Beyond Mutual Constitution: The Properties Framework For Intersectionality Studies
Beyond Mutual Constitution: The Properties Framework For Intersectionality Studies
Maria Rodó-Zárate
Versions of this essay were presented at the Gender, Race, and Sexuality Conference in Bar-
celona: Issues in Metaphysics (Barcelona, 2014), the Feminist Philosophy Workshop (Hamburg,
2015), the Seminario Geografia e Gênero (Ponta Grossa, 2015), the III Jornades de Recerca
Institut Interuniversitari de Dones i Gènere (Barcelona, 2015), the International Conference on
Feminist Geographies and Intersectionality: Places, Identities, Knowledges (Barcelona, 2016),
the LOGOS Research group Seminar (Barcelona, 2017), the Metaphysics Seminar (Barcelona,
2018), and the Seminario abierto de filosofía (Donosti, 2018). We are grateful to the audiences
at these meetings. Many thanks are also due to the three anonymous referees of Signs, as well
as to Suzanna Danuta Walters for her insightful indications and Miranda Outman for her excel-
lent editing work. We also want to thank previous referees of others journals where previous
versions of this article were submitted. Financial support for this work was provided by MINECO,
Spanish Government, research projects FFI2013-47948-P, FFI2014-52196-P and FFI2016-
80588-R (M. J.) and postdoctoral fellowships FJCI-2015-23620, IJCI-2017-34112 (M. J.) and
FJCI-2014-19743, IJCI-2016-27422 (M. R. Z).
[Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 2019, vol. 45, no. 1]
© 2019 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0097-9740/2019/4501-0008$10.00
1
Numerous works (see Alexander-Floyd 2012; Carastathis 2016; Hancock 2016) have
identified a movement attempting to marginalize race-related discrimination and to silence
Black women’s voices in works dealing with intersectionality. Hancock (2016, 18) engages
with the debate on “whether intersectionality is an intellectual property in need of conservation
Situating the debate in the United States, though, Black feminists put
forward the need to account for the experiences of Black women, given that
single accounts of gender and race were not able to accommodate them:
“The intersection of racism and sexism factors into Black women’s lives in
ways that cannot be captured wholly by looking at the race or gender di-
mensions of those experiences separately” (Crenshaw 1991, 1244). “Intersec-
tionality” was coined, then, to show how different oppressions couldn’t be
analyzed as being mutually exclusive nor as separate from each other: “[These]
problems of exclusion cannot be solved simply by including Black women
within an already established analytical structure. Because the intersectional
experience is greater than the sum of racism and sexism, any analysis that does
not take intersectionality into account cannot sufficiently address the partic-
ular manner in which Black women are subordinated” (Crenshaw 1989, 140;
emphasis added). Moreover, the idea is that sexism and racism are not prop-
erly conceptualized if one assumes their mutual exclusion. In general, then,
additive models were rejected for not being able to account for the experi-
ences of those who suffer from multiple systems of oppression. The additive
model has also been said to advocate a view that ranks difference, making some
oppressions more relevant than others, thus producing primary and second-
ary struggles. The categories “added” would tend to be viewed as a second-
ary forms of oppression compared to the main one. Moreover, this model
precludes the analysis of privilege at the same level as oppression (Choo and
Feree 2010): any model of intersectionality must be able to take into account
privilege as well as oppression, following a majority-inclusive approach (Staunæs
2003) where unmarked categories are also considered. As Patricia Hill Col-
lins argues, there are no pure victims or oppressors, but rather “each indi-
vidual derives varying amounts of penalty and privilege from the multiple sys-
tems of oppression which frame everyone’s lives” (Collins 1990, 229).
Black feminist perspectives, in their willingness to move away from the
additive model, developed several concepts to show that different systems of
oppression do not act independently of each other but are parts of a more
general system of oppression, the “matrix of domination” (Collins 1990, 21)
or the “white supremacist capitalist patriarchy” (hooks 2000, xiv). The au-
thors see different systems of oppression as “interrelated” (hooks 2000, 41),
“interlocking” (Collins 1990, 295), and “intersect[ed]” (Crenshaw 1991). The
or a meme that has gone viral,” noting that, on one side, there are authors who argue that the
roots of intersectionality must be situated in Black feminism (May 2015) and focused on the
experiences of US Black women; otherwise, it loses its analytical and rhetorical power (Jordan-
Zachery 2007). And, on the other side, authors such as Jasbir Puar (2012) suggest that women
of color who are not Black or American are “othered” when the genealogy of intersectional-
ity is only focused on US Black women.
4
The expression “mutual constitution” has been widely used in different scientific fields
to understand different social processes of discrimination and oppression. For relations between
race and law, see Harris (1993) and Gómez (2010); for the mutual constitution of identity and
difference, see Ludvig (2006), among others. Here, though, we are specifically interested in ex-
amining the uses of mutual constitution that appear in the context of the relation among social
categories within intersectionality studies.
5
Under the general concept of affecting each other, we could also place the work of Ivy
Ken (2008) and her metaphor of sugar, in which the most widely used expressions are “trans-
form each other,” “change,” “shape,” “affect,” and “intermingle.” In our interpretation, one
fundamental sense of mutual constitution would fall under the “affecting” category, which
sometimes refers to mutually shaping and at other times to changing nature, as we explain be-
low. “The ingredients affect each other,” Ken writes. “And when these ingredients come to-
gether, they transform each other. No ingredient in the resultant cookie has the same smell, the
same texture, the same look or feel as it did before it went into the bowl. This illustrates very
nicely the race-class-gender theory premise of ‘mutual constitution’” (2008, 162).
6
It should be noted that Lugones develops a much more complex view on the interaction
of social categories than the one presented here—see, for instance, her account on Yoruba so-
ciety and the new gender categories imposed by colonizers (Lugones 2010). The author also
draws on the mestiza tradition of Gloria Anzaldúa and others (see Anzaldúa 1987). Anzaldúa’s
notion of mestiza consciousness could be interpreted as an instance of the category fusion.
fect each other (Anthias 2012) without creating new categories and with-
out fusing or disappearing. Within this category, we find two subgroups: cat-
egories are shaped by and shape each other (Walby, Armstrong, and Strid
2012), and the interrelation of categories changes the nature of them (Garry
2011). In the constitution as new formation interpretation, we also find two
subgroups: when categories interrelate, new categories are formed (Black
women; Hancock 2007) or categories are fused (Lugones 2007).7
stituted by age? And is whiteness for every age constituted at the same time
by sexuality and by every other category? It is not clear how the mutual con-
stitution model can give answers to these questions.
Focusing on the affecting interpretation clarified above, could we say
that white privilege is constituted by age so that white privilege “changes
its nature because of ” or “is shaped by” age, sexuality, gender, class? And
what about race, if its nature is constituted by all other categories and in
all possible configurations? While the affecting sense has intuitive relevance
when it comes to certain categories, it doesn’t seem to be applicable to all
categories in different contexts, and it doesn’t give us more specific infor-
mation about how the affecting relation works or what exactly is shaped or
changed in the interaction.
In relation to constitution as new formation, we distinguished between
new category and fusion. The notion of a new category seems to involve a
proliferation of categories each time there is an interaction. It can be in-
tuitive when we consider gender and race and the particular case of Black
women, but consider sexuality and age: Is there a new category for old les-
bians separate from young lesbians? And are there other new categories for
every configuration with race and class? Similarly, the fusion reading im-
plies a proliferation of categories, in this case of genders, as there can be
an infinite number of interactions with other categories. Moreover, to our
mind, constitution as new formation tends to pose more questions than it
solves. As Garry (2008, 107) notes, “the individual axes must have at least
a minimal degree of stable meaning for the analysis to work. If every inter-
section produced a new gender or a new race (or both!), there would be
no way to make sense of the ways in which ethnicity affects one’s gendered
experience.” In this sense, fusion prevents us from accounting for the cases
in which women who do not share other identities may suffer similar gender-
oppressive effects in certain circumstances, and this would have politically
relevant implications. The fusion relation would be difficult to apply to all
other categories, as Lugones’s view seems to be specifically formulated for
the functioning of gender in the process of colonization. If it only applies
to this case, fusion cannot be suitable for a general account of intersection-
ality. And if it applies to all other categories, how could fusion possibly op-
erate in different directions?
In this section we have critically assessed the prospects of using the dif-
ferent senses of mutual constitution. We have first noted that “constitution”
in the general sense of “being made of ” is quite difficult to apply to many
interactions among social categories and may in fact not be what inter-
sectionality theorists are after. The affecting sense seems to find resistance
in applications to certain social categories and interactions, and it isn’t very
specific. And the new formation and fusion senses are difficult to apply gen-
erally as a kind of relation at work in the interaction between different cate-
gories; they are also problematic if we understand that keeping a distinctive
ontological character for every category is a desirable requirement (more
on this below).
In the next section we will identify a possible common problem among
the uses of mutual constitution, namely the reification of categories, and
will present the properties framework as more suitable for conceptualizing
intersectional relations.
8
Some scholars (Lugones 2007, 2010; Carastathis 2016) regard intersectionality as a cri-
tique of received categories and adopt what McCall (2005, 1773) calls the “anticategorical ap-
proach” to complexity. This perspective rejects the use of social categories on the grounds that
they originated out of relations of dominance and oppression and their use would maintain
such genealogy. Although this is a general discussion and an in-depth treatment goes beyond
the scope of this work, we acknowledge the risks in using categories. However, we think it is
important to maintain them, as they continue to affect oppressed people in their everyday ex-
istence (Ludvig 2006; Yuval-Davis 2006), and so it may be necessary to use them to detect
their functioning and their interrelations and to be able to subsequently address inequalities.
We concur with Hancock (2007, 66) when she says that “intersectionality argues for new con-
ceptualizations of categories and their role in politics, rather than seeking an abolition of cat-
egories themselves.” Our contribution is precisely to conceptualize categories in such a way
that some problems related to their use (essentialization, nonchangeability) can be avoided while
allowing us to detect them in their everyday function in oppressing (and privileging) people.
13, for a similar framing). There thus seems to be two main driving forces in
the debate on intersectional relations. The different views presented take dif-
ferent stances toward them, so we can classify the specifications of mutual
constitution according to the degree to which they can accommodate com-
plex and deep interaction as well as ontological specificity.
Additive models deny complex and deep interaction while preserving
ontological specificity, and strong senses of mutual constitution preserve com-
plex and deep interaction but can’t allow ontological specificity. Specifically,
on the one hand, mutual constitution as affecting has a different behavior
depending on the subgroup we focus on: the mutually shaping relation pre-
serves ontological specificity and dilutes deep interaction into mutual shap-
ing, thus making the requirement for complex and deep interaction difficult
to assess.9 The changing nature sense of affecting, on the other hand, ac-
commodates complex and deep interaction such that it is not entirely clear
that the need for ontological specificity is satisfied, given that the nature of
each category is changed.
With respect to the sense in which mutual constitution involves new for-
mation, its position regarding complex, deep interaction and ontological
specificity also differs. In the case of the formation of a distinct new category
(Black woman), it seems that the requirement for complex and deep inter-
action is satisfied, given that the interaction between categories produces
a new category, although what is involved in this process is not further de-
veloped. Similarly, it appears that this also accomplishes ontological specific-
ity, because at least superficially both Black and woman are present in the
new category Black woman, but it is not entirely clear whether this new cat-
egory preserves the ontological specificity of each of them or whether it is
rather a distinct construct that dilutes their previous respective specificities.
In the fusion sense, the requirement for complex and deep interaction is
satisfied at the expense of abandoning ontological specificity: the fused cat-
egories are not ontologically specific any more. In this way, we see how
these two requirements help to structure the positions in the current liter-
ature and may eventually help to situate other proposals to come.
All in all, none of the extant proposals seems to easily satisfy both re-
quirements, and thus they are presented as competing or contradictory.10
9
Mutually shaping recognizes a certain influence among categories, but the kind of rela-
tion itself is not further specified, so it is not clear what is in fact the interaction between cat-
egories that it proposes.
10
In Walby, Armstrong, and Strid’s (2012, 234) words: “Writers that appear to prioritize
the ‘mutual constitution’ approach to intersectionality nevertheless often also argue for sepa-
rate naming; which might appear somewhat inconsistent” (Crenshaw, 1991; Hancock, 2007). Of
course there is no tension between the two requirements for those who think that one of them
We argue that the reason behind this fact is that there’s an implicit con-
ceptual feature that makes these two requirements opposed to each other:
the reification of the social categories or systems; that is, considering sys-
tems and socials relations as objects that intersect. “Reification” has already
been used in the literature on intersectionality in two ways: reification as giv-
ing priority to objects or things over relations, and reification as rendering
processes invisible (see Gunnarsson 2017, 119–21). Regarding the former,
Lena Gunnarsson considers Karen Barad’s “thingification” problem, the
“turning of relations into ‘things’ ” (Barad 2003, 812), stressing the onto-
logical priority of relations over the entities they produce. With respect to
the latter, Gunnarsson claims that “intersectional theorists often take issue
with more conventional modes of discrimination analysis, which tend to reify
categories like ‘Black’ and ‘woman’ in a way that ignores how they are (co-)con-
stituted through historically formed processes of power” (2017, 122). Be-
yond intersectionality, the problem of reification can still refer to a third fact,
namely, the process of making structures made by human beings resistant to
change (Young 1994).
While acknowledging that all these senses of reification shed light on rel-
evant dynamics in intersectionality theory (and beyond), we want to high-
light another sense of reification that, in our view, is taking place around
the debates on the relation between categories. There is thus a fourth kind
of reification in the sense of being an object versus a property—the fact that
categories are thought of as (physical) objects and not as properties of ob-
jects. Objects have to be understood formally and broadly—as encompass-
ing processes, events, or relations but crucially in contrast with properties
(note that processes, events, and relations also have properties). The rele-
vant point is that the reification of categories seems to be implicitly as-
sumed when trying to relate categories as if they were things that need to
mix in complex ways. This implicit tendency can be seen when examining
the kinds of metaphors of intersectionality that have been proposed: a cross-
roads (Crenshaw 1989), gels under different lights (Haslanger 2012), a mar-
ble cake (Jordan-Zachery 2007), egg yolk and egg whites (Lugones 2007),
and a Rubik’s cube (Romero 2018), to mention a few. The proposed met-
aphors try to visualize in complex ways how the different things relate to
each other, but after all, in the visual imaginary, they remain things (see
Rodó-Zárate and Jorba 2018 for a development).11
should not be met: e.g., the deep interaction among categories in the case of additive models and
ontological specificity in the case of anticategorical approaches.
11
Moreover, intersectionality is generally visualized as different lines that intersect or fig-
ures that overlap (see Dhamoon 2011), reinforcing the reification problem. In Devon Carbado
In sum, the reification problem gives rise to the tension of either mix-
ing categories in such strong ways as to make their ontological specificity
difficult to maintain or separating them to maintain their ontological spec-
ificity on pain of not recognizing the complexity of their interaction. In what
follows, we will argue that if we get rid of reification in this sense, we find a
way to preserve the two requirements presented for a theory of intersectionality.
and Mitu Gulati’s (2013, 71) words: “The notion that two things ‘intersect’ brings readily to
mind a Venn diagram within which each thing exists both inside and outside of the intersec-
tion. . . . Although the metaphor of intersectionality conveys this idea, the fuller theory of
intersectionality, and Crenshaw’s conceptualization of this theory, rejects it. Fundamental to
Intersectionality Theory is the understanding that race and gender are interconnected, and
as a result they do not exist as disaggregated identities. In other words, there are no noninter-
secting areas in the diagram.”
12
Conceiving of categories as properties and being a woman, Black, etc., as positions
within those criteria does not imply a static conception of categories but can recognize “his-
torically formed processes of power” (Gunnarsson 2017, 122) in which a category can cease
to be relevant to take into account certain purposes and another may become salient and im-
portant. In this sense, the proposal here can encompass both a certain stability and a certain
fluidity that may allow for empirical analysis as well as for the recognition of change (Walby,
Armstrong, and Strid 2012, 228).
ism and white supremacy, capitalism, ageism, and so on, would be seen as
properties of a whole system, which can be construed as the system of power.
The shift in conceptualization proposed here presents a framework that
considers systems as “adjectives” and not as “nouns.” That is, the whole
system of power is patriarchal, capitalist, and racist—these three properties
are its features. So far the proposal resembles Collins’s and bell hooks’s con-
ceptualization of a whole system that contains the others, but we add an
important specification of how we can understand their ontological char-
acter more concretely: that is, as an object that is a whole system with its
different properties or characteristics (capitalism, heterosexism, racism, etc.).
In this sense, it would be not adequate to say that it is a system with differ-
ent subdivisions, but rather it is one system with different properties or char-
acteristics.13 Through this framework, social systems can maintain their dis-
tinctiveness (patriarchy would be a hierarchical organization based on gender
constructs and capitalism on social class)14 without denying that they are
related and that their effects constitute the whole system of power.15 Similarly
for the individual level, categories are conceived as properties of individuals,
and as such they are not separable from those individuals, even if they can
be distinguished in thought and theory and named separately. From this
perspective, the framework maintains ontological specificity, which just
involves characterizing social categories independently of each other. As
Nira Yuval-Davis (2006, 201; our emphasis) explains:
Class divisions are grounded in relation to the economic processes of
production and consumption; gender should be understood not as a
“real” social difference between men and women, but as a mode of
discourse that relates to groups of subjects whose social roles are de-
fined by their sexual/biological difference while sexuality is yet an-
other related discourse, relating to constructions of the body, sexual
pleasure and sexual intercourse. Ethnic and racial divisions relate to
discourses of collectivities constructed around exclusionary/inclusionary
boundaries . . . that can be constructed as permeable and mutable to
different extents and that divide people into “us” and “them. . . .”
“Ability” or, rather, “disability” involves . . . discourses of “normality”
13
Our proposal does not make an a priori hierarchy among systems but rather regards
them all as contributing to the whole system of power.
14
We acknowledge that our definitions are simplistic and that there are important debates
on how to conceptualize them, but this goes beyond the scope of this essay.
15
For reasons of exposition, from now on we will focus on the level of the experience/in-
dividual, although as we have seen, the proposal applies to the systemic level as well.
from which all disabled people are excluded. Age represents the dimen-
sion of time and the life cycle.16
16
We believe Yuval-Davis conceives of social divisions as a kind of criteria of social differ-
entiation without reifying them, but it is still the case that many authors who speak of mutual
constitution implicitly conceptualize these criteria as things. This fact is manifest in their strug-
gle to find complex ways and terms to express the relations among them. Once we think of
categories as properties, we see that they are already together in a certain configuration from
the start.
17
It is important to note that the specific content of those indicators is not predetermined
by the model proposed here, so the framework is compatible with various accounts of what
gender, race, etc., are.
18
The properties framework can include as many categories as needed in the analysis—
which ones will be relevant is an empirical question to be determined differently in different
research (see also Hancock 2013).
19
See Yuval-Davis (2006), Valentine (2007), Anthias (2012), and Rodó-Zárate (2014) for
the importance of context in intersectionality.
tance of context in order to identify the kind of relation, which we also see as
an empirical matter (see also Hancock 2007, 2013).
From this plural perspective we argue that there is a wide range of other
possible relations that might provide a more nuanced examination of cases.
We will provide some specific examples. One interesting relation is that of
intensity, in the sense of intensification and mitigation. In the case of in-
tensification (Verloo 2009; Khader 2013; Rodó-Zárate 2015), the idea is
that when there are (at least) two oppressive categories, one intensifies the
effects of the other. As already mentioned, we could say that being poor in-
tensifies the oppression for women in the case of the right to abortion. That
is, in countries in which abortion is illegal or restricted, women with the eco-
nomic resources to travel to another country would be better positioned than
women with fewer economic resources to undergo such a process.20
If we look in the other direction, we find a less examined kind of rela-
tion, namely, that of mitigation between two oppressive positions (Rodó-
de-Zárate 2015).21 As Joseli Maria Silva and Marcio Ornat argue in their
article on travesti prostitution networks and their transnational mobility be-
tween Brazil and Spain, “the meanings that surround Brazilian nationality/
raciality are used by travestis, who mobilize elements of Brazilianness to their
advantage in the Spanish sex market” (2015, 1082). Even if the represen-
tations of Brazilian women are loaded with elements of colonial subordina-
tion, Brazilian travesti women negotiate with their (oppressive) cultural and
racial identity in Spain to mitigate their class and sexual oppression, as they
gain erotic capital with their ethnicity, which improves their economic situ-
ation. Moreover, we regard the extreme case of mitigation as the possibil-
ity of cancellation of the oppressive effects of a category (Verloo 2009). In
fact, Mieke Verloo (2009) presents strengthening and weakening as two pos-
sible kinds of the broader notion of interference.22
20
Serene Khader (2013, 68), focusing on the particular case of the moral acceptability of
transnational commercial surrogacy, problematizes the notion of intensification because “the
intensification thesis supposes that gender oppression subjects all women to qualitatively sim-
ilar harms and that race and class oppression increase the severity of those harms.” Nancy
Ehrenreich (2004) also develops a conceptualization of intersectionality based on symbiosis,
one aspect of which is the mutually supportive character between discriminations where one
system would enforce another one. This, too, would be a case of intensification.
21
As Khader (2013, 68) writes, “the intensification thesis supposes that gender oppression
subjects all women to qualitatively similar harms and that race and class oppression increase
the severity of those harms.”
22
This concept is not restricted to these two notions. As Verloo (2009) states, interfer-
ence should be regarded as an umbrella concept between inequalities under which different
forms of relations among categories are possible. However, no further specification is provided
as to what relations fall under this umbrella concept.
Notice, too, that neither intensification nor mitigation can explain all ex-
isting interrelations among categories. Consider, for instance, the specific case
of the right to vote in the United States for African Americans and women.
Even if we acknowledge that African American women had to deal with sex-
ism, racism, and the combination of both when struggling for their right
to vote, they did not have “less” or “more” right to vote because it was de-
nied twice (intensified). As a result of the double discrimination, they just
couldn’t vote. How being a Black woman differs from being a white woman
or a Black man in the case of the materialization of the right to vote cannot
be approached here as an intensification or mitigation relation.
Actually, the additive effect could also be possible in the properties and
emergent experience frameworks. The effects of different categories may be
related in an additive way in some cases. For instance, Lisa Bowleg (2008,
313) notes that the household income of Black lesbians is relevantly lower
than that of both Black married heterosexual couples and Black male same-
sex couples.23 Actually, the author uses this example with the aim of show-
ing how social hierarchies are mutually constructed in the lives of Black les-
bians. However, as we see it, the annual median household income seems
to decrease with every oppression position added. This is not to say that
Black lesbians’ identity is additive but that the effects of their social position
in relation to a specific indicator may be the result of an additive relation.
We believe one could recognize this additive function in particular cases with-
out endorsing an additive model of intersectionality, given that in our view
there is a variety of possible kinds of relations with respect to the effects of
categories of experience. With this plural approach, the proposal is thus able
to satisfy the requirement for complex and deep interaction among catego-
ries, always understood in their relation to the whole experience.
As we have seen through the examples above, the properties framework
and the emergent experience view in intersectionality may have some rele-
vant implications for social science research. First, the properties framework
allows the consideration that all categories configure the experience but at
the same time that every category may be individuated for a specific analysis,
23
“According to the National Gay and Lesbian Task Force’s analysis of Black same-sex
household data from the 2000 US Census Bureau, Black same-sex couples reported an annual
median household income ($49,000) of $2,000 lower than that of their Black married hetero-
sexual counterparts ($51,000). Black female same-sex couples, however, reported a median in-
come of $9,000 less than Black married heterosexual couples, $7,000 less than Black male
same-sex couples, and a stunning $21,000 and $29,000 less than White female and male same
sex couples respectively, illustrating clearly how structural inequalities grounded in intersec-
tions of race, sex, and sexual orientation affect Black female same-sex couples adversely” (Bow-
leg 2008, 313).
Concluding remarks
The question of the relation among social categories lies at the heart of
intersectionality theory. The shift from additive to mutual constitutive mod-
els resulted in the adoption of the latter model without much scrutiny, lead-
ing to different conceptions and senses of mutual constitution. We have
reviewed the main uses of mutual constitution in the literature and have
classified them into two groups (see table 1)—constitution as affecting and
constitution as new formation. On the one hand, constitution as affecting
includes two subtypes: mutually shaping and changing nature. On the other
hand, constitution as new formation includes new category and fusion. Be-
sides some particular problematic aspects of these kinds of relations, we have
mainly argued that these proposals face the dilemma of not being able to
clearly and adequately accommodate two main desiderata for intersectional-
ity theory: the need to account for complex and deep ways in which social
categories interact, and the need to maintain ontological specificity. We have
argued that these proposals cannot accommodate both desiderata because
of an implicit conceptualization common to additive and mutual constitu-
tive models: the reification problem. This problem rests on the fact that au-
thors tend to implicitly conceive of categories as objects (broadly construed)
and not as properties. Once we reject reification in this sense, we can concep-
tualize categories as properties—of an individual and of a system. The prop-
erties framework paves the way for us to see the interaction among catego-
ries as producing the emergence of a new entity (the experience or system,
respectively) with a certain overall character, which cannot be predicted a
priori from the behavior of the single categories involved. Within this frame-
work, we have proposed a plural and contextual model that also follows from
the partiality critiques previously raised.
In conclusion, we argue that the properties model is more suitable for
conceptualizing intersectional relations in such a way that categories and so-
cial systems can maintain their own ontological character while allowing their
effects to be in complex relations. Shifting from conceiving categories as ob-
jects that intersect to conceiving them as properties that, arranged in a certain
configuration, produce an emergent experience (or system) may contribute
to a better understanding of intersectional relations and may provide a fruit-
ful framework for feminism and social sciences as well as for political action.
References
Alexander-Floyd, Nikol. 2012. “Disappearing Acts: Reclaiming Intersectionality in
the Social Sciences in a Post–Black Feminist Era.” Feminist Formations 24(1):1–
25.
Anthias, Floya. 2012. “Intersectional What? Social Divisions, Intersectionality, and
Levels of Analysis.” Ethnicities 13(1):3–19.
Anthias, Floya, and Nira Yuval-Davis. 1983. “Contextualizing Feminism—Gender,
Ethnic, and Class Divisions.” Feminist Review, no. 15: 62–75.
———. 1992. Racialized Boundaries: Race, Nation, Gender, Colour, and Class and
the Anti-racist Struggle. London: Routledge.
Anzaldúa, Gloria. 1987. Borderlands/La Frontera: The New Mestiza. San Francisco:
Spinsters/Aunt Lute.
Bailey, Moya. 2013. “New Terms of Resistance: A Response to Zenzele Isoke.”
Souls 15(4):341–43.
Barad, Karen. 2003. “Posthumanist Performativity: Toward an Understanding of
How Matter Comes to Matter.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society
28(3):801–31.
Bilge, Sirma. 2010. “Recent Feminist Outlooks on Intersectionality.” Diogenes
57(1):58–72.
Bowleg, Lisa. 2008. “When Black 1 Lesbian 1 Woman ≠ Black Lesbian Woman:
The Methodological Challenges of Qualitative and Quantitative Intersectionality
Research.” Sex Roles 59(5–6):312–25.
Brah, Avtar, and Ann Phoenix. 2004. “Ain’t I a Woman? Revisiting Intersectionality.”
Journal of International Women’s Studies 5(3):75–86.
Brown, Michael. 2011. “Gender and Sexuality I: Intersectional Anxieties.” Progress
in Human Geography 36(4):541–50.
Butler, Judith. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. Lon-
don: Routledge.
Carastathis, Anna. 2014. “The Concept of Intersectionality in Feminist Theory.”
Philosophy Compass 9(5):304–14.
———. 2016. Intersectionality: Origins, Contestations, Horizons. Lincoln: University
of Nebraska Press.
Carbado, Devon W., and Mitu Gulati. 2013. Acting White? Rethinking Race in
Post-racial America. New York: Oxford University Press.
Cho, Sumi, Kimberlé Williams Crenshaw, and Leslie McCall. 2013. “Toward a Field
of Intersectionality Studies: Theory, Applications, and Praxis.” Signs 38(4):785–810.
Choo, Hae Yoen, and Myra Marx Feree. 2010. “Practising Intersectionality in
Sociological Research: A Critical Analysis of Inclusions, Interactions, and Insti-
tutions in the Study of Inequalities.” Sociological Theory 28(2):129–49.
Collins, Patricia Hill. 1990. Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and
the Politics of Empowerment. Boston: Unwin Hyman.
Collins, Patricia Hill, and Sirma Bilge. 2016. Intersectionality. Cambridge: Polity.
Crenshaw, Kimberlé Williams. 1989. “Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race
and Sex: A Black Feminist Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist The-
ory, and Antiracist Politics.” University of Chicago Legal Forum 1989: 139–67.
———. 1991. “Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Vio-
lence against Women of Color.” Stanford Law Review 43(3):1241–99.
Davis, Kathy. 2008. “Intersectionality as Buzzword: A Sociology of Science Per-
spective on What Makes a Feminist Theory Successful.” Feminist Theory 9(1):67–
85.
Dhamoon, Rita Kaur. 2011. “Considerations on Mainstreaming Intersectionality.”
Political Research Quarterly 64(1):230–43.