Criticism
Criticism
Criticism
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Cambridge University Press and The Classical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to The Classical Review.
http://www.jstor.org
based on choice, an echo of the moral philosophy of the Ethics. On the other hand,
character can be realized only in action and plot - the terms are almost synonymous
in the Poetics - and so Aristotle's tragedy is not character-based but 'agent-centred'
and excludes any other source of causation, even divine agency. At the same time,
character's role in determining human action and thus contributing to the unity of
a play rules out some of the traditional features of the hero's status and concentrates
attention on his appeal to the tragic emotions of pity and fear.
Aristotle's theory of the emotional effect of tragedy on audience or reader
complements his view of action and character and is consistent with his philosophical
beliefs as set out in other works. Pity and fear are to be seen not as 'uncontrollable
instincts or forces' but as 'part of an integrated response to the structured material
of poetic drama' through 'cognitive understanding of the mimetic representation of
human action and character'. The analysis of pity and fear in the Rhetoric demon-
strates their interlocking nature; while pity is primarily altruistic, it too, like fear, has
a self-regardingelement, being aroused by the innocent sufferingof tragic agents 'like
ourselves', since we too are exposed to human vulnerability and are just as liable to
a fall from happiness and prosperity. In tragedy, even when that fall is averted, there
may be a fear of what was in prospect, perhaps accompanied by a proleptic pity for
the sufferer,and this explains how Aristotle is able to reconcile his theory of the tragic
emotions with the possibility of a 'happy ending', which he accepts and even, in
chapter 14, prefers. It is the poet's mimetic art that enables him to arouse these
emotions by creating dramatic situations to which his audience can react as it would
to similar events in everyday life. H. rightly rejects attempts to translate katharsis in
the Poetics as either 'purgation' or 'purification' or to allow it a simple identity with
the katharsis of Politics 8: it does, however, produce a result comparable to medical
therapy and is closely linked to the pleasure derived from tragedy, since both depend
on a proper understanding of the 'plot-structure', as he prefers to render muthos. This
thorough review of katharsis is supported by an appendix appraising the main
interpretations, both past and present, of the notorious clause in Aristotle's definition
of tragedy: H.'s personal preferenceis for one form of the view which posits' a process
(or effect) of psychological attunement or balance', related to the doctrine of the mean
and the concept of habituation.
Just as the relation between action and character and the nature of pity and fear
reflect aspects of Aristotle's moral and psychological teaching, so his identification
of prosperity and adversity as 'the poles between which the action of tragedy moves'
echoes his view that eutuchia and dustuchia result from the possession or lack of
'external goods' and not from the operations of chance, which the requirements of
unity of plot exclude from influencing,let alone controlling, tragic action. Indispensable
to Aristotle's theory of the tragic plot is the metabasis (change of fortune) or lusis
(denouement) resulting from recognition and reversal,which provide the turning-point
of a tragedy, and hamartia,which is the third component of the complex plot, though
not explicitly or implicitly a necessary feature of all tragedy: it is by means of hamartia
that Aristotle is able to steer his theory of tragedy between the Scylla of Platonic
moralism and the Charybdis of arbitrary and undeserved misfortune. H.'s discussion
of this all too often misapprehended topic, accomplished without recourse to what
he calls 'hamartia hunting', has a freshness about it which his readers cannot fail to
appreciate and is the most lucid and convincing that your reviewer has yet seen. The
same may fairly be said of H.'s final chapter on the Nachleben of the Poetics.
So far so good - even if a bare summary does scant justice to the breadth and depth
of H.'s argument or to his felicity in expressing it, which defies paraphrase. Possibly