The Guilt of Reification Adorno s Critiq (1)
The Guilt of Reification Adorno s Critiq (1)
The Guilt of Reification Adorno s Critiq (1)
10. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Introduction’, in The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology, pp.
1–67, here p. 63.
198 futurethoughts
16. Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume I, trans. Ben Fowkes,
Penguin, London, 1976, translation amended. For a brief commentary on Fowkes’s
translation of phantasmagorische Form as ‘fantastic form’ rather than ‘phantasmagoric
form’, the latter of which I have opted for here, see Rose, The Melancholy Science, pp.
40ff.
17. Karl Marx, Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy (Raw Draft),
trans. Martin Nicolaus, Penguin, London, 1993, p. 156.
200 futurethoughts
misattribution has contributed to the debasement of the term.’ Rose, The Melancholy
Science, p. 38. In his defence, Marcuse makes no claims that the term Verdinglichung
appears or originates in Hegel, instead consistently underscoring that he is interpreting
the notion from a Marxian standpoint.
31. Adorno, ‘The Experiential Content of Hegel’s Philosophy’, p. 73.
32. Ibid., pp. 73–4.
33. This oft-quoted remark appears in a set of notes taken by Adorno from a
conversation about Sohn-Rethel’s ‘Historical Materialist Theory of Knowledge’ (1965),
stressing the conservative dimension of the philosophical practice of generating
concepts and categories: ‘The confrontation of the categories with one another does
not, however, take place in their purity, but with the object [am Objekt]. The constitution
of the categories, the reflection of the exchange abstraction as philosophy, demands the
abandonment (the forgetting) of their social genesis, or of genesis altogether. Historical
materialism is [the] anamnesis of the genesis.’ Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Notizen von einem
Gespräch zwischen Th. W. Adorno und Alfred Sohn-Rethel’, in Alfred Sohn-Rethel,
Schriften IV. Geistige und körperliche Arbeit. Theoretische Schriften 1947–1990. Teilband 1, ed
Carl Freytag, Oliver Schlaudt and Françoise Willmann), ça ira Verlag, Freiburg, 2018, pp.
129–33, here p. 131.
out takes 205
34. Émile Durkheim, The Rules of Sociological Method and Selected Texts on Sociology
and Its Methodology, 2nd edn, trans. W.D. Halls, ed. Steven Lukes, Palgrave Macmillan,
Basingstoke, 2013, p. 20.
35. Ibid., p. 21.
206 futurethoughts
36. Ibid.
37. A similar claim had already been advanced in Émile Durkheim, The Division of
Labour in Society, 2nd edn, trans. W.D. Halls, ed. Steven Lukes, Palgrave Macmillan,
Basingstoke, 2013, pp. 273–4.
38. Durkheim, The Rules of Sociological Method, pp. 23–4.
39. Ibid., p. 25.
40. On more than one occasion Adorno links Durkheim’s concept of social constraint
to that aspect of ‘logical compulsion’ required by Hegel’s philosophy of objective spirit,
to those ‘positive realities … defended in the Philosophy of Right … the realities that today
we would term coercive situations’. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Aspects of Hegel’s Philosophy’,
Hegel: Three Studies, pp. 1–51, here p. 20; Adorno, Lectures on Negative Dialectics:
Fragments of a Lecture Course 1965/1966, trans. Rodney Livingstone, ed. Rolf Tiedemann,
Polity Press, Cambridge, 2008, p. 16. Cf. Axel Honneth, ‘Hegel and Durkheim: Contours
of an Elective Affinity’, in Nicola Marcucci, ed., Durkheim and Critique, pp. 19–41, Palgrave
Macmillan, Cham, 2021. This work is part of Honneth’s broader project of reviving a
non-Marxist theory of the division of labour for the theory of modern democracy. In this
regard, see Axel Honneth, Die arbeitende Souveräne. Eine normative Theorie der Arbeit,
Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 2023.
out takes 207
first edition of The Rules; and then in the 1920s, with the publication of his Le socialisme.
For the most part, these minor writings have less to do with Marx himself than with
Marxists or readers of Marx (Antonio Labriola and Gaston Richard), the notion of
socialism (principally in Saint-Simon) and socialists (Saverio Merlino). For these writings,
see Émile Durkheim, Durkheim on Politics and the State, trans. W.D. Halls, ed. Anthony
Giddens, Stanford University Press, Stanford CA, 1986, pp. 97–153; and Émile Durkheim,
Socialism and Saint-Simon, trans. Charlotte Sattler, ed. Alvin W. Gouldner, Routledge,
Abingdon, 2010. Though there is a case to be made for the overlap between Hegel and
Durkheim, there are no significant commentaries on Hegel in Durkheim’s oeuvre.
58. For an account of Adorno’s criticisms of Lukács, see Timothy Hall, ‘Reification,
Materialism, and Praxis: Adorno’s Critique of Lukács’, Telos 155, Summer 2011, pp. 61–82,
and Konstantinos Kavoulakos, ‘Lukács’ Theory of Reification and the Tradition of Critical
Theory’, in Michael J. Thompson, ed., The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory, Palgrave
Macmillan, New York, 2017, pp. 67–85.
59. Cf. Simon Jarvis, Adorno: A Critical Introduction, Polity Press, Cambridge, 1998, pp.
45ff.
out takes 211
and forgoes that such structure provides the ‘condition and the
content of the social facts’ it examines. By treating empirical
material as the factual and limiting its investigation accordingly,
such sociology thereby indexes as true a partial perspective of
social reality and pre-emptively abandons ‘the emphatic idea of
objectivity’ that critical theory holds as essential.68 In place of this
idea, it codifies as objective processes associated with ‘the regu-
larity of repeated occurrences’,69 the statistically average, and the
‘law of large numbers’,70 or testable and demonstrable hypotheses
that subsequently allow for prediction and prognosis.71 Such an
account both dismisses and approximates a notion of social law,
of the lawlike structure of society.
The resemblance of Adorno’s critique here to his reading of
Durkheim is neither formal nor coincidental. Instead, it dem-
onstrates how he subtly figures the historical advancement and
prevalence of post-war sociological positivism as both a definite
continuity and a discontinuity with its precursors – or, seen in
reverse, how Durkheim deviates from the positivist tradition
that follows in his wake.72 Indeed, the contrast between the two
bodies of work and their critique is instructive for clarifying how
post-war sociology broadly represents something of a qualitative
regression internally to positivism. This is how we are to make
sense of the observation that, although Adorno inveighs against
sociological positivism for abandoning the emphatic notion
of objectivity in the assumption that the regular is the lawful,