Natural Law Ethics
Natural Law Ethics
Natural Law Ethics
THOMAS AQUINAS’
NATURAL LAW
Natural Law Ethics – The theory and tradition that
says there are universal ethical standards
discoverable through human reflection on human
natural inclinations.
What Is Natural Law and Where Does It Come
From?
There are a lot of laws in this world. There is what we
called human laws where we are more familiar with.
life,
procreation,
sociability, and
knowledge.
The first fundamental human good is our own life.
If we observe human behavior we will notice that
people have a natural inclination to preserve
themselves.
The second fundamental human good Aquinas
identifies is the human natural inclination toward
sexual reproduction. Like the first inclination to
self‐preservation, this inclination toward sexual
activity (and hence reproduction) can be thought of
as instinctual in human beings.
The third natural inclination is toward sociability. Here again we
can hear the echoes of Aristotle the notion that humans are social
animals. We have a natural inclination to sociability in that we
naturally have social relationships from the day we are born –
with our parents, our siblings, our friends, our own children, etc.
The fourth natural inclination Aquinas identifies – our natural
inclination toward knowledge – also has echoes of Aristotle. As
Aristotle said, we are rational animals. “All men by their nature,
desire to know.” Since this is a natural inclination that all human
beings have, we should think broadly about what is claimed here.
A very basic example of this natural inclination is that we are
curious creatures; we want to know things.
Natural inclination is the concept that human
nature directs human beings toward certain
fundamental goods, which human beings then
naturally value.
How should we behave toward these goods, these
fundamental values?
Confucianism (5th cent BCE): never do to others what you not like them to do
to you.
Buddhism (5th cent BCE): hurt not others whit that which pains thyself.
Jainism (5th cent BCE): in happiness and suffering, in joy and grief, we should
regard all creatures as we regard our own self
Zoroastrianism (5th cent BCE): do not do unto others all that which is not well
for oneself.
Classical paganism (Plato, 4th cent BCE): may I do to others as I would that
they should do unto me.
Hinduism (Mahabharata, 3rd cent BCE): do naught to others which if done to
thee would cause thee pain.
Natural law ethics incorporates virtue ethics.
In Aquinas’s view, our human nature was intentionally
created and designed by God, and our lives only reach
their natural end when they take us closer to God. The
virtues are the fruits of performing actions toward a goal
– our human good.
The most important difference is that Aquinas’s list, in
addition to having moral virtues, also includes
theological virtues. While moral virtues are formed
through repeated actions and habit, the theological virtues
– faith, hope, and charity – have their origin in God’s
grace.
TYPES OF VIRTUES
Ethical standards are not solely derived from one’s society. Since God has
created human beings, Aquinas believes we can discern God’s plan for us
by examining and reflecting upon the natural inclinations of human beings.
Natural law ethics therefore has a considerably developed solution to the
problem of human nature. Human beings are rational and social beings that
are naturally striving toward basic goods. Ethical standards are importantly
rooted in human nature, though human nature is not their ultimate origin,
since God is responsible for human nature being what it is.
With regard to the problem of relativism, Aquinas maintains that
the apparent relativity of ethics does not detract from the
ultimate universal features of ethics, which are grounded in the
universal features of human beings. Like the other universalists
we have looked at, Aquinas will accept the fact that there is
cultural diversity and disagreement in ethical standards, and will
advise us not to take the ethical disagreement and cultural
relativity we observe as conclusive proof that there are no
permanent and universal standards in ethics. For Aquinas, the
standards exist just as surely as God exists, and human
skepticism alone concerning these matters does not disprove
their existence.
As a solution to the problem of conduct, natural law ethics
answers questions about how to determine the right thing
to do and how one should live a life, in terms of the
natural law. An action is right when it is consistent with
the natural law. As a highly developed solution to the
problem, natural law ethics offers several ethical
principles that offer guidance in making such a
determination: the Principle of Natural Law, the Golden
Rule, the Pauline Principle, and the Principle of Double
Effect. As an ethical theory, it offers much practical
guidance.