Review of Radical Political Economics, 31(2):27-45
All rights of reproduction
in any form reserved.
0 1999 by URPE
ISSN: 0486-6 134
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
of the Individual
Korkut
A.
Ertiirk
ABSTRACT:
Postmodernity raises for Marxism the question of
what happens
to the alienated
subject’s
consciousness
and
purposeful
action in the aftermath of its alienation. Arguing that
some of Marx’s own ideas can shed light on this question, I make
a conceptual distinction between form of consciousnessand mode
of consciousnessto capture what I take to be the kernel of his
thinking on the transformation
of the “average” individual
and
her/his consciousness
in his Early Writings,
and especially in
the Grundrisse.
Though
little agreement
exists
on whether
postmodernism
is a higher stage of modernism
or its fundamental
critique, certain characteristic
themes in postmodernist
discourse
are by now quite well-known and readily identifiable. Among these
are the skepticism towards science, the criticism of scientism and
the emphasis
on the other and on
the notion of progress,
deference,
the interest in the particular and the indigenous
in
contradistinction
to the general and the universal, the stress on
the connection
between
knowledge
and power
relations,
and
finally the dislike of doctrines and general world views, i.e., mega
narratives.
Though it is at times suggested
that postmodernism
and Marxism are potential political allies (Ryan 1982)) at the level
of theory postmodernist
writers see Marxism as another grand
narrative that needs to be deconstructed
even when they seem to
reaffirm (more recently) its spirit (Derrida 1994).
In this paper my purpose is neither to try to reconcile these
two isms nor to rebut the postmodernist
critique of Marxism.1
1 For a Marxist critique of postmodernism,
see Callinicos
(1990). and for
an argument that postmodernism
can theoretically
enrich Marxist economics,
see Milberg and Pietrykowski
(1994).
I would
like
Skillman,
criticisms,
to thank
B. Ollman,
E.K. Hunt,
M. Goldfield,
and H. 0x1
and suggestions. All remaining
N. Cagatay,
G.
comments,
G. Mongiovi,
for their
useful
errors are mine.
Review of Radical Political Economics
Rather,
I ask how one can account
for the condition
of
postmodernity
and what the advent of postmodernist
discourse
means for Marx. Not a few postmodernist
writers
see as the
the
defining
characteristic
of the “condition of postmodernity”
awareness
of the breakdown of ‘the grand narratives of the West
and the all-around legitimization
crisis that had brought about
(Lyotard 1985). On more neutral ground, it can also perhaps be
defined simply as a mode of human existence that is progressively
colored and shaped by the commodiiication
of daily life (and
spheres
of communication
and human imagination),
which has
created
a semblance
of empowerment
in the
sphere
of
consumption
enabling individuals to forge life styles that could
deviate from what is dictated by tradition. Postmodernism
is then
seen as the culture of this new mode of human existence.
Some
Marxist writers have in fact understood it as such, and called it
the “cultural logic of late capitalism” (Eagleton
1985; Jameson
199 1). I share with them the materialist approach that tries to
account for postmodernity
in the context of the transformation
of
life and the individual, but part ways with them when I try to
bridge the story back to Marx, dropping the qualifier late before
capitalism.
The question
postmodernity
raises for Marxism
is this:
more specifically
his theory of
Marx’s analysis of capitalism,
a powerful
account
of how the
commodity
fetishism,
gives
predicate becomes the subject under capitalism, but does not pay
much attention
to the implications
of the nascent
subject’s
transformation
in the historical context of commodity fetishism.
to the
alienated
subject?
How
does
his
What
happens
consciousness
get transformed,
and how does that affect the
nature of purposeful action? Below I address these questions and
try to theorize about them.
I base my argument on a conceptual
distinction
between
The former refers
what I call forms and modes of consciousness.2
to the nominal content of the hierarchy of ideas ranging from
that might reflect
different
class
systematized
world
views
interests in the sense of Lenin, or to the constitutive elements of
the “ideological superstructure” in the sense of Western Marxism.
Postmodernism
is then just another form of consciousness,
or if
be defined in
you like an ideology, that can for our purposes
terms of the following four attributes: i) it has a grain of truth; ii) it
obscures reality more than it elucidates; iii) it serves the interests
of a class or a particular social strata; and iv) it constitutes the
building blocks of social reconstruction
of reality. Its basis in
reality (first attribute),
I argue, is the transformation
of the
average or the typical individual and his/her existential
reality
2 Below, I argue that the seeds
especially in the Grundrisse.
28
of this distinction
can be found
in Marx,
June 1999
Marx, Postmodemity,
and Transformation
under capitalism, which it unreflectively
reflects
(second attrithe transformation
of the
bute).3 Here, I try to conceptualize
average individual by theorizing about the metamorphosis
of the
mode of his/her visceral “self-knowledge”
which colors the way
he/she internalizes
ideas about the outside world and his/her
place in it. I call this the mode of consciousness,
referring to a
deeper
layer as distinct from views
and ideas held by the
individual.
Thus, the telltale postmodemist
skepticism against all mega
narratives
can be seen as the intellectual outcome of this very
transformation
of the alienated subject and of its historically
unique vantage point along with the reality it is a part of. For
universalist
doctrines
can only break down if the individual
ceases to believe in them, and that reflects a transformation
in
how the individual instinctively situates him or her self in relation
to other individuals and the outside world.
The following discussion is organized into two main sections.
In the first section, I begin by contrasting the capitalist mode of
consciousness
with the precapitalist mode, and then move on to
discuss the main parameters
of the transformation
of existential
reality under capitalism. At the end of this section I take a step
back in the logical sequence and discuss Marx’s analysis of the
historical
emergence
in thought of the ideal of the bourgeois
individual capitalism was to create. This introduces
the contradiction between the “political society” and the “civil society,” which
is the focus of the second section of the paper. As Marx argues;
the molding of the actual individual to its bourgeois
abstraction
presupposes the intervention of the political society, which in turn
requires that the individual is willing to play the role of the citizen
who is called on to act in the name of the state. This means that
the fiction of citizenship has to be powerful enough to motivate
the individual to act in self-sacrificial
zeal and in contradiction
to
bourgeois
individual.
That the
the very ideal of the selfih
individual as the citizen does so, I argue, is ultimately an attribute
of the hold-over of his/her precapitalist mode of consciousness.
However, over the long haul as the bourgeois individual ceases to
be an ideal projection and becomes closer to an actual fact, a new
capitalist mode of consciousness
begins to emerge. The political
society and the citizen complete their historical mission, and the
individual ceases to be a “true-believer.”
Thus, I argue that the
ultimate cause of the legitimization
crisis
the postmodernist
writers talk about is the transformation
of the existential reality of
the individual
and his/her
mode of consciousness.
I end by
reflecting on the contradictions
of the emergent politicization
of
the civil society,
and what its connection
to identity politics
implies to traditional Marxist understanding of class domination.
3 In this paper I only concentrate
June 1999
on these two first attributes.
29
Review of Radical Political Economics
THE PRECAPITALIST
AND CAPITALIST
MODES OF CONSCIOUSNESS
In pre-capitalist
social entities,
production
relations
are based on relations of personal dependence.
The individual is
born into a static world where his social standing, vocation, and
mode of life is to a great extent pre-ordained with almost absolute
certainty. The community binds individuals together.
Or, rather
the individual exists only as a member of the family, the clan, or
the community.
His
“productive
activity
and his share
in
production are bound to a specific form of labor and of product,
which determine his relation to others in just that specific way”
(Marx 1973: 157). The community’s control over the individual is
in
complete, direct, and natural, and individuals are imprisoned
definite categories
in their relations with one another.
In the
developed
system
of generalized
exchange,
however,
all this
changes.
The “ties of personal dependence,
of distinctions
of
ripped up...” (ibid.
blood, education, etc., are in fact exploded,
163). and all past ideologies, morality, religion, are turned into a
“palpable lie” (Marx 1970: 78).
In both social formations, the individual is, and remains, a
social being, or what Marx called, a species-being. That is, in both
cases the reproduction
of the conditions
of existence
of the
with
the
reproduction
of
the
individual
is
coterminous
collectivity-though
of course what that collectivity
is changes
drastically.
Likewise
in both cases, the self-knowledge
of the
individual
entails an “ideological”
recognition
of this essential
social aspect of human existence. But, what varies from one case
to the other, along with the objective structure of the individuals
bond to the community, is the nature of one’s inverted recognition
of this link. In other words, both the structure of the individual’s
bond to the community
and the exact form of his mystified
awareness
of this bond is altered, but the human need and
propensity
to reaffirm
the social dimension
of his existence
remains. 4
If we think
of consciousness
as the bridge
between
experience
and being, as E.P. Thompson (1978) once suggested,
we can perhaps think of a two-layered
cognitive structure that
emerges from the life-experiences
of the individual. While one is
contingent on one’s individual experiences
that might be shaped
for instance by social position and status uis-a-uis others, the
other deeper layer pertains
to the mode of one’s unmediated
recognition
of the community that is more or less common to
4 For a discussion of Marx’s understanding
on man as a species-being, see Hunt (1986).
30
of “human
essence”
and views
June
1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
everyone in a given mode of material existence. I suggest that in
this common mode of recognition,
or mystified
self-knowledge,
one can find the basis for defining a mode
consciousness
that is
unique to a given historical era, or to different social formations in
a given era.
Accordingly
then, the pre-capitalist
mode of consciousness
can be defined as the individuals
indirect recognition of himself
and his bond to the community through a sacralized mediator,
regardless of what exact form that mediator takes. That is to say,
the individual recognizes in an inverted way his existential reality
of being imprisoned
in a static world,
and in an existence
preconditioned
by
his
immutable
membership
in a
given
community by instinctively thinking of himself an organic member
of an indivisible
collectivity
defined
by a mystical
mediator.
According to Marx, in precapitalist social entities, the God is the
mediator onto whom the individual projects whatever is sacred in
him. The
individual’s
visceral
awareness
of the
existential
cord” is what lies behind
this
importance
of his “umbilical
sacralization,
and religion is but a mystified expression
of this
bond. The observance
of communal rituals (as conjured up by
whatever
specific
form this idealist expression
takes) by the
individual
is then the practical
link that ties the inverted
recognition of the collectivity to its reproduction.
As I will discuss
in greater detail below, during the period of bourgeois revolutions
the state replaces God as the mystical mediator, and though the
nature of social rituals change they remain as sanctified
as
before.
By contrast,
the capitalist mode of consciousness
which
emerges in advanced capitalism can be defined as the average
individual’s idealized (and inverted) internalization
of his existential
condition
of separation/isolation
and objective
dependence
on
anonymous others. The unity between the experiencing
self and
the experienced
external
world
is objectively
all the more
multi-dimensional,
and tight, but the relationship
expansive,
between
the two from the point of view of the individual’s
existential reality appears fluid and in fact non-existent except for
the unidirectional
link of utility and narrow self-interest.
His life
conditions
him to appropriate
his life experiences
through the
prism of his self-interest
oriented rationalism,
and he tends to
internalize this as true independence
and sees his connection to
social entities defined on the basis of abstract political principles
a result of individual
rational choice.5
As capitalist
mode of
consciousness
takes hold in advanced
capitalism,
social life
becomes desacralized,
and social reproduction
no longer depends
on observance of a common set of rituals, which in the meantime
of
5 Hence the appeal of the contract theories
June 1999
of the state.
31
Review
of Radical
Political
Economics
subjectively lose much of their meaning and cohesion-enhancing
effect.
Rational behavior, that is, its lack or presence,
is hardly a
distinguishing
characteristic
between
these
two
modes
of
consciousness.
For the mode of individual behavior in one, though
very different,
is as rational (or as irrational) as behavior in the
other. In an existence that is not yet individualized,
where one
can objectively
improve one’s relative position only by proving
useful to his natural superiors, acting in one’s self-interest means
something very different than the same where existence is already
individualized
and characterized
by objective
dependence
on
anonymous others. It is only in the latter that the gap between self
interest and social interest acquires a systematic character, and
for instance
the free-rider
problem
takes
on a systematic
character. For only then the vantage point of the individual ceases
to be an empty presupposition
and becomes an abstraction based
imputing the
in reality. As Marx says, it is only by idealistically
individual (and his consciousness)
of the latter age onto that of the
earlier that history is turned into an evolutionary
process
of
consciousness
(Marx 1970: 94), and only then can we distinguish
the rational modem man from his less rational forebear.6
TRANSFORMATION
OF EXISTENTIAL
REALITY
I started out the previous section with a discussion of
the implications
on human
self-knowledge
of the fact that
morality, and religion into
capitalism turns “all past ideologies,
palpable lies.” According to Marx, “all that is solid melts into thin
air, all that is holy is profaned” and the ruling ideas become those
of the ruling class. 7 But, how does this happen? What are the
dynamics that transform the existential reality of the individual
under capitalism, and how do the ideas of the ruling class become
the ruling ideas? Below, I specify and discuss
four dialectical
dynamics that help us understand this process and the sense in
which the reality turns into a whirlwind.
1. Idealization of Equality-Depoliticization
of Actual Inequalities. The bourgeois
political
revolution
overthrows
all social
distinctions
of the old society by “declaring” them to be nonpolitical. These distinctions which gave the old society a directly
political character are by no means overcome, but they no longer
directly or exclusively
determine the individual’s relation to the
6 In Weberian sociology this is seen
is thought to
“rational
will,” which
Gemeinschaft
to Gesellschaft.
as the transition
accompany
the
7 “The ruling ideas of each age have
classes” (Marx and Engels 1974: 85).
32
ever
been
from “natural will” to
transformation
from
the ideas
of its ruling
June 1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
state, his separation and exclusion from certain spheres of social
of actual
inequalities
reduce
the
life.
The
depoliticization
importance
of these inequalities
in both a “positive”
and a
“negative” sense. On the one hand, the affairs of the state are no
longer the private business of rulers, but that of the citizen. But,
at the same time, the citizen is divested of his actual individuality,
and “endowed
with an unactual universality” as the “imaginary
member of an imaginary sovereignty” (Marx 1967: 223, 226, 229).
He is any member of the civil society who is, just as anyone else,
granted the equal right to become bourgeois, as long as he aspires
to be something
that he actually is not. That something,
the
idealized bourgeois man, is the real sovereign, i.e., he who is in
thought, if not yet in reality, freed from the bonds of the old
society which had fettered his “egoistic spirit” (ibid.: 239).
2. Personal Independence
and Freedom-Objective
Dependence and the Rule of Illusion. With the development of capitalism,
“unactual universalities” begin to appear all the more real to the
individual. The personal
restrictions
of the earlier epoch now
acquire a general and anonymous form as “objective restrictions of
the individual by relations independent of him and sufficient onto
themselves” (Marx 1973: 164). This is just a reflection of the fact
that production
relations
which
were
based
on relations
of
personal
dependence
are now replaced
by those based
on
relations of objective dependence,
which develop in tandem with
the increasing
independence
of individual producers
and consumers.8 A tenant farmer’s master is no longer a particular
landlord but the relations of land tenure. Not only the worker but
also the capitalist becomes subject to the capricious vicissitudes
of the market and the laws of competition. A multitude of social
interconnections
created
by human beings
now assume
an
independent
existence,
turn into an alien force that rules over
them. Individuals
perceive this as the reign of abstract ideas,
since the social relations they have created are divorced
from
them not only in actuality but in thought as well, i.e., they only
exist as one-sided abstractions in their consciousness.
“Thus, in
imagination,
individuals
seem freer
under the dominance
of
of life seem
bourgeoisie
than before, because their conditions
accidental: in reality, of course, they are less free because they
are more subjected to the violence of things’* (Marx 1970: 84).
3. Personal Development-Personal
Powerlessness
and Isolation. Just as abstract labor develops on the basis of concrete labor
and predominates
the latter, abstract individual acquires a reality
3 “Relations
of personal
dependence...at
the outset are the first social
forms, in which human productive capacity develops only to a slight extent and
at isolated points. Personal independence
founded on objective dependence
is
the second great form, in which a system of general social metabolism,
of
universal relations, of all-round needs, and universal capacities is formed for
the first time” (Marx 1973: 158).
June 1999
33
Review
of Radical
Political
Economics
which supersedes
that of the concrete-local individual from which
it originates.
On the one hand, the abstract individual is the
concrete individual who is tied to the cash-nexus with his naked
self-interest and free of all precapitalist ties which bind him to his
natural
superiors
(Marx and Engels
1974: 70). On the other
hand, he is much more than that. He is the individual whose
needs, capacities, pleasures,
productive forces have at one and
the same time proliferated to an unprecedented
degree, but have
been usurped away from him by social capital.9 For him these
abilities to a great part remain unrealized, and to the extent that
they are realized it is only in a one-sided way and through his
subservience
to social capital.10 As social capital appropriates
whatever
creative
activity one might have in the sphere
of
production,
a sphere of pseudo-creativity
gradually takes hold in
consumption.
The eventual
commodification
of everyday
life
seemingly empowers individuals through possession of articles of
consumption
in forging life styles that deviate from the dictates of
tradition.
The construction
of a self-image
that bolsters
one’s
illusions about life becomes the main source of self-esteem
and
worth. Money buys personal ability, might, and thus social status.
4. Enlightenment
and the Development
of Reason-Triumph
gets
of Unreason
and Irrationality.
As the rule of things
generalized,
from the vantage point of the isolated individual it
becomes
rational not to know, not to understand
the outside
world. At best, the individual can hope to become an expert in a
detailed topic and rely on other experts’ opinions on all other
realms of his life, even in those realms where his subjectivity is
supposed
to count.
Objectively,
rationality
acquires
a quite
restricted meaning. No longer the liberating force against the rule
of tradition and authority, it becomes confined to “the world of
calculation,
manipulation,
control,
exact
sciences,
rule over
nature, utility, in short: the world of objectivity,” and divorced
from “the world of art, inner feelings, beauty, human freedom,
religion, in short: the world of subjectivity” (Kosik 1976: 59). The
individual
finds himself in a world where,
“human reality is
divided both in theory and in practice between the sphere of the
efficient,
i.e.,
the world
of rationalization,
resources
and
technology, and the sphere of human values and meanings which
9 “In fact, however, when the limited bourgeois form is stripped away, what
is wealth other than the universality of individual
needs, capacities, pleasures,
productive
forces, etc., created through universal exchange? The full development of human mastery over the forces of nature, those of so-called nature as
well as of humanity’s own nature?” (Marx 1973: 488).
10 “Universal
prostitution
appears
as
a necessary
phase
in
the
development
of the social character of personal talents, capacities,
abilities,
activities.
More politely expressed:
the universal relation of utility and use”
(ibid.: 163). See also Berman’s (1982) fascinating discussion
of Gothes’s Faust
as the harbinger of a new age in which self-affkmation
becomes possible only
when in a pact with the Devil.
34
June
1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
in a paradoxical
fashion become the domain of the irrational”
(ibid.: 59). Thus, in the developed stage of capitalist production, it
is not only the abstract individuals
alienated labor which enriches
social capital, but also his reason, which is equally estranged from
him. The rationality of capital which was idealistically imputed to
the person in an earlier age is substituted as his own. He begins
to act like a “rational man.”
The idealization
of one side of the first of these
four
dynamics
(equality) creates a homogeneous
social space across
which ideas, life styles, and cultural values of the dominant
classes can be transmitted
to the rest of the society. Elements of
the second dynamic (personal freedom)
provide the ideological
wherewithal for the ruling class in its attempt to establish cultural
hegemony (in the sense of Gramsci), as the bright side of the
rule of
existential equation, liberty, individual freedom, property,
are fetishized
and
presented
as the
universal
law,
etc.,
expression
of the human spirit. Within the “sphere of exchange”
these ideological notions in turn find a degree of support11 as
they connect in the life experiences
of the isolated individual to
the formal equality of contractual relations in the market, to the
limited yet significant incidents of upward social mobility, and to
the-restricted
and one-sided-personal
development
the elements of the third dynamic
give rise to. Finally, the fourth
dynamic systematically undermines critical thinking and cultivates
in the individual what Lukacs had once called a “reified mind.”
Having described
what the transformation
of the existential
reality of the individual under capitalism entails, we can now turn
to a discussion of the main parameters
of the historical process
that has brought it about.
The Historical Emergence of the SeZf23ufficient Monad
In his Early Works Marx remarks that the truth of
religion lies in the realm of philosophy. 12 He sees the history of
Enlightenment thought as the history of the philosophical critique
of religion by the emerging bourgeoisie.
In this sense, it is the
history of the creation of a new image of the “ideal man” and
society. The development
of philosophy is the critical decomposition of religion by reason, which demonstrates
the falsity of
religion. The falsity of religion is established in the fact that it is
shown to be logically inconsistent when it claimed itself universal
and its internal coherence absolute.
11 In his famous phrase Marx identifies the sphere of exchange as the
“ very Eden of the innate rights of man,” where alone rules, “ Freedom, Equality,
Property and Bentham” (Marx 1967b: 176).
12 See especially
his, “ Critique of Hegel’s Dialectic and General
Philosophy,” and “On the Jewish Question.” See also Lefebvre (1969).
June 1999
35
Review of Radical Political Economics
According to Marx, the reason for the existence of philosophy
then becomes
to provide
what it criticized
religion as being
incapable of providing, i.e., the true universal, logically consistent
principles
of human existence.
Thereby,
philosophy
creates
in
thought the ideal society and the “ideal man.” It reproduces
the
idealized self-image of itself, positing it as that of humanity free
from religious flaws. It replaces one Absolute with a superior
Absolute, one that is impeccably logical and consistent. However,
Marx points out that no sooner than successfully
completing its
task philosophy
confronts its helplessness
in realizing its “ideal
man” and “the perfect state of affairs” about which it so fruitfully
speculated.
For philosophy
itself
lacks
the
means
of its
realization. Those means lie within the realm of political action
which alone can transform society, change man and his relation to
the truth of
other
men and to Nature.
Thus,
Marx says,
philosophy lies in the realm of politics.
The
“political
society”
takes
over
from
philosophy
its
historical objectives, and the gap between “what ought to be” and
“what actually is” manifests
itself in the rift between
the “civil
society” and the “political society.” The creation of the “ideal man”
who is nothing other than the “bourgeois man”-the
self-sufficient
monad posited as the emancipated
rational individual who does
not yet exist as such in the civil society, but whose ideal is quite
real and has already turned into a potent force-becomes
the aim,
and even the reason of existence,
of the political society. The
contradiction
between
the two is borne by the citizen who is
called upon to self-sacrifice
in one heroic battle after another in
defending
the rights of the “egoistic man,” i.e., the “bourgeois
man.”
THE CONTRADICTION
BETWEEN
POLITICAL AND CIVIL SOCIJWY
THE
Just when capitalism begins to destroy all traditions
and loyalties the political society takes on a contradictory
task.
The success of the main organ of the political society, the state, in
furthering the capitalist cause requires it to be able to present
will. While it facilitates
itself as the embodiment
of universal
accumulation based on the profit motive, at the same time it has
to be the constitutive basis of a new abstract community. 13 This
contradiction
is internalized by the individual as his social life is
split into two separate
realms, 14 and the political society is
13 This abstract community is not only imagined in the sense of Benedict
1976) in the sense of
Anderson
(1983), but also mysttfed (or illusory-Ollman
MaEi.
14 “Where the political state has achieved its full development,
man leads
a double life, not only in thought or consciousness
but in actuality. In the
36
June 1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
reduced “to mere mearts for preserving
these so-called rights of
man and that the citizen thus is proclaimed to be the servant of
the egoistic man, the sphere in which man acts as a member of
the community
degraded
below that in which he acts as a
fractional being, and finally man as bourgeois rather than man as
citizen is considered
to be the proper and authentic man” (Marx
1967: 237). Life within the civil society systematically
continues
to produce “antagonistic” class interests and divisions, but the
individual as citizen participates in the abstract community owing
to the holdover
of his
precapitalist
propensity
for
social
attachment.
The rise and the consolidation
of the bourgeois
society depends on the exploits of the citizen, the fantastic
form
of his self-deception,
and the boldness with which he goes about
creating a new reality derived from his instinctive disposition to
truth,
a
disregard empirical reality in the spell of a transcendental
disposition
that in turn derives from his precapitalist
mode of
consciousness. 15 As Marx remarks,
‘The political society is as
spiritual in relation to civil society as heaven is in relation to
earth. It stands in the same opposition to civil society and goes
beyond it in the same way as religion goes beyond the limitation of
the profane world...” (Marx 1967: 225).16
Consider the way nationalism, a new form of consciousness
of the new abstract
community)
(i.e., the idealist expression
implanted from above by the cultural elite, succeeded in providing
regime after
the unifying
vision
that dismantled
one ancien
another. Especially
in those societies
that were latecomers
to
capitalism in 19th century Europe (Hobsbawm 1990), nationalism
was the harbinger of a new way of life and “salvation” on earth.
The reason it could mobilize the citizen had its objective causes no
political community he regards himself as a communal being; but in the civil
society he is active as a private individual, treats other men as means, reduces
himself to means, and becomes
the plaything of alien powers” (Marx 1967:
225).
15 In ‘The Eighteenth
Brumaire
of Louis Bonaparte,
Marx writes, “But,
unheroic as bourgeois society is, it nevertheless
took heroism, sacrifice, terror,
civil war, and battles of peoples
to bring into being. And in the classically
austere traditions of the Roman republic its gladiators found the ideals and the
art forms, the self-deceptions
that they needed
in order to conceal
from
themselves
the bourgeois
limitations of the content of their struggles and to
keep their enthusiasm
on the high plane of the great historical
tragedy.
Similarly, at another stage of development,
a century earlier, Cromwell and the
English people had borrowed
speech,
passions
and illusions
from the Old
Testament for their bourgeois revolution. When the real aim had been achieved,
when the bourgeois
transformation of English society had been accomplished,
Locke supplanted
Habakkuk” (Marx 1963: 16-17).
16 Again in “On the Jewish Question,” Marx goes onto say, “The members
of the political state are religious by virtue of the dualism between individual
life and species-life, between the life of civil society and political life. They are
religious inasmuch as man regards as his true life the political life remote from
his actual individuality,
inasmuch as religion is here the spirit of civil society
expressing the separation and withdrawal of man from man” (Marx 1967: 23 1).
June
1999
37
Review
of Radical
Political
Economics
doubt (Hrosch 1993). but the self-sacrificial
zeal with which the
citizen went about slaughtering and being slaughtered in one war
after another was not because somehow the class interests
of
workers, peasants, merchants, industrialists, and petty-bourgeois
elements merged in contradistinction
to those of the same in other
nation-states
in some unique historical juncture, but because the
fatherland
had become
the secular God.
Once again, “[t]he
phantoms
of their brains got out of their hands. They,
the
creators, have bowed down before their creations” (Marx 1970:
7).
In the twentieth century the fiction of citizenship was further
strengthened
by the challenge of the organized labor movement
(Marshall 1964). For once at the turn of the century political
reform incorporated the labor movement into the “national life,” in
the
advanced
capitalist
countries
working
class
struggles
concentrated
on extending democratic
rights to “lower” classes,
extending the public sphere over the private, and, therefore,
on
making the citizen more a fact of life.17 Thus, in practice, the
political objective of the working class (and its allies) has been to
give real content to the abstract community promised under the
bourgeois
order
by trying to repoliticize
actual inequalities.
Gramsci was perhaps unique in his cohort of Marxist writers who
theoretically
reflected
on this process in the early part of the
century. In his view, class struggle had to take the form of, as he
put it, a “war of position” that targeted the cultural hegemony of
the ruling class without which neither socialism nor a socialist
movement
could be viable.
In other
words,
working
class
struggle, in order to go beyond narrow economic demands, had to
become a war for the soul of the citizen, because, he argued, the
success
of the intellectual
and moral leadership
of the ruling
class, and thus its hegemony, depended on its being able to put
forth an outlook for the society as a whole.
Thus,
it was
understandable
that the political landscape was charted by the
polar alliances of the progressives
and the conservatives.
Just as
the progressives,
led ideally by the working class and its allies,
tried to give real content to citizenship, the conservatives
fought a
rearguard action trying to keep the abstract community abstract.
This was no doubt historically the basis of the welfare state
and the much talked about “relative autonomy of the state.” The
less the state was overtly biased
in its mediation
of class
differences within the civil society, the more legitimacy it had with
the “lower” classes. Many on the Left have in fact seen this as the
contradiction
between the legitimacy and accumulation functions
17 Therborn
(1977)
stresses
the important role wars and mobilization
played in the extension
of franchise
to the working
class in the advanced
capitalist countries.
He also comments
on gender,
race, and opinion which
historically
outlasted class as the criteria of exclusion
from citizenship.
For a
broader discussion of the gender bias of citizenship, see Lister (1993).
38
June 1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
of the capitalist state, and have discussed the crisis of the welfare
state, and contemporary
conservative
attack against it, in this
light (Wolfe 1977; O’Connor 1984).
POLITICAL
AND CIVIL
IN LATE CAPITALISM
SOCIETY
All the anti-state agitation of conservative politicians of
our day aside, capital accumulation still requires the assistance of
the state, perhaps
more so now than ever. Likewise,
class
differences
within the civil society remain as real as ever. If
anything, especially in the United States, class differences
have
become much more pronounced since the 1970s. So, what is of
crucial importance
in the contemporary
reconfiguration
of the
contradiction
between the political and civil society, I think, is the
“socially
dominant”
universal
fact
that
the
notion
of
the
individual18 has to a large degree changed or is in the process of
changing.
This ultimate@ reflects the transformation
of the existential
reality of the actual bourgeois individual, and its salient features
can be captured by the emergence of what I called the capitalist
mode of consciousness.
As the individual becomes closer to his
ideal projection
in his actual existence,
use for the abstract
community and the fiction of citizenship wane. His concerns
of
the profane world acquires an existential primacy over the sacred
ideals of the citizen, who in his eyes turns into a relic of history, a
character out of the old Hollywood movies of the G.I. Joe fighting
the Nazis, or more threateningly into someone who is culturally
backward
and unurbane.
The emotional
pull of the abstract
community
and the sacredness
of the symbols of its idealist
(nationalist) expression remain a powerful force in the cultural life
of the “lower” classes, especially in the United States where a
progressive
working class political culture remains weak. But, as
we move up the social ladder, the nation-state and all that it
implies becomes routine and already desacralized.
Since
the dominant
individual
progressively
ceases
to
perceive himself an integral part of the abstract community, his
purposeful action becomes confined to acting individualistically
on
his narrow self-interest.
If he joins this or that group, it is solely
to further his self-interest
as a free-rider
rather than out of
with no apologies,
conviction. He becomes the home economicus
doing away with the various forms of self-imposed
asceticism that
hitherto bolstered his projected image (and the ideology) of the
1s The socially dominant notion of the individual in a given era reflects the
existential
reality and the self-perception
of individuals
that make up the
dominant classes, and those of all lower social strata, which in a diminishing
scale try to emulate their life styles and sensibilities.
June 1999
39
Review of Radical Political Economics
“upright citizen” which had also justified in his mind his position
of privilege. 19 A “hedonistic”
life style that is associated
with
“permissive” consumerism
and a self-centered
narcissism comes
to define the universal individual,20 and the notion and the very
language of social obligation in public discourse withers away.
But, the fact that acting on one’s narrow
self-interest
becomes the socially sanctioned
norm of individual behavior is
ultimately what causes the breakdown
of universalist ideologies.
Because no one thinks others act in accordance
with them is
exactly why they turn into “palpable lies” and fall apart. The
shared illusions symbolized by these failing ideologies support, in
turn, institutions that are at one and the same time the means by
which i) coercive power is exercised over the individual, and ii)
one participates
in the mystified abstract community and affirms
thereby the social dimension of his existence. Their failure, on the
one hand, undermines and weakens the authoritarian
control over
the individual by the state. For instance, it becomes harder and
harder to send individuals
off to fight wars (especially
if they
come from middle or upper middle class families)21 or demand
any kind of sacrifice for the so-called “national” good. Likewise,
19 Though I cannot pursue it here, an important dimension of this change
involves
the transformation
of the family and “gender
relations,”
for the
“patriarchal”
family was, among other things, man’s “haven in a heartless
world” (Lasch 1977). that is, a kind of microcosm of the abstract community.
Thus, given the traditional gender division of labor, man’s consciousness
was
split between the logic of the market and the “collectivist”
spirit of the family,
while that of women had as a rule been shaped by the latter. Thus, the women’s
movement that has emerged with the gradual dissolution
of the “patriarchal”
family, which for a complex set of reasons overlapped with the weakening of the
abstract community,
developed
two very different voices. One voice saw the
problem of emancipation
as one of eradicating all barriers to women becoming
“equal” members in the public sphere as men, while the other indicted
the
inhumanity of the society from its unique vantage point, which revealed
how
little human life (and caring labor) is valued. Thus, while one voice criticized
and condemned
all aggression,
the other advocated
the right of women to
become combat soldiers, pilots, etc.
of modern
29 This is, according to Bell (1979)) the cultural contradiction
capitalism. Bell’s argument is based on the misconceived
notion that deferred
gratification and thus a high saving rate on the part of the bourgeoisie
is a sine
qua non of capitalist economic growth.
21 In one of the episodes of a recent public television series titled Genesis,
Jewish, and Muslim theologians
to
Bill Moyers
asks a panel of Christian,
interpret in the light of contemporary
sensibilities
the Old Testament fable of
God testing Abraham’s loyalty by ordering him to slaughter his son Jacob. One
of the panelists, Burton L. Visotzky, remarks that in this encounter Abraham
passes the test of God, but fails miserably from Jacobs
point of view, and that
the fable had its contemporary parallel in the Vietnam War when the father was
willing to sacrifice his son in his blind adherence
to some higher authority.
Indeed,
the protest against the war for the first time in history turned the
ancient fable upside down as the son rebelled against the bleak fate imposed
on him by the political society. A companion
to the TV series is now also in
print: Moyers ( 1996).
40
June 1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
alternative life styles and sexual practices
that were previously
suppressed
in the name of social integrity find an opening to
assert their legitimacy in the mainstream of the society.22 But, on
the other hand, with the breakdown
of shared
illusions
the
individual also finds it harder and harder to experience the social
anomie increases:
the
dimension of his existence.
Durkheimian
free-rider
problem becomes
universal;
the imagined community
breaks down; and the melting pot ceases to melt.
FROM CITIZEN TO THE “ AUTHENTIC”
INDIVIDUAL AND POSTMODERNISM
Just as in Marx’s discussion of how credit disappears
during a crisis of circulation
when
exchange
reverts
to its
primitive form as cash becomes
the only accepted
medium of
payment,
so too when social institutions
fail the trust of the
individual in the public disappears and social solidarity reverts to
its “primitive” form where people are forced to trust only those
who are members
of their own local community
or revitalized
tribe. The source of self-identity
shifts away from the abstract
community towards the tribe, where the individual feels she is a
meaningful participant, and her diversity (authentic-self)
is valued
and recognized.
By contrast, her social security number and tax
liability tend to become the sole vital signs of her membership
in
the abstract community.
As the political society loses much of its pull over the
individual, life in the local community-or
what Habermas
calls
the “lifeworld”
of the individual-emerges
as the sphere
of
authenticity and meaning, the enclave relatively free from both
political alienation (the web of relations associated with the state)
and economic alienation (the market relations) .23 Resuscitating
and defending this sphere from the onslaught of the market and
the state becomes
the constitutive
basis of new “progressive”
identities
and associations.
So do the shared
experiences
of
marginalization
on account of one’s living style, sexuality, race,
ethnicity,
gender,
or even a common
physical
handicap.
Yet
and when long
others gravitate
towards
their natural tribes,
extinct they try to reinvent them. But, the vast majority vacillates
between
an angry frustration
and longing
for a sense
of
community,
as attempts
to intervene
in public life through
mainstream institutions on account of collective grievances
prove
22 Thus, for instance, many homosexuals today demand not only to be free
of harassment,
but also the right to marry, become
priests, and thus lead
“conservative”
mainstream lives.
23 Within the Left, for the reformulation
of the concept of the civil society in
a tripartite framework where it stands in contrast not only to the state but also
the market economy, see Habermas (1984). Arato and Cohen (1984).
June 1999
41
Review of Radical Political Economics
futile, and they find out that all those illusions that kept them
holding the line as patriotic citizens are indeed illusions.24
In this social geography,
postmodernism
bespeaks
the
wisdom
of the “authentic” and actual bourgeois
individual.
It
articulates a vision that owes its existence to the capitalist mode
of consciousness,
and thus stakes a claim to be the voice of the
self-sufficient
monad who mistrusts all forms of association and
“find[s] in other men not the realization but rather the limitation of
his own freedom”
(Marx 1967: 236). It is not much of an
exaggeration
to suggest that this is a vision from within
a
Hobbesian
world without the contract and no Hobbes watching
over it. Existence is flux, a big blur. All social intercourse
and
meaning is infinitely variable and contingent. Other than narrow
self-interest,
only two certainties fix the existential landscape on
which one goes on living: the sensation of pleasure and pain (the
body), and a sense of detachment from all else.
Power is also another constant,
but not as tangible and
certain. It is rather diffused, almost imperceptible.
The individual
finds herself in situations where she is coerced to do things that
inclined to do. She feels
dominated.
Her
she is not naturally
reaction to domination takes the form of individual resistance
(what Foucault calls Zocal resistance and Lyotard local determinism)
and all-around
impertinence,
which together
define the outer
bounds
of emancipatory
politics in this neo-Hobbesian
world.
Only through’ resisting
domination
at the local level can the
individual learn to respect the fundamental
difference of others,
and empathize with their own form of resistance and search for
identity and meaning. But she mistrusts those who feign to speak
for all disaffected
groups or humanity as a whole, that is unreal.
Since her objective dependence
on anonymous others is lived as
complete
detachment
from social reality at large, any macro
world-view that questions the way things are is as meaningless as
rhetorical
ploy of
one that celebrates
it, except
as some
domination.
Social reality thus dissolves
into discourse,
and all
world-views
become mere narratives on equal footing. Not one of
them can be privileged over the others by claiming to be closer to
truth. Only the narratives
that talk about human emancipation
distinguish
themselves
by being the most dangerous,
for they
were in the past responsible
for terror and tyranny (Lyotard
1985).
24 In the third world, and likewise
in what used to be the second, the
weakening
of the political society has taken on a much uglier face as it led to
the politicization
of primordial identities of individuals
whose dependence
on
natural superiors remains strong.
42
June
1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
CONCLUSION
Postmodernist
writers make a great issue out of the
argument that no extra-discursive
vantage point from which to
theorize can possibly exist. However, it must be born in mind that
during Marx’s time workers, through their exclusion from society,
literally had a vantage point from outside. For Marx, it was almost
in the nature of a practical necessity that the very reality of their
exclusion
sooner
or later would lead workers
to demand
a
drastically
new order,
rather
than an equal shot at being
bourgeois. The latter thought would have been ludicrous then.
In the twentieth century, workers won a seat at the table
through their struggle. But, paradoxically,
their political success
and enhanced power deepened the nature of class domination at
a more profound level. World War I was a time of rude awakening
for the Left. The loyal citizens they proved to be, workers all over
Europe acted as the guardians of their respective
nation-states.
As the century unfolded, it became evident that in their private
moments
they
could
even
be induced
to fancy
becoming
bourgeois.
The dream made the abstract community so much
more real. The cultural hegemony of the ruling class could bridge
a class divide that no longer appeared to be a chasm, but some
imponderable
distance of a seamless
social space. Of course,
there were problems. A segment of the workers continued to hold
out, and the intellectuals,
as Schumpeter
bemoaned,
were a
perennial threat.
Now, at the end of the twentieth century, all this seems
transposed.
The political ascendancy
of the ruling class and
capitalist triumphalism of the late, again paradoxically,
appear to
hide a weakening in the structure of class domination at a deeper
level. On the one hand, the ruling class today has so much
greater control over both the workers and the social machine that
molds the “reified mind.” The foot soldiers of this machine, the
intellectuals,
are much less of a threat. (Those who are not willing
practitioners
of reification are in disarray, too preoccupied
with
their own job insecurity and political despair.) But, on the other
hand, the ruling class is no longer persuasive when it feigns to
speak in the name of all. This is not because they are losing the
Gramscian “war of position,” but because the very foundation that
made hegemony possible is fraying. Not only the class divide has
objectively
become
much deeper,
but, more importantly,
the
abstract community (and the dream), which has so effectively
bridged the divide in the past, has lost its luster.
June 1999
43
Review of Radical Political Economics
Anderson,
B. 1983. Imagined
Communities.
ReJections
on the
London: Verso.
Origins and Spread of Nationalism.
Arato, A. and Cohen, J. 1984. Social Movements,
Civil Society,
and the Problem of Sovereignty.
Praxis International
vol. 4/ 3,
Oct.
Bell, D. 1979. The Cultural Contradictions
of Capitalism.
London:
Heinemann.
Berman, M. 1982. All That Is Solid Melts into Air: The Experience of
Modernity. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Callinicos, A. 1990. Against Postmodernism:
A Marxist Critique.
New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Derrida, J. 1994. Specters of Marx. New York: Routledge.
Eagleton, T. 1985. Capitalism, Modernism
and Postmodernism.
New Lef Review 152: 60-73.
Habermas, J. 1984. The Theory of Communicative
Action. Vol. 1:
Reason
and the Rationality
of Society.
Translated
by T.
McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press.
Hobsbawm,
E. 1990. Nations
and Nationalism
Since
1780.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hrosch,
M. 1993. How Nations are Formed. New I_.+$ Review
198: 3-20.
Hunt, E.K. 1986. Philosophy and Economics in the Writings
of
Karl Marx. In Marx, Schumpeter, Keynes. S. Helburn and D.F.
Bramhall (eds.). New York: M.E. Sharpe, Inc.
Jameson, F. 1991. Postmodernism,
or, The Cultural Logic of Late
Durham: Duke University Press.
Capitalism.
Kosik, K. 1976. Dialectics of the Concrete. Boston:
D. Reidel
Publishing Co.
Lasch, C. 1977. Haven in a Heartless
World. New York: Basic
Books.
Lefebvre,
H. 1969. The Sociology of Marx. New York: Vintage
Books.
Lister, R. 1993. Tracing the Contours of Women’s
Citizenship.
Policy and Politics 2 1.
2nd edition. Cambridge:
Cambridge
Ollman, B. 1976. Alienation.
University Press.
The
Postmodem
Condition.
Manchester:
Lyotard,
J.
1985.
Manchester
University Press.
and Social Development.
Marshall, T.H. 1964. Class, Citizenship
University of Chicago Press.
Marx, K. and Engels, F. 1974. ManiJesto of the Communist Party.
In The Revolutions
of 1848. D. Fembach,
(ed.). New York:
Vintage Books.
Marx, K. 1973. Grundrisse. M. Nicolaus (ed.). New York: Vintage
Books.
44
June 1999
Marx, Postmodernity,
and Transformation
. 1970. The German Ideology. C.J. Arthur (ed.). New York:
International Publishers.
1967. On the Jewish Question. In Writings of the Young
Ma;x on Philosophy and Society. L.D. Easton and K.H. Guddat
(eds.). New York: Anchor Books, Doubleday and Company.
. 196713. Capital,
vol. I. New York:
International
Publishers.
. 1963. The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte.
New
York: International Publishers.
Milberg, W. and B. Pietrykowski.
1994. Objectivism,
Relativism
and Importance of Rhetoric for Marxist Economics.
Review of
Radical Political Economics 26: 85-109.
Moyers, B. 1996. Genesis. New York: Doubleday.
Accumulation
Crisis.
New
York:
Basil
O’Connor,
J.
1984.
Blackwell.
Ryan,
M.
1982.
Marxism
and
Deconstruction:
A
Critical
Articulation.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Therborn,
G.
1977. The Rule of Capital and the Rise
of
Democracy.
New I..@? Review 103: 3-41.
Thompson,
E.P. 1978. The Poverty of Theory and Other Essays.
New York: Monthly Review Press.
Wolfe, A. 1977. The Limits of Legitimacy: Political Contradictions
of
Contemporary
Capitalism.
New York: Free Press.
Korkut A. Ertiirk
Department of Economics
University of Utah
Salt Lake City, UT 84112
Korkut@econ.sbs.utah.edu
June 1999
45