Block.1
Block.1
Block.1
Contents
1.0 Objectives
1.1 Introduction
1.2 Moral Intuitionism
1.3 Human Person in Search of Himself/Herself
1.4 Love and the Moral Precepts
1.5 The Dynamics of Morality
1.6 The Constant and the Variable in Morality
1.7 Let Us Sum Up
1.8 Key Words
1.9 Further Readings and References
1.0 OBJECTIVES
This unit aims at introducing the students to the philosophical need for Ethics
starting from a brief discussion of Moral law and how the human person in his or
her process of growth intuits the ethical principles. Discussions pertaining to the
dynamics of morality is undertaken to show how on the one hand new situations
call for new responses from moral point of view and on the other hand certain
fundamentals of ethics remain the same in so far as there is something of a
common human nature adequately understood.
1.1 INTRODUCTION
Let us begin our study of Nature and Scope of Ethics by understanding what we
mean by moral law. But two things need to be clarified before we raise the question
with which we are concerned here. First, the moral law is called ‘law’ only
metaphorically, or if one prefers, analogically. The primary meaning of law is “a
rule of action, promulgated by him/her who is in charge of a community in view
of the common good”. This is called positive law. If the legislator is considered
to be God, it is divine positive law; if the legislator is human person, and it is
human positive law. Human positive law can further be subdivided according to
what the common good aimed at. (e.g. civil law, criminal law, commercial law,
etc.) In a case, a positive law lays down rules to be observed by human persons.
It is prescription. Then there is another sense of ‘law’ which is quite different. In
this sense it is a formula expressing a constant of behaviour of things and of
persons. So we have physical law (including laws studied in physics, chemistry,
biology, etc.), psychological law, sociological law, etc. (Since the constant of
behaviour among human persons is less fixed and foreseeable than that among
things it is more of a statistical constant). As distinct from positive law, this kind
of law is called ‘natural law’. It is descriptive. It can also be called prescriptive
to the extent if it is considered as willed by God and includes the divine positive
law, and descriptive to the extent that this divine will is the ultimate cause of the
constant of behaviour in things and human persons. However, moral law
corresponds exactly neither to the positive law nor to the natural law. On the
5
Introduction to Ethics contrary, the sense of the ‘absolute should’ is an immediate datum of the moral
consciousness itself.
Secondly, in the language of Moral philosophers, moral law includes not only
general and abstract rules of action (e.g. “do good and avoid evil”), or, in our
language, the sense of the absolute should, but also particular and concrete
precepts (e.g. help the poor, obey legitimate authority, be truthful, do not kill the
innocent, adultery is wrong, etc.). These particular and concrete precepts, we are
here calling the specifications of the moral law.
Hence our question: How are the general data of the moral consciousness
particularized and concretized in specific precepts and what is the cause of this
difference among men? In terms of moral value, we can raise this question as
follows. If the moral value par excellence is human person’s self-realization as
human how can this moral value determine specific moral values? And why is
there disagreement as to whether such and such an action is a ‘good’ (moral
value) or not?
Saurez is perhaps even more explicit in his doctrine that even the secondary
principles – which like the primary are self-evident in themselves – require a
certain amount of thought and experience. This is truer of the tertiary principles
which require study and discursive thought. But all moral principles can be derived
from self-evident principles. One notable difference between Thomas and Saurez
is that the former derives the concrete principles in a way corresponding to ‘human
person’s natural inclinations,’ the latter derives them in a way corresponding to
a legal system. For Saurez these precepts have their immediate norm the ‘good’
of human nature. The need of experience and reflection is similarly – indeed
even more insisted upon by contemporary ethicists. Why this greater insistence?
To speak more specifically of thinkers like Thomas Aquinas, Suarez and Ross
are we to say that the examples they give of first principles (or of pirma facie
duties) are meant to serve merely as examples or are we to say that they are
meant to be included among the first principles themselves? In the first case we
could perhaps disagree that the examples they give are good examples but still
agree with their doctrine that there exist first principles intuitively known by
every man. The question would be then which are these fist principles. In the
second case to question the aptness of the examples would be to question their
doctrine itself. Irrespective of what such thinkers actually mean we have got to
study the problem in itself.
If there is any principle that cannot be denied, it is the immediate data of moral
consciousness. If these data cannot be denied they are self-evident. They are
self-evident not as principles, that is, as formulae but as data whether they are
thematically formulated or not. The immediate ontological foundation of the
moral obligation is human inter-relatedness and that the norm for moral good
(as distinct from the moral right) is human person as a social being. We have
also reflected how the only moral precept which is immediately given that is 7
Introduction to Ethics self-evident and cannot be justified on a mere moral level is that human person
should be human (as an individual and social being). Hence all other precepts
(what we are here calling specifications of the moral law) must somehow or
other flow from this fundamental precept that a person should realize himself/
herself as human.
Hence the moral precepts (moral values) flow from the first fundamental moral
precept that human person should be himself/herself (the moral value par
excellence not by way of mere logical deduction or of mere mediate inference.
The former are related to the latter not simply as logical conclusions or as
implicitly correlated to their premises. Logic has got to do with ideas, with mere
ideas. It cannot be denied that this relation of the explicit to the implicit of the
clear to the unclear to the unclear of the concrete to the abstract is here present.
But it is present in the sense that a continuously developing human consciousness
is related to its stages past and future of its development. Existence is more than
logic.
Ignorance of the moral precepts is therefore not necessarily the result of perverse
customs as if this result were accidental. It is a fact of experience that perverse
customs not only weaken the will to pursue the moral good but darkens the mind
to recognize what the moral good is. But this is more easily possible on an
individual level. Here we are placing ourselves on the level of mankind and its
historical progress. This ignorance and the variety of morals can be explained by
human historicity itself, that is, by the historical progressive development of his
human moral consciousness.
However, we must not easily take it for granted that this development has always
and everywhere been a linear progress. It may have suffered setbacks, reverses
and regress. We need not go into that. What is more pertinent here to ask is
whether we should reasonably suppose that human person has now attained the
some of his/her self-consciousness and of his/her moral consciousness. What is
reasonable to suppose according to us is that he/she has not. Apart from the fact
that one cannot predict the future, contemporary moral problem of the morality
of abortion hinges to a great extent on whether one should consider the human
foetus a human person. The so-called women’s liberation movement indicates
no matter what its merits and demerits are that women have not been treated as
8 full human persons everywhere in the world. One could think of many other
indications. If progress is still possible it can only be done by the passage of time Nature and Scope of Ethics
and on the part of human person by experience and by his reflection on his own
experience.
The primary intuitively grasped demand that human person realizes himself as a
human person is particularized and concretized in moral precepts. This too can
be expressed in terms of love. Universal love is particularized and concretized –
it is objectified – in the moral precepts. Hence as love not just one moral virtue
among others but the form of all of the moral virtues, so too love is not just one
moral precept among others but it is the form of all of them. It is what makes
moral precepts moral precepts. Indeed it could hardly be called a precept since
taken by itself in a non-objectified sense, it does not prescribe anything definite.
And in the same way one can hardly call the moral realization of oneself as
human as an obligation. This too taken by itself in a non-objectified sense does
not oblige human person to do anything specific. And there is hardly any meaning
in the saying that human person should love (love cannot be enforced) so too
there is hardly any meaning in the saying that human person should fulfil himself
as human.
If love is the form of the moral precepts and if love – like human moral
consciousness – is a progressive affair this means that acting according to the
moral precepts is acting according to love but that this awareness admits of
degrees. This means that love can also be considered to be not only the beginning
of the moral life but also its end. At the beginning it is present as a seed – which
is more than mere potentiality but already an actuality albeit in a seminal form.
The seed can develop into a fully mature and fully conscious lobe. And if it is in
love that human person perfects himself as human, it is in this fully mature and
fully conscious love that he/she does so.
Suffice it here to remark already that though human person can develop one or
other of his/her faculties independently of the rest (or at least quasi independently)
one cannot develop himself/herself as a human person without developing the
core of his/her being namely his/her love and this is not achieved by mere study
and reflection – although these can be very useful – but by doing. As scholastics
say the operation is the perfection of being.
9
Introduction to Ethics
1.5 THE DYNAMICS OF MORALITY
Here we examine two questions which are intimately linked. In an evolutionary
visions of human person to what extent can we say that morality (that is, the
specification of the moral law) are universally valid for all human persons to
what extent can we say that they are unchangeable? If one maintains their universal
validity one is charged with absolutism with holding the opinion of a static nature
of human person incompatible with present day theories about man’s dynamic
and evolutionary nature. If on the other hand one were to maintain a relative
validity one would fall into a philosophically untenable moral relativism. Can
the dilemma be overcome?
The Evolutionary nature of human person and of his human consciousness has
long been recognized one way or another. Charles Darwin gave the theory of
evolution a biological basis. An Evolutionary view of the world and of human
person is today at the basis of a great deal of scientific philosophical and
theological thinking. The thinking of such human persons as Pierre Teilhard de
Chardin and of Aurobindo comes of course spontaneously to mind.
Again since moral consciousness has been in fact intimately linked to and
condition by religious consciousness, different religious beliefs have produced
different moral values. And a change in religious consciousness has often wrought
a corresponding change in morality. The history of religion affords us with many
examples (e.g. human sacrifice, burning of witches, saturnalia, etc.). This change
is primarily and directly in religious consciousness and only secondarily and
indirectly in moral consciousness. It is a change in the religiously conditioned
morality. 11
Introduction to Ethics However, a change in civil law governing the mores of the people does not
necessarily mean a change in morality. When a civil law declares that something
is legal it does not mean to say that it is moral. Civil law as such does not pass a
moral judgment. Legal means allowed as far as the state is concerned. It is not
the business of the state as such to promote the moral beliefs of one section of its
population as against those of another. This is important to remember today
when many countries proclaim themselves to be secular – today when society is
increasingly pluralistic.
The variable in morality raises the important question regarding the kind of
certitude we can have in moral matters. To put it bluntly if what is believed to be
morally right today can be proved to be morally wrong tomorrow and vice-versa
can one be absolutely certain of what is morally right or morally wrong? In more
philosophical terms if human person is conditioned by his/her existential situation
and if human (and moral) consciousness is always in a process of development
and is dependent on physiological, cultural, social, psychological environmental
and other factors, can he/she ever be certain of having reached objective moral
truth if there is such a thing as moral truth?
At the very outset, we have to distinguish carefully between moral relativity and
ethical relativism. Moral relativity is simply the view that different people
especially in different civilizations and cultures have or have had different moral
beliefs and what is believed to be morally right at a given time or place may be
believed to be morally wrong at a different time or place. This is an undeniable
empirical fact. But ethical relativism is the philosophical theory that no foundation
exists, there is no universal moral norm (or basic moral principle), but what is
morally right is relative to the individual or group of men in question. If such a
theory can give reasons for such a position (as Sartre does), it is ethical relativism
in the strict sense. If it cannot give reasons but simply admits that it is strictly
impossible to say what is morally right and morally wrong it can be reasonably
called ethical skepticism.
In an evolutionary view of human being, that is, on the accepted theory that
human consciousness of himself/herself is increasingly developing, can we
pretend to say the last word on what human person is? Obviously not. Human
person’s knowledge of his/her self is a progressive and dynamic knowledge,
always tending towards a better and better understanding. In this sense human
person’s knowledge of himself/herself is relative. And if this is true his/her moral
knowledge is also relative in so far as it is progressive and far from complete.
12
Nature and Scope of Ethics
Check Your Progress I
Note: Use the space provided for your answer
1) Explain Absolute Ethics and Relative Ethics.
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
2) How are love and moral precepts related?
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
3) How do the concepts of love and moral percepts help to build an ethical
society?
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
4) What is the notable difference between Aquinas and Saurez’s idea of
self-evident or moral principle?
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
Sharma, S. P. Nature and Scope of Ethics. New Delhi: Mohit Publications, 2003.
14
Nature and Scope of Ethics
UNIT 2 IMPORTANCE AND CHALLENGES
OF ETHICS
Contents
2.0 Objectives
2.1 Introduction
2.2 The Challenge of Situation Ethics
2.3 Cultural and Ethical Subjectivism
2.4 Morris Ginsberg’s “On the Diversity of Morals”
2.5 Let Us Sum Up
2.6 Key Words
2.7 Further Readings and References
2.0 OBJECTIVES
While spelling out the importance of ethics in so far as it affects human conduct
and behaviour in the society, this unit seeks to respond to the some of the important
challenges to ethics as a philosophical discipline particularly from certain
approaches to make ethics itself relative. Thus we attempt to look at some of the
figures in the tradition of Western Philosophy like Fletcher and Ginsberg, figures
representing these challenging currents of thought and we offer an in-depth
evaluation of their positions.
2.1 INTRODUCTION
Ethics is the philosophical treatise which studies human behaviour and tries to
determine what is right or wrong behaviour. It is also called moral philosophy.
(from the Greek ‘ethos’ and the Latin ‘mores’ which mean ‘custom’, ‘ways of
behaviour’, ‘human character’).That there is in man a spontaneous awareness of
a distinction between ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ behaviour is an indubitable fact. But
philosophy, here like elsewhere, cannot content itself with simply registering
facts, it tries to reflect on the ‘meaningfulness’ of such facts, establish them (or
reject them) on a rational basis, understand their implications, draw their practical
consequences and above all intuit their ultimate cause (if any).
The importance of ethics is obvious. From as far back in history as we can tell,
man has always sought to know how to lead a ‘good’ life and to draw up rules of
15
Introduction to Ethics conduct. Thinkers of all cultures tried to explain in what this ‘good’ life consisted
and, especially, why precisely it was ‘good’. It is not so much that traditional
moral values are questioned (e.g. the ‘just’ war, inviolability of life in cases of
the hopelessly suffering and of unwanted pregnancies, sexual intercourse only
between the legally married, indissolubility of marriage, etc.), but, more radically
still, that the very ‘meaningfulness’ of an unchanging and universally valid
morality is brought into question. The causes of this modern questioning are
hard to pin down. Certainly the spread of education, advances in science and
technology, problems arising from modern way of living like the ever-increasing
urbanization, easier communication media, faster means of travel whereby people
of one culture come in closer contact with people of another culture, etc are
some of the causes.
But if, as we have already implied, moral thinking is intimately linked with
philosophical thinking in general, it might very well be that these causes, whatever
they might be, are to be sought for on a deeper human level. Human person,
perhaps, is not so much asking about the morality of this or that human act, but,
more deeply still, about himself: the meaning of his life, the direction of human
history, the significance of the human world he lives in, the ambit of his knowledge
and the possibility of his ever getting an answer to the questions he asks. Ethics,
of course, cannot dream of suggesting answers to such radical questions. But it
might well prove to be a ‘way of approach’ to questions which lie beyond its
own field of enquiry.
Fletcher has, to say the least, a rather legalistic definition of love. So long as an
act is done “selflessly” without the agent seeking any clearly manifest material
gain, it is a moral act. Even the sickest of mentally deranged acts could also be
roped in as ethically laudable if they were done without any demonstrably material
profit being sought in the process. But if love is selflessness, before we can
assess its rightness or wrongness, shouldn’t we first enquire into the nature of
the self? Besides, as one might well ask, why should love be the norm of morality
and not hate? Ultimately one can only answer that question by saying that love
enhances one’s personhood, one’s “human nature adequately considered.” It
makes one more fully human, more fully alive. And hate does not do that. This
obliges us to recognize a more basic and deeper norm ‘love in itself.’
To give Fletcher his due, one has to admit that he does give the impression that
he has done some critical reflection on love and its authentic meaning, even if it
wouldn’t stand up to anything like a deeper metaphysical query. He trots out
some fancy terminology from Tillich to this end: Using terms made popular by
Tillich and others, we may say that situationalism is a method that proceeds, so
to speak, from (1) its one and only law, agape (love), to (2) the sophia (wisdom),
containing many “general rules” of more or less reliability, to (3) the kairos
(moment of decision, the fullness of time) in which the responsible self in the
situation decides whether the sophia can serve there or not. Whence he goes on
to make a highly simplistic summary of how the rival ethicists proceed: “Legalists
make an idol of sophia, antinomians repudiate it, and situationists use it.”
Finally, Fletcher, taking his cue from Socrates to the effect that the unexamined
life is not worth living, suggests that “unexamined ethical maxims are not worth
living by.” and then he unleashes a salvo on the maxim that “The end does not
justify the means.” On the contrary, he asks, “If the end does not justify the
means, what does?” And he answers, “Obviously, ‘Nothing.’” Whence his another
proposition of situation ethics, “Only the end justifies the means; nothing else.”
In the light of the preceding, this boils down to say that anything done out of
love (the means) is thereby justified or made morally good. He is careful to
quickly add, “Not any old end will justify any old means” only love would do
the job. And then he tops it off with another chilling remark, “Being pragmatic,
the situationist always asks the price and supposes that in theory and practice
everything has its price. Everything, please note. Even for a ‘pearl of great price’
whatever it is – might be sold for love’s sake if the situation calls for it.” This
kind of remark is chilling because it can be used to justify the suicide bomber
who blows himself up with a host of innocent civilians – and, as we have seen,
Fletcher actually does that.
Even if we don’t fully endorse Fletcher and his brand of situation ethics, is there
something we can learn from what he has tried to tell us? He is reminding us of
a timeless and oft-forgotten maxim: unless an action, however good in itself, is
done with the motive of sincere love, it has no real ethical value, whatsoever.
17
Introduction to Ethics
Check Your Progress II
Note: Use the space provided for your answer
1) Define Ethics and its importance.
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
2) Illustrate Joseph Fletcher’s Situation Ethics.
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
Kant was determined that his system of ethics have an autonomous source. Basing
mortal conduct on external grounds – the will, of God (Occam) or of positive
law (Durkheim) would be to ask for trouble. An atheist would be deprived of
any moral foundation and positive law would scarcely help matters: it is
susceptible to so many variants, often on the basis of vested interests and
corruption, that it would afford, at best, a very shaky moral set-up. On the other
hand, Kant’s agnostic epistemology, influenced by Hume, rendered it quite
impossible to take the “natural law,” based on human nature, as the norm of
morality. As the first Critique had argued, we cannot know the ‘thing-in-itself’
(the noumenon) and human nature is one of those things, precisely. The only
solution was for him to ground it among those a prior practical principle built
into our very mental makeup, parallel to those speculative principles that The
Critique of pure Reason has uncovered. These a priori synthetic judgments were
endowed with the qualities of strict universality and absolute necessity. One
could as much expect exceptions to moral laws as one could require, say, the
Principle of Identity or Contradiction to allow for contravention on the basis of
special circumstances.
But, if one were not to go along with Hume and Kant and accept that not only is
there a common human nature in which we all participate, but can discern what
basically constitutes it, the problem is dispersed at once. In the first place, this
doesn’t open the door to all manner of cultural exploitation and foisting
questionable pre-understandings and perceptions onto recalcitrant people and
their cultures. The basic make-up of all humans or “common human nature”
would comprise the following data: we are embodied beings with a capacity to
transcend space and time, are social by nature, rooted in a world and have some
sort of relatedness to the ultimate: only that and nothing more. No host of uncritical
“commonness” are being smuggled in as a kind of packaged deal, forcing people
to accept certain attitudes to people, places, things and even God as constituting
our “common human nature”.
24
Challenges and Importance
UNIT 3 ETHICS IN HISTORY OF INDIAN of Ethics
PHILOSOPHY
Contents
3.0 Objectives
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Sources of Moral Ideals in India
3.3 Ethics: Its Meaning in Indian Tradition
3.4 Ethics in Vedic Period
3.5 Ethics in Dharmasastras and Itihasas
3.6 Way of Righteousness in the Gita
3.7 Ethical Concepts of Hindu Tradition
3.8 Ethics in Buddhism
3.9 Jaina Ethics
3.10 Let us Sum up
3.11 Key Words
3.12 Further Readings and References
3.0 OBJECTIVES
• To give the students of philosophy general glimpse of ethics in Indian
tradition;
• To enable them understand the ethical consciousness of India; and
• To enumerate various ethical concepts of different Indian philosophical and
religious traditions.
3.1 INTRODUCTION
Moral consciousness is an undeniable fact of human experience. The moral
sensibility is something essential for the peaceful society and the work. Even
gods are believed to incarnate to restore righteousness and peace in the society.
Down through the centuries, many religious teachers, and philosophers were
interested in the rational ground of morality. The caste duties of the Hindus
prescribed in the Dharmasastras are well articulated commands, which are meant
to regulate the life of the community. Ethics as a speculative science is based on
the foundations of the moral behavior of man, but a substantial portion of the
moral codes are based on religious beliefs, social customs and traditions. When
we take the Indian ethics too the morality is very much based on certain beliefs,
customs and traditions of Indian religions.
It is true that the foundations of Indian ethics can be sought in the metaphysical
and the theological beliefs in the form of worship, prayers and in the form of
ideals and principles that directed man’s life in the society. When we speak of
Indian ethics, we cannot deny the intimate relationship that prevails between
ethics and Hindu or any other religion. Ethics and religion are so closely related
25
Introduction to Ethics and whatever may be the religion, it contains within itself some system of morality
for the guidance of its followers. And thus Indian ethics is the indispensable part
of Hindu religion and other religions of Indian origin. Indian ethical ideals and
principles are very much found in the Vedas and in other Indian literatures and in
other teachings of the Indian religions.
Like religion and art, morality also is an institution of life for anyone to adopt in
his life. By this institution of morality one’s actions from the moral point of view
might be branded as good or bad, right or wrong, praiseworthy or blameful etc.
And again by morality one may be entitled to judge others’ action as good or
bad, right or wrong. In this sense morality can be regarded as a particular way of
looking at issues of character and conduct. It is in this sense of morality, that we
talk of human beings as moral agents but not of animals, we also talk of moral
concepts, laws and principles etc for a morally good or morally right life.
Morality means conscious living within the frame of certain principles of conduct
laid down by those regarded as authorities. So in general morality as an institution
of life consists in the awareness of an important distinction between what is and
what ought to be. So men should live not merely in the light of what is but also
what ought to be. Specifically speaking morality is the awareness of a living
based on a distinction between our animal demands and the demands of the
higher faculties of human life, which make the human distinct from the animals.
Since the ancestors of Hindus in India were spiritual in nature they fixed their
attention on a life beyond death. They regarded the human soul (inner being) as
an eternal entity co-existing with the Supreme Being. They believed that every
human soul goes to the round of births, rebirths and reaps the fruits of actions.
When a soul comes to be associated with the gross material body, it is bound to
perform certain deeds and in conformity with laws divine, reaps the fruits thereof.
The belief is that, if good deeds are performed, happiness results and if evil
deeds are performed, misery falls to the lot of the doer. The human soul never
dies; it can never remain without doing ‘actions’ and can never claim exemptions
from reaping the fruits of its deeds. It reaps as it sows. Any man ultimately looks
for happiness which is the fruit of Karma and so he should necessarily know
what is good and what is bad. Every law giver and every thinker of India in
ancient period felt, the supreme necessity of framing certain rules of conduct
and of presenting the ultimate end to which all the life of a human being is to be
directed in this lesson on Indian ethics we will be dealing with the Hindu ethics,
some ethical notions of Buddhism and Jainism.
The very concept of Indian morality is both authority based and social reasoning.
Both in Buddhism and Jainism reason has been given a prestigious place. In
Jainism right faith is given the first place among the three jewels. One is advised
to use his reason in ascertaining the validity and worth of the precepts before
following them. In Buddhism too the use of personal reason is neither disallowed
nor despised. The four noble truths are to be followed but even then Buddha
says wherever there is disagreement, questions can be asked for removing doubts.
In modern Hindu thought, reason is given better place, especially in the ideas of
Vivekananda and Gandhi. For them reason is not the source of moral ideas, but
yet they believe in the role of reason in the matters of morality. Hence, the primary
role is given to Vedas and Smrtis as the fundamental source of morality in Indian
tradition, but besides them, all the above mentioned sources also played their
roles in deciding the question of morality and immorality in Indian tradition.
The highest goal of life for the Upanishads is no longer happiness as in the Rig
Veda, but liberation from bondage to the transitory existence and the re-attainment
of the inner essence of the soul. The Upanishadic ethics is primarily atman-
centric and intellectualistic. The Upanishads declare that the Vedic sacrifices are
totally irrelevant for the realization of moksa. And so man is constantly exhorted
to seek his individual liberation and not worry about other social, moral obligation.
This kind of philosophical individualism definitely undermines the values of
social morality. For the Upanishads, the identification and the realization of the
self with Brahman is very important. In this metaphysical realm only we can
speak of Upanishadic ethics. The oldest Upanishads say that the perfect sage is a
saint who burns evil away and he is free from evil. So it is in the avoidance of
evil, we can see the clear moral teaching in the Upanishads. Katha Upanishad
declares in 1,2,24 that he who is always impure is born again and again that he
fails to reach the highest goal. Good conduct is very much necessary for the
attainment of man’s metaphysical good (identification of the self with Brahman).
And man who is wise is morally a good man whose nature approximates to the
divine model (Kat.Up 1, 2, 24, Ch.Up 8, 6, 1). So the Upanishads are clear in
saying that the man who has wisdom does not sin. He ceases to do evil and
through his wisdom he annuls the evil of his former life.
28
Ethics in the History of
3.6 WAY OF RIGHTEOUSNESS IN THE GITA Indian Philosophy
The realization of the Supreme Reality through a life of righteous actions is the
central well-knit theme of all the eighteen chapters of the Gita. Actions are to be
performed with the realization of Brahmajnana. To attain the Brahmajnana one
is advised to make a diligent search through devotion, renunciation and self-
surrender. From attachment desire springs from desire wrath arises, from wrath
comes infatuation, from infatuation loss of memory and mind and finally from
loss of mind he perishes. So liberation from all kinds of bondages is possible
only by the realization of the Brahman or surrender unto the Lord and vice versa,
the realization of the Brahman is only through the liberation from all kinds of
bondages. Actions are to be performed without any attachment to the fruit of the
actions. This is one of the means of attaining Brahmajnana. Thus Gita emphasizes
both on Karma Yoga and Gnana Yoga for the attainment of the Supreme Bliss,
but yet Karma Yoga is superior to Gnana Yoga. Here Karma Yoga simply means
a mode of realizing the Brahman through devotional meditation on the name of
God, and the practice of one’s own duties without any attachment. One will be
blessed with Brahmayoga, which will lead him not only to moral success but
also to the infinite spiritual joy and peace.
There is another way promoted by the Gita to attain the ultimate realization in
life and liberation from the cycle of births and deaths, which is known as Karma
Yoga (Path of activity). The Gita has described this way as the method of
disinterested action (NishkamaKarma). To attain moksa one has to be freed from
the bondage to one’s own actions. So the Gita suggests the golden rule that
actions should be done with the spirit of non-attachment to their fruits. Both the
epics, itihasas have a bundle of ethical and moral codes and injunctions. The
practical guidelines of the essential ethical ideals and thoughts of Hindu tradition.
29
Introduction to Ethics
3.7 ETHICAL CONCEPTS OF HINDU TRADITION
Doctrine of Karma
The doctrine of Karma states that whatever a man suffers or enjoys is the fruit of
his own deed, a harvest sprung from his own actions, good or bad committed in
his previous life. Karma is of four categories: 1) Sanchita Karma, which means
the accumulated past actions 2) Prarabdha Karma, which means the part of
Sanchita Karma, this results in the present birth itself. This is also called pre-
destination 3) Kriyamana Karma, which means present willful actions or free
will 4) Agami Karma, which means the immediate results caused by our present
actions. Karma simply means action. And this Karma must remind us that what
is called the consequence of an action is really not a separate thing but it is a part
of the action and it cannot be divided from it. The consequence is the part of the
action, which belongs to the future but yet the part is done in the present. Whatever
a man sows he shall reap.
Transmigration of Soul
The doctrine of Karma and transmigration of soul are so closely bound up together.
After the death of the body the life of the individual is continued in another body
and so on in indefinite series. According to this theory, the soul though pure and
blessed in itself, gets entangled in the Samsara (cycle of birth and rebirth). It is
because of the Karma it passes through innumerable births (transmigration) before
it regains its original state.
Varnadharma
In Hindu ethics, we find varnasrama dharma as a social stratification, based on
above said gunas, profession and birth. Although theoretically it is justified to
have such a classification of people in the name of their propensity and quality
they posses in terms of their attitude, caste system in Indian ethics remains an
issue. It has been very much practiced and all ethical principles and codes are
based on it. By way of profession one’s caste is determined in some ways, both
in theory and in practice. This looks somehow fine and rationally justified. Yet
social mobility in the ladder of categories of people is not very much practical
and it is not ensured. Even if a person develops sattva guna and becomes a
teacher of scriptures, he / she cannot become a ‘Brahmin’ for the very reason that
he was not born a Brahmin. Although theoretically Hindu ethics preaches it,
social mobility in such practice remains only an utopia. One’s birth, jati determines
everything in caste systems. A Sudra is denied of the right of undertaking
purificatory rite in the form of investiture of sacred thread (Upanayana), which
is supposed to give a man his second birth. He is not allowed to perform Vedic
sacrifices or read or listen to the Vedas. Severest punishments were prescribed
and carried out, if a Sudra even dared to recite or had a chance to hear the Vedas.
A Brahmin unconditionally deserved the greatest honour and all kinds of gifts.
He could not be given any corporeal punishment. He was exempt from the state
taxes. The severest punishments were prescribed for the offender of a Brahmin.
Hence, Hindu ethics regarding varnadharma is still a contested and controversial
moral and social code.
There are ten demeritorious deeds from which the Buddhist are advised to keep
away. These deeds are rooted in greed, hatred, and delusion and they will bring
suffering to others. These ten deeds are divided into three sets: 1. Actions of the
Body 2. Verbal Actions 3. Actions of the Mind. Bodily actions are killing of
living beings, stealing, and unlawful sexual intercourse. 2. Four verbal actions
are: Lying, Slander, Harsh Speech, and Meaningless Talk. 3. The other three
actions of the mind are: Covetousness or being desirous especially of things
belonging to others, ill-will, wrong views.
Five precepts
Telling about ten meritorious and ten evil actions, the Buddhism invites the lay
Buddhists to adopt five precepts voluntarily to follow in order to live together in
civilized communities with mutual trust and respect. Following these five precepts
helps the lay Buddhist to make a spiritual journey towards liberation. These five
precepts are purely voluntary ones. A good Buddhist should remind himself to
follow the five precepts daily they are as follows, I take the training rule to
refrain from Killing living creatures, Taking which is not given, Sexual
misconduct, False speech, and Taking intoxicating drugs and liquor. The precepts
are the basic practice in Buddhism. They are also an indispensable basis for
people who wish to cultivate their minds. Without some basic moral code, the
power of meditation can often be applied for some wrong and selfish motive.
These five refrains is called as Pancasila
Then that preliminary faith should be supported by right knowledge again for
having right faith based on general acquaintance (samyag- darsana) in support
of right knowledge. Right faith does not imply that one must blindly follow the
Tirthankaras. But one must have the right attitude of respect towards truth. Further
by studying the teachings of the Tirthankaras one can strengthen his belief. But
these two are rendered useless unless they are followed by rigorous practice.
Right conduct is the third indispensable (samyag-caritra) condition of liberation.
It is this that enables one to stop the influx of new karmas and also to eradicate
old ones. It consists in the control of passions, senses, thought, speech etc. Right
conduct is therefore described as refraining from what is harmful and doing
what is good. Right conduct enables man to liberate himself from bondage. The
Jaina prescription for right conduct: One must follow the five great vows namely
the panca-maha-vrata for the perfection of right conduct. They are Ahimsa,
Sathyam, Asteyam, Brahamacaryam and Aparigraha. Ahimsa denotes abstinence
from all injuries to life – either trasa or sthavara. Satyam is abstinence from
falsehood. It is speaking what is true, good and pleasant. Asteyam refers to
abstinence from stealing. Brahmacaryam pertains to abstinence from sensual
and casual pleasures. One must refrain himself from karma of any form altogether
34
either in speech talk or action. Aparigraha: By this what is meant here is that Ethics in the History of
Indian Philosophy
abstinence from all kinds of attachments. It lies in giving up attachment for the
objects of five senses.
Hinduism also accepted the fact that man’s dharma comprising of all his duties
and virtues, changes with the changing times. Hindu religio-culture is very
composite, so we need to choose those aspects of Hindu-religio culture, which
are most in harmony with our modern values and we also need to frankly reject
other ideals, which are not in harmony with modern values. From all these that
we saw above, we can conclude this lesson on Buddhists ethics basing our
concentration on the urgent call of Buddhism to the modern world today.
Buddhism calls for tolerance in the world today so that peaceful co-existence
among the people can be possible. The Buddha’s advice is, “Let us live happily
not hating those who hate us. Let us live free from hatred among those who hate
us. Let us live happily and be free from ailment. Let us live happily and be free
35
Introduction to Ethics from greed among those who are greedy (Dhammapada 197-200). Buddha says,
“If a person foolishly does the wrong, I will return to him the protection of my
boundless love. The more evil that comes from him the more good will go from
me. I will always give of only the fragrance of goodness.
Ranganathan, Shyam. Ethics and the History of Indian Philosophy. Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass, 2007.
36
Ethics in the History of
UNIT 4 ETHICS IN THE HISTORY OF Indian Philosophy
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY
Contents
4.0 Objectives
4.1 Introduction
4.2 Epicurus
4.3 Aristotle
4.4 Thomas Aquinas
4.5 William of Ockham
4.6 Thomas Hobbes
4.7 Jeremy Bentham
4.8 Immanuel Kant
4.9 John Stuart Mill
4.10 Emile Durkheim
4.11 Let Us Sum Up
4.12 Key Words
4.13 Further Readings and References
4.0 OBJECTIVES
As Sir David Ross points out, in a classical work Foundations of Ethics, written
over sixty years ago, there are, broadly speaking, two approaches to ethics. This
is better known as the distinction between deontological and teleological ethics.
The Greek word for an ‘end’, in the sense of a goal to be achieved, is telos.
Hence, ‘teleological’ ethics comprises all those kinds of ethics which see the
criterion of morality in terms of whether an action fulfills the overall total end of
human life in general and of moral activity in particular. The word ‘deontological’
was coined by the British moralist, Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), from the Greek
word, deon, literally, that which is binding. Deontological ethics views the morally
good in terms of doing ones duty. Deontology would be the science of moral
duties. We shall see that these two approaches differ more in emphasis than
anything else; they are not mutually exclusive water-tight compartments.
4.1 INTRODUCTION
Let us start with teleological approach. Ever since Aristotle, practically the entire
Western tradition of philosophizing has accepted his contention that the ultimate
human end is “happiness.” Now this could be understood as either exclusively,
or with a strong stress on, individual or private happiness. This, in turn, can be
understood in two further ways: as pleasure (but not in the narrow, crude sense
that the term usually implies), in which case we have the school hedonistic ethics;
or it can be seen as self-realization and this is the eudaimonic approach. The
other alternative is to see happiness more from the standpoint of others, of the
community. Thus the utilitarian ethics may once again be looked at from a personal
37
Introduction to Ethics or a social dimension. Summarizing all this in a convenient diagram, we can
represent it thus
Teleological Ethics
The norm of morality for Aquinas, then, is ultimately God’s eternal law or “eternal
reason”, but more proximately it is “human reason” which can work out its
implications by critically reflecting on what the “natural law” entails. That which
is in conformity with the demands of the natural law, as discovered partly by the
right use of human reason, is morally good; that which is not, is morally bad.
Obviously, for Aquinas, the norm of morality (“natural law”) is intrinsic to the
human act and not an extrinsic command or anything else outside of it.
But Ockham seems to confuse the whole issue by giving a place to both God’s
ordered power as well as right reason. The former refers to God’s free decision,
whereby he has established the actual moral order, opting to make certain actions
right and other wrong. He would hardly make a general change in this matter.
All this seems to conflict with his other notion which says that a morally good
act should also be in conformity with the “right reason.” Indeed, he goes along
with the common medieval assumption that a person is obliged to follow what,
according to his sincere conviction, is in conformity with it, even if he were in
error. But this last idea seems to do more credit to Ockham’s head than his heart.
For if he thereby opened up the possibility for a person who does not accept
divine revelation (how else, except through divine revelation could we come to
know what is right and what is wrong, since God freely decides this), yet there
seems to be a certain contradiction here: if “right reason” can somehow account
for moral rightness, then it is not quite dependent exclusively on God’s free
choice.
Most human beings, however, do not know precisely how to apply this standard
in daily life, especially when it is a matter of making an option between multiple
choices. To this end he offers “a felicific calculus” as a guideline for the common
man in his decision making process. First of all, he observes, it would seem
reasonable that one should choose that action which would bring about the greatest
amount of pleasure for the greatest number of persons for the longest stretch of
time. He then proposes seven norms to help one in making such a measurement.
It is all a matter of focusing on the pleasure concerned and checking out its
intensity, duration, certainty, nearness, fecundity (its capacity to include other
pleasurable sensations), purity (its freedom from any admixture of unpleasant
sensations) and inclusiveness (the number of people affected by it). Bentham
widened the meaning of pleasure to involve certain altruistic and “unselfish”
elements. Be that as it may, the stress he put on the quantitative dimension of
pleasure almost “begs for a misunderstanding”.
41
Introduction to Ethics
4.8 IMMANUEL KANT (1724-1804)
The “sage of Konigsberg” was to have a major impact on the development of
contemporary western thought. The second volume of his famous philosophical
trilogy of the “critiques” was devoted to new and revolutionary insights into
ethics. Right at the onset of his critique of practical reason he rejects all such
system that is based on a “heteronomous” source, that is, on some principle or
norm outside the human person. Were we to maintain such a point of view, he
tells us, in effect, if a person had to reject that norm, and then there would be no
basis helping him or her to be a moral person. Thus, he begins by noting that in
us there are not only some a-priory (hence universal and necessary) principles of
speculative knowledge in us, but similar principles of practical knowledge. In as
much as these are a-priori, they constitute an internal norm of morality in man:
“autonomous principles.”
For Kant, the only thing that can be called “good” without qualification is a
“good will” – all other “goods,” such as health, wealth and long life can be used
for bad ends: they are only relatively “good”. Now, what precisely is a “good
will”? A will which acts for the sake of duty alone (and no other motive) is a
good will. This is perhaps Kant’s way of telling us that a “good will” does not act
out of self-interest. Be that as it may, the kind of language he used has given his
doctrine a very “rigorist” appearance. This “duty” is rooted in the moral law
itself, which, in turn, is manifest moral consciousness (a-prior synthetic practical
judgments). Now, “universality” is the very form of the moral law – so, once
again, a certain rigidity is to be expected of its “categorical” demands: allowing
the possibility of exceptions would do violence to this “universal” form of the
normal law. The first general formulation of the basic categorical imperative is,
for Kant, “I must act such that my way of acting could become a universal
procedure.” There are other formulations popularized by Kant, especially “Never
treat a person merely as a means,” but they always enshrine some kind of
universality as constitutive of its very form. He derived three “postulates” from
the undeniable fact of the categorical imperative: human freedom, the immortality
of the soul and the existence of God. This is no contradiction of what he had
maintained in the earlier Critique: there he held that one cannot prove these
truths from pure reason, whereas in the second critique he says that practical
reason can and must postulate.
43
Introduction to Ethics Durkhiem has well brought out the link between human social consciousness
and moral development. However he is loath to admit – against the views of
even some of his later disciples – that there seems to be a common underlying
structure, some kind of common principles at work everywhere, that is, the basis
of the admitted diversity of moral set-ups. Again if morality is primarily a matter
of “following the crowd,” how do we account for the emergence of radical thinkers
who openly and daringly rejected and challenged the existing mores of a given
society?
Check Your Progress II
Note: Use the space provided for your answer
1) Brief Durkheim’s materialist explanation of religion.
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
2) Explain Kant’s views on moral obligation.
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
3) Explain Thomas Aquinas’ views of moral philosophy.
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
..............................................................................................................
Now, any worthwhile discussion of ethics, sooner or later, confronts us with the
phrase “human acts”. We should pause for a moment to underline the meaning
and significance of what these words imply. They are actually the legacy of old
scholastic thought and still relevant today. We must need to distinguish between
what could be called “acts of humans” and “human acts” (the Latin maintains
the word play more neatly: actus humanus and actus hominis). A human act is an
act put forward by a person acting in full capacity as human, i.e. out of full
awareness and freedom – after all knowledge and free choice are what characterize
humans as humans. Only when someone does something knowingly and freely
can he/she be held accountable for that act and accordingly, be praised or blamed
for it. If someone were, unknowingly, to drink a cup of poisoned tea, no one
could accuse him or her of attempted suicide. One might say that what he or she
had done was “objectively” a suicidal act (i.e. of itself it would bring about the
person’s death or serious illness, if medical intervention were not sought
immediately), but “subjectively” he or she could not be blamed for the act. This
example should also make us realize that we cannot behave as if only “subjective
morality” were important, since that is the area where praise or blame (“moral
accountability”) comes in. if the action were “objectively wrong” in itself it would
have some bad effects on the agent – psychologically and physiologically – even
if he or she did not do it “full knowledge and full consent,” to use the time
honoured formula. Ethics, then, is more concerned with actions done as a result
of knowledge and free choice: only such actions make us better or worse persons
all-round. Acts of humans, that is, actions done unintentionally, unknowingly
(including doing an “objectively” wrong action while not knowing such an act is
wrong) would not affect one all-round as a person.
45