GraduInBCT1 2
GraduInBCT1 2
GraduInBCT1 2
Department of Psychology
University of Portsmouth
1
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The author would like to thank all the following people and organisations:
• My friends and family (Kiitos tuestanne isä ja äiti, ukki ja mummo sekä
tietysti veljeni Leijonamieli!)
• Dr Kim Bard, my personal tutor for her fantastic guidance and inspiration. She
never got, or at least seemed not to get, tired of my at times totally
unintelligent questions. I would never have got through this without her.
Suffice to say then that an exhaustive expression of my gratitude toward her is
hampered only by space limitations and a lack of fitting superlatives.
• The pupils and the teaching and administrative staff at the school I ran the
empirical portion of my study with. A special thank you to the teacher who
delivered my large and heavy box of questionnaires to and from the school.
• Dr Darren Van Laar and Miss Andrea Jones for their help with all the little
practical problems.
• Architectural lighting design office Laterna for generously letting me use their
printing- as well as Internet facilities.
2
UNIVERSITY OF PORTSMOUTH
DEPARTMENT OF PSYCHOLOGY
Declaration Of Originality
NAME ………………………………………………
SIGNED ……………………………………………..
DATE ………………………………………………..
3
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Title…………………………………………………………………. …… …………...1
..
Acknowledgements……………………………………………….…….……. ..……
…...2
Conclusion………………………………………………………….…………….….29
..
Abstract……………………………………...…………………………. . . .……….
….31
4
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Regressions………………………………………….… … . . ….
….44
Notes…. . .…………….…………………………………...……….……….……….
….62
5
GENERAL INTRODUCTION
This masters thesis initially set out to fulfil two aims, one theoretical and one
empirical. The first aim was to come to grips with how this phenomenon called trust
from sociology to organisational science. The second and quite separate aim was to
use and expand upon existing methodology and see how far that avenue of research
would prove useful in a particular context. The intention was to measure trust,
identify international, gender and age differences therein and also to explore factors
resulting in trust. These two endeavours are now presented as two separate wholes i.e.
Parts I and II. The first part has also been submitted for review in an international
at the very end that the two parts are brought together and purposely compared and
contrasted. References, appendices and endnotes however, have not been separated
It should also be stressed at this stage that the reader is not urged to “trust” or
to have “faith” in that this thesis will deliver an utterly convincing account of trust.
Cynicism and scepticism will do nicely. Although one does hope that, at the end, the
reader ends up feeling that the author has indeed met both of his aims and that reading
this chronicle of a year’s work has been time well put to use. And so, without further
ado, what follows should hopefully present an equal challenge for the reader to take
6
“Any escape from solipsism requires a leap of faith. Religions have 'faith' all
7
ABSTRACT
related disciplines, as to how one should understand and study the phenomenon of
The proposed model illustrates how and when specific factors regarding the trusting
person and the trusting relationship affect the trust event. It is not however a recipe for
producing trust or for achieving the desired effects that may result from trust. This
upon specific parts of the problem, instead of perpetuating the existing confusion of
trying to address all aspects of the problem at once. The proposed model highlights
gaps in the existing literature and points to future applications ranging from
8
INTRODUCTION
This theoretical treatise on trust begins with a discussion of the problems involved in
trying to achieve a synthetic conception of interpersonal trust and after which it tries
to reconcile the major definitional difficulty, i.e. the difference(s) between trust and
confidence. The overall form of the model is then established and the model presented
factors, on which consensus exists, that are not trust, a necessary precursor to the
consideration of elements that are necessary to trust, and yet are not trust per se. The
following section then lists, compares and most importantly, integrates concepts that
have been used in the literature when referring to trust. Next, the new trust model is
reiterated with examples. The empirical aspect of trust research is then reviewed to
evaluate the usefulness of the model (which is reiterated in its entirety with examples)
and to identify remaining gaps and future directions. Finally, the concluding section
revisits the main advantages of the proposed model whilst reminding the reader of its
extensive potential.
“It is argued that trust, understood often in a very vague an unsystematic way,
9
The problem of definition
Trust is a concept fraught with trouble. This is true both philosophically speaking as
well as in relation to empirical research endeavours. As one digs into the topic one
soon discovers that researchers dealing with trust are often riddled with scepticism or
known and understood that it seems that no one can actually be bothered to define it
circumvent defining trust itself whilst directing the gist of explanation elsewhere.
Mayer, Davis and Schoorman (1995) clarify this by stating that there are:
relationship between risk and trust; confusion between trust and its
Problems are also unavoidable when trying to bring together and find a common
thread in the efforts of all those interested in the phenomenon. Trust is a topic that has
provoked considerable interest and often heated debate within psychology, political
Kokkonen, 2002), and yet, psychologists tend to ignore the –often considerable–
10
theoretical advances made in other disciplines, e.g., sociology, regarding trust (e.g.
Luhmann, 1979, 1988; Lewis & Weigert, 1985; Misztal, 1996). But why is it then that
the literature offers so little evidence of these efforts aiming to converge? At least
within psychology, systematic research into trust began already in the late 50’s after
which related fields were quickly joining in. Therefore, it cannot be merely a matter of
there not having been enough work done by each so as to benefit the others. If
anything, the opposite is closer to the truth. Lewicki and Bunker (1995) explain the
situation beautifully:
So, without efforts to achieve synthesis the metaphoric elephant’s leg might remain a
tree and its trunk is just as likely to be described as a snake. What is clearly needed
then is a new tactic; bravely weeding out solipsisms and other unnecessary
synthesises current ideas and produces directions for future research efforts. Although
at present a truly comprehensive answer may still prove elusive, through successive
iterations one should at least expect to get closer. In other words, this at least is a bona
11
The problem of Synthesis
of trust as the following account by Lewicki and Bunker (1995) aptly illustrates:
141-2)
This essay therefore aims to take heed of Lewicki and Bunker’s reservations whilst
model specifies how and when important dimensions of the trusting person and the
trusting relationship influence the trusting event. But should this involve
considering trust either as a state or a process is arbitrary (e.g. Luhmann 1979) since
one can easily imagine developing states as well as organised, state-wise proceeding,
processes. Therefore, as the structure of the trust phenomenon can remain ever-
elusive when simply bringing ideas together, one must build a chain of logically valid
statements. While academics disagree on the form of trust, few at least (openly)
1979). What this means in practice is succinctly explained by Lewis and Weigert
(1985):
It is not possible to develop plans of action, which take into account all
possible contingent futures. If all possible future events were accorded equal
12
reduce this complexity to manageable proportions. This reduction of
contingently possible future events are thought of as zero for all practical
This shall be our starting point on which a model of trust can be built. It takes the
reduction of complexity as being the purpose and prime modus operandi of trust. The
condition of trust must first be entered into. This means that such a condition has a
specific starting point in time and thereby should not be regarded as an ongoing
personality attribute (cf. Rotter, 1980; Wrightsman, 1992). Here the distinction
between confidence and trust becomes essential. If trust is viewed as concerning the
that to do this constantly and in conjunction with every decision would plainly be
universal attitude. That would either be too risky or too great a burden” (p. 72). But
how is it then that trust achieves its aim of reducing complexity if it is not a universal
attitude) that merely expects the continuance of the status quo, then a condition of
confidence can and does manage to assign a working probability of zero to most
possible future events. This would include things like “I’m safe to go outside as the
weather forecast didn’t mention anything worrying”, or “I’m sure this food won’t go
off until Friday”. To be more precise, we can be confident about many things but we
still only trust people whether it is individuals or groups. Initiating a trust condition on
13
the other hand, also implies the use of appropriate behaviour to communicate this
intention to the chosen trustee. There are however, probably not that many people
food. Since many (e.g. Hosmer, 1995; Johnson-George & Swap, 1982; Lewicki &
Bunker, 1995; Möllering, 2001; Rotter, 1967, 1971, 1980; Tschannen-Moran & Hoy,
outcome, the trusted party must therefore be aware of being trusted to be able to
action as in for example parents reducing their monitoring of their child, the meaning
In broad terms however, it is enough for the trustor to perceive that the trustee
understands and accepts being trusted. Thereby, a case of apparently misplaced trust
could boil down to insufficient communication on the part of the trustor. Nonetheless
as this essay deals with trust and not (mis)perceptions of intention, it is assumed
hereafter that the trusting intention is made sufficiently explicit or that an implicit
mutual understanding could also be easily made explicit. Then, as both parties agree
on the meaning of the trustor’s action they also come to acknowledge the
(1972) who first noticed that: “the wording of the Rotter Interpersonal Trust Scale
items, suggest that the “trust” involved is of a contractual nature” (p. 143). More
importantly though, they go on to describe this contract as being a case of: “…direct
occasions. The first interaction involves a commitment from party A to party B. The
second involves the fulfillment [sic] or lack of fulfillment [sic] of that commitment”
14
(p. 144). Trust as a contractual event as described herein also presupposes the mutual
and Hoy’s (1998) words, there needs to exist a time lag “between when a commitment
is made and when the recipient [i.e. trustor] knows that it has been fulfilled” (p. 188).
to as resolution since it refers to a juncture when the question of whether trusting was
short. The contention here is that this willingness also needs to be communicated
through behaviour for it to have any functional relevance. Thereby, the dispute as to
whether trust is either just behaviour (e.g. Deutsch, 1960; Rotter, 1967, 1971, 1980;
Zand, 1972) or a psychological condition of some sort (e.g. Kramer, 1999; Larzelere
& Huston, 1980; Lewis & Weigert, 1985; Möllering, 2001) is resolved since the trust
event requires both to unfold. Simply put, the “psychological” leads to the
“behavioural” i.e. the intention is communicated to the trustee whose action(s) lead to
the resolution of the trust contract. In essence, the “behavioural” leads back to the
“psychological” as the trustor assesses the pros and cons of having had trusted the
Now only two things remain unexplored. Firstly, how is it that one moves
from a willingness to take a risk i.e. from whatever bases or reasons the initiation of
the trust commitment is based on, to actually taking the risk i.e. to commence the trust
event? Second, what happens after the outcome becomes apparent? Luhmann (1979)
is pessimistic about it ever being possible or even necessary to fully bridge the gap
between reasons and trust. He argues that: “The very multitude of the ways of
creating trust makes it fruitless to search for general formulae” (p. 84). What this
15
means is that although one may reasonably assert the existence of factors, such as
information, upon which trust is based on a full list may never be accumulated. In
other words, trust is more than the sum of its parts. This is because regardless of the
amount and type of “good reasons” there is always something in addition to them akin
to what Simmel describes as “quasi-religious faith” that enables the “leap” from
interpretation (of reasons) to expectation i.e. the state of trust (Möllering, 2001).
Additionally, there can never exist a single reason or even a specific constellation of
reasons that would make one automatically trust another person (Hosmer, 1995). That
is to say, each and every trusting situation is unique and that we are not trusting
automata i.e. we can never say what it is precisely that makes us trust.
Finally, the matters of resolution and consequences of trust are given their
respective places within the model. Since the trusting condition covers a more or less
distinct temporal period1 of favourable expectation it does not matter whether this
expectation proves justified or misplaced since it cannot affect the nature of the
Consequently, a model claiming to describe the operation of trust per se, as it happens
in the present, should not concern itself with predicting the future (Möllering, 2001).
Hence we arrive at a view of trust close to that of Rousseau, Sitkin, Burt and Camerer
(1998) in which: “trust is not a behaviour (e.g. cooperation) or a choice (e.g. taking a
risk), but an underlying psychological condition that can cause or result from such
actions” (p.395). The present model (Figure 1) however goes further by describing
this psychological condition as a form of social contract that also considers the roles
16
What is Trust not?
made about what it is most definitely not. Terms that have often been used
synonymously with trust (e.g. cooperation, confidence and risk taking) need to be
interchangeable with each other). Since trust is a cross-culturally meaningful idea that
may be expressed in numerous ways depending on language and culture (see e.g.
Pagden, 1988), it is therefore of the utmost importance to at least reduce the existent
confusion regarding its usage among the English-speaking academia. Only then does
or, in some sense, more obvious trust-related concepts will be given a brief mention
the latter that will be integral in building a more unified understanding of the trust
phenomenon.
stupidity (Friedland, 1990 as cited by Hosmer, 1995). Trust is not simply hope or faith
(Luhmann, 1979; Lewis & Weigert, 1985). Most importantly it is not synonymous
with confidence (Luhmann, 1988, Misztal 1996, Möllering, 2001). Luhmann (1988)
contends that whereas both trust and confidence may lapse into disappointment, it is
only with trust that the risk inherent in a situation has to be recognised and accepted.
According to Luhmann (Ibid.): “If you do not consider alternatives (every morning
you leave the house without a weapon!), you are in a situation of confidence” (p. 97).
Trust is not prediction or reliance (Deutsch, 1958; Lewis & Weigert, 1985; Mayer,
Davis & Schoorman, 1995) since the whole point of trust is to transcend the limits of
17
available information (Deutsch, 1958; Möllering, 2001). As stated by Mayer et al.,
1995: “To equate the two [i.e. predictability and trust] is to suggest that a party who
can be expected to consistently ignore the needs of others and act in a self-interested
fashion is therefore trusted, because the party is predictable” (p. 714). Hence, trust
does involve prediction based on previously acquired data but on its own
predictability is insufficient.
never be conflated with the concept itself (Mayer et al., 1995; Möllering, 2001), as is
the case with most research employing a game paradigm (e.g. Deutsch 1960; Parks,
Henager & Scamahorn, 1996). This is because trust may lead to cooperation but so
can a number of other things like greed and coercion. The appearance of a dark cloud
above is not the same thing as getting soaked even though the former can lead to the
1972), although along with risk and vulnerability it appears to be a necessary, yet on
its own an insufficient, requirement for the emergence of trust (Mayer et al., 1995).
These factors will be dealt with in more detail under the rubric of ‘Necessary
requirements to interpersonal trust’ but before that the relationship between trust and
distrust needs to be made clearer. It will be shown that trust should not be seen as
simply the opposite of mistrust. In the 1960’s and 1970’s trust and distrust were
thought of as a dichotomy wherein you could only either trust or distrust another party
(Deutsch, 1960; Luhmann, 1979; Zand, 1972). Moreover, there was a distinctly
Hosmer, 1995) contested this view of a dichotomy and instead suggested that the two
should be seen as opposite ends of a single continuum. In their view one moved from
more to less trust and then onto mistrust on a continuous scale. More recently
18
however, trust and distrust have evolved into separate continuums wherein they can
be simultaneously directed toward the same target, in much the same way as one may
entertain strong feelings of both love and hate toward a single person (Lewicki &
Bunker, 1995).
Agreement also seems to rest within the literature on that distrust can also be,
Kee & Knox, 1970; Lewicki, McAllister & Bies, 1998). Even Rotter (1971), who has
been maybe somewhat inappropriately labelled as the origin of extremely rigid views
on distrust, acquiesces in saying that “It is clear that the expression of distrust in many
(1992) states that distrust should not be equated with misanthropy or cynicism. Yet,
This section reviews the literature as regards elements that are sine qua non to the
formation of trust yet are not positioned in a specific temporal or causal position in
relation to trust. First of all, interpersonal trust, as defined herein, needs a specific
target or referent person that is often referred to as the ‘trustee’ (Kee & Knox, 1970;
MacDonald, et al. 1972; Mayer et al., 1995). This may seem self-evident but since
numerous academics have also (or only) considered trust in relation to non-specific
targets or abstract systems (e.g. Couch, Adams & Jones, 1996; Couch & Jones, 1997;
Lewis & Weigert, 1985; Rotter, 1967, 1971, 1980; Wrightsman, 1992) this point
needs to be made. The difference between trust in such “fuzzier” entities as human
nature, or the purchasing power of money, and trust in a specific person is that the
19
former should come under the heading of confidence since they do not include a
conscious recognition and acceptance of risk (Kee & Knox, 1970; Luhmann, 1988;
Misztal, 1996; Möllering, 2001). What is also missing from trust in abstract systems is
(Gambetta, 1988; Mayer et al., 1995; Sitkin & Roth, 1993; Zand, 1972).
between total knowledge and total ignorance. With full knowledge there is no need
for trust as there is no unknown to pose a risk and with total ignorance one can only
Finally, although there is considerably less agreement in this regard (e.g. Lewis &
Weigert, 1985; Fine & Holyfield, 1996), it seems reasonable to assert the necessity of
at least a minimal level of emotional involvement between the trustor and trustee in
order to enable trust. Fine & Holyfield (1996) posit that trust: “…is possible only in a
world of cultural meanings, emotional responses, and social relations…one not only
The general tendency among scholars of avoiding generalisations about trust because
of its supposedly high context- or level of analysis specificity has also lead to an
unnecessary partitioning of trust and its origins into a range of different and
purportedly separate sub-types. The typologies constructed thus far have usually been
based either on the foundations of trust (e.g. calculus-based trust; Lewicki & Bunker,
1995) or the context in which it manifests (e.g. relational trust; Larzelere & Huston,
1980). The following does not intend to be an exhaustive list of the various
taxonomies produced to date. It only intends to give some idea of the range and
20
thereby limitations of this listing-types-of-trust approach. The terms used in the
literature have all been italicised for the sake of clarity and increased ease of
comparison.
Lewicki and Bunker (1995) suggest that there are three kinds of trust:
Hosmer, 1995) also posits three but under the different names of: process-based,
kinds: cognition- and affect-based, whilst Larzelere and Huston (1980) insist on a
distinction between dyadic and generalised trust. Couch and Jones (1996, 1997)
however have termed these two respectively as relational and global trust whilst
adding a third one called network trust. In contrast, a number of scholars have only
considered a single type of trust variously termed either generalised trust (e.g. Rotter,
1967, 1971, 1980), trust in human nature (Wrightsman, 1992) or anything to that
effect. Finally, Kramer (1999) considers as many as six types including: dispositional,
based trust.
Appearances may however, deceive and these different types may actually be
rather compatible. It will soon become apparent that the terms listed above can in fact
implied to form “good reasons” (Lewis & Weigert, 1985) for forming a decision to
trust. This on its own should not however, as it has already been argued: “...lead us to
the common but erroneous inference that trust is fundamentally an individual and
21
behavioural phenomenon produced by rational machinations of autonomous
cognitivist account of trust. Among the remaining terms, we find such examples as
‘identification’, ‘dyadic’, ‘relational’ and ‘network’ that all point toward the social
function of trust. Hence, it can be argued that this category of terms does not actually
differentiate (a) separate kind(s) of trust from those referred to by the first –i.e.
cognitive– list. Whereas the first category concerns the bases of trust (i.e. information
of some kind) the second one refers to the manifestation of trust within social
interaction. Even the insistence of some (e.g. Larzelere & Huston, 1980; Lewis &
Weigert, 1985) that the social sphere should be treated as the only or at least as a
separate origin of trust, can actually be reconciled with the abovementioned groupings
information. Finally, the terms left over from the previous two categories i.e.: ‘person-
based’, ‘global’, ‘generalised’ and ‘in human nature’ can also be conveniently
propensity to trust. Not surprisingly then, the trustor’s personality can be thought of as
Additionally, there are also those who catalogue the numerous purportedly
necessary properties of the trustee (see Mayer et al., 1995 for a review). These factors
will be considered herein as also coming under the loose heading of ‘social
information’ that may contribute to trust. The following section will endeavour to
combine the three facets of trust bases (cognitive, social and personality) unearthed in
this section to produce a synergetic description of trust as a social event based on the
22
previous research that has stumbled onto the “chicken and egg”-paradox of either only
considering the antecedents or the results of trust. Yet, a complete view of trust should
not fight against trust being both a noun and a verb (Tschannen-Moran & Hoy, 1999).
Or as Lewis and Weigert (1985) put it: The roots of trust extend to every modality of
human experience but it does not thereby lose its unity” (p. 972).
enables two things. First, a model can be drawn up that shows the interrelationships of
the various elements involved in trust in their proper sequential order (antecedents,
necessary concomitants, trust itself and consequences). Second, one can plot the
achievements of previous research onto this model and in so doing produce a clearer
picture of how each of them contributes to the whole. The function of this model is
automata but to factor in all the elements involved in the trusting event.
event. The trustor’s decision to trust is based on various sources of information (as
defined loosely) and a conscious weighing of the increases in risk, vulnerability and
regarding the trustee’s actions. A certain level of agreement needs to exist between
the trustor and the trustee regarding the nature of the actions required of the latter and
the time frame within which to execute them. This is essential for enabling the trustor
to conclude whether his or her trust in the trustee was in the end justified or in fact
misplaced. This judgment of un/trustworthiness can then bring about various effects
that can only manifest in connection with relevant future events and not with the
present one.
23
Figure 1: A model of interpersonal trust operationalised as a contractual social event
(4) Trust:
Duration of trust “contract”
Trust-initiating behaviour
(5) Resolution
(6) Effects:
- Cooperation
- Social capital
- Spontaneous sociability, etc.
24
Working through the model
Now that some conceptual foundations for a new conception of trust have been laid it
is time to run through the proposed model from start to finish. Let us take two
individuals, Bill and Ted, who have known each other for a score of years. To
simplify things, it is assumed that through their friendship they have developed a
conducting oneself in morally correct ways. Bill then is the trustor who has access to a
sizeable quantity of trust information relating to himself, his family and friends, the
by the first and topmost of the boxes in Figure 1. Bill then weighs all this information
against the possible hazards of trusting Ted when it comes to a particular instance. It
is important to include this referent event for trust in the model since (due to reasons
outlined above) we are not dealing with generalised or universal trust but trust in
So, in order for the trust contract to begin Bill must yield to an increase in risk
and his dependence on Ted as well as becoming vulnerable to e.g. Ted’s possible
abuse of the situation to his advantage. There must also exist at least a minimal level
of positive emotional involvement between Bill and Ted for a condition of trust to
commence. For example, an unfulfilled promise would not matter as such if the
person expecting promise fulfilment, i.e. Bill, had no emotional investment in the
matter to start with. If Bill suffers only general annoyance or slight frustration but no
personal hurt we would not consider the situation as having been one of trust. To sum
dependence parallel to the trust agreement. The status of these factors can then only
25
be reviewed at the resolution of the trust contract. The long vertical box number 2 on
Then after much deliberation, which may or may not have been entirely
conscious, Bill decides to trust Ted and so he makes that all-important leap of faith
from reasons for trusting into actually doing so. The third box in Figure 1 represents
this “leap”, as well as the Simmelian “quasi-religious faith” enabling it. In the present
example Bill needs to then communicate his willingness to trust Ted by engaging in
an appropriate action. This might entail lending Ted something or asking him to do a
favour. Yet, regardless of how trust is displayed (or only somehow implied) the
trustee, i.e. Ted, agrees to take on the responsibility and thus through mutual
is through a series of similar agreements that Bill, like the rest of us, is able to ease the
1, the fourth box with the dotted lines indicates this, the actual trust stage.
Finally, as Ted delivers i.e. returns the borrowed item or shows having had
done the favour (or equally fails to return the item or shows having had forgotten the
favour) the trust contract terminates. As Bill can then judge the wisdom of having
placed his trust in Ted the matter is resolved. The fifth box in Figure 1 designates this
juncture. The concluding stage of the model, although it is beyond the scope of the
trust event per se, is vital in the larger scheme of things. In other words, the effects of
trust are what connect the model and any practical applications it might have to
reality. In fact, Figure 1 might just as well have feedback loops leading back from the
However, the impression that the present form of the model is intended to give
is that the whole process is a future-oriented one. So regardless of whether Ted does
26
deliver and Bill’s trust in him proves to have been justified or not the resolution of the
matter provides Bill with a wealth of new information. It can also lead to changes in
attitude, emotion, etc. and above all new actions e.g. trusting Ted with regard to other
things or more important things and maybe even to trusting people in general more.
Most importantly though, each running through of the “trust program” as laid out
herein changes the initial set-up of future trust events and so has nothing whatsoever
to do with the present one. In other words, the feedback loops from the final box (if
one wanted to add them) would lead to the first and second boxes in a similar
interested in trust one must also look at the methods that are partly to blame for the
emergence of this confusion. The earliest method used in trust research was The
Prisoner’s Dilemma game e.g. Deutsch (1958, 1960). Since then the use of such
mixed motive games has largely been phased out or discontinued all together (see e.g.
Parks et al. 1996; Ostrom & Walker, 2003 for recent exceptions) due to extensive
criticisms regarding their validity. Rotter (1971) for example states that: “…if the
results of these studies were characteristic of everyday behavior, the normal adult is
normal day’s activities.” (p. 444). See Kee and Knox (1970) for a comprehensive
critique of this approach. The paradigm that emerged to supersede the use of mixed-
motive games was the employment of questionnaires (e.g. Couch, Adams & Jones,
1996; Johnson-George, & Swap, 1982; Larzelere & Huston, 1980; Rotter, 1967, 1971,
1980).
27
The problem with questionnaires is that they all retain the baggage of the unresolved
definition issue. Therefore, what the questionnaires actually measure may vary from
the respondents’ typical behaviours in certain circumstances to their beliefs about the
truthfulness of the actions of others and everything in between. This has lead to trust
questionnaires being criticised for their reductionism (Lewis & Weigert, 1985;
Möllering, 2001). However, Möllering (2001) also laments the fact that the open-
operationalise” (p. 416). Therefore, qualitative research into trust remains hard to
come by. Gladly there are some (e.g. Fine & Holyfield, 1996) that have achieved
some progress in this regard. Although the presently constructed model of trust does
not indicate the superiority of any single method in studying trust in the future, it
does, with its broad basis within the literature, present a promising framework for re-
The largest obstruction to the advancement of trust research has thus far been a
unified way to define interpersonal trust. This essay aims to exceed this impediment at
least in general terms. However, the model still needs to be developed to enable it to
reflect, for example, changes occurring during the human life span. From a
developmental point of view, the literature on trust presents a gaping hole in that the
phenomenon has been considered in early infancy (e.g. Erikson, 1995) and adulthood
(see above) but little explicit consideration seems to have been given to how the one
might develop into the other, or indeed if they are related at all. Within the
fill in the same questionnaire about a single individual. This is often done in
28
etc. so it could equally well be done with perceptions of trusting and trustworthiness.
The inclusion of specific others into the equation boils down to the issue of
regardless of whether the trustee is an old friend or a new acquaintance. But if trust is
seen along the lines of the proposed model, as being akin to a contract that is
renegotiated each time someone is trusted, then the identity of the trustee does matter
alongside a plethora of other situational factors. And yet, even though associations
have been sought between the individual attributes of the trustor (e.g. Deutsch, 1960;
Wrightsman, 1992) and the level of trust, as well as between the trustee’s attributes
and the level of trust (e.g. Mayer et al., 1995) no consideration seems to have been
as the proposed model describes the trusting event in its entirety. Thereby,
interpersonal trust research should occupy itself not with identifying and classifying
different types of trust as they occur in various settings, but with exploring which
elements of the proposed model differ, in what circumstances and how. For example,
Conclusion
It has been shown that there exists considerable uncertainty within psychology, as
29
interpersonal trust as a contractual social event. This model enables future research to
focus only on certain aspects of the trusting event at a time. The model should also
alert researchers to the fact that trying to factor in all the (possible) variables involved
in a trusting event may in fact prove impractical. For example, the sources of
information that might lead one person to decide to trust might not be the same for
People’s evaluations of the sufficiency of these “good reasons” (to lead to trust, i.e.
the “leap of faith”) might also be expected to vary as well as their awareness and
involved in the negotiation and execution of the trust “contract” the equation becomes
ever more complex, albeit the contributing pieces remain conceptually simple. Further
research is thereby needed to explore all the facets of the proposed model first on their
own and only then in some combinations so that possible interactions can be
unearthed. This needs to be done also within a developmental framework to see how
the process of trusting changes during our life span as well as during our various
relationships. The viability of the proposed model should also be tested cross-
culturally to see whether people of varying backgrounds for example extract and
import upon numerous spheres of human existence and thereby deserves to be studied
further. However, to do this properly one must transcend the existent confusion and
embrace a completely new approach. This essay goes some way to provide an idea as
30
ABSTRACT
Interpersonal trust seems to have run the gamut of explanations within psychology
and all related disciplines and yet the amount of empirical research conducted has
yielded very little in terms of linking trust with other phenomena. This study extends
previous findings by illuminating some of the processes that result in trust. Altogether
259 Finnish and British adolescents between the ages of 12 and 16 filled in a set of
the present sample, emotional intelligence and self-esteem appear to explain a large
proportion of the variance in trust scores as measured by two separate scales. Some
significant differences also emerged between and within the sub samples but only
with very small effect sizes. Hence, these findings may well be of negligible value to
advancing our understanding of the formation and negotiation of trust. The present
results are also discussed in relation to current and future empirical trust research.
31
INTRODUCTION
interesting history to its name. The need for a proper understanding of the workings of
trust grew out of the escalating suspicions brought about by the Cold War.
Psychologists (e.g. Deutsch, 1958, Mellinger, 1958) were eager to join the
scientific solution to the costly and dangerous armaments race. Subsequently, the
major societal upheavals of the 1960’s USA (i.e. “The atom bomb, the Asian war, the
college student, the hippie, the black revolutions and the problems of pollution and
perspective. Trust was now studied as a generalised personality trait, i.e. collective
problems were seen to stem from the individual. Since then, interest in trust has
Moran & Hoy, 2001) interpersonal relationships (e.g. Johnson-George & Swap, 1982;
Larzelere & Huston, 1980; Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985), sociology (e.g. Lewis &
Weigert, 1985; Luhmann, 1979, 1988; Misztal, 1996) and organisational science (e.g.
Gambetta, 1988; Kramer, 1999). And although the aims of today’s trust research may
dissent), it may well produce more tangible, meaningful and useful results since its
applications.
But, as always, a continual increase in the variety of theory and practice may
not be an entirely good thing. It means that it is now increasingly difficult to choose a
particular approach and to justify doing so. And yet, although academics interested in
32
whatever) most appear to at least accept that it must be something measurable. But
be more precise, choices made within the confines of a Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD) or a
comparable non-zero sum game. Such studies do indeed yield easily attainable
measurements but what in the end do such quantifications tell us about the individuals
Rotter (1971) for example is of the opinion that whenever trust researchers
add that: “One exception, evidenced from such studies as those of Deutsch (1960) and
Wrightsman (1966), indicates that trust and trustworthiness are positively associated”
(p.444). Macdonald et al (1972) on the other hand found that PD was related to self-
Rotter’s scale was not. But then again, no relationship was found between the two
trust indices suggesting that the two actually measure completely different things.
According to Butler (1983, as cited by Sitkin & Roth, 1993) the primary finding
emanating from relevant individual differences research is that personality traits and
whereas reciprocal trust from the other party is. His view is therefore, in essence, a
reiteration of Rotter’s view above in that trustworthiness appears to beget trust and
vice versa.
anything but each other has it then been a case of perhaps not measuring the right
33
things? In other words, there might be some other factors that, as yet, have been
attainable but not with the tools presently available i.e. the thing being incorrectly
measured would be trust itself. Thereby, current trust scales might not be sensitive
enough for reaching the level of individual differences. But how about group
consistently making more trusting ratings of their partners. Rotenberg (1984) on the
other hand failed to obtain a similar gender difference in children. He did however
find that there was a same sex pattern in children’s trust in their peers in that girls
trusted girls more than boys and boys trusted boys more than they trusted girls.
Goddard et al. (2001) on the other hand, found teachers’ trust in students varying as a
function of the students’ socio-economic status (SES). In other words, some evidence
exists of the amount of trust varying at least between some distinct groups and in
trusting was made a central part of the current study along with hopefully identifying
other correlates of trust apart from trustworthiness. The chosen contenders for such
factors are self-esteem (Rosenberg, 1965) and emotional intelligence (Schutte et al.,
1998) and psychosomatic health/stress. The presently chosen sample population also
consists of school-aged children or, more precisely, adolescents as it was thought that
to them issues of trust might be especially salient and topical as they are negotiated
alluded to above, the present study has therefore two specific hypotheses. The first
34
one asserts that the level of trust and distrust, as measured by the two scales (Couch et
al., 1996: Trust Inventory and Macdonald et al.: 1972: Self-Report Trust Scale)
age and/or gender (and possibly as a function of some of the individual differences
measures). The second hypothesis to be affirmed or rejected attests that levels of trust
and distrust can be predicted from one or more of the following factors: somatic
35
METHOD
Participants
The participants of this study consisted of two separate opportunity samples. The first
combined sample was therefore a total of 259 participants. Of the British sample,
48.9% were female and 44.5% male (6.6 % refused to disclose their gender). Of the
Finnish sample, 57.4% were female and 42.6% were male. So thereby of the whole
sample, 52.9% were female and 43.6% were male whilst 3.5% failed to make their
gender known.
follows: 13.9% were 12, 32.8% were 13, 35.8% were 14 and 16.8% were 15 years old
and one girl did not indicate her age. Whereas the ages of the Finnish sample were
spread out so that: 6.6% were 12, 28.7% were 13, 26.2% were 14, 31.1% were 15 and
7.4% were 16 years old. Thus, of the entire sample, 10.4% were 12, 30.9% were 13,
31.3% were 14, 23.6% were 15, 3.5% were 16 years old and the one (0.4%) did not
Materials
Every participant was given a set of papers consisting of: an informed consent form, a
F and G respectively.
36
Development of the set of questionnaires used
It was decided that for one of the purposes of the current study, i.e. the possibility of
connections between psychosomatic stress and trust, a new assessment tool was
needed (see Appendix B). This new questionnaire was construed entirely by the
Finnish research team and then translated by the researcher for use with the British
sample. Items were constructed to reflect the range of age-appropriate physical as well
symptom checklist (Aro, 1988), nine items taken from the General Health
based on the Maslach Burnout Inventory (Maslach & Jackson, 1986), and the
question, “How was your health during the last year?” The two questions relating to
bullying and being bullied -"How often have you taken part in bullying others in this
school term?" and "How often have you been bullied in this school term?"- were taken
from Olweus (1993). The rest of the items were loosely based on related work done
Procedure
The study was run independently in Finland and in the UK after which the two parties
shared datasets with one another. The British sample was collected all in one session
under the supervision and with the assistance of several teachers. When the
participants were all seated and settled the researcher spoke about the instructions for
filling in the questionnaire. It was emphasised that the questionnaire was anonymous
and was to be filled in independently. The concept of anonymity was also briefly
discussed to ensure that everybody understood that taking part would not have any
effect on the participants’ grades or anything else at school or outside of it. Before
filling in the questionnaires the participants were asked to read through the informed
37
consent form. The researcher explained how they could consent to the researcher
using their responses by signing the informed consent form. The participants were
assured that anyone who needed assistance with the questionnaire would be given it
Ethical considerations
When dealing with under aged participants one must obviously tread extra carefully
and this was to be no exception. In the current study this care is evident in several of
the following procedural details. Fully informed consent was obtained from all
participants. The meaning of some of the perhaps more unfamiliar words in the
consent form like anonymity and consent were briefly discussed with pupils to ensure
that everybody understood the terms. The participants were also informed of the
expected, rather long (i.e. 45 minutes), duration of the study. Running the study took
so long because there were in total eight questionnaires to fill in. This procedure had
been previously agreed upon with the Finnish research team and so at the time of
running it was not known if all of the responses would be used in the present analyses.
The participants were reminded that they could feel free to respond in
complete honesty, as individuals could not be identified from their answers. They
were also assured that taking part would not have any adverse (or favourable) effects
on their grades. In fact, the school would receive the same summary information that
participants received (if they so wished). It was made clear to the participants that
they were free to withdraw their participation for any reason and at any point,
including after the questionnaires had been handed in. The participants were also
given a separate sheet (see Appendix G) to take away providing names and contact
information for advice and counselling services if, despite all precautions, the
38
RESULTS
This section is divided into four subsections. The first subsection describes how and
why the initial data set was reduced down to the final set of summary indices. The
second subsection then summarises the acquired data set by listing Ns, minimums,
maximums, means and standard deviations. The third then illustrates the analyses of
variance that were employed on the data in order to discover significant group
differences. Finally, the fourth subsection describes the process of running multiple
hierarchical regression analyses on the data whilst illustrating the results thus
unearthed.
DATA REDUCTION
of the experimental variables i.e. trust, self-esteem, emotional intelligence and the
various health measures. For this end, means were calculated for each participant and
each measure. With the pre-existing measures i.e., self-esteem, emotional intelligence
and the two trust scales it was possible to compute both a positive and negative mean
score for each participant thus reflecting the two opposing facets of these constructs
and enabling a larger range of comparisons. These mean scores were arrived at by
first performing principal components analyses with Varimax rotation on the acquired
responses in order to ascertain the relevance of the scales’ constituent items. These
analyses were run first on both samples separately and then with the entire combined
data set and only items that loaded similarly throughout and with Eigen values over .5
First of all, the self-esteem scale turned out to be extremely robust, with
positively worded items loading on one factor and negatively worded items on
another. Seven out of the ten items loading positively on the first factor also loaded
39
negatively on the other. Hence, all items were kept and the individual scores were
computed as the mean of responses to positively worded items and the mean of
there were only three negatively worded items to start with but they all loaded on one
factor only. The analysis also spread out the positively worded items over several
factors but since intelligence can be argued to be such a multifaceted concept and
since none of the items loaded significantly on several factors (either positively or
negatively), all positively worded items where assumed to mirror one underlying
structure. Only item number six did not load on to any factor and was thereby not
used in computing the final emotional intelligence sores. The score for trust (SRTS)
ended up being the mean of responses to items 1, 6, 7 and 9, whereas distrust (SRTS)
was calculated as the mean of responses to items 2, 4 and 5. Items 3, 8 and 10 where
thereby excluded, as they did not produce factor loadings in any consistent manner.
Finally, the scores for trust (TI) and distrust (TI) were computed as the means of
responses to items 3, 6, 17, 18, 19, 20 and 7, 9, 11, 13, 14 respectively. Items 1, 2, 4,
5, 8, 10, 12, 15 and 16 were thus excluded, as again they did not produce factor
With the specifically designed health questionnaire this process was rather
simpler as no factor analyses were required. Apart from the four items: 1.6, 1.11.1,
1.11.2 and 3.1, responses to the health-related questions were recoded. Responses to
questions 1.8.1 - 1.8.4 reflecting tiredness were tallied so that only responses 5 and 6
indicators of significant somatic stress. Finally, of the responses the participants gave
to the general health questions 3.3.1 – 3.3.9 only responses 3 and 4 were considered
40
indicative of serious health problems. Responses to questions 1.2 to1.5, 1.7, 1.9.1
to1.9.9, 1.10.1 to 1.10.13 and 2, were consequently left out of analyses completely
because they were designed according to the research interests and needs of the
Finnish research team and so were deemed not to have significant import upon these
particular analyses.
ANALYSES
Descriptives
Score for good emotional intelligence 258 1,00 5,00 3,56 0,52
Score for bad emotional intelligence 258 1,00 5,00 2,65 0,71
Score for good self esteem 257 1,20 5,00 3,93 0,78
Score for bad self esteem 257 1,00 5,00 2,75 0,96
Score for trust (Self-report trust scale) 258 1,00 5,00 3,61 0,62
Score for distrust (Self-report trust scale) 258 1,00 5,00 2,80 0,79
Score for trust (Trust Inventory) 258 2,00 5,00 3,75 0,58
Score for distrust (Trust Inventory) 258 1,00 5,00 2,88 0,72
41
Some of the results provided in Table 1 above are now clarified so as to save the
reader from having to refer to the Appendices for deciphering their meaning. Self-
reported frequency of having been bullied and of having taken part in bullying others
at school were both measured on a four point scale. For both questions the response
scale ranged from (1) “not at all” to (2) “rarely” and then to (3) “about once a week”
and finally to (4) “several times a week”. The means obtained therefore denote a
relative rarity of occurrence both in being the victim and perpetrator of bullying. The
attained mean score for self-reported state of health during the last six months on the
other hand corresponds closely with response option number four (on a five-point
scale ranging from “very bad” to “very good”) i.e. “quite good”. The remaining
figures should however be decipherable with the aid of the previous subsection.
Analyses of variance
nationality, gender or age. With reference to nationality it was found that Finnish
participants (Mean = 3.89, SD = 0.53) scored significantly higher on trust (TI) than
the British participants (Mean = 3.62, SD = 0.60) did, F(1,235) = 10.4, p =0.001, Eta2
= 0.042. A similar result was obtained when the Finnish participants (Mean =3.77, SD
=0.55) were found to score significantly higher than the British participants (Mean =
3.46, SD =0.65) also on trust (SRTS), F(1,235) = 16.676, p < 0.001, Eta2 = 0.066. The
two nationalities differed also in respect to distrust (TI) so that the British participants
(Mean = 3.03, SD = 0.74) scored significantly higher than Finnish participants (Mean
=2.71, SD =0.68), F(1,235) = 6.687, p = 0.01, Eta2 = 0.028. There was however, no
42
The two samples also differed significantly regarding self-reported health with
British participants (Mean = 3.91, SD = 0.83) did, F(1, 256) = 5.626, p = 0.018, Eta2 =
0.022. The final difference between the two nationalities shows Finnish Participants
(Mean = 2.97, SD = 0.97) scoring significantly higher on bad self-esteem than the
British participants (Mean = 2.55, SD = 0.9) did, F(1, 255) = 12.477, p < 0.001, Eta2 =
0.047.
emotional intelligence and self-esteem measures with gender the following scores
yielded significant differences among the present sample. Females (Mean = 3.82, SD
= 0.56) were found to score significantly higher on trust (TI) than Males (Mean =
3.71, SD = 0.59), F(1,230) = 4.683, p = 0.031, Eta2 = 0.02. Females (Mean = 3.66, SD
= 0.43) were also found to score significantly higher than Males (Mean = 3.47, SD =
0.55) in good emotional intelligence, F(1,230) = 6.778, p = 0.1, Eta2 = 0.029. Quite
surprisingly then, Females (Mean = 3.05, SD = 0.94), also scored significantly higher
self-esteem. It was found that 16- (Mean = 3.31, SD = 0.95) 15- (Mean = 2.84, SD =
0.94) and 14-year olds (Mean = 2.95, SD = 0.92) scored significantly higher than 12-
year olds (Mean = 2.29, SD = 0.92) and that 16- and 14-year-olds scored significantly
higher than 13-year olds (Mean = 2.56, SD = 0.4), F(4, 251) = 4.249, p = 0.002, Eta2
= 0.063.
43
Regressions
The purpose of this phase of the analyses was to examine the relationship of the
and bullying) to trust and distrust. Separate hierarchical multiple regression analyses
indices with trust and distrust. For each of the four trust indices (trust and distrust as
measured by the TI and the SRTS), the regression analysis consisted of three steps.
The first step examined the relationship of age, gender and nationality with one of the
trust indices as the dependent variable. The psychosomatic health indices were
entered as the second step, whilst the third step added the emotional intelligence and
self-esteem measures. The four regression analyses were thus conducted with each
trust and distrust score as the dependent variable. The results of the hierarchical
regression analyses are presented below for each of the trust variables.
* p = 0.05, ** p = 0.001
Table 2 above shows that nationality contributed significantly to trust (as measured by
the TI), as did the psychosomatic health measures but that emotional intelligence and
self-esteem contributed the most. And it was specifically the scores on good self
44
comparison of the Beta values showed that the contribution of emotional intelligence
was about three times that of self-esteem. Of the psychosomatic health measures the
significantly.
* p = 0.05, ** p = 0.001
Table 3 shows that again age, gender and nationality contributed significantly to trust
(as measured by the SRTS), as did the psychosomatic health measures, and that again
emotional intelligence and self-esteem contributed the most. Again, only the scores on
good self esteem and good emotional intelligence contributed significantly. As with
trust (TI) comparison of Beta values showed that the contribution of emotional
intelligence was about three times that of self-esteem. Of the psychosomatic health
measures the number of days off school due to illness, the frequency of having bullied
45
Table 4: Result of hierarchical regression with distrust (TI) as dependent variable
* p = 0.05, ** p = 0.001
Table 4 above shows that age, gender and nationality contributed significantly to
distrust (as measured by the TI), whereas the psychosomatic health measures did not.
Again, emotional intelligence and self-esteem contributed the most. But this time
however, scores for both good and bad emotional intelligence as well as self-esteem
contributed significantly.
* p = 0.05, ** p = 0.001
distrust (as measured by the SRTS), nor did the psychosomatic health measures.
not. As with distrust (TI), scores for both good and bad emotional intelligence
contributed significantly.
46
DISCUSSION
The two samples obtained for the present study, i.e. British and Finnish adolescents
differed significantly with respect to three of the four calculated trust indices.
Analyses of variance showed that the Finnish participants scored higher on both trust
scores and lower on one of the two distrust scores. Females were also found to score
significantly higher than males on one of the two trust scores. Further significant
differences were identified with regard to gender, age and the remaining indices.
Females were found to score significantly higher than Males in good emotional
intelligence and bad self-esteem. With regard to age there was only one significant
difference in that the score for bad self-esteem appeared to increase somewhat as a
function of age. All effect sizes were however very small. Through hierarchical
regression analyses it was found that a significant proportion of the variance in trust
scores as measured by two separate scales (the Trust Inventory and the Self-Report
intelligence provided the single largest contribution toward explaining the variance in
trust scores. Neither the frequency of having been the victim of bullying nor
pronounced tiredness however contributed at all toward the variance in any of the
trust scores.
In short then, both hypotheses received some support. Within the present
nationality and gender. In addition, some of the variance in trust and distrust scores,
again within the present sample, appears to be explainable in part with differences in
47
There have been no previous studies as yet linking such factors as psychosomatic
health, emotional intelligence and self-esteem with trust. The current study thereby
paves the way for more research of the present kind. The attained results offer an
interpersonal trust. They show that the ability to understand others’ emotions does
indeed play a significant role in trusting. A higher emotional intelligence score may
What the relative contributions of perception and cognition in this process are remains
esteem can only be hypothesized about at present. One possibility is that an individual
with a superior regard and respect for him- or herself more readily seeks the company
The failure of the present study to obtain larger group differences might be
partly attributable to the chosen method and the assumptions embedded therein. The
than trust in one’s peers or familiar everyday authority figures (parents, teachers, etc.)
for example. Then again, trust in specific individuals and in reference to specific
things has thus far only been assessed with a few relational trust scales between adult
couples (e.g. Larzelere & Huston, 1980; Rempel et al., 1985) and with children in
specific target individuals outside the romantic relationship context. On the other
hand, knowing the infinitesimal effect sizes of the presently achieved group
48
self-esteem to variance in trust scores (as compared to nationality), such group
procedural artefacts. And even if the presently uncovered group differences were
replicated and made even more distinct they would still be, as such, somewhat lacking
in usefulness. In other words, there is simply no way of saying how scoring higher on
the existence of such group differences in trusting does not tell us anything of who,
Within psychological trust research such problems have often been cleverly
explaining the attained measurements. Rotter (1971) for example asserts that his scale
George and Swap (1982) on the other hand assert that although “…real-life
experiences of trust are undoubtedly associated with such feelings as love, liking,
respect and mutuality” (p. 1315) trust as measured by their scale does not. What this
means is that such results as have been uncovered through various measurements of
trust may well have an extremely restricted range of application or that they do not
actually reflect reality (as we know it). Surely no one in their right mind would admit
One must therefore remember that although such instruments remain in wide
use they still retain the baggage of the unresolved definition issue. In other words,
they may still contain items that are not entirely justified, either in the sense of
behaviours from which trust is then inferred. For example, both the Trust Inventory
49
and the Self-report Trust Scale contain items (alongside ones that directly address
trusting and not trusting) that implore about the respondents’ faith or belief in the
truthfulness of other people and their actions. What this implies is that trust is a
cognitive construct of some sort with (maybe) added bits of emotional and moral
flavour. Secondly, such items as “I make friends easily” from the Trust Inventory
(Couch et al., 1996) can, in actual fact, tap into a range of things. This example could,
for instance, be said to reflect trust itself (as a personality attribute) of which making
friends easily is a part of, a functional consequence of trust i.e. “people trust me and
friends easily leads to people trusting me”. Thus, it should come as no real surprise
that within the present study it was precisely these rather vague items that had to be
dropped from analyses. Research will always be guided by various assumptions, but
what research on trust desperately needs is for these assumptions to be made explicit.
related phenomena secures the focus of measurement entirely into the cognitive
domain. Thereby, implicit in the use of questionnaires is the assumption that the focal
methods and most types of survey or experiment) are limited, because they predict a
singular model of human interpretation” (p. 416). This is in agreement with Lewis and
Weigert’s (1985) view in that psychologists try to: “…reduce trust to its cognitive
50
In the case of trust being the object of study, this age-old struggle between
quantitative and qualitative methods is especially pertinent as it, yet again, leads us
cannot be justified for good without proper clarification of whether one should study
And even if trust manifests in all of these domains then does it do so through a
Conversely, this lack of consensus might also be seen as reason enough for employing
more qualitative methods. One might contend that if even the researcher cannot put
his or her finger on what trust is supposed to be then he or she should let the
participant do this. But why then are the participants’ own formulations of trust not
being employed more frequently within trust research? The prevailing consensus
seems to rest on not assigning subjective views any value whatsoever when a
and target specific nature of interpersonal trust as well as the variety of connotations
But how should one gauge trust if not with questionnaires? For achieving
the qualitative and quantitative approaches. The qualitative element might however
mean that it might be especially difficult to stop participants from making any number
of digressions into any number of things related to the operation of trust whilst not
necessarily describing the “thing” that is trust. One solution for this particular
51
between people was especially salient. Some success has, in fact, already been
and Holyfield (1996) for example, explored the functioning of a mushrooming society
where initiates trust their lives in the hands of people who, to them, appear to be
expert in discerning edible mushrooms from toxic ones. Equally, one might
establish and maintain such a level of trust in their colleagues that they can perform
without being in constant mortal fear. Both examples are extreme but still they are
cases of noncontrived trust i.e. they do not place people in unnatural game-playing
situations or reduce people’s trust to its cognitive content. And yet, the unavoidable
problem also faced by trust research seeking to use naturally occurring instances of
trust is the necessity of inferring trust from behaviour. This is the exact same hurdle at
which the non-zero sum games-paradigm fails to deliver. It can never achieve
as trust. And yet, the problems of such an approach should not be used as vindication
including (but not limited to) what it is based on and what its consequences are,
research on trust has to impose some kind of a framework upon people within which
they can explore the phenomenon and produce some description of its workings as it
relates to them. And it is precisely because of this reason that the questionnaire
however have a lot of promise for the advancement of trust research but they still
terms of usefulness.
52
Future directions
The present findings should now be placed in a larger context. This could be
achieved, at least in part, by employing a larger battery of trust measures and a wider
variety of emotion-related scales to assess the role of affect in the negotiation of trust.
Looking at the presently achieved results and particularly the fact that so many of the
trust scales’ items had to be dropped from analyses, it might also be constructive to
try and combine pre-existing trust scales into (a) more robust one(s). Of the presently
“fashionable” emotion structures, alexithymia (e.g. Bagby, Parker & Taylor, 1994)
and the need for affect (e.g. Maio & Esses, 2001) might prove interesting when
In a similar vein, the role and contribution of cognition to the equation that is
trust needs also to be clarified. And even though many, e.g. Lewis and Weigert
(1985), are of the opinion that one should avoid seeing trust as being: “…produced by
curious that the relationship between intelligence and trust remains completely
unexplored. The two should be studied in concert even if only to show that no
scales completely for granted. If, for example, specific others are to be used, as
for deciding upon who in each case should be included as such. Advances in theory
should also help in providing a more lucid framework for conducting qualitative
studies in. In other words, there are numerous ways in which psychological trust
research can and should now be developed. Only the lack of imagination might stand
in the way.
53
Conclusion
Now, the present findings should not be too difficult to summarise, whilst keeping the
and, to some degree, self-esteem as well appear to play a significant role in the
development of trust. This discovery should now be expanded upon with all available
methods whilst ensuring and enhancing their validity. Trust is fascinating subject
matter for psychological enquiry and it will surely continue to bear much enlightening
fruit for years to come. For now though, what better way to conclude than with
but within our own smaller circles of influence, we can model and encourage
a little more trust. The consequences can be beneficial, the risks do not seem
too great, and a younger generation may be a little more ready for a better
54
GENERAL DISCUSSION
Now then, what have we learned through these twin endeavours of exploring trust?
The two main parts of this thesis can be understood as two opposing means of trying
to influence the ongoing research effort. The theoretical approach (Part I) is obviously
more of a head on assault as it aims to give adequate reason for starting completely
new lines of research or for at least dramatically diverting current ones. The empirical
approach (Part II) on the other hand describes a more subtle way of effecting change,
from the inside out as it were. Both have their possibilities and their limitations
relative to one another and the field as a whole. Thus, an overview of these merits and
The principal gain of Part I is that it offers some relief from the soliptical
synonym over-use involved in explaining trust only with reference to such terms as
Couch & Jones, 1997; Deutsch, 1960; Goddard, Tschannen-Moran & Hoy, 2001;
Larzelere & Huston, 1980; Rempel, Holmes & Zanna, 1985; Rotter, 1971, 1980). The
reality. Merely conceptual musings on the other hand can easily falter when the
doing so one may easily fail to recognize the potentially circular nature of
This is not to say that the model proposed in Part I is entirely free of
bit sketchy at parts but gladly Part II can help to make up for some of this
imprecision. For example, whereas Part I is deliberately vague when it comes to the
55
“information” that trust is supposedly based on, Part II clearly shows that at least
emotional intelligence and self-esteem are part of this structure (or process). They
factors to trust. On the other hand, Part I places the attained empirical results of part II
in a larger context by showing that they only pertain to specific segments of the
equation that is trust. This is true both in terms of the history of trust research as well
as the proposed model describing the trust event. Firstly, the achieved results belong
type of trust research. Thereby, they add at least emotional intelligence to the
hypothetical set of variables to be considered before the start of the actual trust
condition (see Figure 1, p. 24). Secondly, they add to the complexity of things since it
should not be assumed at this stage that emotional intelligence and self-esteem do not
affect the whole process of negotiating the trust contract. Part II therefore points
toward the potential value of exploring the relative contributions of cognition and
Hopefully then, this portrayal of two separately conducted enquiries has also
necessary in this field, as in any other, but only when it is justified. Diversification for
its own sake only leads to more confusion, which has already been noted and
addressed by several academics interested in trust (see Part I). Thus, although
integration and synthesis of theory and practice may be the more difficult and
56
PERSONAL REFLECTIONS CONCERNING THE MSC
Now that the reader has been inundated with all things trust-related -both in theory as
well as practice- it is time to ask the simplest of questions: what does it all mean then?
First of all, the MSc has meant that for a whole year I have not had to think ahead
about what to do next. But still, I would not think that ‘liberating’ was the best word
for describing the endless hours of working alone, that this year involved. The
surprisingly few lectures offered only occasional momentary relief from the reading
and writing, reading and writing... Thus, what the exact contribution of the actual
course to my future career -as opposed to solitary study- will be remains to be seen.
myself some actual paid work of a similar kind. As to the scientific value of the
present work is concerned I am now slightly sceptical. It has been mostly my own
persistence in the fact that I have been on the trail of something extremely important
all along which has at times perhaps lead me to forget that this is still only an MSc
thesis. But indeed, if my work does gather interest beyond merely achieving a passing
grade from the powers that be then that is just great. Here, I was actually going to
launch into the politics of the how and why we do science as we do it and maybe we
should do it differently, but after all the work that has gone into the thesis proper I
effective forum for heated commentary about wasting the taxpayers’ money on
useless research etc. anyway. I think my take-home message would be that the social
nature and context of research should be taken into account more. This should be
done both in terms of less isolation when studying as well as in deciding upon what
kinds of research can actually bear valuable fruit even if only conducted by a student
57
REFERENCES
Deutsch, M. (1960). The effect of motivational orientation upon trust and suspicion.
Human Relations, 13, 123-139.
Fine, G. A. & Holyfield, L. (1996). Secrecy, trust and dangerous leisure: Generating
group cohesion in voluntary organizations. Social Psychology Quarterly,
59(1), 22-38.
Fukuyama, F. (1995). Trust: The social virtues and the creation of prosperity.
London: Hamish Hamilton.
Gambetta, D. (1988). Can we trust trust? In Gambetta, D. (Ed.) Trust: Making and Breaking
Cooperative Relations, pp. 213-237. New York: Basil Blackwell.
58
Gurtman, M. B. (1992). Trust, distrust and interpersonal problems: A circumplex
analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 989-1002.
Hosmer, L. T. (1995). Trust: The connecting link between organizational theory and
philosophical ethics. Academy of Management Review, 20, 379-403.
Lewicki, R. J., McAllister, D. J. & Bies, R. J. (1998). Trust and distrust: New
relationships and realities. Academy of Management Review, 23, 438-458.
Lewis, J. D. & Weigert, A. (1985). Trust as a social reality. Social Forces, 63(4), 967-
985.
Luhmann, N. (1979). Trust and Power. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons.
Maio, G. R., Esses, V. M. (2001). The need for affect: Individual differences in the
motivation to approach or avoid emotions. Journal of Personality, 69(4), 583-
615.
59
Maslach, C. & Jackson, S. E. (1986). Maslach Burnout Inventory. (2nd ed.).
Consulting Psychologists Press, Inc.
Olweus, D. (1993). Bullying at School: What We Know and What We Can Do.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Ostrom, E., Walker, J. (Eds.) (2003). Trust and Reciprocity: Interdisciplinary Lessons
from Experimental Research. London: Russell Sage Foundation.
Pagden, A. (1988). The Destruction of Trust and its Economic Consequences in the Case of
Eighteenth-century Naples. In Gambetta, D. (Ed.) Trust: Making and Breaking
Cooperative Relations, pp. 127-141.
Rosenberg, M. (1965). Society and the adolescent self image. Princeton, New Jersey:
Princeton University Press.
Rotenberg, K. J. (1984). Sex Differences in Children’s Trust in Peers. Sex Roles, 11,
953-957.
Rotter, J. B. (1967). A new scale for the measurement of interpersonal trust. Journal
of Personality, 35, 651-665.
60
Rousseau, D. M., Sitkin, S. B., Burt, R. S. & Camerer, C. (1998). Not so different at
all: A cross-discipline view of trust. Academy of Management Review, 23(3),
393-404.
Schutte, N. S., Malouff, J. M., Hall, L. E., Haggerty, D. J., Cooper, J. T. Golden, C. J.,
Dornheim, L. (1998). Development and validation of a measure of emotional
intelligence. Personality and Individual Differences, 25, 167-177.
61
NOTES
1
Although one can easily imagine diverse arrangements regarding the time of
resolution being made either totally explicit or only implied, the trustee has to have
some conception of the time frame involved. This can vary between say: “I will return
this book in two weeks” and “I will return this book when I have read it”.
2
It should be noted that the term ‘information’, as used in this context, should be
62