The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
The possibility that sounds might be objects, entities, or things is an open
question. However, many theories of sound close the question down via reductive
assertions. Some argue that sounds cannot be things because things are
autonomous entities whereas sounds are relative. Others argue that sounds
cannot be things because things are durable bodies whereas sounds are temporal
phenomena. The following essay begins by reviewing and critiquing these
arguments as they appear in musicology, sound studies, and philosophy.
Arguments against sound’s autonomy are generally motivated by
anthropocentric ideologies, which by presuming humans’ ontological privilege
reduce sounds to human experiences, practices, and conditions. Meanwhile,
arguments against sound’s durability are troubled by the Sorites paradox. The
trouble with these arguments is that they dissimulate sound’s absolute otherness
and lasting impact; moreover, in the end they can neither disprove nor af�rm
sound’s object-potential. In an attempt to rehabilitate the question of sound’s
thingness, the second half of my discussion proposes an object-oriented ontology
for sound. Developed by Graham Harman, object-oriented ontology (OOO) offers
an open-ended conception of thingness as a continuous metabolism of temporal
relationality and durable autonomy. In OOO, things are paradoxical: every entity
consists of a necessary, hidden essence and contingent presence, separated by an
irreconcilable ontological rift. Consequently, things are irreducible to their
relations even as they are their relations. As things in the object-oriented sense,
sounds would retain their potent and absolute otherness while losing none of the
experiential relativity that’s crucial to aesthetic theories. Further, the withdrawn
ambiguity of entities in OOO ensures that ontology remains an open question. In
fact, the dif�culty involved in either committing or objecting to sound’s thingness
demonstrates that sound calls the ontology of objects into question. Sounds
make questions out of thingness and things.
sound object, object-oriented ontology, Graham Harman, anthropocentrism
Is a sound a thing?
To doubt the productivity of this question is only reasonable. Neither philosophy
nor empirical science can prove or disprove sound’s thing-status. One would be
2 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
justi�ed in wondering if the matter isn’t an ontological conundrum but a
semantic quibble based on the vagueness of the terms. But the meaning of the
word “thing” hinges on how real things actually are, not just on what people think
they mean when they speak about things. Words are real relationships between
humans and other beings, and these relationships have real, sometimes
dangerous effects.
It’s standard in certain practices to treat sounds as things. Electroacoustic
composers such as Chris Cutler, Curtis Roads, and Steve Takasugi use terms like
“sound object”, “sound particle”, or “sound specimen” to describe sounds,
samples, and musical phrases that function as relatively stable, self-contained
units. Sound artists explore and interrogate the tactile materiality of their
medium. Toshiya Tsunoda, for example, treats �eld recordings as found objects
that, isolated from the context in which the artist captured them, acquire a
certain autonomy.[1] In contrast, the pop-music industry sells, steals, and
squabbles over sonic units as commodities, mythologically assimilating
“intellectual property” to other forms of property like cars and houses.[2] Scholars
since Adorno have fearfully predicted the commodity form’s suppression of artists’
creativity, listeners’ individuality, and music’s communicative ability.[3]
Shrewd recognition of sound’s object-qualities – its durability, autonomy, salability,
and physicality – also underlies its evermore frequent deployment as a weapon.
American forces in the Middle East and Guantánamo regularly use loud music as
a kind of aerial bomb, siege weapon, or torture instrument, and unleash sonic
cannons upon peaceful protesters like those of the Occupy movement. Soundcannon manufacturers explicitly compare sounds to rubber bullets, suggesting
that the former may substitute for the latter in efforts to comply with
inconvenient legislation against shooting people.[4] This fungibility implies that
because sounds and bullets impact human bodies with equivalent force, sounds
and bullets are the same kind of entity: those who make and buy sound cannons
use, understand, and advertise sounds as self-contained, tangible objects durable
enough to permanently damage human �esh.
But the manufacturers seem to anticipate that the harmful aspects of their
products would not escape those (thoughtful TV viewers and liberal
Congresspersons) who take the conception of sound-as-thing to its logical
conclusion.[5] To preempt humanitarian criticism, then, the manufacturers
3 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
downplay the autonomous physicality of sound, emphasizing instead its
intangible, communicative qualities. The idea is to dissimulate the cannon’s
cruelty and allow it to masquerade as a harmless mass-communication device.
This tactic takes advantage of prevailing ideologies that tout the �eeting
intangibility and relativity of sound, and discourage or decry its thing-power: its
physical impact and otherness.
It’s all too easy to perpetuate ideologies of transience and relativity by insisting
that sounds are not objects but experiences or practices. Discourses that abjure
the thingness of sound tend to close themselves off to alternate views, foreclosing
the possibility of further questioning by reducing sound to relativistic origins that
are too subjective to contest. Temporality and relationality are integral aspects of
the being of sound, but they do not tell the whole story. Anthropocentrism
desensitizes theorists to the other aspects of sound which are irreducible to
human experiences and circumstances.
Humanistic objections to sound’s thingness generally draw upon an apparent
incompatibility between what the objectors take to be the de�ning qualities of
things and the de�ning qualities of sound: things are durable and autonomous,
sounds are transient and relative. The relativism of most sonic theories is of a
peculiarly anthropocentric kind that presumes the ontological priority of human
beings or human social structures, as if sounds could not exist without us. This
assumption is inaccurate. Discourses built upon concomitant theories therefore
cannot effectively critique acoustic weaponry, musical torture, and other forms of
sonic abuse because those practices subscribe to the same ideologies, denying
sound’s autonomous, lasting impact in the interests of humanistic dissemblance.
In §1 of my discussion, I’ll critique sound scholars’ objections to the autonomy
entailed by sonic thingness, arguing that such objections issue from
anthropocentric ideologies. As I’ll cover in §2, the apparent incompatibility
between things and sounds derives from a reductive understanding of sounds
and things in terms of durability. Given that sound’s potential object-status
cannot be disproved on the basis of sound’s transience or its relationships with
humans, I will reconsider sonic thingness as a serious possibility in §3. What are
sounds and what are things, if sounds can be things? I will propose an objectoriented ontology for sound based on Graham Harman’s pioneering work, which
reveals things to be stranger and more potent than humans want to believe. As
4 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
OOO foregrounds the hiddenness and paradoxicality of things, maintaining their
autonomy and durability without sacri�cing their relationality or temporality, this
ambiguous metaphysics demands that humans give up the mistaken
presumption that we were ever ontology’s star players, and recognize the potent
otherness of sound. OOO seems to advocate the de-anthropocentric tenets of
radical ecology: humans neither possess nor are entitled to mastery over
nonhumans; so nonhumans, including sounds, exist for themselves, not for us or
because of us. These precepts might be more desirable than anthropocentrism,
especially at this moment in our planet’s history, but decisions for or against sonic
thingness on the basis of any ideology are precisely what I set out to oppose.
Fortunately, as I conclude in §4, OOO forces the objectness of sound to remain an
open question which itself calls things and relations into question.
Before delving into the argument proper, I would like to clarify my use of sources
and terms. This essay is about sound, not speci�cally about music, though it was
in musicology that I �rst encountered the question of sound’s thingness. My
interdisciplinary inquiry therefore addresses musicology as well as sound studies.
I draw on both analytic and continental philosophies, taking no part in their
con�ict, only seeking their responses to the questions at hand. Although my
discussion of OOO occurs largely in §3, I introduce Harman’s tenets in preceding
sections where relevant. I consider all sounds to be ontologically equivalent
regardless of their source, duration, loudness, or assigned cultural value. And I use
the terms “thing”, “object”, and “entity” interchangeably throughout. This usage
conforms to Harman’s but diverges from phenomenological usage such as that of
Heidegger, who distinguishes between objects and things.
In musicology and sound studies, arguments against the possibility of sound’s
thingness are common. A popular contention is that things are self-contained
whereas sounds are contingent on what people do. For proponents of this view,
distinguishing between human perceptions or practices and the sounds involved
therein requires several undesirable moves, e.g.: misrepresenting the
fundamentally human activity that is music;[6]ignoring deconstruction, the
“linguistic turn” and other philosophical trends;[7]and submitting to undesirable
ideologies.
5 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
For example, Rodgers claims that any conception of sounds as “differentiated
individuals” is actually a metaphor based on capitalist, individualist, and scienti�c
ideologies that render human subjects classi�able and quanti�able.[8] Since the
nineteenth century, she argues, sounds have been understood analogously to
human bodies. Scientists and philosophers began to treat sounds as autonomous
entities when the dissection of human bodies into autonomous components,
classi�cation of humanity as an autonomous species, and discrimination between
members of autonomous genders and ethnic groups became customary, all in
the name of “fantasies of control.”[9] For Rodgers, sonic autonomy is a reifying
metaphor that perpetuates the desire for biopower and the reductive
categorizations that result in racism and chauvinism.
In contrast, the idea that sound is ontologically indistinguishable from human
perceivers dates back to the beginning of modernity. According to Erlmann’s rich
historical analysis, an analogy between sound-perception and reasoning, both of
which were understood as forms of sympathetic resonance, dominated
philosophical and scienti�c theories from Descartes’ time to Adorno’s. The
analogy became so prevalent that by the nineteenth century it was no longer an
analogy but a physical con�uence: sound could not exist unless someone human
heard it. Sound, hearing, and hearer became one and the same. “[W]e ourselves
are the string that, set into motion, perceives its own sound from inside to outside,
perceives itself…as if one were this tone oneself; its essence and our own are one,”
said Ritter in 1806.[10] Thus we are ontologically prior to any sound. In listening,
we make sounds what they are: as Helmholtz claimed, “aerial vibrations do not
become sound until they fall upon a hearing ear.”[11] Erlmann identi�es this
solipsistic, anthropo- and ego-centric perspective with “hypochondria”: “an
ampli�cation of not just one’s sense of bodily malfunctioning, but of a person’s
sensory sphere more generally and of everything else along with it: meaning,
subjectivity, language, and thought.”[12]
Regarding the con�ation of sound and hearing, Erlmann’s concern isn’t
sound’sloss of autonomy – the other’s loss of otherness, which I hope to
foreground here – but our own. Depriving sounds of their autonomy means
depriving us of ours: “the more that the boundaries of the object world appear to
dissolve…the more [one’s] own self loses its substance.”[13] That said, restoring
sounds’ autonomy – admitting their self-contained existence by acknowledging
that what one hears isn’t just oneself shuddering in an empty world – does not
6 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
restore the “freedom” of the human subject. Rather, “self-contained” sounds are
authoritarian and oppressive in Erlmann’s analysis. He therefore disapproves of
music that seems to achieve autonomy from its perceivers or “total object status.”
In such music, “the attendant concept of a ‘for someone’ or audience have all but
vanished.” Existing only for itself, such music is “inhuman” in the cruel sense of
totalitarianism, Erlmann writes. If a listener cannot hear (or impose) “echoes” of
herself in what she hears, “Listening becomes Gehorchen, an act of
obedience.”[14]
What Erlmann calls obedience Harman calls “sincerity”. In OOO, every object
essentially exists for itself, not “for someone”, i.e. not for the sake of or because of
any human requirement or presence; but from the object-oriented perspective,
this state of affairs is nothing like totalitarianism. To practice OOO is indeed to
expose ourselves to the autonomous otherness of objects. Doing ontology
means“mak[ing] oneself ever more vulnerable” to nonhuman things.[15] It entails
“radical openness to other beings, without goal.”[16] From this perspective,
listening doesn’t mean listening for oneself but coming into contact with sonic
entities that are irreducible to oneself. However, such vulnerability need not entail
the destruction of our freedom or curtail our own in�uence upon what we hear.
As Harman suggests (§3), a thing is one thing for itself and another thing for each
of us. What does hint at authoritarianism is the notion that nonhuman autonomy
is morally objectionable. So does the related notion that sounds or any other
nonhumans ought to be “for someone” (cf. Sterne). If one objects to the idea of
sonic thingness on the assumption that things are autonomous and sounds
shouldn’t be, the objection is susceptible to charges of xenophobic utilitarianism.
A related problem pervades Kane’s incisive critique of what Pierre Schaeffer, the
inventor of sampling and musique concrète, called l’objet sonore. Inspired by
Husserl’s phenomenological reduction, Schaeffer claimed that if one ignores a
sound’s references to the world beyond itself – forgetting its implications of a
source, ignoring its semantic and communicative potential – one will hear the
sound “in itself.” This “in-itself” or essence of sound is a “sound object”: a sound
that “no longer functions for-another as a medium” but rather “designate[s]
something ‘discrete and complete.’”[17] Schaeffer hoped that such “bare sounds”
might function as “basic ontological unit[s]” that provide common ground
between musical and acoustic research.[18] He attempted to guide listeners
towards sound objects by using recording equipment to separate sounds from
7 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
8 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
their original causal sources. Ultimately, though, the reduction is an act of
consciousness: one simply excludes referential possibilities from one’s attention.
What’s left is not the sound that enters one’s ears from outside but the content of
one’s own, deliberately restricted perception. A sound object is “the fruit of a
mode of ‘considering’ or listening to the fragment torn from the whole.”[19] It
“only comes into being when it is cognized, when it is something capable of being
apprehended by a subject.”[20] Here again, sound object and sound perception
are one and the same. A sound object amounts to the subjective decision to hear
in a certain way, perhaps analogous to the designation of a class, type, or
category.[21]
What Kane objects to in Schaeffer’s work is the ignorance of subjective difference
and sociohistorical context that listening to sound objects entails. If a sound
possessed the discrete, stable “in-itself” that Schaeffer unsuccessfully proposed,
then every listener who heard it would essentially hear the same thing; the
difference between listening experiences would be moot.[22] For Kane, however,
sounds are precisely the unique, temporally situated, sociohistorically determined
situations of those who hear them. Sounds “do not simply constitute a realm of
essence detachable from their moment, sites of production, or reception. Rather,
they need to be recognized as a sedimentation of historical and social forces.”[23]
From this perspective the idea of sonic autonomy is nothing but “hardheaded
idealism.”[24]
According to Kane, Schaeffer contracted his idealism from Heidegger, who
understood technology as something separate from its sociohistorical
context.[25] Harman agrees with Heidegger on this point, though Harman is no
idealist but a broad-minded realist. As I’ll discuss (§3), in OOO things do exist
independently of human concerns, actions, and social structures; in fact being an
object meansbeing autonomous, irreducibly other, permanently uncanny. But for
Kane, that autonomy makes sound objects untenable. Music consists of
“historically speci�c persons involved in artistic or critical engagements with the
technological means at hand,” he says, suggesting that sonic ontologies should
proceed from the same perspective.[26] Sonic discourse “must resist the reliance
upon ahistorical ontologies,” he contends.[27] The implication is that when
discourse eliminates sociohistorical context and subjective difference, e.g. by
positing the thingly autonomy of sound, music is reduced to “phantasmagoria”: a
product that disguises its human origins in order to appear self-suf�cient – and
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
that smacks of ideology.[28]
But so does Kane’s assertion that sounds “are simply a sedimentation of historical
and social forces.” Like Erlmann’s, this analysis is phantasmagorical in the
opposite sense: it conceals the self-contained, nonhuman otherness of sound so
that sound may appear ontologically dependent on human productive forces. As
Cox notes, this kind of analysis “falls prey to a provincial and chauvinistic
anthropocentrism…for it treats human symbolic interaction as a unique and
privileged endowment,” perpetuating the falsehood that “human beings inhabit a
privileged ontological position.”[29]
In that sense, despite Kane’s disagreement with Schaeffer, the two theorists make
the same reduction on different scales. Schaeffer’s guileless use of recordings to
divorce sounds from their instrumental sources deprives the sounds of their
speci�c nonhuman otherness, reducing them to subjective human experiences.
For Schaeffer the essence of sound is the content of a particular human subject’s
deliberately honed aural perceptions. While Kane opposes this solipsistic analysis,
his objection boils down to the claim that the sociohistorical situations of listening
subjects must be taken into account. From that more encapsulating perspective,
Schaeffer’s basic thesis may hold true: a sound is its production and reception by
(sociohistorically situated) humans.[30] Schaeffer’s thinking differs from Kane’s
only in the latter’s speci�cation that the humans in question do their listening and
creating in the context of interpersonal relationships. Kane’s unwritten
assumption that musical sound must be thought anthropologically belies the
same anthropocentrism that undergirds Schaeffer’s. For both theorists, the
essence of sound is only human.
While it’s true that an exhaustive analysis of music must account for the human
players, actions, traditions, social circumstances, and ideologies involved, such an
analysis should also account for what makes sound soundand not just another
human construct. Schaeffer recognized that music exists somewhere “between
nature and culture.”[31] Despite the false dichotomy produced by his reductive
terminology, his remark is telling. It implies that music consists of nonhuman
entities and acts (“nature”) as well as human ones (“culture”). Speci�cally, sound
objects or sounds in-and-for-themselves are “givens” or “grounds” that humans
�lter and interpret when we make and hear music. “Sound dwells in all things,”
but “melodies…inhabit only the bosom of man,” Schaeffer intoned: music is
9 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
10 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
humans’ selective reduction of the all-encompassing otherworld of sound.[32] If
human perceptions and practices reduce essentially nonhuman sounds to
enculturated, sociohistorically conditioned phenomena, the common essence of
music and acoustics is not perception but the worldwide population of
idiosyncratic, self-contained, nonhuman sonic entities that exceed perception.
Altogether, objections to sound-things as autonomous entities are largely
objections to the chauvinistic, authoritarian, or essentialist ideologies of rei�cation
implied thereby. According to Sterne, scholars fear that thanks to the
“objecti�cation” of sound “we have forgotten how to think about music as…driven
by involvement and participation, and this forgetting has limited the possibilities
for ourselves and for a more just and egalitarian world.”[33] The general opinion
seems to be that it would be better to reduce sound to a matter of human action,
culture, history, or ideology than to risk underplaying humans’ ontological
privilege. This despite the unpopularity of idealism and the audible sense that
there is something to sound that is not ourselves. That otherness is what makes
sound sound, an alien being that no perception or representation can entirely
capture.
Humans’ desire for control over ourselves and our environment is in a sense
understandable, as perhaps it goes along with our instinct for self-preservation.
When foreignness invades our ears, we sense this control slipping away, and with
it our existential certainty. Like any deep desire, this attitude can be overcome;
but dispelling ourselves from the center of concern is never easy. With an
ideology that might stem as much from instinct as from centuries of use, we cling
to views like Sterne’s: sound is a thing only insofar as it is “for someone” – a nonautonomous “bundle of affordances.”[34] Citing Heidegger, Sterne writes that
things are only things – that is, only exist at all – because of what they enable
people to do.[35] A thing is nothing of its own accord, only the possibility of some
human action. Sterne reduces all things to commodities: use-value plus
exchange-value.
The problem could be Heidegger, who believed in humans’ ontological priority.
His essay “The Thing” seems to in�uence several arguments against sonic
thingness. The jugness of a jug is in no way determined by the jug, he writes. By
putting wine in it, I decide that it’s a jug.[36] Insistent on rigid differences
between humans and nonhumans, Heidegger grants the ability to encounter
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
something “as” something (jug as jug, sound as sound) to humans alone –
although experience reveals that cars relate to sounds as sounds and not as
petrol, elephants relate to sounds as sounds and not as food, sounds relate to ears
as ears and not as delicate champagne glasses. “Heidegger seems to think that
human use of objects is what gives them ontological depth,” Harman writes.[37]
“This approach wrongly casts Daseinin philosophy’s starring role, while preserving
the unfortunate belief that the world…[consists of] neutral slabs of material
accidentally shuf�ed around or colored by human viewpoints.”[38]
Heidegger’s reductive view of things de�nes them �rst by their availability to
humans, second by their durability. “A jug is a thing insofar as it things,” he says,
and “thinging” seems to mean a thing’s “gathering” of its constitutive and
relational characteristics into a “manifold-simple” unity that “stays for a while.” A
thing is a phenomenon that issues from the world and in its own way “stay[s] put”
to in turn implicate the world.[39] Presumably a sound couldn’t be a thing for
Heidegger, since although sounds are of the world and available to humans,
sounds do not “stay.”
Accordingly, many music and sound scholars object to the idea that sounds
possess anything like the durability of things. Instead they subscribe to traditional
theories of sound as vibrations of a medium.[40] In all such views, the preeminent
quality of sound is transience: sounds do not “last,” therefore they are not things,
and arguments to the contrary are paradoxical. For example, Eidsheim writes: “the
experience of sound is temporal – arising and coagulating only to pass all too
quickly. Thus a musical experience is not somethingthat can be captured in
notation, but an open-ended and pluralistic negotiation of sound in all its
physicality.”[41] Similarly, for Cox, “sounds are peculiarly temporal and durational,
tied to the qualities they exhibit over time,” so “[i]f sounds are particulars or
individuals…they are so not as static objectsbut as temporal events.”[42]
O’Callaghan recognizes that sounds have qualities of objects andevents. Sounds
are “traveling particulars [that] are in certain respects surprisingly object-like. They
can be created; they have reasonably de�ned spatial boundaries but persist
through deformation; they survive changes to their locations and other
properties; and they are publicly perceptible.”[43] Granted, “they make peculiar
11 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
12 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
sorts of objects: their capacity to overlap and pass through themselves [and
others] makes them stranger than most everyday objects.”[44] Indeed, a sound is
also “something that happens to” something: “a dynamic occurrence that takes
place within [a] medium.”[45] Eventually O’Callaghan discards sonic objects in
favor of events. He concludes: “whatever events turn out to be, sounds should
count as events.”[46] But having conceded, given sound’s ambiguity, that “the
difference between events and time-taking particulars and objects may be just a
matter of degree,” he apparently permits the possibility that events might turn
out to be objects.[47]
Struck by this same possibility, Cox proposes that instead of basing sound’s
ontology on that of objects, philosophers should do the opposite: consider the
ontology of objects in terms of that of sound. “Indeed to begin with sound is to
upset the ontology of ‘objects’ and ‘beings’, suggesting that the latter are
themselves events and becomings.”[48] This is the beginning of an idea that is at
home in OOO; but unlike Cox, Harman realizes that it cuts both ways: if being
means occurring, then occurring is also being. Entities are events and events are
entities (see §3).
O’Callaghan and Cox are unwilling to go this far. In their analyses, despite the
latter’s commitment to Deleuzian �ux, events and objects do not ontologically
�ow into each other but stumble into an ancient paradox. If objects are merely
events of long duration – or as Cox says, “becomings that, however, operate at
relatively slow speeds” – then presumably sounds (which in Cox’s view are
notobjects) are events of short duration or becomings at higher speeds.[49] Does
this mean that protracted sounds are in fact objects? Does it mean that shortlived objects are not objects? A may�y lives for twenty minutes: its lifetime is
shorter than a Romantic symphony, shorter than the average piece of drone
music. Yet isn’t a may�y a thing, in the sense of an autonomous, durable entity?
How long must staying stay in order to be thinging?
This is a version of the Sorites paradox, �rst attributed to Eubulides of Miletus: how
many hairs must someone lose in order to be bald? If a rock loses its atoms one
by one, how many can it lose before it’s no longer a rock? How long must a sound
be in order to be a thing? These questions are paradoxes because their solutions
rely on indeterminable limits. The durability of sound is relative. The blare of a car
horn might fade out of my hearing in a matter of seconds but linger in the ears of
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
13 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
a street elephant or imperceptibly �utter a thread on a tasseled awning long after
the fact. The durability of things is equally variable: compare a quick-dissolving
tablet with a may�y or sequoia. But the problem runs deeper than that. Where
do sound and tablet end, breeze and water begin? The problem with sounds and
things is ontological vagueness. There’s no decisive boundary between what they
are and are not.
Thomasson believes that this is a problem with language, not an ontological
problem or even a philosophical one: “vagueness resides in our representations,
not in the world” and its denizens.[50] Phenomena themselves aren’t vague, only
our descriptive terms. This includes the words “object” and “thing”, which
Thomasson says are too vague to make ontological distinctions. To ask if some
phenomenon quali�es as a thing is therefore an “underspeci�ed, unanswerable
question,” she attests.[51] But this argument simply shuts the question down.
Why couldn’t there be vague objects without rigid ontological boundaries? Aren’t
human bodies such objects? Wouldn’t my body remain my body if someone took
a kidney out of it? Yet isn’t it simultaneously true that there is no difference
between my body and my kidney? The boundaries between us are �uid, fuzzy
questions.
Might a sound be a vague object? I’ve cited several theorists who believe that the
boundaries between sound and not-sound are questionable, yet some
boundaries must exist. Even these theorists sense some kind of division between
what sound is and what it’s not. Otherwise, they wouldn’t argue a distinction
between sounds and things. Just as quantum physics turns the difference
between particles and waves, entities and changes, into an open question, so the
question of sound’s thingness reopens the question of things’ vagueness.
It therefore isn’t true that “vague predicates” like the word “thing” say nothing
about reality. Vague predicates reveal that reality is vague; they open it for
questioning. It’s durability that is “purely arbitrary” as an ontological criterion.[52]
The Sorites problem demonstrates that duration isn’t evidence enough for or
against the thingness of sound or any other event. Rather, sound’s apparent lack
of durability complicates the questionable relationship between durability and
things.
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
14 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
In other venues, I’ve made every objection to sonic thingness. I’ve argued against
phantasmagoria, atemporality, ideologies of rei�cation and domination. These
objections remain valid in any realm that assumes: clear distinctions between
human and nonhuman beings; the ontological, ecological, and ethical priority of
humans over nonhumans; and the idea that all it takes to make and perceive art
is sociohistorically conditioned human creativity. I no longer believe in any of
those things. However, that’s not to say that all aspects of prevailing sonic theories
are not true. Chauvinism and totalitarianism areunacceptable. A sound isa wave,
temporal phenomenon, and subjective experience. It is indeed reductive to
represent such phenomena as entities and vice versa. Sonic experience is one of
the most intimate experiences we have with our own bodies, as it happens in the
depths of our heads; at the same time, this experience issociohistorically
conditioned. But none of that is all there is to it. Sounds may be all of that as well
as objective, non-ideal entities that exist in and for themselves, possessing and
questioning autonomy and durability.
Adhering to a rigid dichotomy between things and events entails overlooking a
crucial quality of both: things and events both perpetrate their being and in doing
so physically impact other beings. In Bennett’s vital materialism, a thing is an
entity with “thing-power”: “a source of action that can be either human or
nonhuman; it is that which has ef�cacy, can do things, has suf�cient coherence to
make a difference.”[53] Objects are “agents,” Morton says, “in that through them
causalities �ow.”[54]
Sounds possess their own sounding-thing-power which renders it impossible to
ignore the fact that the being of things is a doing and an impact. Sounds are
indeed causal agents: in music they inspire emotions, in sound cannons they
in�ict injuries. Shaken by the sonic thing-power of music, Morton writes: it “tunes
to me, pursuing my innards, searching out the resonant frequencies of my
stomach, my intestines, the pockets of gristle in my face…sound as hyperobject, a
sound from which I can’t escape, a viscous sonic latex.”[55] On this view, sounds
are things, their effectiveness reminds us of all things’ potency – and it’s
reasonable to acknowledge that “music is a collective encounter between human
and nonhumanbodies.”[56]
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
Thing-power is non-equivalent to Heideggerian affordance, which is for humans
alone. Instead, thing-power is the effect that things have on any and all other
things, which may or may not be human. Yet from Harman’s perspective even
this idea is incomplete. In vital materialism, he argues, each object seems
“exhausted by its presence for another, with no intrinsic reality held cryptically in
reserve.”[57] But this unreachable “reserve” exists in OOO, wherein things are
radically autonomous and durable, irreducible to any relationship or set of
relations even as they are inherently relational, contextual, temporal, and
effective. This is one of many contradictions metabolizing at the heart of every
being.
OOO is a plausible foundation for a credible theory of sonic thingness. Harman’s
metaphysics provides all entities with enough relationality and transience to
satisfy sound theorists andmaintains the otherness of things. It enables relations
themselves, including events, to count as things.
The �rst tenet of OOO is that things are radically autonomous. Even though an
entity is the uni�ed, systematic relation of its manifold qualities and components,
which in turn is determined by contextual relations, the entity is also something
separate, over and above those relations. Harman writes: “objects will be de�ned
only by their autonomous reality. They must be autonomous in two separate
directions: emerging as something over and above their pieces, while also partly
withholding themselves from relations with other entities.”[58] A sound is its
frequency and amplitude; it is also more than that. It’s an issuance from a source
and a phenomenal relationship to hearers; and it is more than that.
This “something more” is a withdrawn essence unique to every individual, a
“hidden surplus” inexplicable in terms of any relationship between the individual
and another.[59] Objects “withdraw from human view into a dark subterranean
reality that never becomes present to practical action any more than it does to
theoretical awareness.”[60] Further, “the same is true of the sheer causal
interaction between rocks or raindrops. Even inanimate things only unlock each
other’s realities to a minimal extent, reducing one another to
caricatures.”[61] Harman explains: “[i]f numerous entities encounter any given
object, each runs across it as a vastly different causal power to reckon with. Each
of them frames it from a speci�c perspective, opens itself up to it as a distinct and
limited kind of impact…[T]he sum total of all such impacts never adds up to the
15 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
16 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
reality of the [thing] – there is always more where that came from. Every entity
forever holds new surprises in store.”[62]
Harman’s term for the radically autonomous, super�uous, extraordinary, and
imponderable essence of every entity is “tool-being”. This has nothing to do with
the thing’s role in human praxis; instead a thing’s tool-being is the aspect of it that
withdraws from every causal and perceptual relation. “The tool-being of the
object lives as if beneaththe manifest presence of that object.”[63] “[T]he real
force of tool-being lies in its resistanceto all holism, its withdrawal behind any
seamless web of relations…resist[ing] all possible practices, signi�cations, and even
inanimate contexts.”[64]
A thing’s withdrawn aspect is its essential aspect: what makes it truly itself. A
thing is durable in that there is always something left over of it from its relations,
and what’s left over is the object’s existence in-and-for-itself, in its own terms and
nothing else’s, not even in terms of atoms and quarks. Generally speaking, “there
is strife between the presenceof a thing and its being.”[65] “The true chasm in
ontology lies not between humans and the world, but between objects and
relations.”[66] All relations are reductions.
Nothing demonstrates this more effectively than sound. A human listener
experiences an aria as a sound shaped by composers’ choices, performers’
idiosyncrasies, and certain aesthetic traditions – not as anything else, even though
the sound has countless other features. To a delicate glass, that same sound
wouldn’t be an aria but a shattering blow. The human listener reducesit to an
operatic experience, unable to perceive it as a fatal blow. The glass reduces it to a
blow, unable to experience it as an aria. The air reduces it to a minor change,
unable to detect either the aria or the death blow. Meanwhile the sound itself is
not only aria, disturbance, and mortal strike, but also more than all of those
phenomena. Every sound “withdraws into its vast inner reality, which is
irreducible to any of its negotiations with the world. Only in its relations with
other entities is it caricatured, turned into a unitary pro�le.”[67]
The reductiveness of relation is evident in all the sonic theories I’ve described.
Each perspective reduces sound to one or a few of its numerous aspects, e.g.,
subjective experience, temporal event, sociohistorically conditioned human praxis
or the possibility thereof. These perspectives ignore others, e.g., sound as an
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
autonomous agent with enough durable, tactile force to serve as a bulletreplacement. And all perspectives overlook the hidden surplus of every sonic
interaction. That excess is the sound in itself: not the exclusive phenomenon that
Schaeffer called l’objet sonore, but something that eludes every phenomenon
and description.
A thing’s durability is its excessiveness and hiddenness and its “reversal” into
presence, into unitary pro�les interacting with others.[68] The staying-power of a
thing is this continuous alternation between hidden essence and present
caricature. This “metabolism between [essential] being and [relational] beings” is
the meaning of being.[69]
During its metabolism, a thing creates and exudes its own temporality and
context. In OOO, temporality is not the fact that things don’t last; instead a thing’s
temporal existence is precisely its metabolism of its hidden reality and relational
caricatures as it withdraws from and manifests in its encounters. Temporality “is
really nothing more than this very interplay of reality and projection,” says
Harman.[70] “This thorough duality of every situation, this interplay of equipment
and observer, shadow and light, is the speci�c chiaroscuroof every moment.”[71]
In addition, simply by being themselves, things to some extent determine how
they relate to others, thereby generating and characterizing the total relational
web that we call “the world”. Being entails projecting oneself into contextgenerating relations. Every entity is “sincerely engaged in executing itself,
inaugurating a reality in which its characteristic style is unleashed.”[72] Things
create their contexts as they are their contexts.[73] Objects explode being and
time, as “even the single instantis already outside of itself…[T]he supposed static
instant is not really static at all, but rather ek-static– already torn apart by its own
incurable ambiguity”: that “internal strife between an entity’s subterranean force
and its seductive façade.”[74]
Thus an apparently “static” thing isn’t unchanging or ahistorical but quite the
opposite. A thing isstrife, relation, and context even as it is not. Moreover, “the
converse is also true: every set of relations is also an entity.”[75] Morton builds on
this last point in his postulation that an autonomous object may be a grand
system of relations on spatiotemporal scales too vast for any human to take in. On
this view, global warming is a thing, even as it is also an event and a condition. An
earthquake is a thing, so is a climate. Such grand objects, which Morton calls
17 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
“hyperobjects”, are ambiguous, at once nonlocal and contextual, viscous and
withdrawn.[76] Even the most humble objects share these qualities.
And so does sound. Since things in OOO are ek-static systems and self-contained
essences, the OOO perspective neither brackets nor entirely submits to the
contingencies so vital to sonic theories. Thereis room in OOO for sounds to be
sociohistorical, temporal relations as well as durable entities that are irreducibly
other.
OOO has other advantages too. First, if all relations are incomplete, since no
entity includes all of itself in any relation, then no entity or type of entity is
ontologically prior to any other. Even the relationship between a thing and its own
phenomenal qualities excludes the essence of the thing. Hence neither humanity
nor any of its practices or constructs can claim ontological privileges. Rather, in
OOO, things are absolutely �rst, not just as facets of a viscous cosmic mesh, but as
self-contained, withdrawn individuals known to nobody, not even themselves.
Every being includes an in�nite regress: “everyessencehas a deeper essence as
well.”[77] OOO posits an “irreducible dark side” to every object, which in the end is
“unanalyzable” as it contains “objects wrapped in objects wrapped in objects.”[78]
This is OOO’s second advantage. Rather than foreclosing attempts to question
the being of things, by virtue of its in�nitude this paradoxical regress
alwaysresistsforeclosure. Things withdraw their singular truths from the briefest
surface-encounters and the deepest ontological probes, which means that there
is always more to ask. Where visible objects like the jug tend to obscure, in a
dazzling display of pretended obviousness, the relational non-relational
contradiction that essentially metabolizes them, sounds foreground this
contradiction. Sounds’ strangeness illuminates the fact that all things and
relations are stranger than they ever seem. Sounds make questions out of
thingness and things.
In the shifting but inclusive light of OOO, sounds put rigidifying ideologies and
ontologies in their place. Additionally, as OOO illuminates the weird viscosity of
entities and encounters, sound’s extreme otherness and bizarre thingness
become more overt possibilities. While Cecchetto doesn’t embrace sound-things
explicitly, his sonic theory is consistent with OOO. He acknowledges the in�nitely
withdrawn quality of sound, which like dark matter is perceptible yet ultimately
18 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
imperceptible. “[E]very sound is a ghost,” he writes, “which is why we are always
looking for the sources of sounds, trying to place and identify them: we hunt
down hauntings and �ush them out, only to always hear more.”[79]
Distinguishing what we hear from what sound actually is, Cecchetto also
recognizes the reductiveness of relation. When we hear a sound we register what
we hear and “foreclose” the rest, he says.[80] And since hearing is irrevocably tied
to signi�cation, we only ever hear what is meaningful to us: only sonic content
that we can relate to ourselves and other beings. What we hear is a caricature of
actual sound – listening is reduction. The sound itself, the “‘sound-ness’ of its
sounds disappears,” withdraws from all hearing.[81] As irreducible otherness that
eludes every relation, sound is equivalent to Harman’s tool-being: the objectness
of objects. Cecchetto’s analysis paves the way for committed theories of sonic
thingness based on OOO.
Theories that reject the possibility of sonic things by denying sound’s autonomy
and durability do so based on anthropocentric ideologies or reductive de�nitions
of thingness that annul sound’s otherness and impact. Such theories are
primarily motivated by the fear that understanding sounds as durable,
autonomous objects would dissimulate sound’s innate relationality and
temporality. But object-oriented ontology offers an open-ended conception of
thingness as a continuous metabolism of temporal relationality as well as durable
autonomy. In OOO, things are paradoxical: every entity consists of a necessary,
hidden essence and contingent presence, separated by an irreconcilable
ontological rift. Consequently, things are irreducible to their relations even as they
are their relations. As things in the object-oriented sense, sounds would retain
their potent and absolute otherness while losing none of the experiential relativity
that’s critical to aesthetic theories. OOO provides a democratic forum in which
relational sonic theories and object-based sonic practices may approach
reconciliation. At the same time, OOO discourages attempts to posit a privileged
type of being (Dasein or any other) to which sounds, entities, or relations may be
ultimately reduced. Instead, the withdrawn ambiguity of entities in OOO ensures
that every ontology, including that of sound, will remain an open question.
But what if OOO were subject to critique? It’s possible that like any other theory,
this ontology rides on a hidden ideological undercarriage, not an anthropocentric
19 of 26
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
20 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
one but just the opposite. Indeed it’s tempting to reduce OOO to the deanthropocentric ideology that advances the agendas of radical ecology. Radical
ecology critically opposes the capitalist principle that humans’ ontological and
ethical priority entitles us to a coldly utilitarian view of nonhuman beings. Instead,
radical ecology promotes an ontological anarchy in which no entity is sovereign
over any other, but each entity celebrates the absolute otherness of every other.
Using OOO, Morton calls for ecological awareness in the form of a “double denial
of human supremacy.”[82] This means that humanity deserves neitherontological
priority northe privilege of distancing itself from other kinds of being. OOO
“provoke[s] irreductionist thinking…in which ontotheological statements about
which thing is the most real (ecosystem, world, environment, or conversely,
individual) become impossible. Likewise, irony qua absolute distance also
becomes inoperative,” as all events and entities equally constitute the same kind
of thingly being.[83] Morton’s ecological metaphysics is a vital extrapolation of
OOO, and the echoes of radical ecology are clear. Does that mean that ecological
de-anthropocentrism indeed powers OOO from underneath, as an ideology?
I’d like to say that if it did, all the better. But my argument is precisely that sound
cannot be reduced to human experiences, actions, or constructions, ergo the
question of sound’s thingness cannot be reduced to an ideological decision.
Arguably any attempt to decide the question on utilitarian, semantic, aesthetic,
ecological, or ethical bases would not respond to the question but foreclose it on
grounds that will probably turn out to be ideological in the light of critique.
Fortunately all humans, nonhumans, and relationships are things in Harman’s
work. OOO isn’t a matter of anthropocentrism or de-anthropocentrism but
simply of things on equal ontological footing. Hence to respond to the question
of sound’s thingness with OOO isn’t justto say that we oughtto appreciate sound’s
thingness, otherness, and durability because, for example, only such awareness
can alert us to sound cannons’ dissembling rhetoric. Such ethical reasoning is
possible, even wholeheartedly welcome, but it’s just one of many insights that
OOO facilitates. To respond to the question of sound’s thingness with OOO really
is to say something about reality. At the very least, it reveals that sound
demonstrates just how strange reality is. From that observation, in�nite questions
follow.
References
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
21 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
[1]Joanna Demers, Listening Through the Noise (New York: Oxford University
Press), 125.
[2]Jonathan Sterne, MP3: The Meaning of a Format (Durham: Duke University
Press), 191.
[3]Theodor Adorno, “On the Fetish-Character in Music and the Regression of
Listening,” In Essays on Music, trans. R. Leppert, (Los Angeles: University of
California Press, 2002), 288-317.
[4]LRAD Corporation, “LRAD for Public Safety Applications Fact Sheet.” Accessed
23 July 2014. http://www.lradx.com/site/content/view/323
[5]LRAD Corporation, “The Global Leader in Long Range Acoustic Hailing Devices:
Public Safety.” Accessed 23 July 2014. http://www.lradx.com/site/content
/view/254/110
[6]Christopher Small, Musicking (Middletown: Wesleyan, 1998), 8.
[7]Seth Kim-Cohen, In the Blink of an Ear (London: Continuum, 2009), 13.
[8]Tara Rodgers, “‘What, for me, constitutes life in a sound?’: Electronic Sounds as
Lively and Differentiated Individuals,” American Quarterly63(3): 510-511.
[9]Ibid., 512.
[10]Johannes Ritter quoted in Veit Erlmann, Reason and Resonance (Cambridge:
Zone, 2010): 198-9.
[11]Hermann von Helmholtz, “On the Physiological Causes of Harmony in Music.”
Science and Culture: Popular and Philosophical Essays, ed. D. Cahan (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1995), 46-75
[12]Erlmann, Reason, 210.
[13]Ibid., 211.
[14]Ibid., 332
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
22 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
[15]Graham Harman, Tool-Being (Chicago: Open Court, 2002), 226.
[16]Timothy Morton, Hyperobjects (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
2013), 164.
[17]Brian Kane, Sound Unseen (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014), 25, 16.
[18]Ibid., 36.
[19]Ibid., 16.
[20]Ibid., 19.
[21]Ibid., 34.
[22]Brian Kane, “The Music of Skepticism,” PhD diss., University of California
Berkeley, 2006, 131.
[23]Kane, Unseen, 53.
[24]Ibid., 36.
[25]Brian Kane, “L’objet sonore maintenant: Pierre Schaeffer, sound objects and
the phenomenological reduction,” Organised Sound12(1): 22.
[26]Kane, Unseen, 40.
[27]Kane, “L’objet,” 22.
[28]Kane, Unseen, 40. Adorno, In Search of Wagner, trans. R. Livingstone. (London:
Verso, 2005), 74.
[29]Christoph Cox, “Beyond Representation and Signi�cation: Toward a Sonic
Materialism.” Journal of Visual Culture10(2): 147.
[30]Kane, Unseen, 38.
[31]Pierre Schaeffer, Solfège de l’objet sonore, trans. L. Bellagamba (Paris: INA-
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
23 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
GRM, 1967), 11.
[32]Ibid., 15.
[33]Sterne, MP3, 190-191.
[34]Ibid., 189.
[35]Ibid., 193.
[36]Martin Heidegger, “The Thing,” in Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. A.
Hofstader (New York: HarperCollins, 2001), 170.
[37]Harman, Tool-Being, 16.
[38]Ibid., 19.
[39]Heidegger, “The Thing,” 171-175.
[40]E.g., see Helmholtz, “Physiological Causes,” 52-53.
[41]Nina Eidsheim, “Sensing Voice: Materiality and the Lived Body in Singing and
Listening,” Senses and Society6(2): 136.
[42]Cox, “Beyond,” 156.
[43]Casey O’Callaghan, Sounds (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 25.
[44]Ibid.
[45]Ibid., 26.
[46]Ibid., 58.
[47]Ibid., 27.
[48]Cox, “Beyond,” 157.
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
24 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
[49]Ibid.
[50]Amie Thomasson, Ordinary Objects (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007),
105.
[51]Ibid., 114.
[52]Harman, Tool-Being, 294.
[53]Jane Bennett, Vibrant Matter (Durham: Duke University Press, 2009), viii.
[54]Morton, Hyperobjects, 29.
[55]Ibid., 30.
[56]Citation omitted for blind review, 207-208, emphasis added.
[57]Graham Harman, The Quadruple Object (Alresford: Zero, 2011), 12.
[58]Ibid., 19.
[59]Harman, Tool-Being, 2.
[60]Ibid., 1.
[61]Ibid., 2.
[62]Ibid., 227.
[63]Ibid., 220.
[64]Ibid., 171-174.
[65]Ibid., 4.
[66]Ibid., 2.
[67]Ibid., 169.
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
25 of 26
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
[68]Ibid., 67.
[69]Ibid., 68.
[70]Ibid., 145.
[71]Ibid.
[72]Ibid., 220.
[73]Ibid., 23.
[74]Ibid., 64-65.
[75]Ibid., 260.
[76]Morton, Hyperobjects, 201.
[77]Harman, Tool-Being, 258.
[78]Morton, Hyperobjects, 44.
[79]David Cecchetto, Humanesis: Sound and Technological Posthumanis
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2013), 47.
[80]Ibid., 153.
[81]Ibid., 51.
[82]Morton, Hyperobjects, 19.
[83]Ibid.
SHAR E THIS
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM
The Thingness of Sound | Essay by Mandy-Suzanne Wong – Sonic Field
26 of 26
ESSAY
SOUND
METAPHYSICS
THING
https://sonicfield.org/the-thingness-of-sound-essay-by-mandy-suzanne...
OBJECT ORIENTED ONTOLOGY
THINGNESS OF SOUND
ONTOLOGY
OOO
PHYLOSOPHY
THINKING RESONANCE
Mandy-Suzanne Wong
SEPTEMBER 13, 2022
SEPTEMBER 26, 2022
What Sounds Do –
Open Call for Papers
SONIC FIELD © 2022
A Year of Deep
Listening
AUGUST 18, 2022
APRIL 21, 2022
Listening After
Nature: Field
Recording, Ecology,
Critical Practice
Hiss and a Roar: Tim
Prebble’s Vault of
Sonic Inspiration
12/6/2023, 10:35 AM