Ronald Dworkin
Ronald Dworkin
Ronald Dworkin set out a third theory in Jurisprudence, separate from naturalism and positivism.
In Law's Empire, Dworkin has distinguished three legal conceptions: conventionalism, pragmatism
and "law as integrity”. By criticizing conventionalism and pragmatism, Dworkin concludes that "law
as integrity" is the most plausible and defensible.
Dworkin provides a third theory of law, which he believes not only better represents what actually
happens when judges decide cases but is also a morally better theory of law. Integrity is Dworkin's
version of legal theory.
Principles are, however, distinguished from 'Policies': policies are concerned with a social goal, such
as providing subsidies for farmers affectedly floods. Policies are therefore a matter for the
legislature.
Principles and Policies are different from 'Rules’ because rule could only determine whether a
particular act is valid or not. There is nothing in between, for instance a will must be witnessed by
two witnesses and if only one has signed, then the will is invalid. A rule has, therefore, an all or
nothing character.
General distinction - Principles are propositions that describe rights; policies are propositions that
describe goals.
Distinction between a principle-based and a policy-based approach to justice: Arguments of policy
justifying a political decision by showing that the decision advances or protects some collective goal
of the community as a whole. The argument in favour of a subsidy for aircraft manufacturers, that
the subsidy will protect national defence, is an argument of policy. Arguments of principle justify a
political decision by showing that the decision respects or secures some individual or group right.
The argument in favour of anti–discrimination statutes, that a minority has a right to equal respect
and concern, is an argument of principle.
Rights as “trumps”
For Dworkin, rights, as described by principles, are ‘trumps’ which serve to protect the individual
against the encroachment of measures which seek to advance collective goals.
To this extent, a right is a claim which an individual person can make that their interests be not
sacrificed for the sake of the advancement of some social goal. The requirements of pragmatism
and utilitarianism may sometimes mean that legislators will make decisions based on policies
which are intended to secure some benefit, substantial or otherwise, for society generally. Such
policies may require the sacrifice or at least a limitation of certain individual rights, including the
general right to equal concern and respect. Justice requires that the courts should protect these
rights and so principles must become the basis for judicial decisions in relevant situations.
For Dworkin, once a right has come into existence as a genuine right, then it can never be
extinguished. In every case where there is a conflict between rights and social goals, the rights of
individuals must take precedence. In this regard, Dworkin makes a distinction between ‘strong
rights’, which cannot ever be extinguished or restricted, and “other, weaker rights”, whose
operation may in exceptional circumstances be restricted for the sake of some overwhelming
beneficial goal which is in the general interest.
The Role of Judicial Decision Making in Dworkin’s Theory
Dworkin points out that judges are required to construct a theory of law which can fit past legal
decisions and makes the law as good as possible. In doing this, the judges are required to search out
legal principles which have been previously mentioned in the historical and social characteristics
of the legal system and then improve the law for the future by "making it more coherent”. Hence,
we can say that according to Dwokin's theory, in dealing with a certain case, the judge should try to
interpret the law in a way which promotes the coherence of the legal system as well as possible.
For Dworkin the judges’ discretion is weak because they are constrained, and he believes that
judges only ‘find law’ and not ‘make law’. So, he opposes judicial discretion as,
(2) Judge made law is retroactive and creates new duty after the event.
Law as integrity requires judges to treat the techniques that they use in interpreting statutes and
measuring precedents not simply as tools handed down by the legal system, but as principles they
assume can be justified in political theory, and when that is in doubt, they construct a theory of the
system to better them.
To Dworkin, a judge must treat any general principles or rules as thumb he has followed in the past
as provisional and stand ready to abandon these in favour of more sophisticated and searching
analysis when the occasion demands.
As a consequence of this conception of law, judges and lawyers are invited to search for an answer
in legal materials using reasons and imagination to determine the best way to interpret legal data. It
is therefore possible for them to confront fresh and challenging issues as a matter of principle, and
this is what law as integrity demands of him.
Constructive Interpretation
In the Pre-interpretive stage, a participant identifies the rules and standards that constitute the
practice. Then, in the interpretive stage, the interpreter settles on some general justification for
those elements identified at the pre-interpretive stage. At the post-interpretive stage, the
participant adjusts his sense of what the practice really requires so as to better serve the justification
he accepts at the interpretive stage.
The Role of Principles in Legal Arguments
In order to demonstrate the role of principles in legal arguments, he cites the cases of Riggs V Palmer
and Henningsen V Bloomfield Motors.
Riggs V Palmer
The beneficiary under a will had murdered the testator, who was his grandfather, to claim the
inheritance. The law at the time in the US had no provision to exclude such claims by wrongdoers.
The court, however, considered whether it was just and fair to grant the inheritance to the murderer
of the testator. They reasoned out that all contracts are regulated by the fundamental principle of
common law that no one shall be permitted to profit by his own fraud or to take advantage of his
own wrong. They refused to give the murderer the inheritance.
Henningsen had bought a car and signed a contract which said that the manufacturer's liability for
defects was limited to making good the defective parts. After buying the car, the car crashed injuring
its passengers. Henningsen argued that the manufacturer should not be permitted to rely on the
contractual limitation and ought to be made liable for medical and other expenses of the injured. He
was not, however, able to cite any statute or legal rule in support of his argument. Yet, the court
considered a number of competing principles such as (i) freedom of contract (ii) the freedom of
contract is not so sacred as not to admit of any qualification (ii) the manufactures' obligation to
consider the safety factor in the manufacture of passenger vehicles and (iv) courts should not permit
themselves to be used as instruments of inequity and injustice. A number of such principles arose,
for and against each party to the action. The court had to assess the strength of each principle
against the competing principles, and at the end, the court granted relief to the claimant.
If, in such an instance, two competing legal rules came to the forefront, one rule would cancel out
the other. In the case of principles, the principles that were not considered in arriving at the
decision would remain valid to be applied in another case.
Criticism
As this method is so complex, no judge could attempt to practice this method without it
affecting his ordinary functions.
The judge may intentionally or unintentionally express his subjective and/or political bias in
the guise of him applying principles.
Does not facilitate judicial discretion.