physics.bgsu.edu_p433_Spacetime7.html

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 20

9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.

html

Back to the coure home page.

Back to Table of Contents.

Chapter 7
Newton: His Life and Times
Isaac Newton was born in 1642, the year Galileo Galilei died, and he died in 1727. The range of Newton's
activity was far reaching. Not only was he an eminent scientist, but he was also interested in biblical criticism
and, later in life, he became a functionary in the British government as head of the Royal Mint. The last 22 years
of his life he was the president of the Royal Society, the epitome of establishment science.

His scientific achievements are indeed impressive. By the time he was 24 years old, he had made three
discoveries, any one of which would have garnered him a Nobel Prize, had such an institution been in effect at
the time. The year before, he had discovered the binomial theorem. Newton's own recollection of these days,
written in 1718, is that: In the beginning of the year 1665 I found the method of approximating series and the
rule for reducing any dignity [power] of any binomial into such a series. [The Binomial Theorem] The same year
in May I found the method of tangents of Gregory and Slusius, and in November had the direct method of
fluxions [the differential calculus] and in the next year [1666] in January had the theory of colors [Newton's
Theory of Colors] and in May following I had entrance into the inverse method of fluxions [the integral
calculus]. And the same year I began to think of gravity extending to the orb of the moon . . . All this was in the
two plague years of 1665 and 1666, for in those days I was in the prime of my age for invention and minded
Mathematics and Philosophy more than at any time since. (Hall, 1980, pp. llf.)

Later biographers of Newton were to refer to the year 1666, when Newton was 24, as the Annus Mirabilis, "the
marvelous year." In that year, the plague broke out in London forcing Newton to retire to Lincolnshire where he
spent his time in reflection and experimentation. Newton's theme developed his theory that light had a "mixed
nature," that is, that white light was a combination of distinct colored rays which could be decomposed by a
prism. The simple and elegant experiments upon which this conclusion was based were published in the
Philosophical Transactions in 1672. Newton's views were the source of much dispute among his contemporaries,
and Newton, who was a very private man, was led to be very cautious about what he would commit himself to
publicly (For a discussion of 17th century optics and the controversy over Newton's views, see Sabra, 1967.).

The second major achievement of Newton's during this period was the invention of the calculus. From antiquity,
many mathematicians had discovered various rules for calculating the areas and volumes of special objects, such
as the sphere and the cone. Archimedes, for example, discussed several methods for estimating the volumes of
various regularly shaped objects and also for estimating the areas of conic sections. These rules for calculating
areas and volumes form the basis of a rudimentary integral calculus. Newton's contribution was to codify these
methods into a single unified comprehensive method which could be applied generally, and not merely to special
cases. He also worked on general methods for calculating the rates at which functions change. Again, prior to
Newton's time, special rules had been developed for calculating rates of change for special functions. Newton's
contribution, again, was to provide a codified systematization of these rules and to formulate a general procedure
whereby rates of change could be calculated, in principle, for any arbitrary functional formula. Although Newton
did this in 1666, when he was 24, he did not publish the results or suggest to anyone that he had accomplished
these tasks until much later. This hesitancy on his part led to a bitter priority dispute between Gottfired Wilhelm
Leibniz and himself. Leibniz, of whom we will say more in the next chapter, developed and published his own
version of the calculus before Newton. Leibniz had access to some of Newton's correspondence in 1676, and
later, Newton tried to establish that Leibniz had stolen the basic idea of the calculus from him. This led to a bitter
priority dispute which raged from 1710 to Leibniz's death in 1717, and which spilled over into a dispute about
fundamental philosophical principles and about the nature of space and time. The general consensus today is that

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 1/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

the calculus was developed independently by both Leibniz and Newton (a recent book by A.R. Hall, 1980, is a
detailed study of the dispute).

Newton's third basic discovery was his conjecture that the moon was held in its orbit by gravity, i.e., by the same
force that pulled apples to the earth was also pulling the moon to the earth. This was a key idea in Newton's
subsequent development of the principles of classical mechanics. Among other things, it marked the end of the
Aristotelian model which had divided the universe into two parts, the heavens and the sub-lunar realm, each
governed by its own set of laws. Newton's insight eventually led him to formulate a theory of mechanics which
postulated one set of laws for all mechanical phenomena anywhere in the universe.

Again, Newton was hesitant to publish his results and, in fact, he did not mention them to anyone for another 20
years. Various explanations for Newton's reticence have been offered. The standard story is that Newton was
worried about the fact that the predictions of his theory did not agree closely enough with the actual measured
orbital velocities and positions of the moon. The mistake turned out to be an error in the measurement of the size
of the earth rather that an error in Newton's mechanics. Even so, the treatment of the motion of the moon
remained incomplete even in the published version of Newton's theory, The Mathematical Principles of Natural
Philosophy [Principia].

Newton was moved to publish his views in response to a question from the astronomer Edmond Halley, who was
the clerk of the newly formed Royal Society of London. Halley served as a go-between communicating results
from one scientist or philosopher to another (in those days communications were difficult and there were few
journals). I.B. Cohen gives the following account of what happened: The history of the Principia begins with a
definite event: a trip from London to Cambridge to see Newton, made by Edmond Halley, one of the secretaries
of the Royal Society, famous today primarily for his contributions to astronomy and for the comet named after
him, but then also considered an able geometer. The date is 1684, presumably August. Newton, aged 41, is
Lucasian Professor of Mathematics at Cambridge and a fellow of Trinity College, known at large for his
published discoveries concerning light and color, but admired by the cognoscenti for his work in mathematics
(not as yet published, but to some degree circulated in manuscript) and his grasp of the fundamentals of
dynamics. During the visit, Halley asks Newton what path the planets would describe if they were continually
attracted by the sun with a force varying inversely as the square of the distance. Newton replies that the path
would be an ellipse. This is not a mere guess on Newton's part, but a result he has obtained by mathematics, a
proved statement. Newton--to continue with the story--cannot lay his hands on the calculation,' but promises to
send it to Halley in London. He reworks the material and composes a short tract which Edward Paget takes to
London to give Halley. On reading it. Halley gets so excited that he returns to Cambridge to see Newton once
again. One effect of his visit is that Newton promises to make public his work. He accordingly sends a tract
(presumably the one previously shown to Halley) to the Royal Society. Encouraged by Halley, and by the warm
commendations of the Royal Society, Newton eventually completes a manuscript for publication. Such are the
beginnings of the Principia. (Cohen, 197~, 47)

The Principia is an axiomatic treatment of the principles of mechanics. In it, Newton starts out by laying down
certain definitions and assuming certain postulates, the "three laws of motion." From these laws and the
definitions, Newton deduced a number of theorems concerning the motions of various bodies and the forces
under which they were acting. Despite the fact that Newton had invented the calculus, he did not use the calculus
in writing the Principia, but rather wrote in the geometrical style which was more familiar to his contemporaries.
The result is that all the proofs in the Principia are done in what appears to us today to be a tedious and obscure
manner. Even so, the Principia is a difficult book, and was only slowly accepted by other natural scientists,
especially those who worked outside England. Newton was an extremely complex person. He never married, nor
is there any indication that he had much to do with women at all. He was involved in several controversies about
scientific priority during his lifetime. He was involved in a bitter dispute which the physicist Robert Hooke on
the question of who had first discovered that the gravitational force was an inverse square law. Finally, there
were the bitter disputes with Leibniz. It started with a dispute over priority with respect to the invention of the
calculus. Leibniz then vigorously challenged Newton's conception of space and time and, in particular, his
analysis of gravity, which, for Leibniz, amounted to the reintroduction into physics of occult qualities. This latter
dispute produced a correspondence between Leibniz and a spokesman for Newton, Samuel Clarke, which

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 2/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

continued from 1713 to Leibniz's death in 1717. After Leibniz's death, it was published and is known today as
the Leibniz-Clarke correspondence (see Alexander, 1J56).

Newton, as is characteristic of many great men, was both arrogant and modest. He once compared himself to a
small boy playing on the shore by an ocean of truths only some of which he had explored. In a letter to Hooke,
Newton said, "If I have seen farther [than my fellow man] it is because I have stood on the shoulders of Giants."
Hooke was supposed to get the impression that he was perhaps one of the giants on whose shoulders Newton
stood.

In 1703, Newton became the president of the Royal Society, over which he reigned for the next 24 years until his
death in 1727 (see Westfall, 1980, for the most definitive biography of Newton).

II. The Newtonian System

Before discussing the Newtonian concepts of space and time, we should try to get clear about the Newtonian
system itself. What Newton developed in the Principia was to serve as the foundation of classical mechanics
until the 20th century, but although widely acclaimed when it was first published, it did not command immediate
universal consent. When Newton began to write the Principia in 1684, 61 years had passed since Galilei had
called for a mathematical representation of natural phenomena (Drake, 1956, 237ff~. Describing natural
phenomena in mathematical terms is one task; explaining those phenomena by means of mathematical principles
is another. Galilei had himself produced, of course, several mathematical laws or principles, among them, the
law of falling bodies: s = 1 /2 gt2 which related the distance (s) that an object falls in a time (t), where (g) is the
acceleration due to gravity. The problem with Galilei's approach is that it is too particular. The law of falling
bodies which Galilei formulated is restricted in several ways:

(l) it deals only with freely falling bodies;

(2) it deals with the motion under the influence of one special force, gravity;

(3) it assumes that the force of gravity is a constant.

None of this is meant to take anything away from the magnitude of Galilei's achievement which was great
indeed, but only to illustrate Galilei's approach, which was to formulate particular principles for particular
phenomena. If a full fledged mathematical philosophy was to develop, however, it was clear to some of Galilei's
contemporaries that a more general approach was required (see the discussion in chapter 6, pp.6-43f). Descartes,
in particular, argued that what was needed was a set of general mathematical principles which applied to all
motions under any circumstances. Inspired by the deductive ideal of Euclidean geometry, Descartes hoped to
produce a small set of mathematical principles of natural phenomena (corresponding to Euclid's axioms) from
which descriptions of all natural phenomena could be deduced (corresponding to Euclid's theorems). He
proceeded to do so and, in 1644, he produced a list of 3 laws of nature and 7 rules of impact which formed the
basis of what became known as Cartesian physics. The laws are:

FIRST LAW: Each thing, in so far as in it lies, always perseveres in the same state,
and when once moved, always continues to move.

SECOND LAW: Every motion in itself is rectilinear, and therefore things which are
moved circularly always tend to recede from the center of the circle which they
describe.

THIRD LAW: If a moved body collides with another, then if it has less force to
continue in a straight line than the other body has to resist it, it will be deflected in the
opposite direction and, retaining its own motion, will lose only the direction of its

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 3/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

motion. If it has a greater force, then it will move the other body along with itself and
will give as much of its motion to that other bodies as it loses.
The rules of impact are:

RULE (l) If two bodies B and C are completely equal and are moved with equal velocity, B from right to
left and C from left to right, then when they collide, they are reflected and afterward continue to be
moved, B toward the right and C toward the left, without losing any part of their velocities.

RULE (2) If B is slightly larger than C, and the other conditions above still hold, then only C is reflected
and both bodies are moved toward the left with the same velocity.

RULE (3) If they are equal in size, but B is moving slightly faster than C, then not only do they both
continue to be moved toward the left but also B transmits to C part of its velocity by which it exceeds C.
Thus, if B originally possessed six degrees of velocity and C only four, then after the collision they both
tend toward the left with five degrees of velocity.

RULE (4) If C is completely at rest and is slightly larger than B, then no matter how fast B is moved
toward C, it will never move C but will be repelled by C in the opposite direction. For a body at rest gives
more resistance to a larger velocity than to a smaller one in proportion to the excess of the one velocity
over the other. Therefore there is always a greater force in C to resist than in B to impel.

RULE (5) If C is at rest and is smaller than B, then no matter how slowly B is moved toward C, it will
move C along with itself by transferring part of its motion to C so that they are both moved with equal
velocity. If B is twice as large as C, it transfers a third of its motion to C because a third part of the motion
moves the body C as fast as the two remaining parts move the body B which is twice as large. And thus,
after B has collided with C, B is moved one third slower than it was before, that is, it requires the same
time to be moved through a space of three feet. In the same way if B were three times larger than C, it
would transfer a fourth part of its motion to C, etc.

RULE (6) If C is at rest and is exactly equal to B, which is moved toward C, then C is partially impelled
by B and partially repels B in the opposite direction. Thus, if B moves toward C with four degrees of
velocity, it transfers one degree to C and is reflected in the opposite direction with the remaining three
degrees.

RULE (7) Let B and C be moved in the same direction with C moving more slowly and B following C
with a greater velocity so that they collide. Further, let C be greater than B, but the excess of velocity in B
is greater than the excess of magnitude in C. Then B will transfer as much of its motion to C so that they
are both moved afterward with equal velocity and in the same direction. On the other hand, if the excess of
velocity in B is less than the excess of magnitude in C, then B is reflected in the opposite direction and
retains all of its motion. These excesses are computed as follows. If C is twice as large as B but B is not
moved twice as fast as C, then B does not impel C but is reflected in the opposite direction. But if B is
moved more than twice as fast as C, then B impels C. For example, if C has only two degrees of velocity
and B has five, then C acquires two degrees from B which, when transferred into C, become only one
degree since C is twice as large as B. And thus the two bodies B and C are each moved afterward with
three degrees of velocity. And other cases must be evaluated in the same way.

These things need no proof because they are clear in themselves. (The laws and rules first appeared in The
Principles of Philosophy which appeared in Latin in 1644. These versions are cited from Blackwell, 1966. For a
standard Cartesian text of the times see Rohault, 1969.)

When integrated with Descartes' dualistic philosophy, Cartesianism seemed to provide the promise of a unified
philosophical approach to the world which could replace the weakened and discredited Aristotelian philosophy.
Newton's own ideas about physics were developed, in part, in reaction to the principles of Cartesian physics. As

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 4/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

Newton and other contemporaries saw, there are a number of difficulties with interpreting and applying
Descartes' physical laws and rules.

(l) First, there is a problem about the relation between the laws and rules. The rules are supposed to be derivable
from the laws, but how this is to be accomplished is by no means clear. In addition, the system fails to have the
required generality. The rules, which do all the actual work, apply only to special cases. The laws, of course, are
general, but do not seem to be readily applicable.

(2) Many of the concepts that appear in both the laws and the rules are unclear. Descartes never provides
unambiguous and clear cut rules for interpreting such terms as "force," "quantity of motion," and "resistance."
Without such guidelines, the applicability of the rules to particular cases if not clear.

(3) Despite the Cartesian goal of a mathematical physics, Descartes' principles are not very mathematical.

(4) Where the rules to admit of clear mathematical interpretation, they are often wrong. Consider RULE (4), for
example. If it were correct, then a speeding bullet would not be able to move a heavier, stationary object. But
moving bullets are quite efficient at doing just that, so RULE (4) cannot be right as it stands.

(5) A deeper problem is that there is no systematic role for the concept of relative motion in Cartesian physics.
This can be seen quite clearly by reflecting on the phrase "velocity in B," e.g., as it appears in RULE (7). A
careful reading of the rules makes it clear that, for Descartes, velocity is an absolute property of a body. This
contradicts the Galilean principle of relativity (of which more below; see p.7--45f). Newton saw the failure of
Cartesian physics to do justice to the relational character of motion as a fundamental error (For discussion of
these criticisms and others, see Blackwell, 1966).

Faced with these difficulties, and given the powerful mathematical tools which he had developed, Newton set
out to produce a better set of mathematical principles. Having produced it, it was widely acclaimed by some
(e.g., Halley, and, in general, the English scientists) and rejected by others (e.g., Leibniz, and, in general, the
continental physicists, although there were notable exceptions). The result was that the Newtonian system
struggled with the Cartesian system into the 1700's. Well before 1750, however, almost all (respectable)
physicists were Newtonians.

Essentially, Newton's theory is a theory of particle mechanics, that is, a theory which describes and predicts the
behavior of particles and particle systems as they evolve through time. The immense success of the Newtonian
system in explaining not only the motion of the planets, but also the motion of pendula, the oscillation of
springs, and a whole host of other physical phenomena led certain investigators to think that the principles of
Newtonian mechanics held the ultimate key to the understanding of all physical phenomena. In the 18th century
this contributed to the development of a movement which held, in effect: every natural system is a Newtonian
particle system. The ideal was to reduce all branches of physical knowledge to Newtonian mechanics. The ideal
remained only an ideal as one field after another in the l9th century failed to be reduced to Newtonian
mechanics, until, in the 20th century, the development of the theories of relativity and quantum mechanics
superseded Newtonian mechanics itself.

Newton's theory rests on three laws of motion plus a law of gravitational attraction. The three laws of motion are
set forth at the beginning of Book 1 of the Principia, "The Motion of Bodies." The law of gravity appears in
Book III. "The System of the World." The laws are:

LAW I: The Principle of Inertia Every body continues in its state of rest, or of
uniform motion [= constant velocity] in a right [= straight] line, unless it is compelled
to change that state by forces impressed upon it.
Compare this principle to the first two laws of the Cartesian system. The content of the two formulations
(Newton's and Descartes') is the same but Newton's is more readily applicable (see the next law). On the
basis of this similarity, Descartes is credited with having anticipated the principle of inertia.
https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 5/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

LAW II. The Definition of Force The change of motion is proportional to the motive
force impressed; and is made in the direction of the light [straight] line in which the
force is impressed.

This principle can be given a precise mathematical formulation:

F mv where "F" is the impressed force, and "mv" is the motion of the body. Another key difference
between Descartes and Newton appears here. For Newton, the key kinematic (i.e., dealing with motion)
concept is acceleration (= rate of change of velocity v), whereas for Descartes, as a perusal of his rule
shows, the key kinematic concept is velocity.

LAW III: The Action--Reaction Principle To every action there is always opposed an
equal reaction; or the mutual actions of two bodies on each other are always equal,
and directed to contrary parts.
What this means, in effect, is that if Jones stands on the Earth, Jones exerts a force on the Earth which is equal
and opposite to the force which the Earth exerts on Jones.

In Book III, Proposition VII, Theorem VII concerning the gravitational attraction that all bodies were postulated
to have for each other, Newton writes That there is a power of gravity pertaining to all bodies, proportional to the
several quantities of matter which they contain.

COROLLARY II: The force of gravity towards the several equal particles of any body varies inversely as the
square of the distance of places from the particles.

The statement and corollary can be formulated as follows:

F = G M M' /r^2

where "F" is the force of gravitational attraction between two particles or bodies A and B, "G" is a universal
constant, "M" is the mass of body A, "M" is the mass of body B, and "r^2" is the square of the distance
separating the particles or the center of masses of the two bodies.

The three laws form the foundation of Newton's theory of particle mechanics. From these first principles, the
motion and behaviors of a large number of physical systems can be predicated and described with great
accuracy.

As we said before, the great power and enormous success of the Newtonian system suggested to many people
that the entire universe was a huge mechanism each part of which could be explained completely and with great
precision by these mechanical principles. Although the approach was enormously successful, it was never
completely successful. From the very beginning, there were questions about some of the fundamental concepts
upon which the Newtonian system was based. Newton's view that space and time were an absolute background
for the mechanical motions described and explained by the theory was challenged by Leibniz and George
Berkeley.

Newton's conception of gravity was also challenged. Leibniz saw the Newtonian concept of gravity, which
involved forces acting on bodies which were separated from one another (action at a distance), as an appeal to
"occult qualities," that is, to mysterious "I-know-not-whats" which were being invoked by Newton to account for
physical phenomena. As such, Leibniz saw it as a reversion to the discredited approach of the medieval
philosophers. The Cartesian program, which Leibniz followed, had as its aim the explanation of the motion of
bodies solely in terms of contact forces, on the plausible ground that the influence of one body on another was
more "intelligible" if the bodies were in contact but more or less mysterious if they were not. In his public
response to these criticisms, Newton distinguished between the mathematical description of gravitational

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 6/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

phenomena (the Law of Gravity) from an interpretation or explanation of what constituted the essence of gravity.
In the General Scholium to Book III, added to the second edition, Newton writes:

Hitherto we have explained the phenomena of the heavens and of the sea by the power of gravity, but have not
yet assigned the cause of this power. This is certain, that it must proceed from a cause that penetrates to the very
centers of the sun and planets, without suffering the least dimunition of its force; that operates not according to
the quantity of the surfaces of the particles upon which it acts (as mechanical causes used to do [a reference to
Descartes and his view that the important quantity was the size and not the mass of a body?]), but according to
the solid matter which they contain, and propagates its virtue on all sides to immense distances, decreasing
always as the inverse square of the distances. . . hitherto I have not been able to discover the cause of those
properties of gravity from phenomena, and I frame no hypotheses [hypotheses non fingo]; for whatever is not
deduced from the phenomena is to be called an hypothesis; and hypotheses, whether of occult qualities or
mechanical, have no place in experimental philosophy. In this philosophy particular propositions are inferred
from the phenomena, and afterwards rendered general by induction. Thus it was the impenetrability, the mobility,
and the impulsive force of bodies, and the laws of motion and of gravitation, were discovered. And to us it was
enough that gravity does really exist [as evidenced by its effects], and act according to the laws which we have
explained, and abundantly serves to account for all the motions of the celestial bodies, and of our sea [compare
with Galilei]. (Newton, 1962, pp. 546f.)

This is Newton's public face. Privately, in a letter to Richard Bentley, written February 25, 1692-1693, but
unpublished until much later, Newton wrote: It is inconceivable that inanimate brute matter, should, without the
mediation of something else, which is not material, operate upon and affect other matter without mutual contact,
as it must be, if gravitation, in the sense of epicurus be essential and inherent in it. And this is one reason why I
desired you would not ascribe innate gravity to me. That gravity should be innate, inherent, and essential to
matter, so that one body may act upon another at a distance through a vacuum, without further mediation of
anything else, by and through which their action and force may be conveyed from one to another, is to me so
great an absurdity, that I believe no man, who has in philosophical matters a competent faculty of thinking, could
ever fall into it. Gravity must be caused by an agent acting constantly according to certain laws; but whether this
agent be material or immaterial, I left to the consideration of my readers. (Newton, 1953, p. 54)

What are we to make of this? The point is that Newton is trying to carefully distinguish between the
mathematical expression of a law and its explanation. What he has produced, and all that a working physicist
needs, is a mathematical formulation of the effect of gravity. This is what he uses to describe and predict the
motion of the heavenly bodies. He is with Galilei on this point in urging that the first concern of the physicist
should be the production of mathematical laws of nature. What hypothetical understanding of these laws we
have is of secondary concern. Nevertheless, Newton is unhappy with this state of affairs. He is working in the
"contact force" traditional of 17th century physics and is willing to admit, in private at least, that there is
something more that needs to be said about gravity. What needs to be said, however, is not, in Newton's view,
part of the mathematical principles of natural philosophy. In his heart of hearts, Newton hoped that his readers
would be led to the conclusion that the causal agent producing gravity was, ultimately, God. For Newton, gravity
and the principles of the Principia in general were as much evidence of God's working in the universe as the
Scriptures.

III. Newtonian Space and Time

We turn now to a consideration of the general characteristics of Newton's view of space and time. Although
Newton does define some of the basic terms that he employs, for example, "mass," "force," and "acceleration,"
he does not define "time," "space," "place," and "motion" since he takes these "as being well known to all." In
the Scholium to the definitions preceding Book I, however, Newton does offer some remarks about time, space,
place and motion. In particular, he is concerned to distinguish between absolute, true, or mathematical time
(space~, on the one hand, and relative, apparent or common time (space), on the other. Relative space, relative
time, and relative motions are spaces, times and motions which are measurable by us. . All actual measurement,
for Newton, involves comparing one thing with another. Thus, when one uses a measuring tape to determine that
a room, say, is 12 feet wide, 20 feet long and 8 feet high, what one has determined is a relative space, since the
measured space of the room is what it is in virtue of its relation to the tape as standard. The measurement of time
https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 7/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

involves comparing the duration of a process or activity to the duration of an interval ticked off by our clocks.
Similarly, objects are determined to be in motion only if they move with respect to something or other.

However, in addition to these relative measures, Newton believed and argued for the existence of Absolute
space, Absolute time, and Absolute motions. These absolute quantities are insensible, that is, they cannot be
directly detected by human observers, yet Newton felt that they had to exist. The plausibility and necessity of
these absolutes was attacked vehemently by relationalist critics of Newton such as Leibniz and Berkeley (see the
discussion in the next chapter). We discuss Newton's reasons for holding that such absolutes did exist in the
course of fitting his views on space and time into our categorical framework.

1. Absolute space and absolute time are qualitatively homogeneous.

In the Scholium, Newton says, "Absolute space, in its own nature, without relation to anything external, remains
always similar and immovable." That absolute space "remains always similar" is just to say that its parts are
qualitatively homogeneous.

Even so, in an unpublished manuscript, Newton puts the case more strongly: "The parts of duration and space
are only understood to be the same as they really are because of their mutual order and position; nor do they
have any hint of individuality apart from the order and position which consequently cannot be altered (Hall and
Hall, 1962, p. 136)." This contrasts with the Aristotelian view, at least with respect to space, since Aristotle,
recall, held that space was qualitatively heterogeneous.

2. Absolute space (time) is infinite (Eternal).

Newton's arguments for the infinite extension of space and time (duration) are both conceptual and theological in
nature. Newton says: Space extends indefinitely to all directions. For we cannot imagine any limit anywhere
without at the same time imagining that there is a space beyond it. And hence all straight lines, paraboloids,
hyperboloids, and all cones and cylinders and other figures of the same kind continue to infinity and are bounded
nowhere, even though they are crossed here and there by lines and surfaces of all kinds extending transversely,
and with them form segments of figures in all directions. (Hall and Hall, 1962, pp. 133-134)

Similarly, in the same manuscript, Newton argues that we cannot think "that there is no duration" (Hall and Hall,
1962, p. 137). The first quotation indicates that Newton is thinking of physical space as a realization of a three-
dimensional Euclidean space. In addition, Newton seems to have some theological reason for thinking that space
is infinite in extent and eternal in duration (this latter claim, that space is eternal in duration entails, of course,
that duration is itself eternal). According to this same manuscript, Newton held the view that space and time
were properties of being qua being, by which he meant that no being could exist which was not related to space
and time in some way. Since Newton believed that God was an eternal and infinite being, it followed that space
must be infinite in extent and time (or duration) infinite in extent as well (Hall and Hall, 1962, p. 136).

These unpublished remarks of Newton are somewhat obscure and confusing. However, even the published
Principia contains theological considerations with respect to the nature of space and time. For example, in the
General Scholium to Book III, Newton writes: . . From his true dominion it follows that the true God is a living,
intelligent, and powerful Being; and from his other perfections, that he is supreme, or most perfect. He is eternal
and infinite, omnipotent and omniscient; that is, his duration reaches from eternity to eternity; his presence from
infinity to infinity; he governs all things, and knows all things that are or can be done. He is not eternity and
infinity, but eternal and infinite; He is not duration or space, but He endures and is present. He endures forever,
and is everywhere present; and, by existing always and everywhere, he constitutes duration and space. Since
every particle of space is always, and every indivisible moment of duration is everywhere, certainly the Maker
and Lord of all things can not be never and no where. (Newton, 1962, p. 545)

3. Space and Time are Continuous.

The continuity of time follows from Newton's assertion in the Scholium that "Absolute, true, and mathematical
time, of itself, and of its own nature, flows equally without relation to any thing external . . .." That Newton takes
https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 8/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

absolute time to "flow equably" is a good indication that he thought that the flow of time was continuous and not
discrete. We must, of course, remember that, in Newton's time, to say that an interval was continuous was to say
that it was dense but not point-like.

If we are correct in thinking that Newton implicitly took physical space to be a realization of 3-dimensional
Euclidean space, then the continuity (as opposed to discreteness) of space follows. This is so because, as we
noted earlier in our discussion of Zeno's paradoxes, certain theorems which are true of Euclidean spaces (and,
hence, by hypothesis, of physical space), e.g., the Pythagorean theorem, fail to hold for discrete spaces.

4a. Absolute space is isotropic.

The isotropy of absolute space follows from Newton's treatment of absolute space as an infinite, qualitatively
homogeneous continuum. Given that all the spatial points are qualitatively identical, there is no way for certain
directions, as such, to be preferred. This contrasts, recall, with the Aristotelian position which, because space was
finite and because of Aristotle's doctrine of natural places, treated space as anisotropic (i.e., with intrinsic
preferred directions).

4b. Absolute time is anisotropic.

Newton does not have anything to say about this particular property of time, taking it, one might suppose, as one
of those properties of time which is "well known to all." It might be well to remind ourselveg at this point that
the anisotropy of time is not a feature which is assumed by or derivable from the Newtonian laws of mechanics.
The laws of mechanics for particles or particle systems ~LAWS I-III] are symmetric with respect to time. This
means, in effect, that the laws of mechanics are indifferent to whether mechanical processes proceed in one
temporal direction or the other; were time to somehow "run backwards" (from the "future" to the "past"), the
laws of mechanics would not be violated. Hence, no mechanical experiment could detect such a "time reversal."
From the point of view of mechanics, then, the "directionality" of time is somewhat of a mystery. Some people
have tried to account for the unidirectionality of time by appealing to the laws of thermodynamics. (For such an
attempt, see Reichenbach 1956. For other discussions, see Grunbaum, 1973 and van Fraassen, 1970. There is an
extensive bibliography on the topic in Gale, 1967. For reservations about the thermodynamic approach, see
Melhberg, 1980.)

5. Absolute space and absolute time are object independent.

What this means is that even if there were no objects, absolute space would still exist as a receptacle or container
within which objects could be placed. Similarly, absolute time exists and would exist even if there were nothing
changing nor any object enduring. Thus, Newton says: ...Although we can possibly imagine that there is nothing
in space, yet we cannot think that space does not exist, just as we cannot think that there is no duration, even
though it would be possible to suppose that nothing whatever endures. (Hall and Hall, 1962, p. 137)

These sentiments are expressed by Newton in the Scholium to the definitions in the Principia itself. There
Newton says, "Absolute, true, and mathematical time, of itself, and from its own nature, flows equably without
relation to anything external, . . .." Also, "absolute space, in its own nature, without relation to anything external,
remains always similar and immovable." [Our emphasis]

6. Absolute space and absolute time are mind independent.

It is clear from the comments on absolute space and time in the Scholium that just as absolute space and time are
not dependent for their existence on the existence of objects or processes, so they are not dependent for their
existence on their being thought by some mind.

7. Absolute space and absolute time are immutable.

With respect to absolute time, immutability involves two aspects: (l) absolute time flows equably. What this
amounts to is that absolute time is "ticking off" at a regular rate so that two identical processes which occur over

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 9/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

different stretches of time take the same amount of absolute time to occur. We ignore, for the moment, the
complications that arise if we ask how one could know this to be the case given that absolute temporal intervals
are, by Newton's own definition, inaccessible to measurement; and, (2) the parts "of duration," i.e., individual
moments, are fixed in their relative order to one another in some intrinsic way. What this means is that, if a set of
successive events (each of which is occurring at a different instant of absolute time) were ordered from earlier to
later, then this order from earlier to later is unique. This may seem so obviously true about physical time that
even to say it is to invite confusion, but, in fact, the Special and General Theories of Relativity entail that it is
false. It is, therefore, a significant feature of the Newtonian view.

In fact, it is possible, on Newton's theory, to define a Universal Time. By this we mean a time which, if it could
be measured, would be valid for all observers wherever they might be in the universe. If any one observer A
were capable of determining that a certain duration of absolute time had elapsed, then any other observer B who
could make a similar determination would come up with exactly the same values for the elapsed duration of the
interval in question. Of course, Newton admits that such direct measurement is not in practice possible. Even if
there were a clock whose motion was sufficiently equable to serve as a measure of the elapsed absolute duration,
there is no way that anyone could know this to be the case. Nevertheless, all processes which take a certain
amount of time as measured by (against) some other process, also take up a certain amount of absolute time.
This amount of absolute time is the same for any given process for all observers.

In addition, the immutability of absolute time means that it is possible to define an absolute Now. Since the
moments of absolute times are fixed and immutable, it follows that when A says "now," she singles out a
particular definite moment of absolute time. This particular moment (call it "N"~ is the same for all observers in
all places everywhere in the universe. If asked, any one of them would (were they capable of making the
required measurements) agree that A's utterance occurred at absolute time N.

One of the consequences of this is that, for a Newtonian, it is possible to uniquely determine whether two events
are or are not simultaneous, no matter how far apart in space they may occur. Two such events are simultaneous
if and only if they occur at the same instant of absolute time.

We can construct the following model for such a Newtonian universe. Each moment in absolute time defines
what we may call a "simultaneity slice." A simultaneity slice is a set of events and places all considered at the
same moment. If we imagine a camera taking a sequence of instantaneous flash pictures of a process, then each
picture would be analogous to a simultaneity slice of a small portion of the universe. Now imagine that we have
a camera capable of taking an instantaneous 3-dimensional holographic snapshot of the entire universe. Each
snapshot would be a picture of such a simultaneity slice. If we imagine two observers, at different parts of the
universe, each possessing such a cameras will agree exactly for any given moment, i.e., they can be perfectly
superimposed on one another. Thus, when Newton says that the spatial universe endures forever through time,
we can understand this from the picture we have just drawn to mean that corresponding to each moment of
absolute time there is a unique portrait of the universe as a whole. The succession of portraits represents the
unique history of the universe (for a further discussion of this model, see chapter 9). All of this may appear
trivial and commonplace. However, the ~pecial and General Theories of Relativity deny the possible existence
of such portraits and are incompatible with the possibility of an Absolute Now or a Universal Time function.

In saying that absolute space was immutable, Newton was especially concerned about the immobility of parts or
positions of absolute space. In particular, he was concerned with what took to be the disastrous implications of
the Cartesian view that, in identifying space with the bodies that (seemingly~ occupy space, led to the view that
positions or parts of space could move with respect to one another. Since Newton held that one could only
understand motion in terms of objects being first in one place and then in another, if places themselves move,
then after a body has moved from one place to another, we would no longer be in a position to say from where
the motion had started since the original place from which the body moved would have, in the mean time, moved
to where the object was now as well (compare the similar argument by Aristotle discussed in chapter 5, pp. llff).
For Newton, this is just to deny that objects move and to make their motion unintelligible. But, objects do move
and their motion is intelligible, therefore, the Cartesian view is false. The immutability of absolute space allows
absolute space to serve as a framework in terms of which motions can be defined and understood. Without such
a fixed framework, Newton felt that the concept of motion was incoherenL. Although he does not say so and he
https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 10/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

is notparticularly aware of any problems here, Newton's claim that space is immutable can be interpreted in
hindsight to entail that, for Newton, the geometrical structure of the parts of space remains constant through
time. Since Newton was not alive to the possibility that the geometrical structure of physical space could be
other than Euclidean, he could not very well have been concerned about the possibility that the geometrical
structure of physical space could change. But, the Special Theory of Relativity naturally suggests that the
structure of the 4-dimensional complex of space and time together is not Euclidean, and certain models of the
General Theory of Relativity allow for the possibility that the geometrical structure of space itself changes from
moment to moment. Thus, Relativity Theory gives a sense to the claim that space and time (for the structure of
time as well need not be the same from moment to moment or place to place according to the general theory) are
mutable. (For a discussion of alternative geometries in the context of different theories of space and time, see
van Fraassen, 1970, chapter IV.)

8. Absolute space and absolute time are causally inert.

For Newton, space and time are container-like frameworks within which the actions and events of the world take
place. But, space and time themselves do not causally interact with the material or mechanical processes that go
on in the world. Thus, for Newton, for example, the gravitational attraction of two bodies for each other does not
affect and is unaffected by the structure of absolute space and absolute time. This is similar to the sense in which
the structure of a rigid container is not affected by any objects placed in it or processes that occur in it. Again,
this may appear to be a trivial and commonplace fact about physical space but it is not since it will have to be
abandoned when we move to the General Theory of Relativity.

9. Absolute space is a void.

For Newton, absolute space exists independently of the existence of any bodies in it. Therefore, it is possible for
there to be on Newton's view, empty spaces. This again is a non-trivial claim since it is denied by both Descartes
and Leibniz as well as by Aristotle.

It means that not only absolute space but most of the relative space that is observable by us, e.g., the space
between the planets is empty too. This created problems for Newton, as we have seen since it meant that the
gravitational force acting between two planets, for example, had to act over a distance wlth no intermediate
medium. As noted above, Newton was always unhappy about the idea of action-at-a-distance. In the Optics, he
goes so far as to suggest that there might be an omnipresent aether to serve as the medium for the gravitational
force (not to be confused with the l9th century aether which was invented for the transmission of light rays.
Newton had no need for such an optical aether because, on his view, light was composed of a stream of particles
which could just as easily be shot across a void as through a luminiferous aether). Newton never adequately
resolved this problem nor did any subsequent Newtonian. What was needed was a new way of thinking about
gravity which finds its first full expression in Einstein's General Theory of Relativity.

This completes our survey of the general characteristics of Newtonian space and time. We turn now to a
postponed question, namely, why Newton felt it obligatory to distinguish between the relative spaces and times
which were measurable and observable by human beings and absolute space and absolute time which were not.
We have already noted that Newton felt that without such concepts the concept of motion would be
unintelligible, but, in addition, he had a number of experimental arguments which are often interpreted as
intended, by Newton, to support his absolutistic position. III. Newton's Arguments for the Existence Of Absolute
Space and Absolute Time.

A. The Existence of Absolute Time.

With respect to the distinction between absolute time and relative time, Newton has the following to say:
Absolute time, in astronomy, is distinguished from relative, by the equation or the correction of the apparent
time. For the natural days are truly unequal, though they are commonly considered as equal, and used for a
measure of time; astronomers corrected this inequality that they may measure the celestial motions by a more
accurate time. It may be, that there is no such thing as an equable motion, whereby time may be accurately
measured. All motions may be accelerated and regarded, but the flowing of absolute time is not liable to any
https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 11/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

change. . . The duration or perseverance of the existence of things remains the same, whether the motions are
swift or slow, or none at all: and therefore this duration ought to be distinguished from what are only sensible
measures thereof; from which we deduce it, by means of the astronomical equation. The necessity of this
equation, for determining the times of the phenomenon, is evinced as well from the experiments of the pendulum
clock, as by the eclipses of the satellites of Jupiter. (Newton, 1962, PP- 7-8)

Newton is here alluding to the well known fact that different processes which might be used to measure relative
times do not always agree with one another on the times that they determine. This was pointed out earlier in our
discussion of Aristotle (pp. 5-47ff.) and was also mentioned in the context of our discussion of the implications
of the Copernican revolution (pp. 6-67ff). We noted that there are a number of astronomical phenomena which
are periodical and might be used to define or measure time. Unfortunately, the scales determined by these
different measures do not remain synchronized with one another. Thus, one defines a solar day as the time
interval from one local noon to the next. On the other hand, the motion of the moon can be used to define time as
well. The natural unit is the time between two appearances of the new moon which we might call the lunar
month. Since the background stars are, for all practical purposes fixed in relation to one another, we can define a
sidereal day by fixing on a star which is always present in the night sky and defining the sidereal day to be the
time it takes the star to reappear in a given position in the sky from night to night. The problem which gives rise
to what Newton calls "the equation of time" is that these three measurements do not agree with one another. If
we take the time to be measured by the solar day, then the time for a lunar month varies according to the time of
year. Conversely, if we take the lunar month as our standard, then it turns out that the number of solar days varies
from month to month. Similarly, a given number of solar days does not equal an equivalent number of sidereal
days and as time goes on, the discrepancy gets larger and larger. The discrepancies between the solar, lunar and
sidereal standards obey a mathematical equation (which is the equation of time) and by using it Newton thought
one could get closer to the "true" time of which each was an imperfect measure.

In the early part of the 17th century, Galilei had suggested using the periodic motion of a pendulum as a measure
of time. If this is done, then, because the earth in moving around the sun, is not moving in a perfectly circular
orbit, and has its axis tilted with respect to the plane defined by the earth and the sun, the solar days are not equal
in length at different times of the year.

In 1676, the Dutch physicist Ole Roemer had made observations of Jupiter and its moons and had measured the
periods of the Jovian moons by observing them being eclipsed by Jupiter (the referent of Newton's remark about
"eclipses of the satellites of Jupiter. Roemer also used his measurements to conclude that the speed of light was
finite; see the discussion in chapter 10). If one takes the natural solar day as the standard of time, then it turns out
that the periods of Jupiter's moons vary according to the time of year which they are observed. But, this
contradicts one of the fundamental assumptions of Newtonian mechanics, namely, that the motion of one body in
a stable orbit around another is due to the presence of a more or less constant gravitational force. If the times
required to complete one period varied from one time of year to another, this would suggest that there must be
some further force in addition to the gravitational force which was perturbing the motion of the moons.
However, when the periods of the moons were compared with the time as measured by a pendulum clock, no
such discrepancies between periods was observed. This suggests that the pendulum clock is a more "regular"
standard of temporal measurement than the apparent motion of the sun, at least for the purposes of physics.

Newton's conclusion from these discrepancies was that each of these motions or processes gave only an
imperfect measure of some "true" time. This "true" time could be calculated by means of the mathematical
equation he called the equation of time. However, as we pointed out in our earlier discussion of the same subject
(pp. 5--47ff.), there is no need to assume nor any justification for us to conclude that any such measure would be
"more accurate" than any other measure. The fact that we can define a "mean solar day" or something of the sort
just means that we have replaced one standard of measurement by another. But the conclusion that Newton
draws, which is unwarranted, is that such a standard is, in effect, a more equable measure of absolute time.
Newton was treating what is now understood to be a convention as a matter of fact, namely, what the standard
for measuring time should be. We now think there is open to us to choose any number of different processes or
motions as potential standards. We choose our standards usually on the basis of convenience: in this case, the

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 12/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

physics turns out simpler if we choose the pendulum clock over the other choices (and even more convenient for
modern physics if we choose the period of some radiating atom).

B. The Existence of Absolute Space.

With respect to the distinction between absolute space and relative spaces, Newton offers two arguments in the
Principia. One is based on an interpretation of the results of an experiment which Newton conducted and which
can be conducted in any laboratory. It is generally known as "the bucket argument." The other argument is a
"thought experiment" which we will call "the two globe experiment." It is a thought experiment insofar as
Newton asks us to imagine that would be the outcome of an experiment which cannot, in practice, be performed.

(i) Newton's Bucket Experiment.

The bucket experiment is described by Newton as follows: The effects which distinguish absolute from relative
motion are, the forces of receding from the axis of the circular motion. For there are no such forces in a circular
motion purely relative, but in a true and absolute circular motion, they are greater or less, according to the
quantity of the motion. If a vessel, hung by a long cord is strongly twisted, then filled with water, and held at rest
together with the water; thereupon, by the sudden action of another force, it is whirled about in a contrary way,
and while the cord is untwisting itself, the vessel continues for some time in this motion; the surface of the water
will at first be plain, as before the vessel began to move; but after that, the vessel, gradually communicating its
motion to the water, will make it begin sensibly to revolve, and recede by little and little from the middle, and
ascend to the sides of the vessel, forming itself into a concave figure (as I have experienced), and the swifter the
motion becomes, the higher will the water rise, till at least, performing its revolutions in the same times with the
vessel, it becomes relatively at rest in it. This ascent of the water shows its endeavor to recede from the axis of
its motion; and the true and absolute motion of the water, which is here directly contrary to the relative, becomes
known, and may be measured by this endeavor. At first, when the relative motion of the water was greatest, it
produced no endeavor to recede from the axis; the water showed no tendency to the circumference, nor any
ascent towards the side of the vessel, but remained of a plain surface, and therefore its true and circular motion
had not yet begun. But afterwards, when the relative motion of the water had decreased, the ascent thereof
towards the sides of the vessel proved its endeavor to recede from the axis; and this endeavor showed the real
circular motion of the water continually increasing, till it had acquired its greatest quality, when the water rested
relatively in the vessel. And therefore this endeavor does not depend upon any translation of the water in respect
of the ambient bodies, nor can true circular motion be defined by such translation. There is only one real circular
motion of any one revolving body, corresponding to only one power of endeavoring to recede from its axis of
motion, as its proper and adequate effect; but relative motions, in one and the same body, are innumerable,
according to the various relations it bears to external bodies, and, like other relations, are all together destitute of
any real effect, any otherwise then they may perhaps partake of that one only true motion. And therefore in their
system who supposes that our heavens revolving below the sphere of the fixed stars, carry the planets along with
them; to several parts of these heavens and the planets, which are indeed relatively at rest in their heavens do yet
really move. For they range their positions one to another (which never happens to bodies truly at rest), and
being carried together with their heavens,partake of their motions, and as parts of revolving wholes, endeavor to
recede from the axis of their motions. (Newton, 1962, pp. lOf.)

There are at least two interpretations of what Newton is trying to accomplish in this passage. One, which we will
call the standard interpretation has been given its fullest expression in Nagel (1962). It construes the passage as
an attempt by Newton to experimentally prove the existence of absolute space. The second, recently put forward
by Ronald Laymon (1978), urges that Newton is not trying to prove that absolute space exists, but rather is
illustrating one of the consequences of assuming that absolute space does exist, an assumption Laymond thinks
Newton makes on other grounds. We examine both in turn. First the standard interpretation.

a. The Standard Interpretation

On the standard interpretation the essence of Newton's argument is as follows. Absolute time and absolute space,
in and of themselves, are not detectable. But there are detectable phenomena which we may use to infer the
existence of absolute space and absolute time. The "true and absolute circular motion of the water" serves for
https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 13/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

Newton as an indication of the existence of absolute acceleration, i.e., acceleration of bodies with respect to
absolute space. However, the existence of absolute accelerations implies the existence of absolute velocities even
though these latter (absolute velocities) are not directly experimentally detectable. The existence of absolute
velocities follows from the fact that "acceleration" is defined as the rate of change of a velocity. Thus, if a body
has an absolute acceleration, then that acceleration must be the rate of change of some absolute velocity. But, if
there is an absolute velocity, then the body in question must be moving with respect to absolute space. Therefore,
absolute space must exist. This (alleged) inference by Newton has been vigorously challenged. On the standard
interpretation, Newton is guilty of an elementary logical blunder. We turn to a more detailed analysis of the
bucket experiment the stages of which are diagrammed below. [See figure 7-1]

The standard interpretation of Newton's bucket experiment breaks it down into five stages as the accompanying
diagram indicates. Newton's description stops at Stage 3, Stages 4 and 5 are added to give the experiment a
certain symmetry. In Stage 3, the water and the bucket are at rest relative to one another but are both rotating
with respect to the laboratory. Suppose, at this point, the bucket is abruptly stopped. It is now at rest with respect
to the laboratory and the water which is contained therein continues to rotate with respect to both the bucket and
the laboratory. Gradually (actually, fairly quickly) the surface of the water will resume its earlier plain shape as
the rotational motion of the water decreases. The final stage, Stage 5, will put the experimental apparatus back
into the initial condition with the water and the bucket both at rest with respect to one another and with respect to
the surrounding laboratory. The analysis proceeds as follows. Compare Stage 1 with

NEWTON'S BUCKET EXPERIMENT

Stage 1: Water and bucket at rest. Stage 2: The water and the

bucket are acceler-

ating with respect

to one another.

Stage 3: The water and the bucket are Stage 4: The water and bucket are

at rest relative to one another. in relative acceleration,

Both are rotating with respect when the bucket is stopped

to the laboratory. I abruptly.

1~ F~9 1- l'

Stage 5: The water and bucket come to rest with respect to each other and with respect to the laboratory. with
Stage 3 and Stage 2 with Stage 4. In stages 1 and 3, the water and the bucket are relatively at rest with respect to
one another. However, the shape of the water surface in Stage 1 is planer, but in Stage 3 it is concave. Similarly,
in Stages 2 and 4, the water and the bucket are accelerating with respect to one another. Again, in Stage 2 the
surface of the water is planer, while in Stage 4 the surface is concave. The conclusion to be drawn is that the
shape of the water surface is independent of the relative state of motion of the water with respect to the bucket.
What does this mean?

The paraboloidal surface of the water in Stages 3 and 4 is the result of a deformation of the original water
surface in Stage 1. But, bodies do not spontaneously deform themselves. They undergo deformations only in
response to the presence of forces acting upon them. Therefore, the deformation of the water in Stages 3 and 4 is
an indication of the presence of some forces acting on the water during Stages 3 and 4 that were not present
during Stages 1, 2 and 5. Newton's SECOND LAW OF MOTION tells us that forces indicate the presence of
accelerated motion. Since the water surface is deformed, the water must be accelerating with respect to

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 14/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

something. But, with respect to what something is the water being accelerated? There seem to be three possible
alternatives:

(l) The water is accelerating with respect to the bucket.

(2) The water is being accelerated by some objects at a distance from the experimental apparatus, e.g., the fixed
walls of the laboratory or the fixed stars.

(3) The water is rotating with respect to absolute space.

(l) is ruled out by the data of the experiment. Stage 3 indicates that the surface of the water is deformed even
when the water and the bucket are relatively at rest with respect to one another. Thus, the deformation of the
water surface cannot be caused by the relative acceleration of the water with respect to the bucket. (2) is not
ruled out by the data of the experiment but is ruled out by an assumption that Newton made about the inertia of
bodies. The inertia of a body is a measure of its tendency to resist changes in its state of motion (recall Newton's
FIRST LAW). The receding of the water from the rotating axis of the bucket is an inertial effect, that is, its
magnitude is a function of the inertia of the contained water. Newton assumed that the inertia of a body was an
intrinsic non-relational property that the body possessed. As such, any effects due to it could not be a function of
any relationship between the body in question and any other bodies in the universe. Thus, alternative (2), which
asserts that the inertial effects of the motion of the water are a function of its relationship to distant bodies, is
ruled out.

This leaves (3) as the only viable alternative: therefore, absolute space must exist.

Such is a brief outline of the standard interpretation of Newton's bucket experiment (for more details see Nagel,
1962, chapter 8 ). The elementary logical blunder which Newton committed on this view is to think that
alternative (3) followed from the experimental result. In fact, it follows only on the additional assumption that
rules out (2). But this assumption does not follow from the experimental result and can be (and was: see chapter
8) rejected by Ernst Mach in the late 19th century.

b. Laymon's Interpretation

Ronald Laymon has recently (1978) published a paper challenging the standard interpretation on a number of
grounds and proposing an alternative view of what Newton was up to with the bucket.

First of all, the standard interpretation, as we have seen, commits us to saying that Newton made a simple logical
mistake. While it is not uncommon for great men to make mistakes, the mistake Newton is supposed to have
committed is so obvious that it is hard to see how Newton could have failed to see that he was doing so. Perhaps
then he did not make a mistake, in which case the standard interpretation of what Newton was up to might be
wrong. In fact, Laymon argues that it is wrong. The experiment was not designed to prove the existence of
absolute space at all, according to Laymon, because Newton was already committed to the existence of absolute
space on other (primarily theological) grounds. What, then, was the point of the discussion? The experiment,
Laymon says, was designed as an illustration of one effect of accepting the doctrine of absolute space. At best, it
can be construed as an indirect argument supporting the existence of an absolute space which as been postulated
on other grounds. The structure of the argument is alleged to be as follows:

(l) The existence of absolute space entails the bucket result.

(2) The bucket result holds (experimental fact). Therefore,

(3) The existence of absolute space is confirmed.

Such an argument, which is typical of the inductive experimental reasoning of science, does not, of course, prove
that absolute space exists because it does not rule out the possibility that the bucket result might be due to some
other se of circumstances (e.g., the circumstances outlined in alternative (2) of the standard interpretation).

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 15/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

Newton is construed as offering a legitimate confirmatory argument and not as committing a blunder of any
kind.

As supporting evidence for his interpretation, Laymon points out that a careful reading of Newton's text shows
that Stages 4 and ~ of the standard interpretation are embellishments without textual support. In fact, Laymon
argues, the passage is primarily designed as an argument to refute Descartes' theory of true and philosophical
motion." Descartes' definition of "true and philosophical motion" is "the translation of a piece of matter (a body)
from the neighborhood of the bodies immediately touching it, these being regarded as at rest, to the
neighborhood of others." (Laymon, 1978, p. 404) The bucket experiment shows that such a relational view of
motion is not adequate to the dynamical facts revealed by the experimental result. The argument basically is as
follows:

(a) The force acting on a body is proportional to the "real circular motion" of the body. [Both Descartes and
Newton accept this premise, cf., Laymon, 1978, pp. 405ff.]

(b~ The force acting on the water is proportional to the curvature (deformation) of the water surface. [follows
from Newton's FIRST and SFCOND LAWS]

(c) The curvature of the water surface is inversely proportional to the relative local motion of the water with
respect to the bucket. [The Bucket Result]

Therefore,

(d) The real motion of the water is inversely proportional to the relative local motion of the water with respect to
the bucket.

This follows from (a), (b) and (c).

The conclusion (d) contradicts the Cartesian view, implicit in Descartes' definition of true and philosophical
motion, that the real motion of the water is directly proportional to the relative local motion of the water with
respect to the bucket.

Laymon's interpretation is plausible and a close reading of the text does seem to support his view. His
interpretation has the virtue that it absolves Newton of the crime of committing a logical fallacy. One point
against it is the consideration that Newton does not specifically name Descartes as his foil. Why not, if indeed
the bucket is designed as an argument against the Cartesian position? In fact, Descartes' name appears nowhere
in the Principia. The evidence that Descartes is the target rests on indirect evidence: the wording of the bucket
passage is reminiscent of Descartes; and, Newton's notebooks are filled with speculations and queries explicitly
about the Cartesian system (see Laymon, 1978, for a discussion of the evidence). (ii) Newton's Globe
Experiment We turn now to Newton's thought experiment involving the two globes. Newton writes: It is indeed a
matter of great difficulty to discover, and effectually to distinguish, the true [absolute] motions of particular
bodies from the apparent [relative]; because the parts of that immovable [absolute] space, in which those
motions are performed, do by no means come under the observation of our senses. Yet the thing is not altogether
desperate; for we have some arguments to guide us, partly from the apparent motions, which are the differences
of the true motions; partly from the forces, which are causes and effects of the true motions. For instance, if two
globes, kept at a given distance, one from the other by means of a cord that connects them, were revolved about
their common center of gravity, we might, from the tension of the cord discover the endeavor of the globes to
recede from the axis of their motion, and from thence we might compute the quantity of their circular motions.
And then if any equal forces should be impressed at once on the alternate basis of the globes to augment or
diminish their circular motion, from the increase or the decrease of the tension of the cord, we might infer the
increment or decrement of their motions, and hence would be found on what basis those forces ought to be
impressed, that the motions of the globes might be most augmented; that is, we might discover their hindmost
faces, or those which, in the circular motion do follow. And thus we might find both the quantity and the
determination of the circular motion, even in an immense vacuum, where there was nothing external or sensible
with which the globes could be compared. But now, if in that space some remote bodies were placed that kept
https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 16/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

always a given position one to another, as the fixed starsdo in our regions, we would not indeed determine it
from the relative translations of globes among those bodies, whether the motion did belong to the globes or to
the bodies. But if we observed the cord, and found that its tension was that very tension which the motions of the
globes required, we might conclude the motion to be in the globes, and the bodies to be at rest; and then lastly,
from the translation of the globes among the bodies, we should find the determination of their motions. (Newton,
1962, p. 12 [our emphasis])

The underlined section of the cited material is the thought experiment. It is a thought experiment because it
assumes that one could place two globes connected by a string in an immense vacuum and then place, at will,
bodies at immense distances from them. Such an experiment is not possible to perform although we can think
what the consequences might be if we could perform it. Figure 7-2 illustrates the essentials of the experiment.
[See Figure 7-2]

In both cases, a pair of globes connected by a string is situated in a vacuum far from any other bodies. We may
assume that a dynamometer (i.e., a device for measuring the tension in the strings) is attached to the strings
halfway between the two globes. The globe of the outer circle we may take to be some configuration of distant
objects. In case 1, the distant globe is rotating in a clockwise direction with respect to the pair of globes sitting in
the center of the diagram Newton's Globes

Case 1a

F~g. ~

Case 2a

In case 2, the pair of globes in the center is rotating in a counterclockwise direction with respect to the distant
globe. It is obvious that the relative motions represented by the two cases are exactly the same.

Merely by observing relative motions we cannot distinguish case 1 from case 2. However, Newton argues, there
is difference between the two situations: in case 1 there is no measured tension in the string connecting the two
globes; in case 2, there is a measured tension in the string. The tension in the string in case 2 is due, according to
Newton, to the fact that, in case 2, the globes are "really" rotating whereas in case 1, they are only "apparently"
rotating.

This situation seems analogous to the bucket case. We have two cases where the relative motions are the same
but a force appears in one case but not in the other. The existence of this force is an indication that the globes in
case 2 are accelerating with respect to something. By the design of the experiment, the only objects in the
universe are the two globes with their connecting string and dynamometer and the configuration of distant
objects. The accelerations of the two globes with respect to the distant configuration of objects is the same in
both cases. Yet there is a force in case 2 but not in case 1. Therefore, the cause of the force cannot be the relative
acceleration of the globes with respect to the configuration of distant objects. The only plausible option seems to
be that the globes, in case 2, are rotating with respect to absolute space. In the light of Laymon's interpretationof
the bucket experiment we should proceed with caution in trying to figure out what Newton is up to here.
Laymon argues that the point of the two globes experiment is, again, to illustrate the consequences of accepting
absolute space rather than to prove that absolute space exists (Laymon, 1978, p. 408ff). Laymon's view is that
the globes experiment is intended to be a summary of three different means of distinguishing true from apparent
motion (by properties, causes, and effects) which Newton had earlier discussed in the Scholium. This is certainly
more plausible than the standard interpretation which sees the globe experiment to be an attempt to demonstrate
the existence of absolute space. This view has Newton banking rather heavily on a thought experiment the
outcome of which is not clear. If the only objects in the universe were the two rotating globes and their
connecting string Newton's argument entails that when the globes are "really" rotating as opposed to being at rest
(in this case there is no relative motion in either case), then a tension exists in the string. But, asks, the standard
interpretation, how can Newton know this unless he has already assumed that absolute space exists? If he has
already done so, then this is a bad argument for it. On Laymon's view, it is not a bad argument for the existence

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 17/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

of absolute space because it is not an argument for the existence of absolute space at all (See the discussions of
Mach in the next chapter.).

(iii) A Theoretical Consideration

The discussion of the bucket and globes experiments has led us to the view that Newton must (on pain of logical
error) have had other grounds for holding that absolute space and time exist. Laymon has suggested, and our
earlier discussion supports the view, that religious considerations played a role in Newton's adopting his
absolutist position.

Here we want to consider the possibility that Newton might have thought that the existence of absolute space
and time was a theoretical requirement of his mechanics. Certainly, if Laymon's argument is correct, Newton
thought that the concept of motion was unintelligible without some notion of absolute space and time. Now
consider Newton's FIRST LAW, the Law of Inerita. That law, recall, stated that "every body continues in its state
of rest or of uniform motion in a right [straight] line, unless it is compelled to change that state by forces
impressed upon it." One question that disturbed later Newtonians who were not as convinced of the existence of
absolute space as was Newton was how to understand the phrase "in a right line." particle paths are not straight
in and of themselves, on the Newtonian view, but are straight or curved only in relation to some frame of
reference. The problem for the Newtonians was what frame of reference was to be used in formulating the
fundamental principle of inertia? Newton himself does not seem to have worried too much about it. The
assumption is that he did not worry about it because he assumed that absolute space and absolute time existed
and that one could, in principle at least, think of the inertial properties of objects as manifesting themselves in
relationship to absolute space and absolute time. Thus, the Law of Inertia is taken to assert that every body will
continue in its state of rest or uniform motion in a straight line with respect to absolute space and absolute time.

As a matter of fact, the concepts of absolute space and absolute time do not play an active role in the application
of Newtonian principles to physical systems (We should note that if the standard interpretation of the bucket
experiment commits Newton to a logical error, this interpretation commits him to an error in physical reasoning).
Perhaps this partly explains why Newtonian physics remained secure until the characteristic equations which
connect one observer's description of a physical system with another's were themselves challenged at the end of
the l9th century.

Absolute positions and absolute moments of time, Newton declared, were undetectable, and absolute motion was
almost completely undetectable. As long as one is dealing with unaccelerated motions, only relative motions,
positions and times can be detected. Newton argued that if two observers are moving with constant velocity with
respect to one another, there is no way, in principle, that they can determine by a mechanical experiment which
of them is "really" moving. This is known as the Galileian Principle of Relativity (its first

statement can be found in Galilei's (1970, p. 186) The Principle gives rise to what are called the Galilean
Transformations. Given a physical situation as described by one observer, the transformations tell how an
observer who is moving with constant velocity with respect to the first wlll describe the same situation.

Suth systems of observers moving with constant velocities (not necessarily the same) with respect to one another
are called inertial observers and they define what is known as an inertial frame of reference. Consider observers
moving only in 1 dimension along the x-axis.

o ~ r~

ox

Figure 7-3

The unprimed observer we will consider to be at rest, O' moves along ~he x-axis with a velocity V relative to
0. Suppose, by some happy coincidence, that the origin of the X-system coincides with the origin of the X'-

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 18/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

system when the clocks of the two observers read T ~ T' = 0. At some time t later, an event occurs at a position p
units from observer 0.

~x~

o~~

F g~-~

According to 0, 0' has moved a distance - Vt down the x-axis. Of course, O' does not think that he has moved at
all. He thinks O has moved -Vt' units down the x'-axis. Both observers think they are at rest and the other has
moved. The only thing they agree on is that they are separated by the distance d= Vt. In general, if O sees an
event p occur at some point x in the O-frame of reference, O' will see the event occur at a point x' in the O'-frame
of reference, where x and x' are related by the equation: x = x' + Vt'

Recall that time is absolute in the Newtonian world view. This means that the time as measured by the O-clock
(=t) and the time as measured by the O'-clock (=t') are related by the equation t = t'

The three equations

x = x' - v t' , x' = x + v t, t = t'


are the Galilean Transformations in one dimension. Actually, only one of the first two is needed since the other
can be derived from it using the third. These equations can easily be generalized for motions in 3 dimensions but
we will not stop to pursue this now.

From these equations, one can easily derive equations which relate the velocity of an object as measured by O to
the velocity of the same object as measured by 0'. The result is that if the velocity of an object A with respect to
O is V, then the velocity of the object with respect to O' (=V') is given by V' = V + v where v is the velocity of O'
with respect to 0. Similarly, if A is accelerating with respect to O with an acceleration a, then its acceleration as
measured by O' (= a') is given by

a' = a

This is the crucial result. Any acceleration seen by one inertial observer is seen as exactly the same by any other
inertial observer. But, in Newtonian mechanics, forces are proportional to accelerations. Thus, the Galileian
transformations, characteristic of Newtonian mechanics, imply that any two inertial observers will agree on a
description of the forces acting in any given situation. This is what one means by saying that they "see" the same
physics. Because of this fact, if two observers are moving with constant velocity with respect to one another,
there is no way for them to determine which observer is "really" moving. This is what one means by saying that
absolute motions are not detectable by kinematic (motion) considerations alone. Newton's arguments concerning
absolute motions all involve dynamic (force) considerations. But, these latter effects are equivalent for inertial
observers who are said to be Galilean invariant.

The net effect is that the system of inertial observers functions just like absolute space and time does. The
principle of inertia holds for such observers but no absolute motions are detectable by them. The only hope for
detecting absolute motion rests on finding some (non-mechanical) effect or force which will single out one group
of inertial observers as being somehow distinguished from the rest (i.e., "really" at rest). In the l9th century it
was discovered that the laws of electromagnetic radiation are not Galilean invariant. Experiments were set up to
detect absolute motion but they were not successful. The implications of these results led to the rejection of
Newton's concepts of absolute space and absolute time. (See chapter 9 for a discussion of the role of optical
phenomena in the downfall of Newtonian mechanics.)

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 19/20
9/4/24, 5:33 PM physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html

Return to beginning of this chapter or to the Table of Contents.

https://physics.bgsu.edu/p433/Spacetime7.html 20/20

You might also like