Reintroducing Gabriel Tarde - Tonkonoff
Reintroducing Gabriel Tarde - Tonkonoff
Reintroducing Gabriel Tarde - Tonkonoff
TARDE
The ‘Reintroducing’ series offers concise and accessible books that remind us
of the importance of sociological theorists whose work, while constituting
a significant and lasting contribution to the discipline, is no longer widely
discussed. With each volume examining the major themes in thought of a
particular figure and the context in which this work came about, as well
as its reception and enduring relevance to contemporary social science, the
books in this series will appeal to scholars and students of sociology seeking
to rediscover the work of important but often neglected sociologists.
Sergio Tonkonoff
Designed cover image: Rodrigo Kugnharski / unsplash
First published 2024
by Routledge
4 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
605 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10158
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa
business
© 2024 Sergio Tonkonoff
The right of Sergio Tonkonoff to be identified as author of this work
has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or
reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical,
or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including
photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval
system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks
or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and
explanation without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
ISBN: 978-1-032-05398-1 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-1-032-05397-4 (pbk)
ISBN: 978-1-003-19738-6 (ebk)
DOI: 10.4324/9781003197386
Typeset in Sabon
by Apex CoVantage, LLC
To Martina
CONTENTS
List of f igures ix
This book aims to reintroduce the work of Gabriel Tarde. It seeks to retrieve
Tarde’s figure by showing how his peculiar way of approaching social reality
may be of interest today. Tarde is a theorist of the contagion of social beliefs
and desires, and one of the first social thinkers to conceptualise masses and
publics and to analyse their dynamics. He was also one of the first sociolo-
gists to draw attention to the role of inventions in social life and to deal with
the social world in terms of flows and networks. Moreover, he has explored
the nature-society relation in a non-traditional manner, certainly more orien-
tated to see continuity rather than separation between both of them. We aim
to highlight the enduring relevance of this general theoretical approach and
of many of his specific analyses.
Towards the end of the 19th century, Gabriel Tarde was a world-leading
pioneer in social sciences and humanities. At that time, his sociological, psy-
chological and philosophical ideas gained great visibility and interest. How-
ever, his work was later forgotten and his name was barely mentioned in the
history of social thought. Some of his main concepts survived in the work
of other thinkers whom he influenced, such as R. Park, W. James, F. Boas,
H. Bergson, and, closer in time, G. Deleuze, M. Foucault and B. Latour, that
is authors who are either part of the canon of different disciplines or that are
at least unavoidable references in them. During most of the 20th century,
Tarde was not that lucky. His works stopped being published and his name
barely appeared in books of history of social sciences next to broad exposi-
tions about those whose works were considered real classics: Comte, Spencer,
Marx, Durkheim and Weber, just to name the most important ones.
So, what happened with Tarde? And what happens today? Why is his
work difficult to access and scarcely distributed nowadays, in spite of the
DOI: 10.4324/9781003197386-1
2 Introduction
dominate the scene during almost the entire 20th century. Therefore, Tarde is
not merely departmentally misplaced. He does not fit the disciplinary distri-
bution that still weighs on scientific practices, because he does not respond to
the most profound and transversal epistemological distributions that organ-
ise them, namely atomism-totalism, agency-structure and micro-macro pairs.
If this is true, social sciences have had enough reasons to “forget” Tarde.
because, for Tarde, reality does not only seem to be plural, diverse, changing
and hazardous, but also actually is.
In order to acknowledge this, it is necessary to substitute the telescope for
the microscope and plunge into the realm of the infinitely small, revealing its
dynamics. This is so because everything would be made of an infinity of tiny
forces, imperceptible at human scale. They are the ones which actually rule
the world in all its manifestations. Thus, we read,
The assumption here is that the plurality and motion of the visible world
has its origin in a swarming multitude of minuscule, different forces which
associate with one another as much as they combat and disregard them-
selves, as well. Therefore, a special sensibility for the infinitesimal is required
here. This implies, among other things, that the overabundant and whimsi-
cally detailed writing with which Tarde elaborates his scientific texts does
not (only) depend on his taste for literature and speculation. At a deeper
level, there is an epistemological problem at stake. Classical science is driven
by a will of absolute clarity—the same can be said of philosophies and arts
kindred to it. In them, lack of clarity pertains just to a stage of knowledge;
still, as long as it is aimed in the right direction, it is sure to become accurate
sooner or later. In (neo) baroque science and philosophy, like the one held
by Tarde as model for his sociology, all clarity obtained can only be relative.
Here, as in Leibniz’s metaphysics and in Rembrandt’s painting, the chiaro-
scuro reigns: darkness and light succeed one another rhythmically and end-
lessly, always mediated by an infinity of hues. This never-ending succession
of masses of heterogeneous clarity, in continuity with masses of shadows and
masses of darkness of diverse tonalities, does not take place exclusively on a
bidimensional plane. It must also be conceived in depth, in the direction of
the infinitely small. Also in this sense is clarity relative, as is simplicity. This
implies, among other things, the impossibility of finding ultimate, homoge-
neous and separate elements, no matter how deep we can go towards the
tiny and detailed. To go towards the minuscule, to the detail of things, is to
forever find more details within the detail. It is also to find that the detail is
“intertwined everywhere”, as Leibniz wished.
8 Introduction
I could resort here to the high authority of Mr. Poincaré who, in the 1900
International Congress of Physics, stated that the very simplicity of New-
ton’s Law was perhaps only apparent and illusory. “Who knows—he
argued—if this law is not the result of some complex mechanism, of the
clash of some subtle matter driven by irregular movements. . . . Undoubt-
edly, if our research means became more and more penetrating, we would
unveil the simple underneath the complex, then the complex underneath
the simple, then again the simple underneath the complex, and so on,
without getting to predict which will be the last cycle . . .”. This alleged
shift to and from simplicity and complexity, regularity and irregularity, on
the superimposed layers of phenomena, from the infinitesimal to the infi-
nite, is a very deep vision to which we are led by the consideration not only
of physical facts but also of social ones. This vision in itself constitutes a
rhythm, perhaps a vague one, but of no minor importance because of that.
(Tarde, 1902: 131)
This is not about renouncing scientific knowledge, nor about the search
for clarity. It is about formulating a non-reductionist knowledge whose
starting point are differences and relations, given the fact that it would not
acknowledge any ultimate, simple, homogeneous and separate elements.
Neither would there be immutable elements. Thus, total and final clarity,
the perfect definition of things, implies its denaturalisation by paralysis and
simplification. The (neo) baroque knowledge in question is, instead, consti-
tutively asymptotic, due to its fidelity to diversity, movement and connec-
tion, in a universe which is not only infinite but also infinitesimal. For this
reason, when observing the stars in the sky, this perspective does not find
perfectly circular, regular, uniform orbits of perfectly spherical bodies. Apart
from verifying the elliptic path of “deform” planets, it can also assume that
they are irregular upon close inspection, and contingent in the long run. And
this is so because planets—like everything else—are immersed in an infinite
field of infinitesimal forces without any pre-established centre, direction or
harmony. This turmoil of intertwined vibration and variation is more akin
to Van Gogh’s “Starry Night” than to the graphic schemes of our elementary
education. And the same happens in all other realms of nature—including
human societies.
Tarde expects us to marvel at the social world’s multiplicity and dynamism
every time we look at it—as he does. He hopes we do not ignore the lush
diversity of sociality in its uneven details and its chaotic emergence of singu-
lar events. The question is to understand that social life’s being—or better,
Introduction 9
exist. Throughout his work, we will not find this canonical feeling of loss
implied in the passage from community to society—as it can be found in
Tönnies, Weber and Durkheim. Rather on the contrary, the future is always
better for Tarde because it involves progressive socialisation. But then, if indi-
vidual diversity and change are irreducible, how are social similarities and
regularities possible? And how are groups and institutions produced? Tarde’s
answer is: by imitation.
Tarde defines imitation as an “action at a distance” from one brain on
another. To imitate is to mirror, replicate, reflect something coming from
someone. That something is a specific way of doing, feeling or thinking; and
to imitate it is to repeat it. Thus, imitation is a relational, communicative
activity, which Tarde considers contagious. Imitation bonds, inter-penetrates
and deploys itself as a social tendency. It is therefore an associative, homog-
enising force provoking the regular repetition of similar conducts, thoughts
and feelings in a group of different individuals. These individuals, who claim
to be autonomous, are not in fact able to make use of this alleged auton-
omy. And this is because they are constantly steered by these mimetic social
bonds “compared to which the part that is attributable to their freedom is
of an irrelevant quantity” (Tarde, 1890a: 127). To put it in everyday lan-
guage, which is often welcomed by Tarde, it is a matter of social influence.
More specifically, what is at stake here is the blazing, quick force of fashion,
and the slower, no less persuasive force of custom—two types of imitation,
according to the Tardean scheme.
Making good use of the analogical method that characterises him, Tarde
will say that every instant repeats the sun’s attraction on the Earth, and that
explains the regularity of its elliptic orbit—not spared of the disturbances
resulting from the attraction of other planets. Mutatis mutandis: if every
individual initiative were beyond any form of social attraction, the regularity
shown by the annual figures for marriages, births, work activities, commer-
cial exchanges and religious, political, and aesthetic practices as well as sui-
cides, robberies and murders would not exist. Therefore, individuals cannot
be the elemental forces of social life. The sociological microscope discovers
that imitation is the transmission of beliefs and desires. These are the infini-
tesimal agents that actually weave and drive social processes, and there is a
multitude of them in every individual. What is imitable and imitated are not
individuals as such but rather (some of) the beliefs and desires they transmit.
We do not imitate an individual, nor do we do it in general. It is always a
specific idea or desire, a certain precise judgement or intention (e.g. one polit-
ical idea, one religious dogma, certain legal norm, agricultural technique,
type of love, and not others). Then, economy, science, art, religion and any
other social practice, often substantivised, are nothing but the propagation of
infinitesimal actions traced one over the other.
Introduction 11
Every current way in which we act, feel or think was at some point put
into practice by a subtle or spectacular example that multiplied by way of its
imitative diffusion. Such is the specific way in which social groups and their
institutions are born and reproduce themselves. Now, according to Tarde,
these examples originate from those precise sources he calls inventions, that
is from the creation, hazardous to a certain extent, of unprecedented ways of
doing, feeling and thinking. Countless inventions come to us from different
past times and places, making us what we are. And at each moment, social
life is bursting with innumerable inventions, most of which are tiny and
imperceptible. Each one is an unexpected bifurcation in the regular course
of things, because it brings a novelty that tends to spread as fashion and
that, if lucky, will turn into tradition. Therefore, Tarde can state that imita-
tions are social “periodical forces” (constant in magnitude and direction)
and inventions are social “directing forces” (accidental and divergent). They
prevent the closure of the historical deployment. If all imitation comes from
an invention, then “the normal derives from the accidental” (Tarde, 1882:
271). Here, the accident is not opposed to regularity or to system because it
is at the origin of both.
All things considered,
Notes
1 See Toews (1999, 2003), Borch (2005, 2017), Katz (1992, 2006), Sampson (2012,
2012b), King (2016) and Tonkonoff (2017). In English, there are at least two col-
lections of articles (Candea, 2010; Leroux, 2018) and two important special issues
in journals of social sciences: Barry and Thrift (2007) and Tarde (2004).
2 See for instance, Durkheim’s (1975: 180) severe words: “The origin of our disa-
greement is elsewhere. It comes above all from the fact that I believe in science and
Mr. Tarde does not”. Following this line, Laurent Mucchielli (2000: 181) summa-
rises things in this way: “Durkheim has succeeded in embodying a certain form of
rationality—scientific rationality—that consists of methods, examples, reasoning
logics, standardised proceedings of validation and argumentation, all things that
cannot be found in Tarde, whose thought belongs more to traditional philosophy,
even sometimes to a way of writing and demonstration that is nearer journalism.
Now, in the expression ‘social science’, it is the word ‘science´”.
1
INFINITE AND SOCIAL THEORY
DOI: 10.4324/9781003197386-2
14 Infinite and social theory
Everything undoubtedly starts with the infinitely minute; and we may add
that it probably returns thither; this is its alpha and omega. Everything
that constitutes the visible universe, the universe accessible to observation,
proceeds, . . . out of the invisible and inscrutable, out of a seeming noth-
ingness, whence all reality emerges in an inexhaustible stream.
(Tarde, 1898: 68)
This premise has a philosophical and scientific value and implies a way of
understanding the world in general, and the social world in particular. It also
entails a guide to know it.
It could be said that this is like putting a chair on the head: wrong, useless,
grotesque. We are used to assume that, in social terms, everything occurs
between individuals and groups, and that none of them has nothing infinitesi-
mal (at least nothing important) or infinite (how could they?). Tarde replies
that those who fear error and ridicule should not work in the field of social
Infinite and social theory 15
sciences, or of any other science. He anticipates that the most dynamic vec-
tors of physics, chemistry and biology will move forward in the understand-
ing of nature by the route of the microscopic, and he proposes sociology to
do the same. However, he warns that atomism is not the way. He does not
deny that everything that exists is made of minuscule, potent and dynamic
elements; but he rejects the hypothesis of their ultimate indivisibility and sim-
plicity. He also denies that such elements are separated from each other, and
that they are completely determined and actual. Therefore, he rejects the met-
aphysics of particles that informs Newtonian sciences and he advocates for
a relational and living universe, a universe loaded of virtualities. That is to
say, the universe as it is conceived by Leibniz’s metaphysics and explored in
his mathematics of infinites and his dynamic physics. With this background,
Tarde invites natural sciences to take the sociological model because he hoists
another fundamental principle: everything is a society. Everything, namely
human groups, but also the individuals that make up them, as well as bodies,
cells, molecules, atoms and stars. This also implies that everything is in rela-
tion to everything and that nothing is separate. And even two more premises
are on the basis of this infinitesimal sociology: nothing is identical to itself or
to anything else, and nothing is never still.
To comprehend adequately Tarde’s sociology, it is essential to address these
general principles, even when they appear strange. This will avoid redirecting
this sociology to other well-known, and maybe stronger, fundamentals that
are alien to it—or, better yet, hostile. His perspective remains distorted every
time that the baroque impulse that feeds it is recovered by any classical syn-
taxes (whether rationalist, empiricist or dialectic). It is precisely the introduc-
tion of the infinite and the infinitesimals in the social and subjective field that
prevents Tarde’s sociology from adjusting to usual disciplinary distributions.
Infinitesimals or differentials
It can be said that if 1/100 is the hundredth part of something, then an infini-
tesimal is the infinitieth part of it. For that reason, the English mathematician
John Wallis, who introduced the notation ∞ as the symbol of the infinite in
1655, represented the infinitesimal as one over infinite.
An infinitesimal quantity is an extremely tiny quantity compared to 1/2,
1/3, 1/4, 1/8 and so forth, but it is not 0. It is therefore important to highlight
its extraordinarily small character. In fact, infinitesimals are imperceptible and,
at least in mathematics, their insignificance enables them to be underestimated
when convenient. However, this very same miniscule character turns them into
the path to the resolution of a great number of both practical and theoretical
problems in very varied realms: infinitesimal calculus is a major tool in phys-
ics, chemistry, biology, engineering, medicine, architecture and so forth. That
is why Tarde, and some others, believed that the “key of the entire universe”
is in infinitesimals and in the particular micro-logic that accompanies them.
Wallis’ notation remarks that size is not the only thing at stake here: the
reign of infinitesimals is as minute as infinite. A certain perplexity is then
inevitable: how to reach the infinitesimal part of something? Once we enter
this vertiginous slope, the indefinite division clause will prevent us from stop-
ping. Every time you think you have found the smallest part of what is pre-
sented as entire, it is possible to advance to an even smaller one, without ever
reaching the last term. The infinitesimals are then beyond the usual measures
of everyday life; they are “incomparably small”—with respect to whole num-
bers, for instance. But they are also unreachable as discrete, fixed and final
elements. For that reason, Leibniz named them unassignable and Newton
qualified them as evanescent. This is equivalent to stating that it is not pos-
sible to assign them a precise localisation, or a clear definition.
In view of this, it is possible to understand why so many scientists and
philosophers mistrusted these strange entities. Some rejected them (Berkerly,
D’alambert) and some others took them carefully (Newton and sometimes
Leibniz). There were also some who worked to replace them for mathemati-
cal concepts that were considered more rigorous (Weierstrass, Dedekind,
Cantor, Russel). However, it was precisely this spectral, dynamic, impercep-
tible and inexhaustible character of the infinitesimals that magnetised the
philosophical and scientific thought of Leibniz, Spinoza or Maimon. Closer
in time, and for the very same reasons, they were recovered by Tarde as
well as by the already mentioned De Biran, Cournot, Bergson and Deleuze.1
Another unavoidable reference in this constellation of infinitesimal advocates
is the American philosopher and scientific Ch. S. Pierce. They all understand
that infinitesimals and their associated concepts apprehend somehow the
relational, procedural, micro-genetic and infinite character of everything that
exists. They seem convinced that, whatever the technical difficulties may be,
the infinitesimals manage to penetrate the basic plot of the real, which is
made of innumerable, subtle and fluctuating forces differentially integrated.
That is why, each of them in his own way, has sought to deploy the episte-
mology and the ontology that the infinitely small contain or inspire. And they
Infinite and social theory 17
and heterogeneous series. The basic example is given by number phi in the
infinite continuum of whole numbers.2
Leibniz’s universe
The postulate of the infinitude of nature has had major consequences. It
implied the passage from a geocentric and finitist view, in which the idea of
the complete and hierarchically ordered whole prevailed, to another one in
which the never-ending space prevents the setting of a centre and finding of a
symmetric order for all things. To use the classical formula of Koyré (1957),
it implied the passage from a closed world to an open and endless universe.
This change is crucial but it is still insufficient for the perspective that con-
cerns us because the ontological and epistemological key of the infinitesimal
revolution lies on the statute given to that infinitude. In this regard, there are
two fundamental and alternative directions. On the one hand, the concep-
tion of an infinite universe made of atoms and void, where matter is only
potentially divisible. This is Demócrito’s view and, to some extent, Newton’s.
On the other hand, the idea of an infinitely big universe where everything is
potentially endlessly divisible, but that is also actually divided into infinite
parts. This is Leibniz’s and his progeny’s vision. According to this point of
view, if we recognise the infinite extension of the cosmos and also its poten-
tially infinite divisibility, we are still halfway. The key point lies in conceiving
time and space, but also movement, matter and bodies, made up of interior
infinitudes. In order to have a vivid idea of this, it is worth quoting, once
again, Leibniz’s famous text (1986):
This text summarises the Leibnizian point of view, showing how fantasti-
cal it may be for modern scientific and philosophical common sense. Leibniz
asserts that the universe is actually infinite and that there are living forces in
the smallest portion of matter—including seemingly inert inorganic matter.
Therefore, everything is alive and there are worlds within worlds, all of them
chained and proliferating interminably. In order to better understand these
Infinite and social theory 21
something really fantastic happens: the multiple nests in the absolutely sim-
ple or, in other words, each one hosts the infinite somehow. Each monad is
the “living mirror” of the universe which it expresses from its particular and
unrepeatable point of view (Leibniz, 1986: 74). This implies that every sub-
stance or soul is individualised given its place inside an (infinite) network of
unrepeatable positions. It also implies that the whole universe is expressed in
each monad but in very different grades of clarity—leaving absolute clarity
and distinction only to God.
But each monad acts from that particular position or perspective and, due
to the same principle of continuity, each action has universal consequences.
Every action, no matter how small, extends to infinity as much with regard
to places as with regard to times, radiating so to speak throughout the
entire universe, and being conserved for all eternity. So, . . . the actions of
souls which are always conserved, and even the action of each soul is con-
served in each soul because of the conspiracy and sympathy of all things,
the world being fully complete in each of its parts, albeit more distinctly
in some than in others.
(Leibniz, 2011: 154)
created world. However, not every possible essence is composable with all
the others, precisely because of the criterion in question. Accordingly, there is
a very close relation between pre-established harmony, possible essences and
real existences: ‘to exist is nothing other than to be harmonious” (Leibniz,
1914: 97).
The harmony of the monadological universe then depends on an eternal,
infinite and thoughtful being that created what exists with the simplest means
and the greatest variety of effects, in order to ensure the possible greatest
diversity and concordance. As a multitude of existing multitudes, the world
is the effect of the combinatory harmonisation produced by the Full Cause
or the Principle of Reason, which is God. Because of this Monad of monads,
the world is one even when it unfolds in infinite active subjects. Each of these
subjects reflects in all the rest in very different ways and contains in herself
everything that happens—not only now, but also ever and forever. This is
another extraordinary consequence of this model of the world. Here, every
substance
expresses, although confusedly, all that happens in the universe, past, pre-
sent and future, deriving thus a certain resemblance to an infinite percep-
tion or power of knowing. And since all other substances express this
particular substance and accommodate themselves to it, we can say that
it exerts its power upon all the others in imitation of the omnipotence of
the creator.
(Leibniz, 1908: 15)
which this question is presented and seeks to be solved. Unlike most of the
social sciences of his time—and ours—Tarde argues that the social multiplic-
ity is infinitesimal. Now we are aware that this means micro-linear, unassign-
able, variable and intensive. This leads him to a radical redefinition of what
is usually considered both a social group and its elements. Tarde addresses
the statute of the whole and the parts of the social in a framework that is not
finitist but rather infinist. Therefore, his sociology is neo-baroque and not
classical.
Tarde’s sociology depends on a renewed reading of monadology and,
broadly speaking, it can be read as a translation of its infinitist and infini-
tesimal logic to the social and subjective field. However, the fact that this
Leibnizian syntax operates as an infrastructure of his theoretical discourse
does not imply that Tarde accepts it completely without making important
reforms. He summarises the keys of his rereading in a series of program-
matic slogans scattered in different texts.4 To the already reviewed principle,
according to which everything departs from (and goes back to) the infini-
tesimal, another crucial premise must be added: difference is the alpha and
the omega. According to this version of the Principle of the Indiscernibles,
that in Tarde has maybe a more salient role than in his German master, it is
essential “to identify the essence and end of every being with its characteristic
difference, that is to say, in giving the difference as an end in itself”. “The
initial and final term is always difference, the characteristic, the bizarre and
inexplicable agitation at the basis of all things, which reappears more clearly
and sharply after each successive effacement” (Tarde, 1895: 101). But how to
put into practice these singular ontological principles when addressing social
life? Which general conception of the social and of the ways of knowing it
are requested or permitted?
According to Tarde, these principles imply, in the first place, a micro-
genetic and micro-analytic requirement: everything that appears in front of
us as a defined and stable totality must be aimed at the multiplicity of the
historically specific micro-processes that sustain its duration. Moreover, we
should register the evolutions that configuration constantly has. This is valid
for any social compound, that is to say, for what we call society and its
functional equivalents (culture, civilisation, group), as well as for its mor-
phological correlates (nation, region, city). It is also true for what is usually
called social institutions (government, law, science, religion). It is not a mat-
ter of ignoring the differential traits of these social configurations, but rather
of conceptualising them in general terms and interrogating what they really
are—or, better yet, what kind of reality they have (Tarde, 1901a).
To this, Tarde responds with the following: every social reality is psychic
or, even better, inter-mental. That is its basic statute. In particular, he argues
that everything that is social is made of beliefs and desires that, repeating as an
echo, go from an individual to another, intertwining and in inter-expressing
26 Infinite and social theory
them. Beliefs and desires are not simply microscopic; they are infinitesimal,
that is minuscule, dynamic and expansive, but also non-assignable, micro-
linear and infinite. And this in at least three main important senses: due to
their unlimited capacity to combine, to their intensive character which makes
them susceptible to infinite infinitesimal variations of grade and because of
their unlimited deployment vocation. These minute, evanescent, active and
effective forces propagate interpenetrating and inter-reflecting the minds (and
bodies) they pass through. These fluxes of faith and passion form associa-
tions of very diverse scales and contents. Empires, States, big metropolises,
tiny towns; religious groups, political parties, professions and crafts; finan-
cial markets, universities, youth gangs: every social association is a network
of inter-mental relations that communicate individuals, resembling them and
driving all in a certain direction.
This assertion of the psychic character of social reality may lead us to
believe that this is a conception of the social in which individuals are its
basic constituents, especially if we understand monadology as a metaphysical
atomism or we suppose that, conceiving it in this way, Tarde identifies social
monads with individuals. But this is not the case. In Tarde’s reading, Leibniz’s
great hypothesis certainly implies the reduction of matter to spirit and leads
us to the “prodigious multiplication of purely spiritual agents of the world”
(Tarde, 1895: 309). This point of view may be esoteric, but Tarde finds it
working in the most advanced vectors of natural sciences when they follow
the path of the microscopic to reveal the mysteries of the world. Pulverising
everything that seems sturdy and made of one piece in a human scale, science
discovers a multitudinary nebula of minuscule, active, specific and different
elements, thus atoms in chemistry and physics, cells in biology, viruses and
bacteria in medicine. But this is only the first step. It is also necessary to
spiritualise the corpuscles discovered. That is, it is necessary to treat them
as (micro) forces, and not as particles—and most natural sciences actually
do. Social sciences should follow the same direction if they want to compre-
hend social life in its dynamics. However, in this field, the real forces are not
individuals as such, but rather beliefs and desires that live and act in each of
them—most of the time, in an imperceptible way. Such is Tarde’s main (neo)
monadological hypothesis and the basis of his infinitesimal sociology.
In Tarde’s microscopic view, the human individual is already a set—
or, better yet, a society—configured by a multitude of very diverse infini-
tesimal forces, in accordance with the Renacentist and baroque tradition
that discovers the cosmos as an endless chain of worlds within worlds.
Here, every individual is conceived as a micro-cosmos beating in intimate
relation with the macro-cosmos that contains and constitutes her. Hence,
like Pascal and Leibniz, each individual is for Tarde a means or passage
between two infinites: the infinitely large and infinitesimal ones. Among
other things, this means that the past and the future of the universe is
Infinite and social theory 27
In Tarde’s words,
the states of the soul taken in all their concrete reality [are the] meet-
ing point at the same time of all the actions of external nature and of all
the influences of the social milieu, multiple crossroads where a thousand
physical forces and a thousand historical currents cross for the first and
the last time, currents of ideas, feelings, examples of all kinds, customs and
fashions, which in the form of the words of a language, of the rites of a
cult, of the procedures of right, of national or local customs mark the indi-
vidual soul with their seal and in return receive a new impression from it.
(Tarde, 1898: 25–26)
Micro-mega
Regarding human groups and their institutions, they should also be under-
stood as ensembles of heterogeneous currents of beliefs and desires dif-
ferentially integrated. It is important to underline that, even though they
are psychic currents in continuity with cosmic life, they are strictly social.
Although Tarde understands that there is no (Cartesian) hiatus between
body and soul, or between nature and culture, he also asserts that there
exist irreducibly social forces. Such things are passions and dogmas, interests
and principles—that is to say, beliefs and desires—which are always social
because they are born in the inter-psychic relation and they later propagate
as mental epidemics that reach the most diverse numerical, geographic and
temporal scales. According to Tarde, nothing is psychologically more similar
or sociologically more communicable than faith and passion, convictions and
volitions. Each current carries specific ways of doing, feeling and thinking
that strive to unfold and has an own and characteristic reasoning (or logos)
and purpose (or telos). Therefore, each current differs from the rest and is
opposed to many others, disposing to destroy them if possible. Nevertheless,
regularity and reproduction, as well as the organised composition of diverse
trends, take place, producing polyphonic assemblages that we know with the
name of societies, groups or institutions.
As we have seen, if in Leibniz’s model all substances or souls are correlated
in such a way that each one adjusts to all the rest following its own laws, it
is so because such correspondence has been pre-established by an instance
that coordinates all of them (God) since the beginning of the times. Tarde’s
perspective is neo-monadological because, among other things, his model
of reality no longer has that guarantee. This transforms the world in an off-
centred field of forces dominated by contingency. Nevertheless, this does not
lead to the abandoning of the principle of universal harmony because, also
for Tarde, to exist is to harmonise. But the harmonic conjugation of physical,
psychic or social vectors is no longer presupposed. It is rather a trending and
Infinite and social theory 29
We can see then that in Tarde the real agents of social life are neither indi-
viduals nor groups or societal systems, but rather the multitude of beliefs and
desires of which all of them are made. This implies at least three main ques-
tions: that social monads are not individuals but rather the beliefs and desires
that inhibit and constitute them; that those social agents are smaller, more
varied and variable than the individuals they make up and unmake; and that
they are, at the same time, larger or, better yet, more extensive. This is because,
as they are inter-mental, they always go beyond each individual, working at
least between two of them. But also because, when they propagate, they form
infinitesimal lines of relation of local, regional and planetary scales.
Therefore, the social exists and it is nothing but the multitude of all the
mirroring individuals that, immersed in nature, interact with each other.
However, as we have argued, these are compounded individuals in whose
interior a multitude of (mirror?) neurons interact and, inside them, the social
multiplicity penetrates, reflects and interacts and makes the individuals act
with themselves and with each other.
After all, this phenomenon is much less exceptional than it seems; Is it that
the individual, even when alone, is not moved, without our knowledge and
without his knowledge, by an invisible and innumerable multitude, that of
his ancestors, his countrymen, his educators, whose combined influences,
stored in his brain, . . . they wake up startled and all together at certain
moments, a true swarming and fermenting inner crowd under one skull.
(Tarde, 1892: 291)
Notes
1 For a contemporary defense of infinitesimals both in philosophical and mathemati-
cal terms, see the concise and beautiful article written by Bell (1995). For a history
of calculus, see Boyer (1959).
2 The Argentine writer J. L. Borges, another Leibnizian, illustrated this by imagining
a book of sand. It is a finite volume which seems to contain an infinite number of
pages: “He told me that his book was called The Book of Sand because neither the
book nor the sand has a beginning or an end” (Borges, 1977: 13).
3 That is for instance the case of Russel (1971: 134) who asserts that “In spite of the
law of continuity, Leibniz’s philosophy may be described as a complete denial of
the continuous”.
4 In Tarde’s vast work, there are a few texts where Leibniz’s philosophy is explicitly
thematized. In addition to the extraordinary essay “Monadology and Sociology”, it
is important to mention Les Possibles, La Variation Universal and, largely, “Beliefs
and Desires”. Except for Les Possibles, published posthumously, all of them are
compiled in Essais et Mélanges Sociologiques in 1895. For a philosophical com-
ment on Tarde’s neo-monadology, see Debaise (2008), Alliez (1999), Montebello
(2003) and, particularly, Milet (1970). For an analysis on the relation of Tarde with
contemporary social theory and its impact in the works of Deleuze and Foucault,
see Tonkonoff (2017).
2
INDIVIDUAL, SOCIETY AND
SOCIAL FIELD
At the end of the 19th century, Tarde sought to establish the basis of a sci-
ence of the social that is singular still today. He aimed at formulating a series
of general principles, theoretical concepts and research methodologies which
have difference and change both as starting and arrival points. That is to say,
a science that, drawing from the tumult and the phenomenal variety of the
social world, is capable of addressing the units, similarities and durations that
can be found in it, without losing its constitutive plurality, heterogeneity and
dynamism. Instead of postulating structures and systems that homogenise
diversity making it irrelevant (totalism), or instead of affirming a multiplic-
ity of individualities that makes nominal every group (atomism), this science
of the social pursues an alternative that is able to think of the conjunction
of what is multiple and different, but without homogenising it. And even as
important as this, without fixing it in static frames and assuming that when
there is permanence, there is no change—and vice versa.
According to Tarde, the intellectual framework that will enable this feat
is the thought of infinitesimal difference and its compositions. The develop-
ment of this perspective is found in Leibniz’s philosophical wake and in an
epistemology orientated by analogies taken from the differential and inte-
gral calculus.1 It is then a (neo) monadological and infinitist perspective able
to produce a “quiet revolution” in social sciences because it leads to dis-
cover that variety, fluctuation and incompleteness are the primary charac-
ters of social reality. And the same is true for the field we call subjective or
individual—and also for the rest of nature. This involves the production of
concepts and methods that can address the picturesqueness of the social as
its main trait, rather than considering it as an appearance to dispel, as a mist
that covers its reality, which would ultimately be neat, stable and defined.
DOI: 10.4324/9781003197386-3
32 Individual, society and social field
This revolution starts when “the essence and end of all being is identified with
its characteristic difference” (Tarde, 1895a: 416), and when that difference
is characterised as infinitesimal, that is as minute, continuously variable or
moving, and as necessarily plotted in relation to a multitude of other differ-
ences of the same type. However, this is only the first movement because the
infinitesimal differences are liable to integrate in relatively durable composi-
tions. The revolution is then completed when those compositions are concep-
tualised as incomplete working units, which are only partially homogeneous
because they involve different elements with different origins and rhythms.
Neither the notion of society, with its totalising load, nor the notion of
individual with its corpuscular bias, is appropriate enough for this sociology.
The notions of structure, system, mechanism and aggregate, and their respec-
tive metaphors—the building, the organism, the machine and the set—are
not appropriate either. In order to carry out his program, Tarde formulated
a syntax based on a relatively reduced number of concepts intended to be
alternative to these classical perspectives. On the one hand, he proposed imi-
tation, invention and opposition as the keys to an infinitesimal approach to
the social field (another fundamental concept). They configure the domain
of a “differential sociology”, that is a sociology of differences and variations
oriented toward the study of the repetition, interference and conjugation of
beliefs and desires as “elementary, innumerable and infinitesimal” (Tarde,
1898: 35) social forces. On the other hand, he developed what we can call
“integral sociology”, that is a sociology of the moving compositions pro-
duced by these elementary forces.
On that path, Tarde resorts to hydraulic, electro-magnetic and epide-
miological metaphors that are characteristic in his theoretical language. He
elaborates the important concept of flow, current or social ray, and he seeks
to address social life and its vicissitudes in terms of an enormous multiplic-
ity (a field) of vibrations, contagions or imitative propagations that deploy,
intertwine and fight each other. For the same purposes, he also uses tex-
tile and musical metaphors (threads and wefts and ensembles), altogether
with other figures related to the world of mimesis (mirrors and echoes) and
dreams (somnambulism). Most of these images belong to the baroque tradi-
tion, and Tarde recreates them to convert them into means of apprehension,
description and (micro) analysis of the socio-historical and subjective world.
Moreover, he adds what is perhaps his most original and promising contribu-
tion: the metaphor of the brain. As we have already seen, in this sociology
the brain is both the fundamental organ engaged in social relations and the
general model of the social.2
All this will not make the notions of individual and society—nor the
notion of system—disappear. However, these concepts will be significantly
reformulated when advancing in an infinitesimal comprehension of social
life, which requires a series of successive movements. Firstly, a revalorisation
Individual, society and social field 33
of the picturesqueness of the social, of the exuberance of its variety, its details
and singularities, as well as of the profusion of its accidents and variations,
is required. Once this affinity with the chaotic is acquired, it is necessary to
advance from that tingling mass of phenomena towards the individuals taken
in their relations and specific socio-historical practices. This will make visible
a series of similarities, regularities and associations that may be addressed
as of the double sociological hypothesis of imitation and invention, with-
out assuming the macro-entities that explain them. Looking closely, we may
see that the concordance between different individuals and the organisation
of their reciprocal relations do not depend on an objective spirit, mode of
production or collective consciousness that transcend and encompass them.
Actually, a certain way of doing, feeling or thinking originates in a specific
individual, at a given moment and place, and thence propagates, repeating
from one individual to another one, associating and resembling them.
If we stopped there, this would be an individualistic perspective, as Dur-
kheim (1951), Blondel (1928) or Lukes (1968) has considered. But analysing
the relations between individuals micro-sociologically is, although essential,
still insufficient. Tarde understands that there is a social reality and that indi-
viduals are its consequences rather than its causes. He argues that this reality
is psychic and that it is found within individuals because it passes through
them in the form of (collective) currents of opinion, faith, passion, truth and
necessity. The social is therefore not psychological but “inter-mental”. It is
also often imperceptible. It is made of a multitude of micro-flows intertwined
with an infinity of possible forms of social relations. This is a psychosocial
field in which every individual is formed and transformed, and the same is
true for every type of groups and institutions.
For that reason, Tarde (1895: 34) affirms that sociology is the “solar
microscopic of soul”. Such a scientific device starts its research with these
or those concrete individuals, with their beliefs and desires and specific prac-
tices, but it does not find ultimate and private psychological elements there.
Sharpening the gaze, it will reach a bundle of minute social rays or waves that
run forming relational lines of local, regional and planetary scale. Micro-
mega: such is the paradoxical dimension of the social, its size and also its
statute. Let us see.
We must say why things happened in one way and not in another, and in
this each individual counts. This is not only important in cases in which
“big individuals” make big decisions (Caesar crossing the Rubicon is the
model here). Any action, idea or passion may have immeasurable conse-
quences due to the imitative character of social relations.3 On the other
hand, in methodological terms, the individual is a privileged access way for
socio-historical analysis, precisely because she helps to avoid thinking in
general terms and she forces us to address the networks of specific relations
in which she is immersed. The individual is then an antidote against macro-
sociological reifications. If reification is the action of converting something
into a thing, Tarde sees that this operation works in the comprehension
of the social as collective consciousness (Durkheim), as organismic sys-
tem (Spencer) or as dialectical totality (whether Hegelian or Marxist). In
his view, these macro perspectives are substantialist because they postu-
late entities that, from the top or from the depths, command the relations
between individuals. In response to this, Tarde claims a sociology of the
event in which the individual has a fundamental role. However, he knows
that the individual can also be a reification—this time, an atomist reifica-
tion. For him, the political theories of Hobbes, Locke or Rousseau and the
political economy of Smith and Ricardo are remarkable examples in this
regard. Rejecting supra-individual entities and disaggregating the social in
interactions between concrete people, these classical micro-reductionisms
follow a suitable direction. Nonetheless, their approach is not infinitesimal
enough because they do not address entirely the (social) relations that con-
stitute the individuals themselves. Methodological individualism is still a
panoramic view of the social since it offers a corpuscular perspective that
considers individuals as separated, homogeneous and stable totalities. And
it is still substantialist because it considers them as the ultimate elements,
as the building bricks, of the social.
Tarde understands that if we get closer to this question we will see that,
instead of preceding and producing social relations, the individual is one of
their major results.4 Nevertheless, this does not bring us back to the postulate
of the priority of society and its macro-structures—especially because they
would not exist. Tarde shares with Marx, Comte, Durkheim and with many
others Bonald’s statement according to which it “is society that constitutes
man, that is, forms him by social education” (quoted by Lukes, 1968: 119).
But the problem lies in knowing what society is, as well as in determining
the specific mechanisms of that individual formation, its modalities and also
its duration. For Tarde, the key of both issues is above all in the concept of
imitation. He asserts that this is the major mechanism of formation of subjec-
tivities and, at the same time, the mode of production of human groups. It is
also the reason for their structured but variable permanence over time, that is
to say, the reason for what from afar is often seen as their identity.
38 Individual, society and social field
The first thing to be underlined here is that what Tarde speaks of imi-
tation does not refer to the activity of a single individual who copies oth-
ers from the interiority of her faculties, just like a subject in front of an
object. Rather, imitation is the social relation in which the subjectivity is
built as a socio-psychic configuration of relative coherence and determina-
tion. Tarde (1890:92) claims that “one is not born, but becomes similar”,
and this becoming similar to oneself can only occur by reflecting on others
and resembling them. Such specular relations happen, most of the time, not
only unconsciously but also in an inverted way, like a good mirror: “Having
nothing more than suggested ideas and believing them spontaneous: such is
the illusion typical of a sleepwalker, and also of the social individual” (Tarde,
1890: 98). And what is valid for ideas is also valid for feelings, tastes and
dislikes. According to Tarde, we are a plexus of reflexes and echoes of the
most diverse acts, words, gestures and states that are transmitted by others
and that we reproduce, always making variations to some degree. We would
then be living and imperfect mirrors.
This social influence that forms subjectivity does not cease in adulthood
and the mimetic character of the psyche does not decline either. From birth to
death we copy actions, thoughts and feelings from others. We interiorise them
as memory, we transform them into judgement and will and we put them
into practice as habits. These mimetic relations are therefore not limited to a
psychogenetic period (childhood), nor to a specific institution (family, school).
Everything is pedagogical, all the time, for the mirroring-individuals we are.
Permanent mimesis is limited neither to face-to-face interactions nor to pre-
sent time. It is an “action at a distance”—sometimes very long in space and
time. We copy everything that has been produced by near and far, known and
unknown individuals in very diverse times and geographies, and that reaches
us through an imitative series of individuals that have repeated it. Accordingly,
sensibility (worlds). It also means that they run at unequal rhythms, that
they have dissimilar intensities and that they reach varied geographical and
temporal scales.
Therefore, what from a macroscopical distance appears as a block (soci-
ety), requiring systemic and synchronic treatments, is shredded and historised
but it is also pluralised and particularised in a multitude of heterogeneous
historical fabrics (the social field). Every social thing—ideas, emotions, acts,
relations, institutions, artefacts—is now transformed into a specific creation
among many others, which is propagated, transporting its differential geneal-
ogy and its characteristic dynamic. Each way of doing, feeling and thinking,
as well as each socially circulating object, has its peculiar force and its dis-
tinctive purpose and logic. But this is not all. Each of us, in her apparent uni-
formity and consistency, is made of a myriad of imitative currents originating
from the most diverse sources and directed in the most diverse directions.
And, for the same reason, each one is always intimately communicated with
a multitude of, alive and dead, human beings made in the same kaleidoscopic
manner. So what we may still call ‘individual’ in order to keep a traditional
reference is not simple, indivisible and separated in any sense. In an infinitesi-
mal scale, the individual rather reveals as the, never very coherent, integra-
tion of social forces that configure and exceed her.
A consequence of the aforementioned is that what can be imitated and
what it is actually imitated is never an individual as such, an entire individual,
Individual, society and social field 41
since such a thing would not exist. Far from being structured as a com-
pletely defined totality, every subjectivity functions as the open and vari-
able configuration—the integral—of countless dynamic imitations. And this
applies both to those who copy and for those who are copied. Furthermore,
we never imitate in a global way, but rather in detail. What is copied and
transmitted are psychosocial models, that is always specific, more or less
precise, forms of action, intellection and/or affection. Those, and not other
things, are imitated inventions if we look at them closely and in their socio-
logical functioning. For that reason, when Tarde refers to them in the con-
text of their diffusion, he calls them moulds, clichés or, simply, examples (he
could have also called them information and even algorithms). Hence, labour
is neither copied nor propagated in general, but rather, “the art of carving
flint, taming the dog, making a bow, . . . fermenting bread, working bronze,
extracting iron, etc.” (Tarde, 1890: 47). This applies to the (always social)
forms of love and friendship, to feeding, fashion, art, science and so forth.
When replicated and internalised, these detailed models produce self-sim-
ilarities (individuals) and, when propagated, they give rise to associations
(groups, societies), as well as to regularities in certain shared ways of doing,
feeling and thinking (social systems or institutions).
Each individual participates, at the same time, in different types of lines
of relation, but no one participates (directly) in all existing lines. And, even
more important, each one is simultaneously part of different groupings,
which implies that every individual is a regular carrier of practices, thoughts
and feelings that are never very consistent with each other if we look closely.
Accordingly, someone can be considered and consider herself Scottish and
English at the same time, can be a Catholic and do not reject abortion or
drugs, can support macho and feminist perspectives in different topics and
to varying degrees, can endorse racist immigration policies and neo-Keynes-
ian economic recipes. Those who are passionate about systemic coherence
will see in this signs of mental inconsistencies or typical contradictions of
our post-traditional time. However, Tarde claims that the principle of the
excluded middle is not the main operator of social and subjective articula-
tions, and that the tight coherence of collective values does not exist in
Modernity, but it did not exist before and will not come in the future either.
Due to the multilinear and polygenic character of the social field, no system
configured therein will be able to be completely coherent, closed and stable
and to have an unilinear evolution.6 Among other things, this is an invita-
tion to rethink the dominant narrative, inside and outside social sciences,
according to which past times were organic, well cohesive and homogenous.
Every social field is woven by countless infinitesimal repetitions of innu-
merable past and present inventions that propagate in different directions
and with different scopes at the same time. Therefore, it is necessary to con-
ceive it as a thick intersection of imitative radiations among which countless,
42 Individual, society and social field
both conflictive and creative, interferences are produced. From this point of
view, social history can no longer be described as a unique drama developed
in successive stages, but rather as “a tangled skein, or rather, as a confused
mix of multicoloured skeins” (Tarde, 1898: 61) that deploys according to
different temporalities. This “confusion” proceeds from the lack of unique
direction and the overabundance of those radiations within the same social
field. It is important to underline that radiations themselves do not have to
be necessarily confusing and most of the time they are not (they carry precise
models). Moreover, we must highlight that, within that socio-historical mare-
magnum of dynamic differences, lasting social and subjective configurations
effectively occur. However, they are not the result of organismic or dialectical
systems, but rather arise as more or less coherent integrations of variable and
heterogeneous relations (i.e. as ensembles).
The remarkable plasticity of these integrations, as well as the associative
and subjective power of the flows that compose them, proceeds from the par-
ticular material from which they are woven: beliefs and desires. In fact, that
is the proper level of the social. Beliefs and desires are the real components
and agents of social life—Tarde will say that they are its force and its sub-
stance.7 It is the inextinguishable dynamism of these microscopic forces that
gives an impalpable materiality to the social.
all human bodies would have the same faculty to believe and desire, and their
psychic life would function according to the same basic operations. These
basic operations are affirmation and denial when referring to beliefs, attrac-
tion and repulsion in the case of desires. Each of these operations is subject to
variable degrees of intensity, and a continuum exists between both extremes.
For the same reason, psychic life is made of chiaroscuros, and one can per-
fectly speak of semi-beliefs and semi-desires. In the wake of Leibniz, Maine de
Biran and Cournot, Tarde understands that ideas, passions and perceptions
are distributed in a line which goes from clarity and distinction to confusion
and darkness, passing through an infinite grey range. Moreover, he claims
that there are different degrees of consciousness, and that there are degrees of
the unconscious too. However, in every case it is a matter of reversible con-
ditions: desires and beliefs that inhabit us may turn, in grades and without
interruption, from a conscious state to an unconscious one—and vice versa.
The same is valid for the clarity and the distinction of their contents, as well
as for the (positive or negative) sign of their dynamic. This means that the
volitional attraction and repulsion regarding the same object are fluctuating,
as well as its intellectual acceptance and rejection. Finally, beliefs and desires
may combine themselves in innumerable possible ways, and to an innumer-
able degrees. As a result, all systems of ideas and feelings that are configured
by them can far exceed the principles of coherence required by classical logic,
and they often do so.8 The fact that they harmonise diverse forces does not
imply that they are consistent systems.
From the aforementioned derives the enormous creative potency of beliefs
and desires, as well as their power to propagate. But there is also a negative
condition for both things to occur. Neither beliefs nor desires are determined
by the biological necessities of the human body or by the schematisms of an
innate reason. Nor are they bound by a Law of culture that is universal in
its contents—the prohibition of incest, for instance. All this implies that, by
right, but also in fact, anything can be believed or desired. It also implies that
interests, convictions and volitions that make up the (intra)psychic life are
necessarily received by others, and that they have a formative and structuring
value as well as a transformative influence that never ends. The
wills and beliefs through which we imagine simply coveting and consider
pleasant or unpleasant, good or bad, what we actually believe as such;
These wills and beliefs are not individual but social, that is, suggested
to the individual . . . through his ancestors or his contemporaries, by the
atmosphere of his country and that of his century.
(Tarde, 1891: 457)
At this point, one may ask if social life has necessities and/or reasons that
work as the foundations of socially circulating values, interests and tastes
44 Individual, society and social field
that the individual receives and makes her own. The answer Tarde gives to
this crucial question is negative because he understands that social life is
psychic too. Since it is fundamentally made of beliefs and desires, the previ-
ous considerations are also valid for it: like individuals, groups can believe or
desire anything. There is no biological or rational (or theological) basis for
common beliefs and desires, nor for the social practices and the institutions
they mobilise, shape and sustain.9 Monotheism or polytheism, democracy or
monarchy, monogamy or polygamy, modern or postmodern sciences: there
are no extra-social reasons for the transmission and institutionalisation of
certain shared convictions and passions, and their establishment as dominant
values, truths and practices. It is vain to search for more certain truths or
fairer values hidden behind those prevailing in a social field for more or less
long periods of time. It simply happens that many other truths and justices
are less extended in that very same field, and that many more (an infinity) are
possible, ready to be actualised, that is to say, ready to transform in reality
through their combination in new inventions and their further contagion in
imitative propagations.
Beliefs and desires are then the actual infinitesimal agents of social life.
Both social and subjective reality are made of their incessant diffusion, com-
position and opposition. They are also the cause of the constant mutations
that are registered at every moment in social and personal life. For the same
reason, it is important to conceive that both individuals and groups are made
and un-made in a most primary field, which is however social. This is a
heterogeneous, non-centred and polyrhythmic field made of an innumerable
multitude of inter-mental forces. These immaterial and contagious micro-
vectors, prodigal in actual differences and future possibilities, configure
as models of action, intellection and affection, and propagate as flows or
waves, spreading their visions of the world and their forms of organising
social relations. But, as we know, they also interfere with each other in two
ways: they conjugate giving place to new models that will in turn propa-
gate, or they clash in opposition, producing contagious conflicts, capable of
acquiring the most diverse intensities and scales. And all this happens at the
same time. Systematicity, transformation and social conflict do not occur
in large homogeneous blocs, nor in successive stages ruled by the principle
of mutual exclusion (where one is produced, the other one is displaced or
suspended). They rather happen in a simultaneous, multiplied and dynamic
manner. Tarde also wanted to assess this when he speaks of social field or,
more often, of social life.
Infinitesimal sociology
According to Tarde, the ensembles of similitudes, regularities and concord-
ances between individuals, which lead us to speak of the existence of societies
Individual, society and social field 45
and groups, are due to the presence of similar and precise ideas and pas-
sions in each of these individuals. However, these similarities in desiring and
believing do not refer to the equality of their biological needs, nor are they
the corollary of an innate reason, common to all of them. They do not result
from profound or transcendent collective symbolic structures that configure
them either. Rather, they derive from the imitative propagation of models
of interaction, intellection and affection that, spreading from one brain to
another, shape psychosocial currents which are capable of establishing spe-
cific correlation and correspondence links. For that reason, it is not excessive
to affirm that nations, ethnicities and families, but also industrial or financial
corporations, religious congregations, political parties and criminal gangs,
would be nothing but intermental networks of familiar, national, economic,
religious, political and criminal beliefs and desires respectively.
The approach of this sociology towards any social group is then demanding
and is orientated to discern each of the individuals that integrate it and also
to differentiate the different types of relations that are established between
them. However, its ultimate goal is not the individuals and their relations,
but the flows of faith and passion that guide these relations and intimately
communicate those individuals with each other and with themselves. Only
by identifying and following those flows in their concrete socio-historical
paths, catographing their extensions, measuring their intensities and speeds,
describing their characteristic dynamics and effects, can sociology access the
specific level of the social. This sociology should not be then characterised as
micro but rather as infinitesimal. This approach discovers that the singular
configurations that we call individuals are the result of processes of integra-
tion of a myriad of social beliefs and desires that have turned into personal
memory, judgements and habits. Moreover, it allows us to see that individu-
als are bio-psychosocial ensembles living in continuity with the psychosocial
field and the rest of nature. Far from being the coherent and well-defined
entity we like to imagine, every individual always works interpenetrated with
the others, and overflowed by them. This transforms her into a hesitant and
intermittent configuration that is done and undone in an imperceptible way
several times a day. According to Tarde, every individual is entangled with
the others through two types of imitative current that are distinguishable
for their intensity and their velocity, and not for their contents. One is the
process of slow repetitions which is known with the name of institutions and
customs; the other one is the process of rapid and intense imitations that
Tarde calls fashions—and that include the fickle fluxes of public opinion,
social mood and collective emotions.
Similar considerations are valid for social systems. For the point of view
inaugurated by this sociology, these are nothing but the iterated repetition
of certain specific ways of feeling, thinking and doing. Far from any tran-
scendence or substantialisation, they simply consist of ensembles of models
46 Individual, society and social field
Notes
1 In France, authors such as Cournot, Couturat and Brunschvicg were part of this
philosophical and epistemological impulse, which was continued by Bergson and
Deleuze (maybe Tarde’s most important heirs in the 20th century). In North Amer-
ica, Pierce’s work is also on this Leibnizian path and, in Germany, Leibniz’s devel-
opments were taken by H. Weyl and, in a different way, by H. Cohen and Cassirer.
2 Tarde argues that the comparison of societies with organisms understood as totali-
ties can be advantageously replaced by the analogy with that singular part of the
organism since “society is or tends every day to be only a large collective brain
whose small individual brains are the cells”. Sampson (2017) has developed these
Tardean lines of thought by carrying out an original analysis of current societies
in terms of “neuro-cultures”. Along with him, and in concordance with Lazzarato
(2002), Terranova (2012), Parikka (2007) and others, has developed a research
field whose guiding threads are the links between affect, contagion, neuro-sciences
and digital networks in the era of “neuro-capitalism”.
3 Bergson (1955: 333) writes that Tardean sociology gives us a keen sense of our
responsibility “by showing us how the least of our initiatives can blossom into
incalculable consequences, by revealing how a simple individual gesture, falling in
Individual, society and social field 47
the social milieu like a stone in the water of a pond, shakes it entirely with imitative
ripples that always widen”.
4 Some key figures of contemporary social thought, such as Deleuze, Foucault and
Latour, heavily borrow from Tarde’s work, hence the importance of Tarde for the
contemporary current called “relational sociology”. On this see Tonkonoff (2018).
5 For this reason, Latour (2002: 123) claims that the statistical and methodological
tools with which Tarde dreamt of, and that are necessary for undertaking his sociol-
ogy, arrive with the Internet because they enable tracking exactly “any rumour, any
news, any data, any purchase and sale”. The devices and techniques that today we
call big data “are tracking, before our eyes, just the type of data that Tarde would
have acclaimed” (Latour, 2010: 160).
6 “The aspiration of the social state to be an entirely logical system with the elements
that compose it is never satisfied more than in part, and we see why: it happens
that it was not born abruptly, from a single block, but it was formed little by little
by inter-mental actions, by intersecting imitative radiations, and it continues to be
elaborated by incessant changes, by the exchange of examples and ideas with the
surrounding societies, formed, they also, due to the incomplete fusions of conta-
gious individual influences” (Tarde, 1895c: 79).
7 “My ideas on imitation could not be separated from my ideas on beliefs and desires:
they form a block. Not satisfied with words, I do not admit imitation but imita-
tion of something, and the substance, the force, transmitted from brain to brain by
imitation, is a belief or a desire” (Tarde, 1890: 12).
8 “Our consciousness is constituted in such a way that it entails an infinitude of state-
ments opposed to negations, an infinitude of desires opposed to repulsions and that
have exactly the very same object” (Tarde, 1898: 74).
9 About one century after Tarde, Cornelius Castoriadis (1987) would speak of
imaginary self-institution of society. However, one of the main differences between
Castoriadis (and other post-structuralist authors) and Tarde’s social theory is the
“flattening” and the radical decentralisation of social “imaginary significations”.
In Tarde, beliefs and desires circulate through lines or, better yet, through a-centred
networks, while in Castoriadis they still seem to have an ontologically unfounded
but socially in force-centre. At this point, Castoriadis is closer to the tradition that
goes from Durkheim to LeviStrauss’ and Lacan’s structuralism than to the (neo)
monadological perspective, even though the latter is not absent in his work. In
contrast, Deleuze’s and Latour’s poststructuralism is completely in tune with the
Tardean perspective.
3
THE SOCIAL AS CONTAGION,
CREATION AND FIGHT
The term mimesis is the Greek precursor of the Latin term imitatio, and is as
old as philosophy, to say the least. It has played an important role in meta-
physics, ethics and aesthetics and has also been a key notion in Western theo-
logical thought and Christian morality. Besides, it has had a relevant role in
certain modern sciences such as biology and psychology. However, the wide
range of meanings acquired in these various fields makes it difficult to assert
that this is always the same concept. In view of this fact, Tarde claims that it
may have been more accurate to invent a neologism. He chooses, however, to
speak of “imitation” and defines it as follows:
This quote comprises all that is involved in the Tardean concept of imita-
tion, its description, implications and proposals, that is a relational under-
standing of the social action and the assertion of its psychic nature and linear
DOI: 10.4324/9781003197386-4
The social as contagion, creation and fight 49
shares with Schopenhauer, Nietzsche and Freud the assumption that it is not
possible to identify psyche and consciousness. For him, this is a huge ego-
centric illusion, typical of political and economic liberalism. And when it
comes to Weber’s sociology, it is nuanced and complex in this point since it
acknowledges as social both affective and consuetudinary behaviours. It is
also true that it demands of them a “meant meaning” to be in accordance
with his definition. Tarde, on the other hand, claims that each and every
human individual is dominated all the time, throughout his whole life, by
social forces he does not understand. This does not imply that such acts
are lacking in meaning—rather on the contrary, however, they are meanings
which can be said to be objective, impersonal or even strictly social, and
often unconscious. Consequently, the model of infinitesimal sociology is not
rational choice or hermeneutics, but somnambulism induced by hypnosis.
2002: 82). Only some of them come out of the shadows to acquire a more
distinct, brighter outline, when an act of attention may turn them into apper-
ceptions or conscious ones. The rest remain permanently active but unno-
ticed, and only reveal themselves during sleep and through some anomalous
phenomena in which consciousness is lacking, distorted or interrupted. In
delirium, for instance, small perceptions and their sensitive chaos may storm
in, disrupting the regular action of thought and will. This may also happen
during somnambulism.
De Biran (1841: 262) offered a report on this odd phenomenon. It reads:
This description, which De Biran shared with most scientists of his time, was
valid both in the case of individuals who sleepwalk for unknown medical rea-
sons and in the case of those induced to it artificially by means of hypnosis.
It is hard not to see that what is enunciated here is a mystery, for sleeping is
usually opposed to wakefulness, and consciousness is said to rule our speech
and behaviour. If the sleepwalker’s consciousness is asleep while he walks and
talks, who is it that, acting and talking? It all happens as if they were two
different people, more so considering the complete oblivion brought by the
act of waking up. Is there oneself inside another, then? Judging by the alleged
lucidity in the somnambulist’s conduct, this possibility does not seem absurd,
and De Biran, among others, has it by a considerable hypothesis. But given
the fact that he wants to base all psychology upon consciousness, he orients
his answers towards an organic unconsciousness, made up precisely of small
perceptions. Even when mentioning the ideas that seem to be guiding the
somnambulist, he resorts to physiology as a field that comes in to establish
the causes of mental and behavioural processes taking place in the individual
when their voluntary attention ceases (sleeping and somnambulism) or when,
so to speak, it fails (mental alienation and delirium). Thus, if an unconscious
were to exist, it would be sensitive and vital, a purely affective one. This is
an unconscious in which small perceptions relate closely to imagination, as
happens during sleep, but it is not properly psychological—since, according
to De Biran, where there is no consciousness, there is no psychology.1
A lot is at stake then, in the picturesque figure of the somnambulist and
in the experiences of hypnotic suggestion to which part of the medicine and
psychiatry of late 19th century turned to. These comprise a series of trou-
blesome issues still problematic for the scientific world and for philosophy,
52 The social as contagion, creation and fight
given their importance and huge complexity, that is the relation between the
conscious and the unconscious, body and mind, freedom and determination.
Tarde adds one crucial topic to this list: the relation between individual and
society.
Tarde was very interested in induced somnambulism and its problems,
but his approach was immediately relational and eminently sociological—it
does not focus on the somnambulist himself, but rather on the hypnotiser-
hypnotised pair. Tarde believes to find in this match the most perfect model
of imitative social relation, mainly since there we can find the inter-mental
social bond in its purest state, if such a thing could be said, a strictly physi-
cal relation in which beliefs and desires flow free from any interference of
the physical world or biological bodily needs. In addition, since the hypno-
tist sends simple commands to the hypnotised, there are no contradicting or
resisting beliefs or desires. Here, as in sleep and delirium, there is no distinc-
tion between the inside and the outside; therefore, any suggestion can be
experienced as real. If the hypnotiser indicates it is very cold, the hypnotised
will start shaking.
According to Tarde, this is possible simply because laboratory conditions
operate in an extreme reduction of what happens in normal social life rela-
tions. Experimental hypnosis just reduces, isolates and intensifies what was
always there both in doctor and patient, due to their nature as social individ-
uals. As everybody else, both are made of imitative relations, and “imitation
is a form of somnambulism” (Tarde, 1890a: 97), that is an inter-mental rela-
tion in which someone utters a specific directive and someone else receives
it, executing what is requested quite accurately, and often without a clear
awareness that they have been induced into doing it.
Social life differs from artificial hypnosis not by nature but by number,
variety and coherence of the suggestions involved. It also differs in that sug-
gestions are both unilateral and reciprocal. The social is a polymorph mag-
netic field made up of innumerable suggestions, where all magnetisers are
also magnetised without exception. This complex configuration of the social
field is the main cause for individuals to resist or disregard certain sugges-
tion lines and follow others. If the passivity of the somnambulist is not the
rule for individuals, it is not due to a deliberative consciousness which oper-
ates beyond imitation but rather due to the multiplicity of imitation lines
in each individual involved. These lines are at times concordant among one
another, but at others, competing against or blocking each other. Individuals
and groups intertwine and unwind themselves in this maze-like framework of
crossed hypnotisms. Artificial or induced hypnosis captures the main features
of the process while being in strict continuity with them.
In all cases, social contagion leads individual emotions, thoughts and actions
in the most effective and imperceptible way:
The sanest man, when he buys a property, when he does any business,
industrial or agricultural, yields to unsuspecting impressions; thus, he
always thinks he is doing a good operations. . . Nothing is then more
common than suggestion understood in this way; social life is made of it;
specially trade lives only on suggested whims.
(Tarde, 1886: 137)
and unity are the basis of social groups and social harmonies. Consequently,
difference turns out to be always problematic, as it results in chaos, division
and, along the same lines, confrontation. In this frame, which could be called
ensemblistic-identitarian logic, struggle tends to be conceived as contrary to
social relation. Hobbes’ natural state, as it is the actual or potential war state
among individuals, might be the most comprehensive and pervasive theoreti-
cal model in this respect. In this frame, war and society are strictly antago-
nists, and they are ruled by a “revolving door” principle—there where one
comes in, the other comes out. In this vein, other less acute conflicts such as
murder and crime are often interpreted as “anti-social”.
Tarde, on the contrary, considers struggle as an elementary social rela-
tion. This means that even in its most destructive forms it is, above all, a
social bond—a particular form of social relation established not only among
individuals who gather to charge against some others, but also among rival
parties confronting one another. In this respect, and many others, Tarde is
very close to Simmel (1904: 490), who states: “If every reaction among men
is a socialization, of course conflict must count as such, since it is one of the
most intense reactions, and is logically impossible if restricted to a single
element”.4
The very moment this perspective is adopted, an immense multitude of
social oppositions reveal themselves, disseminated throughout the social
field. This demands for both a decentralisation of the sociological look and
a microanalysis of conflicts and their propagations. The social landscape
becomes then a constellated space, filled with struggles of different kinds
and diverse geographic and time scopes. The multitude of conflicts is nei-
ther necessarily nor usually related to one another, and there is no prime or
central conflict that could unite or subordinate them all—as could be the
case of capital-labour struggle in Marxist framework. In addition, it is no
longer possible to assume that the most spectacular conflicts are always most
important or harming, since all intervene in the general course of social life
and all involve, in one way or another, a huge number of people. Nor is it
possible to suppose that any conflict is harmful per se, let alone, to conceive
a conflict-free society.
world (which turn out to be the same). Tarde argues that for two differences
to oppose one another, a certain similarity must exist between them; and he
claims that this similarity is produced in the way of an inverted mirroring, a
counter-reflection. Then,
Therefore, the next point to bear in mind is that symmetry, or better said
counter-symmetry, is a distinctive feature of all conflictive relations. Oppo-
sites always form a pair, a duality in which one pole constitutes the reverse
side of the other, but this means that they always belong to the same genre.
To name a few examples, there are the concave and the convex in geometry,
pain and pleasure in sensitivity, good and evil in morality. There could not
be, for instance, an anti-space which was not a space of some kind, or an
anti-social phenomenon which was not social in a particular way. Thus, both
crime and law are social phenomena; they oppose one another because crime
is an anti-juridical action, but that does not make it anti-social.5 In fact, crim-
inal organisations are as social as any other human enterprise. Consequently,
for two terms to oppose, they must have a specific common measure, and this
“supposes their similarity and their equality from the point of view in ques-
tion” (Tarde, 1897: 132).
To continue with his infinitesimal portrait of opposition, Tarde states it is
always about a clash of forces. This implies the need to regard dynamism and
variability in each one of them, as well as their reciprocal interaction. Each
force is susceptible to increasing and decreasing in intensity, speed and exten-
sion, and there can also be balance or unbalance between them. According to
Tarde, and against what could be expected, it is balance what characterises
struggle. The peculiarity of the oppositional relation is not the prevalence
of one force over another (in this case we would speak of domination), but
rather the instance of indetermination, equality and vacillation in which none
has succeeded yet. In fact, the highest degree of mirrored symmetry in which
one force appears as the reverse side of the other corresponds to this moment
of unresolved tension, still proportioned on each side. The end of conflict,
either by mutual destruction or by victory of one of the sides, signals the end
of the symmetry of forms and the balance of forces.
To this, we must add that confronted forces at work are always positive.
According to Tarde, there is no opposition between being and nothingness.
58 The social as contagion, creation and fight
In addition to this positive character, confronted forces are not only vari-
able but also reversible. That is they may turn into their contrary force after
going through a neutral state (or ground zero). This implies such a smooth
continuity from one pole to the other that its mere suggestion would disgust
any contender. Thus, the same population and the same individuals can go
from atheistic rebellion to theistic crusades, or from democratic engagement
to dictatorship support—and vice versa.
As might be expected, social opposition comprises wars, murders and
crimes, as well as uprisings, mutinies, sabotages and strikes. Moreover,
after the Tardean conceptualisation, we find the need to further expand this
inventory to economic competition, government elections, public opinion
controversies, religious and ideological disputes, as well as scientific and
philosophical debates; regional, generational and sportive rivalries; and so
many other conflicts. If looked upon carefully, all of them are relations of an
oppositional character in which confronting social tendencies collide because
of being counter-similar. All of them are kinds of the same gender, although
some work in a manner that is concentrated, spectacular and episodic; and
others are invisible, constant and disseminated.
Tarde also establishes a distinction among conflict types: there are con-
flicts of series, of degree and of sign. The latter is, so to speak, the classic
form of conflict and may be considered, to a certain extent, the most impor-
tant. It is produced when a social force unfolding in a given direction clashes
against another in the contrary direction on the same straight line. That is
why Tarde calls it diametrical. It occurs, for instance, when a nationalist
movement fights with a local or regional one, when the habit of honest work-
ing collide against criminal practice or when foreign invasion to a territory
finds resistance on the part of native inhabitants. They are all simultane-
ous oppositions between social currents of the same kind, but in opposite
directions. The other two types of conflict do not refer to struggles between
different forces, but to the ups and downs (or the forward and backward
moves) of the same force. With this categorisation, Tarde widens even further
the conflict-constellation. Oppositions of series or qualitative oppositions are
those consisting of the evolution and counter-evolution of a same force mov-
ing forward and backward, following the exact reverse road. Oppositions of
degree or quantitative oppositions are present in the increase and decrease
of a given tendency. It is the opposition that describes the undulatory curve
of suicide rates, matrimonies, crimes or birth-rates. It may also be found in
ups and downs of commercial exchanges and stock-exchange values; or the
growth and decline of religious, political or aesthetic beliefs.
But there is more. Deeper inside the microscopic approach to the social
field, we will find oppositions occurring not among individuals or groups,
nor within collective tendencies, but rather within individuals themselves.
Tarde claims that the doubts and vacillations that so often arise in a person’s
The social as contagion, creation and fight 59
imitative currents in dispute; to take the lead, to provide the level of detail,
or in individual actions, feelings or thoughts. Hesitation, in its tiniest expres-
sion, is then reflecting the battle among collective currents of oceanic vol-
umes and planetary extensions. Thus, in the folds of an individual decision
between a racist and a cosmopolitan wording, a patriarchal and a feminist
behaviour, a democratic and an authoritarian opinion, the roar of social cur-
rents can be heard, as they collide in the infinitesimal and infinite space of an
“individual” psychic field.
This is possible because, just as in the external physical space, the psychic
field is constituted in such way that it “entails infinity of assertions which
oppose negations, infinity of desires opposed to repulsions, and pursuing
exactly the same goal” (Tarde, 1898: 74). Therefore, our beliefs and wills
may describe an undulatory course with ups and downs, they may move for-
ward in stages and even at times retrieve into previous states. But in addition,
it is possible for us to love and hate the same object of desire simultaneously,
to believe and disbelieve the same truth or dogma. (It is also possible for us
to do it in an infinity of degrees.)
However, that which is valid for socio-psychical battles within individuals
is valid too for those outside them. In both cases, the three types of struggles
distinguished by Tarde may be verified (i.e. conflicts of series, of degree and
of sign):
If there are men or groups of men who evolve in one given direction, while
others inversely—for instance, from naturalism to idealism in art, from
aristocratic to democratic regimes, from democracy to aristocracy, etc.—
this is so because each man may evolve and counter-evolve in this way. If
there are class members or inhabitants in which religious faith increases,
while there are others where it decreases, it is because each man’s con-
sciousness admits ups and downs in intensity. If, finally, there are politi-
cal parties and religious sects asserting and desiring precisely what other
political parties and religious sects deny and reject, this is so because each
man’s spirit and heart is able to include yes and no, for and against, within
themselves, and on the same idea or belief.
(Tarde, 1895c: 96–97)
this chaotic opacity in which all creative action is immersed, and from where
it emerges with the great deed of a new order—whether this be the steam
machine, set theory or The Young Ladies of Avignon. According to Tarde,
this confusing twilight zone will show, if seen in detail, there is nothing mys-
tic or ineffable there. There is no other than the multitude of present and past
inventions taken in their inarticulate form or in their contradictions. Conse-
quently, he states that all creation consists essentially of the unprecedented
composition of some of these materials which used to be either ignored or
opposed before. In this respect, inventions, even the ones with the most
genius, are nothing other than the novel articulation of pre-existing banali-
ties. As an example, Tarde (1895:169) writes, “there is nothing simpler than
to express oneself by means of the letters of the alphabet and the abstract
quantities, even “x” or “y”; and yet, all algebra resides there”.
terrestrial bodies and the gravitation of the moon round the earth, and
understanding the two consequences of the same principle. The invention
of the locomotive consisted in uniting. . . these two modes of action which
had been apart until then, steam piston and wheeled locomotion, etc.
(Tarde, 1898a: 190)
what did Darwin’s thesis about natural selection amount to? To having
proclaimed the fact of competition among living things? No, but in having
for the first time combined this idea with the ideas of variability and hered-
ity. The former idea, as it was proclaimed by Aristotle, remained sterile
until it was associated with the two latter ideas.
(Tarde, 1903: 382)
Following this line of reasoning, we may assert that every invention has
something of a kaleidoscope or collage. Heterogeneity of its components is
cultural or even “material”, given the fact that they often come from diverse
places and times, carrying with them the history of their singular evolutions.
And yet the result of their adaptation works. Furthermore, it functions with
a given direction and a ruling sense. Then, it can well be said that it is a
system. A system that upon a closer examination of its (poly) genesis reveals
itself as something a little bit monstrous or unnatural. Over time, the force
of habit will naturalise it and forget the more or less improper blend of its
constituting differences, and ignore the always somewhat defectiveness of its
articulation. In this respect, the myth of genius plays an invaluable role, not
because genius does not exist but because myth offers an atomistic image of
the invention process, disregarding its social nature, its contingency share
and the incomplete crafting of its results.
At the same time, Tarde insists on a key point: inventions are harmo-
nisations which create harmonies. Their main social function is to gather
diverging tendencies and turn them into something relatively concordant
with each other. By this singular way of integration we aim to describe
The social as contagion, creation and fight 65
already known series. It is in this point where the possibles intervene to make
intelligible that rare event that is invention.
Let us remember that according to this (neo) monadological perspective,
we are to conceive “the actual as infinitesimal part of the real” (Tarde, 1895c:
25). This means that that which actually exists as visible, constituted, indi-
vidualised and numerable is the tiniest portion of that which exists as vir-
tual, invisible, constituent, pre-individual and innumerable. In this field of
virtualities—the field of possibles—a constant struggle for actually existing
is grappled, but this is not a given, and not in all cases. The reason behind
this is the infinitude of the possible, the finitude of the world. As a result, the
realisation of one possibility does eliminate others which will never come
to life, while at the same time inaugurating new series of previously non-
existent possibilities. This is equivalent to asserting that a multitude of pos-
sible ones (Les possibles) come in a procession in the real world, and have a
constant influence on it. Consequently, each society and individual is at every
moment a specific composition of realised possibilities, future possibilities
and aborted ones. The same holds, naturally, for each invention.
As already noted, every invention combines existing imitative lines or
actual examples; we must now add that they do it immersed in the field of
possible that these (and other) existing lines bring with them. And to be clear,
this field is infinite. With this, we reach the hyper-populated shadow from
which each creation arrives—and that each thing created renews. To put it
in another way, all which is actual implies an integration of the infinite into
the finite and, in the social sphere, invention is the demiurge to that passage.
But then, the socio-historical field must be conceived as an immense fabric
of actual relations wrapped up in an even bigger intertwine of virtual rela-
tions. The lines of both moving frames communicate and are in constant
interaction. It is necessary to see inventions as the result of their (partial) inte-
gration. In them, both types of series—actual and virtual—conjugate them-
selves by way of reason and imagination, generating a new difference in the
infinitesimal space of an individual mind. Without providence to determine
which specific composition will take place and no other, and in which indi-
vidual, it must be assumed that there is a fully contingent dynamic ruling this
process—a process which is no other than the polygenesis and configuration
of what we call social reality.
Along with this, it is worth mentioning that this enormous and moving
cloud of possibles from where innovation springs up and feeds is not some-
thing absolutely chaotic to Tarde, for he expresses, “there is certain order
in that disorder”. Instead of imagining the domain of a completely undif-
ferentiated randomness, one should rather speak of a field of probabilities.
As we said, we need to think of possibles as an infinite multitude of potential
forces interacting with one another. They struggle but also couple with one
another, as with the actual forces with which they intertwine. The results of
The social as contagion, creation and fight 67
this combinatorics are unpredictable and can only be known post factum.
Tarde (1985c) states that they are unknowable before they realise themselves,
“even for an infinite intelligence”. However, as long as this potential field
is intertwined with the real world, we may device some strategies to know
something about them (in a partial, asymptotic way).
If every existing thing is the result of a specific combination of realised
possibilities, we can distinguish among unrealised possibilities according to
the gender of the existences to which they are associated. Therefore, there
would be possibilities of a political, economic, religious, criminal kind, and
so on. Once there, one will be located at the point where neither pure contin-
gency nor pure necessity reigns. It is the sphere of “conditional certainties”,
where the accidental and the necessary allow for a measure of their interac-
tion by means of probabilistic calculus. From there, one may also approach
the imbrications of the possible ones among one another and grasp their
interaction and chaining as what they are (virtual forces). That is, one may
approach what Tarde considers the contingent source of necessity and its
determinisms. According to this, there would exist possible of a first, second,
third, nth degree.7 This may allow for a better adjustment of probabilistic
previsions—or, in any case, it may lead us more precisely to know what hap-
pened, for the real can only be intelligible as a case of what’s possible. Thus,
for instance in scientific inventions,
after Kepler formulated his three great laws, the discovery of universal
gravity became a possible of a first degree. Similarly, the discovery of the
electric telegraph after Erstedt’s observation and Ampère’s research, or the
discovery of clocks after Galileo’s isochronism of pendulum oscillations,
or algebra application to geometry at some point in the parallel course
of both sciences. Even before Kepler or Ampère, the discovery of Newto-
nian laws and the electric telegraph were still possible at a lower degree.
Ampère and Kepler made it possible for the conceptions of those astron-
omy and physics possibilities to pass from second or third degree to first. It
is worth mentioning that these eminent figures attributed huge importance
to that passage, and even to the exact date of their passing. According to
Kepler’s own solemn words, it was in 1618 when the Newtonian principle
was mature enough and ready to be accepted.
(Tarde, 1895c: 164)
adequate for their adaptation. This shows that each invention is the product
of social history, as well as is productive of it, and by the same token shows
the crucial role of contingency in social dynamics. In fact, there are here at
least three different series of contingencies and all of them run through the
inventor. One of them is properly social and relates, as already noted, to
the flux of examples which may reach the individual who invents or not.
They are the specific formation and information lines (in mathematics, phys-
ics, philosophy, politics, religion etc.), received by the inventor due to the
socio-historical coordinates in which she finds herself by chance. The other
is properly psychological and relates to personality traits (persistence, rigour,
boldness, prudence etc.), whose composition is always singular and uncertain
in advance. The latter relates to the physical configuration of the body, espe-
cially the brain, derived from biological inheritance and its inherent random
factors.
From there, the beautiful hypothesis of Tarde, which claims that a genius
is a supreme accident in history, since she constitutes the locus of this triple
contingency (biological, psychical and social). Here, some of the most com-
plex vectors of culture intertwine and adapt into a mind which is particularly
apt to dealing creatively with them, since it functions in an exceptionally
constituted brain that, at the same time, is in possession of the right tempera-
mental treats and education for that task. The simultaneous encounter and
successful harmonisation of all these exceptions in just one body is practi-
cally a miracle. Any variation, however minimal, in any of these contingent
series, would have prevented the invention—or given rise to a different one.
Thus, Tarde (1895c: 167) asserts:
A genius is a very singular vital invention that is fruitful in the most sur-
prising social inventions, she is at the same time the highest flower of life
and the highest source of society. She expresses the action of Nature in
History, not the imprecise and continuous action, but intermittent and
clear, and really important. And, when we want to examine this action in
some depth, we are led to perceive, at the bottom of everything, hetero-
geneous, differentiated, original elements, without which nothing can be
explained.
Leibniz is, of course, one of the most impressive and paradigmatic exam-
ples of the Tardean genius inventor. With a particular bio-psychological vig-
our, his social context and his biographical path located him in a crossroad of
opposed intellectual currents and diverse disciplines. In that intersection, he
was able to combine lines that were considered irreconcilable or (very) diver-
gent: NeoPlatonism and Aristotle in his metaphysics, and arithmetic and
geometry in his mathematics. Today it is still difficult to find any important
aspect of philosophy, science and technology that has not been influenced,
The social as contagion, creation and fight 69
from near or afar, by some of his ideas—beginning with the differential and
integral calculus and the binary system.
Now, regardless of how great a genius may be, she is only one kind of
inventor, namely of the highest degree. But he is far from being the one and
only. In line with his definition, Tarde points out that he who invents is any
individual, exceptional or ordinary, celebrated or unknown, in whom for-
merly contradictory or disperse social fluxes coordinate. And this may happen
to anyone in their own right, if not in fact. It is a mistake when, approaching
social dynamics, we consider only the so-called great men and women, while
the key issue resides in the fact that great ideas may appear—as they do—in
“small” men and women as well. Here, we must add that it is necessary to
regard small ideas also, if one wishes to fairly account for social life in any
of its dimensions (political, economic, artistic etc.). At every moment, infini-
tesimal innovations germinate by the million and spread silently, producing
variations every minute, as they are capable of transforming vast courses of
social action.
It is worth mentioning that despite its optimistic tone, this perspective
is not the sociological equivalent to Voltaire’s Candide. When Tarde states
that inventions harmonising a given field do so because they are good and
useful, he refers to scientific and artistic innovations, but also to destructive
or even criminal inventions—as Fieschi’s infernal machine, the Ponzi scheme
or the battle tank. On the other hand, many inventions start as a dissidence
in the ground where it emerges, and sometimes it is criminalised as such
(like Socrates’ philosophical and moral innovations, or Galileo’s scientific
discoveries).
In all cases, we wish to insist that an invention is not something produced
by an individual as a rational, atomistic subject, but rather as a social infini-
tesimal vortex. Consequently, we may perhaps refer to a state of invention
in which mental activity becomes more permeable, intense and rigorous than
usual, precisely because of being more open to a whirlpool of different influ-
ences. This does not mean a loss of clarity, much on the contrary. Beyond
the real or imaginary bonds between invention and madness, it seems to be
here a lucky strike together with a sort of “access to reason”. In Tarde’s view,
all invention is a logical (and theological) work of the first order. It must be
seen as the result of a process in which judgements and propositions, means
and ends, are conjugated in pursuit of maximum coherence with maximum
variety. Now, this logical work is entirely social, that is individual and multi-
tudinous at the same time. It is the result of a social cooperation dynamic that
can be regarded as neither general nor abstract. It cannot be claimed to have
been produced by the genius of a people, or the spirit of the times, nor can it
be said to be the result of some culture in general, nor that it concocted by a
corporation (church, army), or not even by a small group as such (school, cir-
cle, academia). Rather on the contrary. Emerging in an individual or another,
70 The social as contagion, creation and fight
inventions spread out by expanding their influence range gradually and thus
forming groups, corporations and peoples. Inventions combining with each
other in specific ways give the dominant tone to this or that time, and con-
figure this or that culture. For this reason, Tarde (1898) may writes, in the
wordings of the 19th century: “Deep down in every association among men
there exists, let me repeat it, originally, an association of ideas within the
same man”. In addition to this, as can be seen now clearly, these ideas are
accumulated inventions indeed, and to get associated within a mind, they
have sometimes travelled enormous geographic and time extensions by way
of imitative contagion. And at each and every step, they receive small (or big)
contributions that make them evolve. Therefore, each invention implies and
expresses a huge net of social networks—or neural networks, if one wishes.
In the tiny space of their occurrence, each one of them motorises, recomposes
and redirects vast layers of knowledge, doctrine, procedures and techniques
that have been accumulating, sometimes for centuries or millennia. Used as
we are to looking for great causes causing great effects, we come to know
that in social life, it is the small causes of enormous consequences that rule.
Notes
1 In an early text titled Maine de Biran et l’evolucionnisme en psychologie, Tarde
proposes De Biran as a predecessor of Spencer, Taine, Ribot and Wundt, and he
presents his own conception of evolution based in difference rather than in identity.
This text was re-published in 2000 with a preliminary study of A. Deveraux and a
comment of Alliez. On De Biran, see Montebello (2000).
2 There are many coincidences between Tarde’s sociology and Dawkin’s (1976) and
Blackmore’s (1999) memetics approach, to such an extent that some scholars have
seen Tarde as the “forefather of memetics” (Marsden, 2000). According to the
canonical definition, a meme is “a unit of information residing in a brain” (Dawk-
ins, 1982), that passes from mind to mind in a process of “thought contagion”.
Accordingly, religious beliefs can be for example understood as “mind viruses”
(Dawkins, 1993).
3 Bergson (1955: 278/279) affirms that Tarde’s sociology formulates “a certain very
original point of view on causality. In his perspective, causality is, par excellence,
that which operates in human societies where an individual invents and others imi-
tate her. It cannot be reduced to any of the types of causality described by physicists
and metaphysicians. Imitation is a certain sui generis action that is exercised from
spirit to spirit”.
4 See Toews (2018) for a comparison between Tarde’s and Simmel’s sociologies.
5 A general approach on Tarde’s criminal sociology can be found Tonkonoff (2014).
6 It is worth quoting the definition of ‘accidental event’ elaborated by Agustín
Cournot (1975:34), who is recognized by Tarde as one of his greatest masters: “The
events driven by the combination or the gathering of other events that belong to
series that are independent from each other, are what we call accidental, or random,
events”.
7 In this respect, Cournot’s teachings are decisive as well. Tarde devoted some articles
(1903a, 1905a) and a lecture (2002) in the College to Cournot’s work. On Cournot
as a sociologist see Leroux (2019).
4
SOCIOLOGY OF FLOWS AND
ENSEMBLES
DOI: 10.4324/9781003197386-5
72 Sociology of flows and ensembles
Once these questions are answered, it is important to know how those differ-
ent heterogeneous imitative flows compose, and what kind of composition is
that. In other words, what is a social system in this sociology?
Following the line of these interrogations, we will see how Tarde seeks
to establish the principles that rule social contagions (laws of imitation). He
also aims to discover the processes through which social currents compose
with each other (laws of adaptation), as well as to describe the type of con-
figuration that results from those couplings, that is to say, the ensembles or
social systems as he understands them.
Tardean sociology is far from denying the existence of social systems, as
long as they are understood as dynamic configurations of collective currents
of beliefs and desires. As a matter of fact, Tarde formulated an original way
of understanding what a system is, which is condensed in the concepts of co-
adaptation and ensemble. This is an innovative approach still today because
it responds to the question about societal structuration starting from differ-
ence and not from identity, from the small and not from the big, from move-
ment and not from repose—and from below and not from above. According
to this, social institutions such as government, law, market, science, art and
language are neither operational rules somehow chosen by individuals nor
holistic structures which pre-exist and determine them. Instead, they are the
co-adaptation of multiple infinitesimal currents of belief and desire born from
many different inventions. Each of these ensembles is the result of the integra-
tion of psychosocial fluxes of popular faith and passion that, coming from
diverse origins and having diverse contents, spread at different speeds and in
different directions. None of these systems totalises its dynamic components,
but they however manage to partially articulate them, giving to these packs
of fluxes a certain global logic coherence, certain regular rhythm and certain
specific direction. And the same is valid for those systems of systems that can
be called—national and international—societies.
In this context, Tarde also develops the concepts of social intelligence and
collective willingness—or, in his own terms “social logic” and “social teleol-
ogy”. The first one is related to the set of judgements that live in scientific,
legal, philosophical, religious inventions and unfold with their propagation.
The second one refers to the goals that industrial, agricultural, commercial,
political inventions carry and communicate. Beyond this quite artificial divi-
sion between inventions of beliefs and inventions of desires, in which Tarde
sometimes insists, the key here is that convictions and goals articulated in a
syllogistic way are always implied in every invention. That is to say that both
beliefs and desires entail a type of operation according to which given cer-
tain propositions, certain conclusions, will necessarily follow. Hence Tarde,
many times accused of being irrationalist, characterises social thought and
will ruled, at least in part, by that logical device that is syllogism. However,
he proposes certain reforms to the classical syllogistic for he argues that it
Sociology of flows and ensembles 73
one shows how, not so much social bodies, but rather social tissues are
formed, how, not so much national garment, but rather social fabric is
made; the other one deals with the way in which those tissues are organ-
ised, how that fabric is cut and sewed, I mean, how it cuts and sews itself.
the antagonism has been solved in its favour. It has succeeded in displacing
opposing trends—and solving in individuals the doubts in which they were
immersed. This victory very often occurs due to extra-logic causes. We will
explore this point soon.
Before that, let us remember that here what from afar appears as a more
or less homogeneous milieu is actually a field populated by micro propaga-
tions but also by micro-fights. There are a multitude of linguistic, industrial,
commercial, artistic, political, moral minute oppositions that first take place
between social tendencies and later between individuals and groups, so to
speak. That is why these conflicts should be characterised as infra and trans-
individual. If a new trend prevails as a result of these infinitesimal fights, it
will replace the previous logical or teleological model, and we should speak
of a substitution of imitations rather than a coupling of them.
Let us now attend to the social landscape outlined in this way. At every
moment, a multitude of innovations struggle to extend themselves and con-
quer the social field, transforming it to its image and likeness. In its unfold-
ing, each invention may find concordances that strengthen, impulse it and
enable it to advance, or resistances and contradictions that hinder it. The
field in which both things occur is the mind (and heart) of each of the individ-
uals that is reached by the invention in question, and to whom it represents a
model to follow. Hence, if we accept this, we should no longer imagine social
reproduction, conflict and change as centralised, global and homogeneous
processes with a regular and convergent course. Rather, we ought to conceive
social life as a multi-centred and polyrhythmic process in which a multitude
of imitative contagions and a multitude of infinitesimal adaptative harmonies
(i.e. inventions) coexist with a large number of infinitesimal conflicts and
substitutions. All of them take place scattered in hundreds, thousands or
millions of minds (and bodies). But it is also important to note that both this
cooperation and these fights between inventions entail a fundamental logic
and teleological component that, all other variables remaining the same, will
decide which of them will unfold and to what extent. Let us take a closer
look at this.
the syllogism is the (micro) machine that produces the elementary mean-
ings and directions of thoughts, wills and feelings wherever they work and
propagate.
Therefore, he asserts that the more concordant the argument inscribed
in an invention is with those already established as truths and goals in the
context where it seeks to spread, the greater the logical concordance between
them and the faster, more extensive and profound the invention’s unfolding
will be. Another detail should now be added to this: such concordance may
be real or just apparent. That is to say, it can be based on the mistaken belief
that there is concordance between the existing ideas and ambitions and the
new ones. All in all, this is enough for their logical couplings to occur. In both
cases, Tarde will speak of persuasion, giving an amphibious meaning to this
word and linking it not only to rhetoric and seduction but also to reason-
ing. The logic of social contagion operates with something like persuasive
syllogisms.
As Leibniz, Tarde relies on the traditional Aristotelian theory of syllogism,
but he seems inspired in Aristotle’s notion of practical syllogism, rather than
in the theoretical or properly logical one. Aristotle speaks of practical (or
teleological) syllogism when he seeks to address the movement the psyche
makes from desire to action. This entails many complications because intel-
lect as well as “character and volition” intervenes in desire. And it must be
added that, even when reasoning may establish what is true or convenient
regarding a certain desire, action always involves contingency and exceeds
logical deduction. Therefore, the result of a practical syllogism is not neces-
sary but possible. That is why some scholars deny that those kinds of mental
operations have a strictly syllogistic character, and they make them depend
on rhetoric rather than on analytics. Tarde seems to agree with them, but
he does not take the step towards a radical localisation of the social logic
in the field of rhetoric—as, for example Lacan and some of his followers
do.1 However, he insists that social logic is a practical one (and the same
applies to social teleology). That is why, he proposes some reforms to the
classical Aristotelian framework, all of them ultimately related to the practi-
cal and persuasive status of social logic. He establishes that, whether indi-
vidual or social, the syllogistic analysis should consider grades in addition
to the classical opposition between true and false. Moreover, he advocates
for the inclusion of “the illogical” in the study of social syllogisms. And this
is because while the individual logic “demands the complete suppression of
intra-cerebral contradictions, the social logic is well-reconciled with inter-
cerebral contradictions” (1895c: 3). Sociology should then deal with socially
active propositions that, even when they are illogical or poorly built from a
formal point of view, are not pathological and enable social understanding.
The science of the social would lose a great part of its object if it excluded
“illogical” syllogisms that frequently govern vast realms of social life. And
Sociology of flows and ensembles 77
the same would happen if it did not pay attention to the existence of socially
active and effective “semi-desires” and “semi-beliefs”.
It is important to note that the syllogistic functioning of the social logic
does not depend on the individuals’ operative consciousness (i.e. on the indi-
vidual logic). Faced with different innovations, that is to say, with different
arguments, each one believes she chooses freely which one to follow. How-
ever, what actually happens is that this election is the most adequate to past
persuasive arguments sedimented in herself, that is the most congruent with
her cognitive and volitional habits. The social logic demands no more. For
the same reason, it does not require the intervention of a clear and distinct
conscience in the process at stake. And if a conscience as such intervenes, it
will just tend to confirm that concordance of the new with the pre-existing
logical and teleological configuration (unless extra-logical causes appear,
which, according to Tarde, often happens).
As we know, it may also occur that a social trend enters combat with
others. We should now add that this fight is largely logical because every
invention implicitly entails an impersonal reasoning that may be contradic-
tory with the already admitted reasoning in its area of competence. In its
eagerness to unfold and gain ground, new trends argue in its favour and
the opposing existing trends counter-argue and defend themselves. Hence,
a major task of infinitesimal sociology is to approach things in detail. For
example it is a matter of unfolding the implicit arguments in consumption
goods, and discovering that
It can then be said that logic and teleological syllogisms, with their cou-
plings and their collisions, “precede and govern each of the actions of our
lives” (Tarde, 1895c: 175). An infinitesimal approach allows us to under-
stand that propositions and syllogisms are not only found where we expect
to find them (scientific and philosophical theories, political ideologies and
religious dogmas). They can also be found more or less hidden in objects, and
certainly in individual actions and social practices. Every act contains a silent
proposition and a tacit goal. Every behaviour, no matter how small and insig-
nificant it may seem, expresses a particular belief. Moreover, it expresses cer-
tain desires or goals which it intends to generalise. Therefore, to practise any
activity is to defend its creed and to pursue its objectives, both of them often
implicit and far-reaching (certain theory of life or, better yet, of the universe).
78 Sociology of flows and ensembles
A peasant who cultivates a field affirms, knowingly or not, that “the earth
is the mother of wealth” (Tarde, 1890a: 209). Hence, any invention—that is
to say, any new object, idea, feeling, gesture, action, practice—that contra-
dicts this principle will tend to hinder its dynamism and to dry its intellec-
tual and affective sources. Likewise, any other that complements it will tend
to reaffirm its validity and foster its development. Thus, an individual who
has made the criminal activity a regular office, “does not only practice, [but
also] professes, the right to murder and robbery as others profess the right
to work, and she did not wait for Darwin to represent life as a war in which
killing alternates with looting” (Tarde, 1890a: 116/117).
All this gives fashions a significant heuristic value. The rise of an inven-
tion is nothing but the emergence of a new way of doing, feeling or thinking.
And, if we accept this, its spreading addresses the dominant logical and tele-
ological configuration of the social space in which it unfolds. This is valid
for criminal innovations that cause criminal fashions. If modern societies
are characterised by the passage from the traditional sense of honour and
sacrifice to desire of wealth and hedonism, the periodical inventions and
propagations of new ways of appropriating others’ belongings won’t be then
surprising. The scarcity of legal techniques and institutional frames to repair
the publicly hurt pride or religious offences will not be surprising either. To
do sociology of those profound transformations in social values, it is neces-
sary to identify the specific innovations that concurred to produce those val-
ues. The map of its spreading, struggles and (re)compositions shall be drawn
as well. Furthermore, it is possible to map the major lines of the probabilistic
field in which these inventions occur and, maybe, some future inventions
can be glimpsed—because, from this perspective, there is no end of history.
Here, transformations of social values produce new necessities and gener-
ate new problems to which new inventions will seek to respond. Thus, for
instance, “as the solidarity of ancient, aristocratic origin, is dissolved by indi-
vidualism of modern and urban origin, the need to enjoy replaces the need
to be feared or respected, the need for money replaces the need for revenge”
(Tarde, 1890a: 86/87). Therefore, each society has somehow the inventions
and epidemics it deserves—be they legal or illegal, violent or peaceful.
when different inventions have equal logical or teleological value, (1) internal
models will be imitated before external ones, (2) models coming from indi-
viduals or groups considered superior will propagate easier, (3) models with
which we have a closer psychosocial proximity will be more imitated and (4)
the imitation cycle will always be custom-fashion-transformed custom.
The first of these principles could be designated as “the soul of social
things principle”. We already know that innovations are primarily new ideas,
beliefs and desires. This is valid for a scientific discovery and a new profes-
sional technique, administrative proceeding, political creed or religious rite,
as well as for every new consumption object, every new hairstyle, dress or
word, every new painting, song or film. Sociology must identify and describe
those infinitesimal driving forces if it seeks to address the social processes
in which such innovations emerge and inscribe themselves, as well as the
dynamics they inaugurate and the transformations they produce. In addition
to this, another specification related to the intimate composition of inven-
tions should be added: each one contains micro-sets of judgements and ways
of expressing them as well as micro-sets of goals and means to achieve them.
On this basis, Tarde argues that, in the process of social diffusion, ideas
are communicated “first” than their expressions and goals are transmitted
“before” means. In the end, notions and aims come into us much more eas-
ily and they spread much quicker than expressions and proceedings. This is
another way of saying that we believe in beliefs and wish desires, and that if
we do things in a certain manner and not in another it is because the potency
of an invention inhabits us as an organising and ruling force. The first to be
copied are principles and goals, ideas and passions; actions, consumptions,
practices, ceremonies and manners in accordance to them come later. Thus,
when a person copies another, when a class starts dressing up, furnish-
ing, having fun, taking as models dresses, furniture, ways of entertaining
of another class, it is because the former had already borrowed from the
latter feelings and necessities that are the exterior manifestation of these
forms of action. In consequence, this class could and should borrow from
the other one also its volitions, that is to say, to want according to its will.
(Tarde, 1890: 157)
This emphasis on the active power of beliefs and desires, on its relational
character and on its specular dynamic, has an undeniable Leibnizian stamp,
and it leads to the development of a sociology of unfoldings (or propagations)
and folds (or subjectivations). But also, and because of this, it is somehow
related to the perspective of the so-called “masters of the suspicion”.2 Here,
as Marx, Nietzsche and Freud, what people believe they do hardly coincide
with what they actually do. It is true that, in Tarde, there is neither a conflict-
ual centre in the psyche nor a dialectic structuration in societies—as Freud
80 Sociology of flows and ensembles
upper by the lower would not have disappeared. The irradiating source of
examples is now occupied by cities, especially by large capitals. They are the
new lords, the glorious poles of social magnetisation that fascinate themselves
and fascinate peripheral populations, spreading their political, aesthetical or
criminal fashions. Epidemics arisen in cities expand over a whole country
and even transcend their national borders, with a speed and extension that
are proportional to the reputation of their birth. In this way, the propagation
of ideologies, morals, techniques and arts, as well as of fantasies, ambitions
and violence invented in major cities, spreads progressively in the national
and international field, which they influence and conquer.
Another extra-logic factor intervening in the mimetic propagation is the
existing psychosocial distance between the exemplary focal point and its
receptors. This rule can be formulated like this: the degree of influence of a
model will be directly proportional to the closeness to it. But this is a psychic
and not geographical closeness. For Tarde it is clear that the influences from
immediate surroundings, transmitted in face-to-face meetings and in small
groups, are overriding for every individual. Thus, Tarde sees daily interac-
tions as the most fluid means for the imitative diffusion of fashions and fam-
ily as the most vigorous means for the reproduction of traditions. However,
he also was one of the first to highlight the phenomenon of compression of
social distances produced by mass media and their deployment throughout
the social field. With them, the psychic distance tends to get rid of the obsta-
cle of geographic localisation and of the requirement of face-to-face interac-
tions. In fact, they allow psychic intimacy at kilometres of distance.
Finally, Tarde underlines the importance of fashions and customs in imi-
tative propagation. If both work as extra-logic influences, it is also due to
the prestige they have—therefore, this principle is related to the aforemen-
tioned. To do “as everyone does”, and to do it because everyone does it in
this manner, is a (non) logical cause of imitative propagation. If that doing
propagates contemporary examples, it will be a fashion; if it disseminates
past examples, it will be a custom. There are historical moments in which the
new is the most prestigious, and some other moments in which the prestige
of the antique prevail. That domain of one or the other increases the prob-
abilities of diffusion at stake. Tarde says that fashions, that is diffusion of
contemporary inventions, are small streams and customs are big rivers. He
argues that this is also true in post-traditional societies ruled by the authority
of the new, and characterised by the production of innumerous and rapidly
spread inventions. In these societies, as in all the rest, millenary currents of
slow rhythm and long scope structure language, legislation, administration,
religion, family, cooking, clothing and so forth. In these slow currents, small
rapid flows produced by the imitative diffusion are irregularly grafted: a new
word, law, technique, recipe, item or dogma. This theoretician of innovation
affirms: “the part of the traditional and customary element is always the
82 Sociology of flows and ensembles
one prevailing in social life, and this prevalence reveals itself powerfully in
the way how, even the most radical and revolutionary, innovations spread”
(Tarde, 1890: 246). This way, which may be actually called hegemonic oper-
ation, would be the following: to propagate a new idea it is necessary to
formulate it in the already-known and traditional language, and not in its
own terms because, as they are new, they are difficult to be understood. For
instance, this is what Luther, Rousseau and Voltaire would have done in order
to transmit their innovative dogmas: “The old ground is always the vantage-
point from which to tumble down old edifices and to rear up new ones. The
established morality is always the basis for the introduction of new political
ideas” (Tarde, 1890: 247). Furthermore, even when not all fashions become
customs, every custom has indeed started as a fashion. This permanently
repeated socio-historic cycle, through which innovations graft in the flow of
customs and become in turn tradition, is not regressive or conservative at all.
It is rather the proper form of social evolution. The propagation of innova-
tions depends on the traditional configurations, but once deployed these end
up subordinating them. The result is always that “the former custom obeys
and the latter rules, and, so to speak, explodes it” (Tarde, 1890: 140).
Enter any house, a Parisian apartment, a rustic hut, a wild cottage or in the
nomad’s tent and you will see furniture, weapons, tools, household uten-
sils, clothes. There, you will attend religious exercises or manual or intel-
lectual professional jobs, and you will listen to conversations or songs,
Sociology of flows and ensembles 83
It can be seen that the tiny space of a room is not only interesting regarding
the face-to-face interactions that occur there or the testimonies of private life
that can be found in it. Rather, a micro-mega analysis implies the diagram-
matisation of the socio-historical forces that configure in detail the dynamics
of everyday life in a certain time and place. It also shows the domestic setting
as a space open to—and constituted by—the social field in its multiple tem-
porality. And this turns it into an immediately (micro)political, even public,
emplacement. Even if the objects found there were made by nearby and con-
temporary manufacturers, each one always carries something of its origi-
nal geography and history. That is to say, each one contains in its interior
the social forces (i.e. dogmas, principles, necessities, interests) that produced
them and that have evolved throughout its unfolding and diffusion. This is
also valid for all the forms of relations that we understand as domestic. To do
the archaeology of such a tiny place is to discover the minuscule and diverse
origins of all of its components in order to address the micro meanings and
directions they carry. To do its cartography is to map these lines in at least
two senses: (1) identifying the dominant forces in this field of relations and
(2) following them not only to their (multiple) origins but also to their (mul-
tiple) present destinations. By doing this, the home will reveal itself as an het-
erogeneous ensemble of multi-scalar relationships, many of them planetary
in scope—long before the Internet.
All the aforementioned is true for every social institution, regardless of the
number of people and resources they entail (simultaneously or successively).
It also applies then to what we usually call great or macro-social institutions:
positive law, secular moral, monotheistic religions, modern science, nation-
state, post-industrial mode of production and so on. When seen up close,
84 Sociology of flows and ensembles
Therefore, every social system, dynamic as it is, has these two different
axes or dimensions. The most general form of relation between them is the
integration of the infinite in the finite, and the re-unfolding of the infinite
in the system. The model would be the following: in a field where the pos-
sibilities of adding elements are virtually unlimited due to the laxity of their
relationships, a group of rules is established. This group can only be finite in
86 Sociology of flows and ensembles
order to accomplish their organising function and preserve the system over
time. But after that, the field of organised elements can grow indefinitely.
Thus, for example, before Newton’s laws, the successive astronomical dis-
coveries did not contradict themselves, and, after them, they confirm in the
system of celestial mechanics that today we call classical. There, as in any
other system, data may extend ad infinitum, but grammar does not. Gram-
mar may introduce new principles, but there is a moment in which it is not
possible to add a new one without contradicting some others. The same hap-
pens with religions. Each one emerges immersed in a vast plot made of diverse
narratives, myths and legends, whose meanings are certainly heterogeneous
and even more or less contradictory. And its constitution would be nothing
but the establishment of a dominant dogma and some rites in accordance
with it. Once established, this religious grammar has to keep itself relatively
restricted if it aims to make its dictionary coherent. For this reason, it tends
only to incorporate rules that corroborate its principles. On the other hand,
the religious vocabulary (legends, saints, martyrs etc.) is then able to enlarge
without limits, as long as it remains subsumed by the guiding lines.
If this is correct, we should say that the more active the lexical (or narra-
tive) axis of a social system is, the more plastic and changing this system will
be. Likewise, if its grammatical or dogmatic axis prevails, it will tend to be
more static and resistant to transformations. For instance,
These considerations are also valid for systems of desire. Even though
Tarde does not make it explicit, we may add that the dictionary is in these
systems constituted by the repertory of means to achieve goals, and grammar
is the hierarchy of goals that rules and organises this “lexical set” of actions.
Such linguistic, religious and scientific systems coordinate and address the
multitude of collective currents of faith through the co-adaptation of the
inventions of beliefs; the political system, economy and law organise and dis-
tribute collective currents of passions, interests and necessities. According to
Tarde, the common denominator of these teleological ensembles is to refer to
Sociology of flows and ensembles 87
values, and both their dynamics and transformations depend on the change
of the respective values they express.
Law would be exemplary in this for it is a social system produced by the
“mutual and intimate reflection” between (logical) principles and (theologi-
cal) values—with prevalence of the latter. Thus, chattel law is instituted when
private property is born and both the desire to achieve it and the belief in the
importance of its acquisition propagate socially. Likewise, transformations
in criminal law depend on the changes in crime patterns that are in turn ruled
by the transformations in social desires. This highlights the distinctive char-
acter of law which, as language, is not only “an integral part of social life, but
also its integral mirror” (Tarde, 1994: 132). When a new necessity or interest
is invented and propagates, the legislative ensemble is driven to adapt itself.
This does not only occur when new values emerge; but it is also linked to the
ups and downs of current values. Therefore, every time it grows or decreases
the flow of “one of the countless unequal channels through which the river of
national Desire distributes and branches, it is necessary to modify the legisla-
tion, a kind of original map of that basin” (Tarde, 1895: 517).
couplings and substitutions (a kind of selection) that are produced with the
collaboration of different individual minds. And all this occurs in a more or
less impersonal way in individuals mentally related to others in such a way
that it is difficult to identify where each one starts and ends.
We may speak here of a social mind that believes (reasons, knows, opines)
and desires (needs, seeks to, pursues). But we should be careful not to con-
ceive it as a Hobbesian mechanical automaton or as a transcendent totality—
as Hegel’s objective Spirit, Marx’s General Intellect or Durkheim’s collective
consciousness. It is rather the disseminated functioning of a trans-individual
psychic field made of innumerable infinitesimal currents of intellection, affec-
tion and actions. The social mind then lacks a unique centre and a one-way
address and it only exists as a multi-linear network whose nodes are the
singular minds mimetically communicated. This communication may have
any content, no matter how delusional it may seem from an exterior point of
view. However, the collective mental processes here at stake are never exempt
from certain rationality.
As mentioned, Tarde finds syllogism functioning on the basis of any pro-
cess where beliefs intervene. This means that philosophies and sciences belong
to the same family as religions, myths and political ideologies. He then makes
a double movement: he includes reason—however it is defined—in the wider
field of beliefs and, at the same time, he postulates that all beliefs are syllo-
gistically structured. This does not imply that all philosophical, scientific or
religious propositions are true in ontological terms or formally correct. But it
does have notable consequences from a sociological point of view.
Above all, something that may seem obvious takes on a new meaning:
whatever is collectively believed will be true for believers. And this is also
true for individual convictions: it is not possible to believe in what is con-
sidered false. If we add that the establishment of any socially shared premise
is produced through diffusion, we are one step away from saying that social
truths are instituted politically. Tarde does not take this step explicitly, even
though his work enables and presupposes it. The prevalence of some certain-
ties implies both the subordination and the exclusion of other convictions,
and both things occur in the realm of public opinion, that is to say, in a mul-
tiple, virtual and volatile space made of collective beliefs and passions always
on collision and in dispute. Once certain major premises are established
there, certain consequences will follow as logically necessary and therefore
true—and others will remain established as false. And the same is valid for
collective desires. The consolidation of certain values as fundamental and of
certain means as legitimate will organise a social logic of volitions—because
as there are logic syllogisms, there would also be teleological ones. Both tend
to the logical coherence of social thinking and desiring, in spite of their ran-
dom origins and evolutions. Both have a socially effective, binding and objec-
tive character during their historical reign.
Sociology of flows and ensembles 89
Now we see why sociology should contain those interrelated branches that
Tarde called social logic and social teleology. A priority task of social science
is to address in detail the syllogistic economy of the human groups it studies.
When micro-analysing an imitative flow or a social trend, it should iden-
tify the notions working as subjects and predicates in the propositions they
carry. Such social science should also identify which of those propositions
work as major and minor premises and which as conclusions. Furthermore,
it should recognise which conclusions are affirmed as true and possible and
which are rejected as false, wrong or impossible. It should also be registered
the highs and lows of the believing and desiring intensity that invest those
reasonings. All this has to be done without forgetting that these practical
syllogisms belong to the relational field of social actions and interactions,
and consequently, they are always submitted to the non-logical influences of
fashion and custom, personal and collective prestige, psychosocial distance
and so forth.
It is important to mention that, as a branch of sociology, social logic
would be able to adopt a normative position regarding its object, that is
to say, an analogous role to that (plain) logic has with regard to individual
reasoning. Applying adequately the reformed syllogistic, one could identify
which socially ruling reasonings are (formally) correct, which are more or
less correct and which are not at all correct. And this is also valid for the tele-
ological branch of this science which can be assimilated to moral, because it
deals with the means and goals that rule social practices, a kind of scientific
moral dedicated to the study and orientation of social desires based on the
practical syllogisms that drive them. Hence, faced with social thought and
will, this science would be able to objectively describe the social mind as it
actually exists and works in each historical moment. Determining whether
these socio-psychic configurations are structured around true beliefs or ethi-
cally fair goals does not correspond to this sociology—even assuming that
the (classical) alternative between realism and relativism makes sense here.
Nevertheless, it will be able to establish if social truths are logically coher-
ent with themselves and if the means of action implemented are suitable to
serve the socially pursued goals. It will also be competent to examine to what
extent the different prevailing truths and dominant goals are consistent with
each other. Finally, it will be able to measure the matching between social
judgements and goals.
In fact, the utility of real, practical, reasoning does not consist in generat-
ing new propositions, induced or deduced . . ., but rather in clearly modi-
fying our opinion—I add: or mainly the other’s opinion—that is to say, in
making our faith or the other’s faith in these propositions go up or down,
or even in making it change its sign, turning it from affirmative into nega-
tive or vice versa.
(Tarde, 1895c: 256)
Notes
1 Lacan (1966) formulated a “logic of the signifier” to address psychic and social life.
Developing that very same line, Laclau (2014) speaks of the “rhetorical founda-
tions of society”. From his part, Castoriadis (1987) will postulate the imaginary
institution of society and will seek to outline a post Lacanian “logic of magmas”.
2 As it is known, this qualification was coined by Ricoeur (1970: 32) to highlight that
Marx, Nietzsche and Freud, in their own ways, aimed at unmasking the real hidden
behind appearances. “Three masters, seemingly mutually exclusive, dominate the
school of suspicion: Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud”.
3 “The dream has a very striking way of dealing with the category of opposites and
contradictions. This is simply disregarded. To the dream ‘No’ does not seem to
exist. In particular, it prefers to draw opposites together into a unity or to represent
them as one. Indeed, it also takes the liberty of representing some random element
by its wished-for opposite, so that at first one cannot tell which of the possible poles
is meant positively or negatively in the dream-thoughts” (Freud, 1997: 110).
5
THE CONTINUITY OF MULTITUDES
DOI: 10.4324/9781003197386-6
94 The continuity of multitudes
been the one to coin the term “social morphology” and he uses it in the two
aforementioned meanings. We could argue that there is no spatial, numerical
raw determinism in Durkheim, given the fact that he understands the sub-
strate of a group includes, apart from its already mentioned material density,
a “moral” density as well, related to the type, quantity and frequency of its
social interactions. In any case, Durkheim (1982, 1994) and his school would
later take pains to find certain correlations between restricted morphology
and collective representations (Durkheim and Mauss, 2009), or moral den-
sity, as well (Mauss, 1979).2
It is worth mentioning that Marxism, in diametrical opposition to Dur-
kheimian school in almost every sense, tends to agree on the idea of a material
substrate of group structures and social representations. Here, population
and geography are fundamental in relation to economic life. As workforces
and natural resources, they are a crucial element of the material infrastructure
of society, together with its technical production means (tools, machinery
etc.). In addition, the idea of a general morphology made up of social classes
is constitutive of the Marxist point of view. Moreover, it is worth mentioning
that empiricist tradition rejects the possibility that groups are anything other
than aggregates of individuals, but it does not discard the idea of a material
substrate for social interactions. In classical political economy, for instance,
it is of great relevance to consider the number of individuals involved, their
technical means available and the geography they inhabit.
As for Tarde, it is possible to reconstruct in his work the fundamental fea-
tures of a social morphology in a broad sense—the one defined by Durkheim
as “the part of sociology whose goal is to construct and classify social types”
(1982: 127). As we know, for Tardean sociology, social formations cannot be
conceived as internally homogeneous parts of a larger whole—whether it be
organismic or dialectic. Now we must add that they are remarkably free from
any geographical or numerical determination. Here, to make the cartography
of the formations which are present in a given social field is not to relate them
to their number of individuals, or territorial distribution. Rather, it is to map
the different types of inter-mental connections at a distance that we find in
this field, which form diverse while interpenetrated configurations. In Tarde’s
thought, society’s material substrate is the ocean of trans-individual beliefs
and desires whose currents generate, reproduce and transform all associa-
tion types known to history (from the horde to national and international
societies). As will be seen, this implies not only a critique to the reification of
these different social configurations, but also a questioning of both unilineal
evolutionism as much as spatial and populational causalism.
We know that, according to Tarde, there is no social group made out
of simple homogeneous elements; nor are groups simple or homogeneous,
in such ways that they may later gather in larger totalities comprising or
synthesising them. Instead, all social groups are ensembles that combine
The continuity of multitudes 95
These three types of social groupings are the most active vectors in the
highly shifting constellation of the post-traditional social field. They are not
the only ones but they are the most relevant, together with individuals—
understood, themselves as well, as sui generis social configurations.
According to Tarde, they represent morphological milestones in the his-
tory of humankind. An evolutionary line can be traced along them, but
this does not mean that one has replaced the other as they appear. Rather,
once emerged, they live in the same social field and also transform into one
another unceasingly. Hence, there is a synchronic continuity and also some
“smooth” transitions amongst all these different social formations. A great
deal of our social, political, cultural and economic life consists basically in
this game of continuous metamorphoses and their consequences. The num-
ber of participants in each configuration is not a determining aspect in any
case. There is no room for questions such as how many participants in a
group make it qualify as a multitude. And the same holds for the other types
of social groupings. It is not about quantitatively different groups per case,
but of qualitatively different relational regimes. Therefore, the characteris-
tics of the inhabited territory or the spatial distance among its inhabitants
are not determining factors either. Here, social morphology is more topo-
logical than topographical: the other side of the world may be near and the
neighbour next door, very far. To make these assertions plausible, we will
deploy them showing the change of perspective they produce within social
sciences, and outside them.
The crowd
In the end of 19th-centuryEurope, and after a long period of popular upris-
ings, the study of the multitude gained great interest in the scientific and
academic milieu. In this convulsed social context, multitudes were matters
of an urgent political and legal concern. Emerging human sciences felt sum-
moned both in theoretical and in practical terms: which kind of phenom-
enon is this? How and why does it emerge? What characteristics does it
have? But also, how to evaluate its social value? Are multitudes a negative
phenomenon? And eventually, how to control it? Tarde, together with Le
Bon and Sighele, was one of the main intellectual references in the research
and debates around these questions. The three of them were part of a field
of interlocutions that, among others, also includes Freud, McDougall and
Durkheim in a certain way. Their works about this subject are sometimes
grouped under the label of “Psychology of Crowds”. We will soon see that
the question of masses exceeds by far the limits of a specific and subordi-
nated discipline—at least for Tarde. In any case, for all of them, a multitude
is itself a remarkable epistemological and political problem. In the following
The continuity of multitudes 97
Faced with such a landscape, there were some who characterised crowds as
a pathological phenomenon and considered them a threat to the social order
and its survival. But this was maybe a cultural and political symptom. As
regarding hypnotism, the crowd manifests features that contradict the way in
which European civilisation understands itself, that is to say, a consolidated
group of free, equal, rational and pacific individuals. The masses’ mirror
returns the image of those very same individuals intertwined in a thoughtless,
amorphous and often violent movement.
Even when his last works introduce some nuances, Tarde never stops
describing the crowds using a series of disturbing (and polemic) comparisons
typical of his time. In the masses, he finds some traits shared with wild ani-
mals and with the so-called primitive societies—which would also be close to
savage animals in evolutionary terms. Thus, for example, crowds in modern
cities would be not only gregarious but also ferocious in their behaviour.
That ferocity, altogether with their superstitious gullibility, their taste for
idolatry, their constant willingness to direct action, would assimilate them
to archaic societies, as was imagined by late-Victorian anthropology. The so-
called primitive people would be as dogmatic as mobs and, like them, they
would not know indecision. On the other hand, masses are also changing,
contradictory and voluble in their beliefs and goals, as well as intolerant “as
an African despot”. In addition, they would always have something “child-
ish” and would be “female in their temper”, even in those cases in which they
are made of male adults. But this is not all. The crowds are often violent as
criminals and they do everything with a disproportionate vanity—like tribal
chiefs do according to the European believes. Furthermore, all crowds are
98 The continuity of multitudes
also like alienated individuals, always close to hallucination due to their ideo-
logical, religious or patriotic delusions. Therefore, Tarde (1895: 63) could
write that “a group of people, more or less healthy in spirit, easily becomes a
sole and unique madman”.
This eloquent characterisation was shared by vast sectors of the West-
ern intelligence at the end of the 19th century. It was present in the Italian
Scuola Positivista of Lombroso, Ferri and Garofalo—to which Sighele also
belongs. It had also a central role in Le Bon’s famous texts, and Freud was not
indifferent to it. It is difficult not to see to what extent this characterisation
describes, above all, those who make it. It is not too bold to state that these
rhetorical images hardly dissimulate their reference to the popular uprisings
of 1848 and 1871 and, a little further in time, the French Revolution. But
also, as in a dream, they condense all the figures by which the European—
colonialist, patriarchal, individualist and nature-dominating—social order
felt threatened.
Having said that, one should not be discouraged by the barely disguised
prejudices and fears that these analogies entail.3 Rather, it is important to
keep the elementary psychosocial features they seek to illustrate. To summa-
rise them, we will say that the crowd is a kind of social association that can
be distinguished by the unity and simplicity of its ideas, the intensity of its
passions and the coordination of its actions. In it, individual consciousness
becomes unconsciousness and the mental functions we call rational are sub-
jugated by imagination and passions. Within the multitude, class and social
status differences disappear, and everything happens as if memory faded and
there was no lucidity in individuals that make it up. The idea or purpose
embraced by a crowd one day is rejected with equal vehemence the following
day. And, in both cases, nothing stops the tendency to direct actions, without
mediation or measures. If all this happens when reasonable and measured
individuals gather together in a multitude, it is then worth asking how this is
possible and why.
search much in order to find beliefs and desires that cloud its members or the
hypnotists that irradiate them. The infinitesimal (i.e. relational, continuous,
intensive) character of the social and its exemplar causality appear here in a
particularly clear way, especially regarding its capacity to transform and even
distort the individuals.
Before advancing in this key point, let us add another feature that, for
Tarde, is characteristic of this social configuration: it is regressive. And this
in two main senses: one that values its social performance and another one
that refers to an evolutionary scale. He then says that the multitude is men-
tally conservative and materially destructive, incapable of creating something
new but prone to excess. The individual is the only one who innovates; the
multitude repeats and/or opposes the already created. In this, Tarde differen-
tiates from Durkheim (1995), for whom “collective effervescence” can either
preserve traditional values or conceive new ones. Moreover, Tarde affirms
that the multitude is a “retrograde organism” in terms of social evolution.
It is a regressive phenomenon when compared to Modern society and even
more regressive regarding the Modern individual. It happens that a multi-
tude is a simple syllogism, while an evolved society (a nation) is a complex
syllogism—and its individuals are even more complex.
cancelling them as it spreads and gains force and extension. But this cannot
happen without some individuals acting as magnetisers or, to say it in the
political language of the 19th century, as meneurs, that isas leaders, agita-
tors or instigators who are the emission sources of these models (i.e. ideas,
images, goals, emotions, necessities). They channel each one’s previously dis-
persed and diversified psychical energies, concentrating and driving them in
a sole direction.
Therefore, reciprocal and complex suggestions of daily sociality are
replaced by unilateral imitative flows that carry a limited number of beliefs
and desires—in the limit, one single belief charged with desire. To this focali-
sation, reduction and addressing of passions and ideas, we should add the
increase in the desiring and believing intensity, which is related to its propa-
gation. Such is the process of formation of a multitude with its characteristic
monolithic unanimity. Hence, Tarde says that it has the simple and profound
potency of a long unison. In the multitude, the plurality of imitations of regu-
lar and slow rhythm that configure individuals are drastically reduced and,
at the same time, accelerated in a violent contagion. Therefore, an emotion
and a dogma come suddenly to dominate all the group, the individual’s wak-
ing consciousness darkens and reflexibility is turned into automatism. In this
way, the more strengthened and centralised the multitude is, the more indi-
vidualised it becomes. In this context, the individualities it brings together
tend to weaken and disappear.
Any individual, and any group, may become in multitude. When this does
happen, it is not possible to avoid that febrile collective state that, under
certain occasions, drives to atrocity. It happens that when opinions get closer
they turn into convictions and when convictions strengthen each other, they
transform into fanaticism. What was a simple desire in the individual becomes
a passion in the mass. That fervent dogmatism is, for Tarde (1892: 359), the
reason for all the excesses of a mob, including its crimes when they occur.
A multitude first believes and desires with violence, and only later—and for
that reason—acts violently. A “monologisation” of communication and an
extraordinary affective charge concentrated on those few passions and con-
victions transform the economy of social relations and put this singular form
of collective configuration in motion.
Tarde understands that collective over-excitement, monoideism and undif-
ferentiation are mainly premodern ways of relation. It is in that very sense
that the result of the individuals’ association in a multitude is a regression.
It is a purely sociological regression. In addition, masses would recover
anti-cosmopolitan and anti-ecumenical features characteristic of traditional
social formations (e.g. tribes and castes). As they are groupings with an
excited feeling of cohesion, they contradict the socialising and globalising
current that, in Tarde’s view, constitutes the main direction of social his-
tory. Masses transform into strangers or enemies, everyone who does not
102 The continuity of multitudes
The corporation
Tarde does not develop a detailed sociology of corporations like he does
with multitudes and publics. However, he points out the basic characteristics
of this social configuration which he conceptualises in a peculiar way. As
all Tarde’s concepts are, this is extraordinarily broad and strangely precise.
It does includes not only professional groups, but also public administra-
tions, schools and hospitals, which are also types of the corporate genre. The
most intense expressions of a corporation—that is to say, the ones exhibiting
more distinctive characters—are the army and the monastery, and the most
overreaching—or extensive—ones are the State and the Church. Or, to put
The continuity of multitudes 103
it in more precise words, during their most robust period of growth, States
and Churches tend to perform the monastic and military type (without never
achieving it completely).
Corporations then fulfil the requirements of coordination, hierarchy and
division of functions—and also of rationality—that characterise the so-called
“social organisations”. This kind of social formation is undoubtedly very
antique, and the classic sociological narrative watches it developing and
spreading progressively until it dominates Modern social space. That is why
Modern societies were sometimes called “organisational societies”. There,
enormous bureaucratic complexes would fully dominate social dynamics,
displacing Pre-Modern forms of association and transforming them into rel-
ics or even into pathologies. We already know that, from the infinitesimal
perspective, the social landscape is always much more varied, complex and
hybrid than this. This is not because it ignores the historical deployment
of the corporate forms of association and their increasing prominence, but
rather because it considers to be witnessing the persistent activity of masses
and because it also discovers publics.
The first thing to remark is that, seen up close, every corporation is a
multitude. But it is not just that; it is a disciplined, stable and persistent mul-
titude. A second key point to mention is the continuity that exists between
both types of social association. The multitude precedes the corporation in
time; it is, together with the family, the most antique social grouping known
by humans. This was an assumption shared by Tarde, Le Bon and Durkheim,
among others. Tarde argues that the passage from the mass association to the
corporate one entails a civilising evolution produced over time. However, he
also asserts that the result of this evolution is the co-presence of both types
of social formation in the same (Modern) social field, rather than the replace-
ment of one by the other. As important as that diachronic continuity is the
synchronic continuity he finds between both. According to Tarde, there is
not only historical but also sociological continuity between the crowd and
the corporation, since they are both made of the same material. Among other
things, this implies that a corporation can always, and at any time, become a
mass more easily than what is often assumed.
If unity of objectives, coordination of actions and the existence of hierar-
chies are established as the minimum characters of social organisations, we
may then compare these two types of association regarding these features.
Above all, we will no longer be able to affirm without reservations that a
multitude is a disorganised group because a tight coordination oriented to
achieve a goal can be verified in it. Due to its dense cohesion and its sim-
ple objective, the multitude acts with the efficiency and the speed of a sole
and unique individual. The important difference with the corporation is the
spontaneous and ephemeral character of this (proto) social organisation.
Regarding the hierarchical element, we have already seen that the leader or
104 The continuity of multitudes
The press mobilises everything that it touches and vitalizes it. There exists
no Church, however immutable in appearance, which, from the moment
that it submits to the mode of continuous publication, does not develop
the signs of internal mutations impossible to hide. To be convinced of this
efficacy, at once dissolving and regenerating, inherent in a newspaper, we
need only compare the political parties before the existence of the press to
those of the present time. Were they not then less ardent but more durable,
less alive but more tenacious, more fixed in their dimensions and more
solid, more resistant to efforts to renew or fragment them? From the cen-
turies old opposition, so sharp and so persistent, between the Whigs and
Tories, what remains today in England?6
already seen, Tarde refers to a soul of the multitude as well as to a spirit of the
public and of corporations. Each of these social configurations, functioning as
collective minds, leads with precision and efficacy the individual minds (and
bodies) they envelop. But this does not mean that they must be conceived as
transcendent beings, that is entities with a supra-individual existence. From
the infinitesimal point of view, they are social relation regimes that do not
exist outside the socio-psycho-somatic singularities through which they run.
In this respect, they are inter-mental and trans-individual realities that fold
and unfold, following different rhythms and producing different states.
Notess
1 Thus, a manual that used to be a classic in France reads, “quantitative variations
of these elements imply changes in the social structure, in the group’s morphologi-
cal configuration in a broad sense. Such is the basic principle of social morphology
proper” (Cuvillier, 1963: 366).
2 The position of the Durkheimian school is summarised in the classical work by
Halbwachs (1938). On the relation of the Durkheimnian morphology with the
metaphor of the organism and on Tarde’s critiques to this tradition, see Vianna
Vargas (2000).
3 Foucault (1995) and Donzelot (1979) have pointed out the main features of the
production of madness, delinquency and also childhood and colonised cultures as
alterities and objects of intervention at the end of the European 19th century. On
the figure of non-conformist deviant women in this context, see for instance Dean
(1992). For a comprehensive approach to the history of the concept of crowd see
Moscovici (1981), van Ginneken (1992) and Borch (2012).
4 Moreover: “Under certain given circumstances, and only under those circum-
stances, an agglomeration of men presents new characteristics very different from
those of the individuals composing it. . . A collective mind is formed, doubtless
transitory, but presenting very clearly defined characteristics. The gathering has
thus become what, in the absence of a better expression, I will call an organised
crowd, or, if the term is considered preferable, a psychological crowd. It forms a
single being, and is subjected to the law of the mental unity of crowds” (Le Bon,
1908: 26).
5 Between the mass and the corporation, Tarde locates the sects—to which he gives
an important historical and sociological role. Sighele (1898: 46) defines sects in a
strictly Tardean way as follows: “The sect is a selective and permanent crowd. The
mass is a transient sect which has not chosen its members. The sect is the chronic
form of the mass; the mass is the aggravated form of the sect . . . The sect is, then,
112 The continuity of multitudes
the first crystallisation of any doctrine. From the amorphous and confused state in
which the mass manifests itself, any idea must be concretised in the well-defined
form of the sect, unless it later becomes a party, a school, or a scientific, politi-
cal or religious church . . . It is the first stage in which the human group, leaving
the undifferentiated state of the unknown, varied and anonymous mass, rises to a
specification and integration which can then lead to the highest and most perfect
human group: the state”. The type of social formation that Tarde calls “sect” is
what Canetti (1978) and Deleuze and Guattari (1980) later called “pack”. For a
thematisation of the crowd-pack relation in a sense similar to the one we have dis-
cussed here, see Brighenti (2010).
6 And he continues: “In our time, the parties are in the process of perpetual alteration,
of regeneration, and of spontaneous generation. Thus, there is less and less worry
and concern about their platforms, for it is well known that if they come to power,
they will do so only after being thoroughly transformed” (Tarde, 1901: 124).
APPENDIX
Cartographical note
Gabriel Tarde was born in the small city of Sarlat, in a Catholic family. He
received a Jesuit education, studied science and literature in high school and
later attended law school in Toulouse. He got his degree in Paris in 1866. In
1867 he started working as the assistant secretary of a judge in Sarlat and,
in November 1875, he was appointed as an investigating judge. In addition
to his career as a magistrate, Tarde carried out intellectual activities in litera-
ture, philosophy and law (especially criminal law and criminology). His first
productions were distributed within the field of these “three cultures” and
they are fundamental in the development of his sociology. Tarde’s first pub-
lication was a collection of poems titled “Contes et Poèmes” in 1879 and he
continued writing poems and plays throughout his life, some of which were
published in local newspapers. In 1884, he wrote Fragments d’histoire future,
a quite successful novel that was published in 1896. This novel describes a
world where the sun has gone out and humans begin a new underground
civilisation. In the foreword to the English edition, H. G. Wells (1905: 16)
underlines the key of this book and of all the others that will be later written
by Tarde:
time. In one of his first letters, he suggests Ribot the creation of an “asso-
ciation of philosophers that, every year, during the holidays, would go on a
collective summer retreat, a kind of academy in the ancient style”. From that
moment on, there were frequent intellectual exchanges between the two phi-
losophers, as well as an almost uninterrupted publication of articles. Between
1880 and 1893, he published more than twenty texts there, the first of which
was titled “La croyance et le désir, la possibilité de leur mesure”.
In 1887, while working for the General Administration of Prisons, Tarde
also started collaborating with the magazine Archives de l’anthropologie
criminelle et des sciences pénales. Later, in 1893, he became its director when
the journal changed its name to Archives d’anthropologie criminelle de crimi-
nologie, et de psychologie normale et pathologique. He published numerous
articles there, most of them related to criminal law and criminology. This
journal was for Tarde a front of opposition to the Italian Criminal Anthropol-
ogy and a means of dissemination and recognition of his ideas. Under Lom-
broso’s aegis and influenced by French positivists and Darwin’s evolutionary
theory, this school founded its propositions on the fundamental postulate of
biological determination in deviance and crime. In fact, this school supported
the typology developed by Lombroso in L’uomo delinquente (1876): alien-
ated criminals, habitual criminals, occasional criminals, criminals of passion
and born criminals. According to Tarde, crime is a (mimetic) social phenom-
enon, and his divergence with the Italian anthropologists became clear in
1886 with the publication of La criminalité compare. There Gabriel Tarde
developed his considerations regarding criminal statistics as well as an origi-
nal theory of criminal responsibility. Furthermore, the strong controversy
around the notion of the “criminal type” placed Tarde as the main opponent
of the biologicist and psychologist conception of crime. According to him,
the criminal type is just a professional type. The recognition granted to him
in the nascent field of criminology is symbolically represented by his appoint-
ment as honorary president during a congress in Brussels in 1892.4
From 1890 onwards, Tarde resolutely turned towards his sociological
concerns—although without forgetting criminology. Proof of this is that,
in that very same year, he published simultaneously La Philosophie Pénale
and Les Lois de L’imitation, which quickly succeeded both in France and
abroad, making the magistrate of Sarlat an intellectual celebrity. Les Lois de
L’imitation was quickly translated into English, Russian, German and Spanish
and was the object of several celebratory reviews. Delighted with this, Tarde
reports in his diary: “Brunetière has admiration for me (he told me) that my
Lois de L’imitation are among the 10 works of this century”.5 This book is
the first of the three large volumes where he elaborates the basis of his general
sociology. In it, Tarde sets out the essential aspects of his sociological syntax
regarding imitation and invention. Moreover, he establishes the logical and
extra-logical causes of imitative propagation of any invention. The second
116 Appendix
Tarde in Paris
In 1893, Tarde was invited to write a report on the organisation of criminal
statistics in France. On 26 January 1894, he was promoted to the Ministry of
Justice in Paris: “Antonin Dubost, the Minister of Justice at that time, with-
out knowing him, called me and spontaneously offered me the appointment
of head of the department of judicial statistics in his ministry. I accepted, and
I did well” (Tarde, 1904: 333). At the same time, his career as a magistrate
was crowned with the title of Knight of the Legion of Honor, awarded on 14
July 1895 by the Government and the Ministry of Justice for his twenty-six
years of service in the judiciary and public administration. Likewise, Tarde
received the distinctions of Commander of the Order of Vladimir of Russia
and of the Order of Venezuela.
Tarde’s essential task at the Ministry was to summarise the judicial events
that took place in France after 1891. The functions and area of study of his
department of judicial statistics were essentially linked to mercurials, general
accounts of the administration of criminal, civil and commercial justice, the
collection of judicial statistics published abroad and certificates of judicial
Appendix 117
that the external character of the social fact did not apply equally to all indi-
viduals. He also contested its external character and insisted that social phe-
nomena are transmitted from individual to individual—something that had
already been admitted by Durkheim himself, although asserting a “theory
of emanation”. In Tarde’s view, social phenomena are immanent to the indi-
viduals associated and are not more exterior to them than “the wave to the
water drops that compose it”. Finally, he emphasises that the Durkheimnian
definition of social fact is limited because it only considers hierarchical or
unequal relations, ignoring peer-to-peer relationships. For Tarde, Durkheim
is a prisoner of Medieval realism and supports all this reasoning in the false
belief that the whole is greater than the sum of its parts. We already know
that Tarde contested this assumption because he starts from a different one:
the element is always more complex than the ensemble it composes. We also
know that he does not deny the existence of a “social reality”—as it is con-
firmed in an article in 1901—but this is made of inter-psychic states and only
exists in the individuals it communicates. Therefore, in the heat of the contro-
versy, he affirms that “separated from the individual, the social is nothing”.
In his review of Durkheim’s Rules of Sociological Method, Tarde (1895a)
attacks his opponent’s positions fiercely, and perhaps inappropriately. He
mainly concentrates on the thesis regarding crime, normality and social
health developed by his adversary in this cardinal work. For Tarde, Durkheim
considered that the increase in crime rates in that time was normal and also
useful because it prevented the social morality from punishing insignificant
acts. Moreover, he attributed to Durkheim the idea that crime and genius
were two aspects of the very same mental status and the pre-disposition to be
interested only in low and violent crimes. Durkheim (1895a) denied almost
all of these assertions in an article titled “Crime and social health”. However,
he reaffirmed his postulates on crime as a normal social phenomenon for
finding it linked to social life’s fundamental conditions.
The most serious and systematic critiques that Durkheim makes to his
opponent are found in The Suicide (1897). In that book, there is an entire
chapter devoted to discarding the imitative phenomenon as the explanatory
cause or factor of suicide—and of any other social phenomenon. In fact,
the book is an attempt to demolish the individualist explanation of social
actions, of which Tarde would be an exponent. As we already know, when
this book was written, Tarde was the director of the Department of Statistics,
in charge of, among other things, compiling the annual figures of suicides in
France. There, Durkheim got the data he needed for his research with Tarde’s
endorsement and courtesy. At that time, the conflict had not yet escalated
to its critical point. Once the book was published, Durkheim sent a copy
to Tarde, who later communicated to him his intention to refute it. The last
milestone of this controversy took place in an on-site encounter between
both thinkers in the École de Hautes Études Sociales in 1903. As far as we
Appendix 119
[h]e was competing with a fearsome adversary, Bergson, and this competi-
tion discouraged him a little. I was one of those who encouraged him to
persevere. I do not ignore, I said, the merits of your opponent and I hope
that we can have him one day at the Collège. But Bergson already belongs
to the world of teaching, he is a teacher at the École Normale, he can
exert on young minds the action of his science and his talent. You, you are
confined to your office; you must go out: we must give you the public that
you lack. Persevere.
(Léger, 1910: 57)
From then on, extricated from his duties in the statistics office of the
Ministry of Justice, Gabriel Tarde devoted himself to the application of his
120 Appendix
At the end of his life Gabriel Tarde was at the peak of his career. Suffer-
ing from ophthalmologic and health problems, he died on 13 May 1904, at
the age of 61, in his apartment from Bourdonnais Avenue in Paris. His last
writings on “Inter-psychology” systematised his sociology and were devoted
also to the “abnormalities of inter-mental action” and “infantile inter-
psychology”. Tarde left a diverse body of work that manifests the richness
and independence of his intellectual path. In Bergson’s words:
of communication that conveyed his writings, mapping how his ideas dis-
seminated forming a public. We should also have to describe the ways in
which his concepts were adapted and modified, the mutations that occurred
in each of these lines of diffusion. Here, we will only be able to sketch how
some of these lines unfolded in North America.
The philosopher William James, one of the fathers of American pragma-
tism, coined the term “stream of consciousness” and described consciousness
as “an uninterrupted flow”. He once wrote that, in his Principles of Psychol-
ogy (1890), he saw things á la Tarde. However, the convergence between
both thinkers is much wider, above all, because for both of them nature is
“redundant and overabundant”—as Bergson (1955: 240) would say refer-
ring to the former. James and Tarde, as well as Bergson, were
Delving into Park’s ideas, we find that his theoretical developments are
Tardean in their most important traits. This is visible since Park’s doctoral
thesis elaborated during his stay in Germany at the beginning of the 20th
century, titled Masse und Publikum—a title that is a clear allusion to Tarde’s
essay of “The Public and the Crowd”. Park based his interactionist sociol-
ogy on Tarde’s theory of imitation, understanding sociability as a process
that mainly consists in organising attention and arguing that the individual
constitutes a state of the social process.11 Park’s perspective was further
elaborated and refined by Herbert Blumer, founder of the symbolic interac-
tionism movement. In the second part of his book Principles of Sociology,
Blumer distinguishes four types of crowds: the casual, the conventionalised,
the acting and the expressive one. However, Tarde is not cited here, although
there are striking similarities to his descriptions of collective behaviours.
Blumer’s followers, including Turner and Killian, as well as Kurt Lang and
Gladys Lang, all further developed (perhaps without realising it) Tarde’s
approach to the crowd. They were in fact interested in the emergence of
new patterns of interaction, and extended the arguments on the crowd to
phenomena such as social movements and public opinion (another issue
studied by Tarde).
It is worth mentioning other two branches of Tarde’s influence in North
America. As the early (re)introduction to Tarde written by Clark (1969:67)
states, the models of cultural diffusion formulated by North American anthro-
pologists were clearly indebted to Tarde’s sociological framework. Specially
Franz Boas (1897) would have borrowed from it to study, for example,
the patterns of growth of secret societies on the coast of British Columbia.
More recently, Watson (2017) stated that through the mediation of Boas and
the early Boasians, Tarde’s concepts of invention, imitation and opposition
became “ubiquitous structuring precepts for US anthropology”. As Watson
pointed out, the reception of these concepts did not happen in a cultural void
and they were even mixed with Durkheimnian’s categories—in what seems
to constitute a beautiful confirmation of Tarde’s thesis on the propagation of
ideas and their “graft” in diverse cultural milieus. The result of this compo-
sition is also properly Tardean, at least as Watson (2017: 137) describes it:
The influence of Tarde was also important in the studies about “diffusion
of innovations” as well as about public opinion and social and political com-
munication developed in the United States since the 1940s. As Katz (2006)
points out, this is visible in classical studies such as The People’s Choice
(Lazarsfeld et al., 1944), Voting: A Study of Opinion Formation in a Presi-
dential Campaign (Berelson et al., 1954) and Personal Influence (Katz and
Lazarsfeld, 1955). The Tardean idea, according to which, even in the era
of mass communication, personal influence and conversation are crucial for
the successful diffusion of anything, is present in all these cases. Since then,
research on diffusion has emerged independently in the field of rural, edu-
cational and industrial sociology, as well as in market studies. The books
from Rogers (1962) and Rogers and Shoemaker (1971) pick up and concep-
tually and methodologically synthesise many of these investigations from a
Tardean-inspired point of view. Both books are perhaps the most cited works
in all the diffusion literature (Kinnunen, 1996).
Back to France
This brief cartographic exercise drives us to the studies on opinion and the
measurement of “social mood” which appeared in France after the post-
war period, imported from the United States. This line of work was strongly
tied to the influence of Tarde’s paradigm, even when its representatives
half admitted it. Jean Stoetzel (1943), the founder of opinion research in
France, acknowledged Tarde as a pioneer in the study of group psychology,
but did not include him among the initiators of opinion theories. He was
also excluded from the list of founders of social psychology. Once again,
the recognition of Tarde’s contributions was usually relegated or forgotten
in France.
However, his thinking was also continued by authors who were in turn
very influential. As we have seen, Bergson is among the most important ones.
He paid homage to Tarde publicly several times and he included many Tar-
dean ideas in his work. Jean Millet summarises in this way:
Tarde was the first in his time, it seems, to raise the problem of the rela-
tionship between the Static and the Mobile, and to opt resolutely for the
priority of the Mobile . . . Secondly, Tarde was also one of the first to put
publicly back on the agenda the problem of the epistemological meaning
of the Infinitesimal Calculus. . . . Another point of convergence: Tarde for-
mulated a theory of creative Evolution that clearly announces that of Berg-
son. It invokes a élan vital, and at the same time, it accredits the idea of an
Evolution that would be in itself creative. Tarde’s influence on Bergson is
even more remarkable in the field of moral and religious questions. Tarde
provides Bergson with an exemplary causality analysis . . . which Bergson
126 Appendix
will use in The Two Sources (of morality and religion). In Tarde, Heroes
and Geniuses do not impose their will, they preach by example; however,
it will be exactly the same for the Heroes and the Mystics, in Bergson.12
(Milet, 1970: 387)
[H]is long-forgotten work has assumed new relevance with the influence
of American sociology, in particular microsociology. It had been quashed
by Durkheim and his school. . . Durkheim’s preferred objects of study
were the great collective representations, which are generally binary, reso-
nant, and overcoded. Tarde countered that collective representations pre-
suppose exactly what needs explaining, namely, “the similarity of millions
of people”. That is why Tarde was interested instead in the world of detail,
or of the infinitesimal: the little imitations, oppositions, and inventions
constituting an entire realm of subrepresentative matter.
(Deleuze and Guattari, 1980: 218/219)
vigorously maintained that the social was not a special domain of reality
but a principle of connections; that there was no reason to separate “the
social” from other associations like biological organisms or even atoms;
that no break with philosophy, and especially metaphysics, was necessary
in order to become a social science; that sociology was in effect a kind of
inter-psychology; that the study of innovation, and especially science and
technology, was the growth area of social theory; and that economics had
to be remade from top to bottom instead of being used as a vague meta-
phor to describe the calculation of interests. Above all, he considered the
social as a circulating fluid that should be followed by new methods and
not a specific type of organism.
Notes
1 Tarde also is the author of “Les géants chauves” (1892), a fictional story that
portrays a society where the head of each newborn is placed in a mould for study,
play and recreation.
Appendix 129
2 In 1902 and 1903, Tarde (2002) taught a course on Cournot at the Collège de
France and he wrote several articles, such as “La philosophie sociale de Cournot”
(1903); “La notion d´hasard chez Cournot” (1904) and “L’Accident et le Ration-
nel en Histoire d’après Cournot” (1905).
3 See Park’s seminal thesis (1904 [1972]). Also see Santana-Acuña (2015: 212)
according to whom the “Tardean neo-monadology seems closer to Smith’s under-
standing of the social as the result of beings-in-association”.
4 For a historical approach to Tarde’s criminal sociology, see Renneville (2018). See
as well Pinatel (1956: 436), for whom “Tarde has been a criminologist above all”.
5 Carnet 19, 1er. Avril 18 94. Fonds Gabriel Tarde.
6 On the Tarde-Durkheim controversy, see Lukes (1985), Borlandi (1994), Vargas
et al. (2008), Viana Vargas (2000), Candea (2010) and Nocera (2011). To deepen
on the specific debate on the criminal question, see Pinatel (1956) and Tonkonoff
(2014).
7 See Park (1972), Stoetzel (1943), Reynié (1989), Katz (1992, 2006), Katz et al.
(2014), Sampson (2012).
8 Latour and Lépinay (2009) made an introduction of this work, and Lazzarato
(2002) used it to develop his analyses on contemporary capitalism. On the coinci-
dences between Tarde’s and Schumpeter’s economic views, see Taymans (1950).
9 See Van Ginneken (1992).
10 Edwin Sutherland’s influential criminology (1937, 1939) is also widely indebted
to the Tardean mimetic sociology. Sutherland, who was elected president of
the American Sociological Society in 1939, elaborated a “theory of differential
association” to explain crime as a social phenomenon. He postulates that crime is
a social practice transmitted through the learning of specific skills and guidelines,
and argues that the criminal is an ordinary individual, socialised normally in a
milieu opposed to the larger society.
11 This is at least Isaac Joseph’s (2001) hypothesis. On the reception of Tarde in
Park’s sociology, see also Nocera (2008).
12 To the aforementioned, Milet (1970: 388) adds one last point, which he considers
the most important philosophically: “Tarde gave Bergson a very elaborate doc-
trine on the metaphysical and theological meaning of the experience of the mys-
tics. The mystics are not sick, they are truthful witnesses. They must be considered
as messengers of the higher Realities. Tarde is led, from there, to the hypothesis
of higher realities. Bergson even recognizes a personal God. The conclusions are
different, but the starting points were the same”.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
adaptation 63, 64, 65, 68, 71, 72, 73, Boudon, Raymond 4, 90
84, 86, 91, 116, 126; see also Bouglé, Celestin 4, 53
invention Boyer, Carl 30n1
Alliez, Eric 30n4, 70n1, 128 Brighenti, Andrea M. 112n5
Ampère, André 67 Bruno, Giordano 23
archaeology 82 – 83 Brunschvicg, León 46
Aristotle 64, 68, 76, 90 Burgess, Ernest 123
atomism 6, 15, 18, 26, 31, 42
Caesar 37
Baldwin, James M. 122 Calculus 4, 16, 19, 23, 31, 38, 67,
Baroque 3, 4, 7, 8, 15, 25, 26, 27, 32, 39 69, 125
Barry, A. And Thrift, N. 121 Candea, Matei 12n1, 129n6
Beliefs And Desires 4, 10, 25, 26, 28, Canetti, Elias 112n5
29, 30, 32, 33, 42 – 46, 49, Cantor, Georg 16
52 – 54, 58 – 60, 71 – 75, 77, 79, cartography 82, 83, 94
86, 88, 89, 91, 94, 97, 99, 100, Cassirer, Ernst 46n1
102, 104 – 110, 120, 126 Castoriadis, Cornelius 47n9
Bell, John 30n1 change 10, 17, 19, 20, 21, 31, 42,
Bentham, Jeremy 35 47n6, 62, 75, 86, 87, 91, 93, 96,
Bergson, Henri 16, 27, 53, 54, 114, 119, 111n1, 115, 127
121, 122, 125, 126 Clark, Terry 124
Berkerly, George 16 clinamen 104
Bernheim, Hippolyte 53 Cohen, Hermann 46n1
bifurcation 11 collective willingness 72
Blackmore, Susan 70n2 Comte, Auguste 34, 37, 38, 123
Blumer, Herbert 124 contagion 1, 29, 32, 44, 46n2, 48, 49,
Boas, Franz 1, 124 50, 51, 52, 53 – 70, 72 – 76, 97,
Bonald, Louis 37 101 – 102, 105 – 108
Bondel, Charles 123 contingency 3, 6, 28, 36, 62, 64, 65, 67,
Borch, Christian 12n1, 111n3 68, 71, 76; accident, 11, 33, 36,
Borges, Jorge L. 30n2 67, 68, 70n6, 99, 114, 129n2;
Borlandi, Maximo 129n6 randomness 65, 66
Index 139
Cooley, Charles 123 event 8, 37, 63, 65, 66, 70n6, 106, 116,
Copernicus 6 120; eventmental 9, 62
corporations 45, 70, 93, 95, 102, 103, exemplar causality 54, 81, 87, 100, 125
104, 105
Cournot, Antoine A. 16, 43, 46n1, Féré, Charles 123
70n6, 70n7, 114, 129n2 Ferri, Enrico 98
Couturat, Louis 22, 46n1 Foucault, Michel 1, 30n4, 47n4,
crime 5, 11, 56, 57, 58, 87, 101, 115, 111n3, 127
118, 129n10 Freud, Sigmund 50, 53, 79, 89, 90,
crowd 30, 61, 95 – 100, 103 – 105, 92n2, 92n3, 95, 96, 98, 102
111n3, 111n4, 111n5,
112n5, 123, 124; see also Galileo Galilei 6, 67, 69
multitude Garofalo, Raffaele 98
Cuvillier, Armand 111n1 Giddings, Franklin 123
integration 3, 19, 24, 29, 40, 42, 45, 63, micro-macro distinction 6, 128
64, 66, 72, 85, 91, 95, 112n5 micro-mega 28, 82, 83
intermental 45, 119 Millet, Jean 4, 5, 125
invention 1, 3, 5, 11, 32, 33, 35, 36, 39, monad 21 – 29, 30, 31, 39, 66, 114
40, 41, 44, 46, 54, 59, 61 – 70, monadology 25, 26, 30
71 – 82, 84, 85, 86, 90, 104, 105, Montebello, Pierre 30n4, 70n1, 114
106, 107, 109, 115, 116, 117, Moscovici, Serge 111n3
120, 124, 127; innovation 11, movement 8, 19, 20, 21, 32, 42, 48, 51,
35, 38, 46, 61, 66, 69, 73, 82, 58, 72, 76, 84, 88, 93, 97, 104,
90, 128 122, 124, 127
Muccielli, Laurent 12n2
James, William 1, 122 multiplicity 22, 25, 30, 31, 32, 34, 52,
71, 95, 127
kaleidoscope 27, 64 multitude 5, 6, 7, 9, 10, 11, 21, 22, 23,
Kant, Immanuel 65 24, 26, 27, 29, 30, 32, 33, 34,
Katz, Elihu 12n1, 125, 129 35, 39, 40, 44, 50, 56, 66, 94,
Kepler,Johannes 6, 67 95 – 111, 112, 116, 120
King, Anthony 12n1
Kinnunen, Jussi 125 necessity 33, 54, 65, 67, 80, 87, 104
network 1, 23, 26, 37, 45, 54, 70, 87
Lacan, Jacques 76, 92n1 88, 90, 120, 128
Laclau, Ernesto 92n1 Newton, Isaac 6, 8, 15, 16, 19, 20, 22,
Lang, Kurt And Lang, Gladys 124 35, 63, 67, 86
Latour, Bruno 1, 124, 128 Nietzsche, Friedrich 50, 79, 80, 114, 127
Lazarsfeld, Paul 125 Nocera, Pablo 129n6, 129n11
Lazzarato, Maurizio 128, 46n2
leaders 100 – 104, 106, 107, 109; opposition 2, 3, 11, 32, 44, 55, 56, 57,
meneurs 101, 102, 107 58, 59, 60, 71, 73, 74, 75, 76,
Le Bon, Gustave, 96, 98, 99, 103, 107, 91, 94, 109, 115, 116, 117, 124,
111n4, 120 126, 127
Leibniz, Gottfried W. 7, 15, 16, 19,
20 – 26, 28, 29, 36, 38, 43, 43, Parikka, Jussi 46n2
50, 68, 75, 76, 90, 114, 126 Park, Robert 1, 97, 123, 124, 129
Leroux, Robert 12n1, 70n7 Pascal, Blas 23, 26
Locke, John 47 Pasteur, Louis 53
Lombroso, Cesare 98, 102, 115 picturesque 9, 11, 31, 33, 51
Lukes, Steven 33, 37, 129n6 Pierce, Charles S. 16, 18, 46n1
Luther, Martin 36, 82 Pinatel, Jean 129n4, 129n6
Poincaré, Henri 8
Maimon, Salomon 16 possibles 2, 29, 65, 66, 114; see also
Marsden, Paul 70n2 virtual
Martin, Jean C. 125 propagation 101
Marx, Karl 1, 9, 34, 35, 37, 56, 59, 79, public 10, 21, 29, 32, 36, 44, 45, 54,
80, 88, 92n2, 94, 128 56, 59, 61, 67, 71 – 75, 78 – 82,
Matagrin, Amadee 121 84, 90, 101, 106, 115, 121,
Mauss, Marcel 94 124, 127
Mcdougall, William 96, 122 pythagoras 82
Mead, George H. 123
memetics 54, 70n2 rational 2, 4, 17, 44, 49, 50, 69, 75, 90,
methodological individualism 4, 9, 34, 97, 98, 104
37, 47n5, 125, 127 Ravaisson, Felix 114
micro-linear 25, 27; micro-analytic 25, relational 10, 15, 16, 23, 33, 39, 48, 52,
42; micro-genetic 16 53, 79, 89, 96, 99, 100, 110
Index 141