussi que Robert de
Clermont et le Baudrain de la Heuse, maréchaux de Normandie, et non Raoul
de Renneval, commandaient les forces françaises. V. Delisle, Hist. du château
de Saint-Sauveur-le-Vicomte, p. 92 à 108; Preuves, p. 142 et 143.
[48] Godefroi de Harcourt n’avait pas vendu, il avait légué, le 18 juillet
1356, au roi d’Angleterre son immense fortune territoriale dont il avait juré de
frustrer son neveu Louis de Harcourt (Rymer, vol. III, p. 332). M. Delisle n’a
pas trouvé mention dans les actes de ce Jean de l’Isle, auquel Édouard aurait
confié, d’après Froissart, la garde du château de Saint-Sauveur; Pierre
Pigache remplissait ces fonctions dès le 7 février 1357. Ibid., p. 111.
[49] Le prince de Galles et le roi Jean s’embarquèrent le mardi 11 avril
1357 à Bordeaux, où une trêve avait été conclue entre la France et
l’Angleterre le 23 mars précédent; cette trêve devait durer deux ans (Rymer,
vol. III, p. 348 à 351). Nous avons un acte du roi Jean daté de Bordeaux le 25
mars 1357 (n. st.). JJ84, no 801.
[50] Le prince et son prisonnier débarquèrent en Angleterre le jeudi 4 mai
(Grandes Chroniques, t. VI, p. 58), probablement à Plymouth, selon la version
des chroniqueurs anglais, qui pourraient bien avoir raison contre Froissart; car,
dans l’ordre que le roi d’Angleterre expédia le 20 mars pour faire tout préparer
sur la route de son fils et du roi son prisonnier, il est dit qu’ils devaient arriver
à Plymouth (Rymer, vol. III, p. 348). Le mercredi 24 mai, ils firent leur entrée
dans Londres où il était accouru une si grande foule pour les voir passer que
le cortége, qui avait traversé à neuf heures du matin le pont de Londres,
arriva au palais de Westminster à midi seulement.
[51] Nous avons en effet plusieurs actes émanés du roi Jean pendant les
quatre premiers mois de son séjour en Angleterre, qui sont datés de Londres
en août (JJ86, no 416); l’un de ces actes fut passé dans cette ville le 11
septembre 1357 (JJ89, no 247). Un acte passé le 7 juillet 1358 en présence
du roi de France est daté du manoir de Savoie ès faubourgs de Londres
(Rymer, vol. III, p. 401 et 402). L’hôtel de Savoie, résidence de Henri duc de
Lancastre, était situé au sud du Strand, à côté de la rue qui a reçu dans ces
derniers temps le nom de Wellington-Street. Il ne reste de ce grand palais que
la chapelle, naguère reconstruite aux frais du gouvernement sur
l’emplacement de l’ancienne détruite par un incendie en 1864.
[52] On connaît un acte du roi Jean daté du château de Windsor en
octobre 1357 (JJ89, no 220).
[53] Il y a, comme l’a fait remarquer Dacier, trois erreurs capitales dans le
peu de mots que dit Froissart, concernant cette trêve: 1o elle fut conclue, non
en Angleterre, mais à Bordeaux, le 23 mars 1357, dix-neuf jours avant le
départ du prince de Galles et du roi Jean pour l’Angleterre; 2o elle devait durer
depuis le jour de Pâques (9 avril 1357) jusques à deux ans (21 avril 1359), et
non jusqu’à la Saint-Jean-Baptiste; 3o Philippe de Navarre et les héritiers du
comte de Montfort y étaient expressément compris; il convient d’ajouter
toutefois qu’ils ne voulurent en tenir aucun compte, et c’est ce qui a pu
induire Froissart en erreur sur ce dernier point.
[54] Ce traité fut signé à Berwick le 3 octobre 1357. Rymer, vol. III, p. 372
à 374.
[55] Henri, duc de Lancastre, n’ayant pu parvenir au commencement de
septembre 1356 à opérer sa jonction par les Ponts-de-Cé avec le prince de
Galles, mit le siége devant Rennes. Ce siége, qui suivit immédiatement le
désastre de Poitiers et qui dura neuf mois, du 2 octobre 1356 au 5 juillet
1357, est le pendant du siége de Calais après la défaite de Crécy; une si
longue et si honorable défense releva un peu les courages du côté des
vaincus. Charles de Blois, alors prisonnier sur parole du roi d’Angleterre, se
tint pendant toute la durée du siége à la cour du dauphin (Morice, Preuves, t.
1, col. 1513; JJ89, no 276; JJ85, no 115; JJ89, no 312). Le duc de Normandie
envoya, dès le mois de décembre 1356, Thibaud, sire de Rochefort, au
secours des assiégés (Morice, Preuves, t. 1, col. 1512 à 1514). En dépit de la
trêve conclue à Bordeaux le 23 mars 1357, Lancastre ne voulait pas lever le
siége de Rennes; il fallut deux lettres du roi d’Angleterre, la première en date
du 28 avril, la seconde du 4 juillet 1357 (Rymer, vol. III, p. 353 et 359), pour
vaincre la résistance de son lieutenant, qui n’en obligea pas moins les
habitants de la ville assiégée, quoi qu’en aient dit des historiens bretons plus
patriotes que véridiques, à se racheter et à payer au vainqueur une
contribution de guerre considérable (Morice, Preuves, t. I, col. 1522).—Dans
les premiers mois de 1357, Charles dauphin avait chargé Guillaume de Craon,
son lieutenant en Anjou, Maine, Poitou et Touraine, d’inquiéter le duc de
Lancastre et d’obliger les Anglais à lever le siége de Rennes (JJ89, nos 37 et
127). C’est alors seulement que Bertrand du Guesclin pénétra dans l’intérieur
de la place, car, comme le dit Cuvelier dans son poëme (v. 1080 et 1081):
[56] Le bourg, la cité et le château d’Évreux avaient été conquis par le roi
Jean au commencement de juin 1356. Voy. t. IV de cette édition, Sommaire,
p. LXVIII, note 246.
[57] Nous ignorons si ce fut la ruse de guerre, prêtée par Froissart à
Guillaume de Gauville, qui remit les Navarrais en possession du château
d’Évreux, mais la date que notre chroniqueur assigne à cet événement est
certainement fausse. En février 1358 (n. st.), Évreux appartenait encore au
régent, qui délivrait des lettres de rémission à Guillaume de la Goderie,
demeurant à Évreux, dont le valet avait acheté pour les garnisons anglaises
des forteresses voisines de cette ville «anneaux et chapeaux de bièvre et les
plumes....» JJ89, no 83.—On lit, d’un autre côté, dans les Grandes Chroniques
(t. VI, p. 108), qu’au mois de mai 1358 Jean de Meudon, châtelain d’Évreux
pour le roi de France, mit le feu à la ville d’Évreux, ce dont le roi de Navarre
fut très-irrité. Le château d’Évreux avait été livré par trahison aux Navarrais
avant le mois de septembre 1358, date de deux donations faites par le régent
à Guillaume de Tronchevillier, chevalier, et Robinet Boulart, écuyer, des biens
confisqués de Pierre du Bosc-Renoult et de Guillaume Houvet, écuyers,
complices de la trahison du chastel d’Evreux à nos ennemis en ceste presente
année (JJ87, nos 78 et 79). Froissart raconte que Guillaume de Gauville, pour
apprivoiser encore plus sûrement le châtelain, lui parla d’une descente en
Angleterre que devaient faire les Danois alliés de la France. Il y eut en effet,
en 1358 et 1359, des négociations actives avec Valdemar III, roi de
Danemark, qui aboutirent à un projet de descente des Danois en Angleterre
pour la délivrance du roi Jean, dont le texte a été publié par M. Germain
(Mémoires de la Société archéologique de Montpellier, t. IV, p. 409 à 434).
Voy. aussi le rapport de M. Delisle, Revue des Sociétés savantes, année 1866,
4e série, iv, 33.
[58] Le travail du baron de Zurlauben sur ce chef de compagnies (Hist. de
l’Académie des Inscriptions, t. XXV, p. 153 à 168) n’est qu’un essai fort
incomplet. Le savant baron répète, après Baluze, qu’Arnaud apparaît pour la
première fois dans l’histoire à la bataille de Poitiers, tandis que nous avons
plusieurs actes, antérieurs à cette date, qui le mentionnent: le premier, de
février 1354 (n. st.), où le roi Jean assigne 200 livres de rente à Arnaud de
Cervole, écuyer, en récompense de la part qu’il a prise au recouvrement des
châteaux de Montravel, de Sainte-Foy près Bergerac (auj. Sainte-Foy-des-
Vignes, hameau de Gineste, Dordogne, arr. Bergerac, c. Laforce), du Fleix
(Dordogne, arr. Bergerac, c. Laforce), de Guitres (Gironde, arr. Libourne), et
donne en outre au dit écuyer son château de Châteauneuf-sur-Charente
(Charente, arr. Cognac), JJ82, no 93;—l’autre, du 27 août de la même année,
où le roi de France accorde des lettres de rémission à Arnaud de Cervole,
écuyer, qui, avec l’aide de Pierre de Cervole, chevalier, et de neuf autres
complices, avait occupé après l’assassinat du connétable Charles d’Espagne
les châteaux de Cognac, de Jarnac et de Merpins en Saintonge et avait fait
mettre à mort vingt-sept de ses soudoyers en garnison dans lesdits châteaux,
qui avaient volé blés, vins et draps aux habitants de Saint-Laurent (Saint-
Laurent-de-Cognac, Charente, arr. et c. Cognac). JJ82, no 613.
[59] Au moyen âge, il arriva parfois qu’un archiprêtré fut inféodé, au
temporel, à un laïque. Dom Vaissete dit (Hist. du Languedoc, t. IV, p. 292)
qu’Arnaud possédait l’archiprêtré de Vezzins; mais où était situé cet
archiprêtré? C’est ce que personne n’a encore établi jusqu’à ce jour. On lit
dans Rymer (vol. III, p. 350) que les rois de France et d’Angleterre, en
concluant à Bordeaux la trêve du 23 mars 1357, établirent l’un des quatre
gardiens de cette trêve dans la vicomté de Limoges et en Berry, pour la partie
du roi de France, «Mgr Arnaud de Servole, archiprestre de Velines.» Vélines
(Dordogne, arr. Bergerac) donnait en effet jadis son nom à l’un des
archiprêtrés du diocèse de Périgueux. Voy. le Dictionnaire topographique de la
Dordogne, par le vicomte de Gourgues, Paris, 1873, in-4o, p. 335.
[60] On lit dans la seconde vie d’Innocent VI: «Mense julio (1357) miles
quidam gasco, dictus Archipresbyter, collecta societate, intravit Provinciam, et
plurima damna fecit et strages; propter quæ, tota curia romana stupefacta,
papa, data pecunia, pro qua se Provinciales obligaverunt, ipsum abire fecit, et
transitum per Avinionem concessit. Sed interim papa stipendiarios multos
tenuit, civitatemque muris et portis ac fossatis munivit; ad quæ omnes clerici
in curia romana degentes contribuere cogebantur.» (Bal., Vitæ pap. Aven., t.
I, p. 350). On sait que les fortifications dont il est question dans ces dernières
lignes subsistent encore. Cf. Léon Ménard, Hist. de Nismes, t. II, p. 182, et
Preuves, p. 201.
[61] Cf. Jean le Bel, Chroniques, t. II, p. 215 et 216. Froissart reproduit ici
à peu près littéralement le texte du chanoine de Liége. Le roi de Navarre,
détenu au château d’Arleux, recouvra la liberté le mercredi 8 novembre 1357,
grâce aux menées de Robert le Coq, qui avait fait demander à plusieurs
reprises sa délivrance par les États, et à la complicité de Jean de Picquigny,
gouverneur d’Artois, qui l’arracha par surprise de sa prison. La mise en liberté
de Charles le Mauvais est certainement la faute la plus grave, nous dirions
presque le plus grand crime qu’on puisse reprocher à Robert le Coq et à
Étienne Marcel; car c’est le roi de Navarre qui, à peine délivré, fit occuper
entre le 13 et le 25 décembre 1357, les environs de Paris par les compagnies
anglo-navarraises cantonnées jusque-là sur les confins de la Bretagne et de la
Normandie (Gr. Chron., t. VI, p. 71 à 73). Ces brigands étaient si bien aux
ordres du roi de Navarre qu’on s’adressait à ce dernier plutôt qu’au dauphin
pour obtenir des sauf-conduits, quand on voulait voyager de Paris à un point
quelconque du royaume. Nous avons un de ces sauf-conduits accordé à deux
chevaliers et daté de Paris le 12 mars 1358 (n. st.). Ibid., p. 96 et 97.
[62] Le 25 décembre 1358, Griffith ou Griffon de Galles quitta Montebourg
en basse Normandie, où il avait longtemps tenu garnison, et vint occuper la
forteresse de Becoiseau en Brie (auj. château de Mortcerf, Seine-et-Marne,
arr. Coulommiers, c. Rozoy-en-Brie). JJ90, no 57.
[63] St-Arnoult-en-Yveline, Seine-et-Oise, arr. Rambouillet, c. Dourdan.
[64] Eure-et-Loir, arr. Chartres, c. Maintenon.
[65] Eure-et-Loir, arr. Châteaudun. Bonneval et le pays chartrain furent
ravagés dès le mois de janvier 1357 par Philippe de Navarre qui fit une
chevauchée de ce côté à la tête de huit cents hommes. Gr. Chron., t. VI, p.
52.
[66] Cloyes-sur-le-Loir, Eure-et-Loir, arr. Châteaudun.
[67] Les ennemis d’entre Paris et Chartres s’emparèrent d’Étampes, le
mardi 16 janvier 1358, le jour même où se célébrait à Paris le mariage de
Louis, comte d’Étampes, avec Jeanne d’Eu, veuve de Gautier duc d’Athènes
tué à Poitiers, sœur du connétable Raoul d’Eu décapité à l’hôtel de Nesle (Gr.
Chron., t. VI, p. 81). Dans les premiers mois de 1360, le comte d’Étampes
emprunta 1000 moutons d’or à Guillaume Marcel, changeur à Paris, «pour la
raençon du pais d’Estampes à paier aux Anglois», à raison de 400 moutons
d’intérêt pour six semaines; il donna en gage son chapeau d’or du prix de 200
moutons. JJ91, no 399.