View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk
brought to you by
CORE
provided by UT Digital Repository
The Dissertation Committee for Guido Mascialino certifies that this is the
approved version of the following dissertation:
A Critical Appraisal of Relational Approaches to Psychoanalysis
Committee:
Frank Richardson, Supervisor
Robert Abzug
Ricardo Ainslie
Guy Manaster
Alissa Sherry
i
A Critical Appraisal of Relational Approaches to Psychoanalysis
by
Guido Mascialino, B.A.
Dissertation
Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of
The University of Texas at Austin
in Partial Fulfillment
of the Requirements
for the Degree of
Doctor of Philosophy
The University of Texas at Austin
May, 2008
Dedication
To my family back home, and to Frank Richardson, my family in Texas.
A Critical Appraisal of Relational Approaches to Psychoanalysis
Guido Mascialino, Ph.D.
The University of Texas at Austin, 2008
Supervisor: Frank C. Richardson
In the last twenty years, relational psychoanalysis has emerged as an important
voice in psychoanalytic theory and practice. Relational approaches operate within the
tension between intrapsychic and interpersonal levels of explanation. On the one hand,
intrapsychic explanations assume the existence of a private inner life focusing on
internal processes such as fantasy, desires, repression, and unconscious motivations. On
the other hand, interpersonal explanations focus on transactions with others, the daily
give and take of our relationships, and our inextricable participation in the social realm.
Schools in the relational movement often struggle to integrate these two poles, but the
risk seems to be collapsing one explanatory pole into the other. This work argues that
framing this discussion within a wider philosophical horizon can suggest a compelling
new way of thinking about these matters. The theoretical psychology of Jack Martin and
Jeff Sugarman (1999, 2000), the philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer (1977, 1994), and
Martin Heidegger (1993, 1996), offer a view of selfhood that transcends the problematic
internal-external dichotomy pervasive in relational approaches.
iv
Table of Contents
Introduction: Relational Psychoanalysis and the Modern Self...............................1
Chapter 1: The Influences of Relational Psychoanalysis.......................................7
Introduction.................................................................................................7
Interpersonal Psychoanalysis.....................................................................10
Interpersonal Psychoanalysis in Practice....................................................15
Object Relations Theory............................................................................20
Melanie Klein............................................................................................20
W. R. D.Fairbairn......................................................................................22
D. W. Winnicott ........................................................................................25
Therapeutic dimensions of Fairbairn and Winnicott...................................31
Self-Psychology ........................................................................................37
Self-Psychology and Clinical Practice .......................................................41
Chapter 2: Relational Psychoanalysis .................................................................49
Introduction...............................................................................................49
Mitchell and the Development of Relational Psychoanalysis .....................54
Worlds of Experience: Stolorow, Atwood, and Orange..............................65
Social Constructionist Perspectives in Psychoanalysis ...............................71
Relational Psychoanalysis in Clinical Practice...........................................77
Chapter 3: Beyond the Intrapsychic vs. Interpersonal Dualism ...........................83
Differing Concepts of Personhood.............................................................83
Martin and Sugarman ................................................................................86
Beyond Modern and Postmodern Selves....................................................89
Social Constructionism and Cognitive Constructivism...............................91
The Metaphysics of Dynamic Interactionism.............................................93
Free Will and Determinism .......................................................................97
Limitations of Martin and Sugarman's Approach.......................................99
v
Chapter 4: Rethinking selfhood........................................................................ 103
Introduction............................................................................................. 103
Martin Heidegger: theory and everyday life............................................. 106
Dasein as human existence ...................................................................... 110
Authentic selfhood .................................................................................. 129
Gadamer and understanding .................................................................... 132
Personhood and embeddedness................................................................ 137
Chapter 5: Clinical implications ....................................................................... 141
Introduction............................................................................................. 141
Theory and practice reconsidered ............................................................ 144
Hermeneutic dialogue as the model for the theory-practice relationship... 147
Hermeneutics and treatment .................................................................... 152
References ....................................................................................................... 160
Vita …............................................................................................................. 176
vi
Introduction: Relational Psychoanalysis and the Modern Self
In the last twenty years, relational psychoanalysis has emerged as an important
voice in psychoanalytic theory and practice (Beebe & Lachmann, 2003, p. 379). Unlike
many other psychoanalytic schools, relational psychoanalysis does not have a single
founding theorist who introduced a clearly formulated theoretical model. Instead, a
number of diverse and varying positions have coalesced around a unifying concept: the
idea that relationships are the basic building blocks of the mind (Mitchell & Aron, 1999,
p. xiii). The heterogeneity characteristic of the relational movement has understandably
created varying views of what this new paradigm entails concretely (Mitchell, 2000, p.
xiv). As a result, seemingly inconsistent views, sometimes about core concepts, have
emerged within the movement. The underlying premise of this work is that conceptual
clarification of these apparent incongruities could be philosophically and clinically
enriching. There is, at the moment, a dearth of literature addressing the theoretical
diversity within this approach, which underscores a clear need to bring its voices into
dialogue to make sense of their differences. The aim of this work is to do so with the
hope that it will accomplish greater theoretical lucidity and wider cohesiveness of
relational views, without sacrificing their diversity.
There is a notable area of disagreement in the relational movement that seems
ripe for this type of exploration. Mitchell and Aron (1999, p. xviii) observed that
relational approaches operate within the tension between intrapsychic and interpersonal
1
levels of explanation. This observation leaves open the issue of whether this tension
could prove problematic. On the one hand, intrapsychic explanations assume the
existence of a private inner life focusing on internal processes such as fantasy, desires,
repression, and unconscious motivations. On the other hand, interpersonal explanations
focus on transactions with others, the daily give and take of our relationships, and our
inextricable participation in the social realm. Schools in the relational movement often
struggle to integrate these two poles. Postmodern relational approaches have appealed
primarily to the social level of explanation. In its radical variants, they define--perhaps
even dismiss--the concept of the intrapsychic as a culturally constructed discursive
practice; in essence, a culturally sanctioned way of talking about reality (Fairfield,
Layton, & Stack, 2002, p. 2-3). On the other end of the spectrum, thinkers like Mitchell
and Aron (1999) express their concern that the constructed self is incomplete without
the contributions of an inner life in the formation of personhood. They aspire to retain a
concept of intrapsychic reality as something more than just a way of talking. Although
both groups embrace social levels of explanation, they disagree about how allencompassing this dimension should be considered and about the place of the individual
subject in this new picture.
Martin and Sugarman (1998, p. 1) noted that a similar tension between the
social and the individual is prevalent in much of contemporary social science. They
claim this tension results from social science’s response to philosophical critiques of the
modern understanding of selfhood. Among those that have taken issue with a modern
2
construal of the self, Charles Guignon (2004) notes that modernity brought about the
birth of a new worldview in which the self came to be seen as “nuclear”, “a selfcontained, bounded individual, a center of experience and will, with no essential or
defining relations to anything outside oneself” (p. 43). Charles Taylor (1986), a
prominent contemporary philosopher, noted that divorced from the influence of
anything outside itself, the modern self looks only within itself for guidance and
fulfillment. Likewise, the well-known critiques of modernity found in Foucault (1982,
2002) and Derrida (1980, 1997) provide a scathing indictment of the traditional
disembodied and detached modern self. These thinkers call for a much-needed
contextualization of the self that acknowledges its history and cultural sources.
Relational approaches embrace contemporary critiques of the nuclear self, albeit
with some reservations, and are deeply aware of the pressing need to recognize its
cultural embeddedness. This is a timely endeavor that opens up theory and clinical
practice to considerations of social factors. However, Martin and Sugarman (2000)
caution, in the enthusiasm to overcome a nuclear self, we risk privileging cultural
factors to the point of eliminating notions of individuality altogether: “Psychologists are
interested in how humans develop and learn as experiencing individuals. If there are no
such selves to develop and learn, psychological commitments require not just
adjustment or even reconfiguration but also radical reconsideration and quite possibly
abandonment.” (p. 397). It seems then that contextualizing the mind involves a certain
balancing act between the need to recognize the constitutive force of social context and
3
the reality of individual experience. At the same time, individuality requires a defense
that avoids reverting to modern notions of a masterful or bounded self. The risk seems
to be collapsing one explanatory pole into the other.
The purpose of this work is to explore this problematic as it presents itself in
relational psychoanalysis. In order to do this, relational perspectives must be presented
and discussed in their dialogical tensions. In addition, it is argued that bringing this
discussion into a wider philosophical horizon can both enrich our understanding of the
problem and suggest a compelling new way of thinking about these matters. For this
purpose, the theoretical psychology of Jack Martin and Jeff Sugarman, and the
philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer (1977, 1994) and Martin Heidegger (1993, 1996),
among others, will be considered as sources.
Important conceptual changes within a field are seldom absolute or abrupt.
Instead, they often evidence both continuity and rupture from the tradition that precedes
them. Psychoanalysis could be considered emblematic of this phenomenon; theoretical
developments are often couched as a continuation of Freud’s work in some essential
way, while drawing attention to important innovations that redirect the discipline’s
concerns. There are two risks involved in doing this. Overestimating the continuity of
thinking within a tradition can result in presentism, while overemphasizing its
originality risks obscuring the sources from which that thinking sprung. However, when
theoretical innovation is understood within the right relationship to its historical context,
it illuminates both the past and the future of a discipline. In keeping with this aim, this
4
work attempts to properly understand relational psychoanalysis by examining its
influences.
Lastly, asking about the nature of the mind is not just an issue of philosophical
accuracy but also of clinical importance. Another working assumption of this effort is
that there is a rich, complex, and mutually determinative relationship between theory
and practice evident in the psychoanalytic encounter. In order to examine it, this
dissertation will look at clinical material to understand the implications of theory in
practice. In the process of doing so, a certain view about the relationship between theory
and practice in psychoanalysis should become evident. I would like to defend that,
ideally, there is a nuanced and reciprocal relationship between them, where theory
guides our practice but never fully determines it or exhaustively explains it. In turn,
effective psychotherapy practice ought to feedback into our theories. Of course, this
ideal relationship is not always the case, and we often find discontinuities and
puzzlement in the theory-practice relationship.
This author believes that relational psychoanalysis has something to contribute
to psychotherapy at large, and this is why this work has one foot inside and another
outside of psychoanalysis. As such, it is neither an introduction to psychoanalytic work,
nor a scholarly treatise on psychoanalytic matters. It intends to be more that the former,
and less than the latter. In doing so, the hope is that certain ideas become accessible for
discussion within and outside of psychoanalytic communities. Some might argue that it
5
is not only psychoanalysis that requires more dialogic cohesiveness, but the field of
psychology as a whole (Richardson, Fowers, & Guignon, 1999).
6
Chapter 1: The Influences of Relational Psychoanalysis
Introduction
Mitchell and Greenberg (1983) originally coined the term relational to describe
a group of psychoanalytic approaches that believe the mind is constituted by the
internalization of interpersonal relationships (Fossage, 2003, p. 411). Arguably, there is
no central figure in the relational approach, yet Stephen Mitchell has been proposed as
an organizing theorist who defined its loose boundaries and consolidated the unifying
themes that helped in the “emergence of a tradition” (Silverman, 2000, p. 146; Mitchell
& Aron, 1999, p. i). In spite of the spirit of openness and integration that relational
approaches claim, Mitchell and Aron (1999) position the school as a competing
alternative to traditional models: “Relational concepts do not provide understandings of
different phenomena from those explored by the drive/defense model; relational
concepts provide alternative understandings of the same phenomena” (p. xii).
This description establishes a division of the psychoanalytic world into two
spheres: those who apprehend the central roles of relationships in the formation of the
mind, and those who don’t. This border between relational and classical psychoanalysis
could be construed as somewhat arbitrary, particularly given Mitchell’s
acknowledgement that Freud himself has important relational strands in his thinking
(Mitchell & Aron, 1999, p. vii; Frank, 1998, p. 141). It seems that there is a degree of
continuity in psychoanalytic theorizing in its recognition of the social dimensions of
7
human existence. At the same time, there are important theoretical differences that
cannot be easily overlooked. Indeed, the current theoretical landscape is complex and
sometimes murky. As Spezzano (1995) tries to make sense of it he notes that:
One danger is overgeneralization. Not all analysts who think of themselves as
classical will see themselves accurately portrayed here, nor have all American
analysts who think of themselves as not classical abandoned all the principles I
label as classical nor embraced all the ones I have labeled as contemporary.
Even these labels are problematic because what I call contemporary analysis has
roots going back 80 years to Ferenczi in Europe and 50 years to Sullivan in the
United States, while what I call classical analysis is still evolving as
contemporary structural theory. (p. 44)
We can and often do encounter such gray areas when looking at the history and
also the current state of psychoanalysis. We can find seeds of future thinking in earlier
writings, and reinterpretation of early theory in light of new developments. Many
contemporary schools overlap and differ concurrently across different important issues.
As a result, there is a risk of overstating the differences between relational and classical
approaches. Nevertheless, there are genuine differences across psychoanalytic schools.
Acknowledging common threads between them should not amount to a hasty equating
or leveling of all positions. Spezzano (1995) reminds us that there is also a danger of
“blurring the differences” when conducting “an initial effort to define a school of
analysis” (p. 44).
8
Relational approaches dwell in this theoretical richness and ambiguity because
of the variety and wealth of their influences. Understanding them requires placing them
in the proper context of the history of ideas in psychoanalysis. In fact, the “relational
turn” (Beebe & Lachmann, 2003, p. 379) that has gained such prevalence in
psychoanalysis today is rooted in a series of gradual shifts that culminate in the
retrospective analysis that Mitchell and his colleagues present. As such, tracing their
influences helps understand their theoretical paradigm. In Mitchell and Aron’s own
words: “The exploration of history is often helpful in shedding light on current
controversies and in generating ideas about where we need to go” (p. xiii). However, it
is difficult to provide a succinct and coherent narrative describing the precursors of
relational psychoanalysis. The following account intends to do both more and less than
that. Less because it will be selective in the psychoanalytic milestones it tackles, but
more because it will zero in on these to discuss their relevance to relational approaches.
Mitchell and Black’s (1995) description of the term relational lends itself as a
good starting point for inquiry: “The term relational was used …to highlight the
common theoretical framework underlying interpersonal psychoanalysis, British school
object relations theories, and self-psychology.” (p. 263). What follows then is a brief
examination of the aforementioned sources, object relations, self-psychology, and
interpersonal psychoanalysis.
9
Interpersonal Psychoanalysis
Sullivan was a unique figure in the history of psychoanalysis: “…more
identified with the psychiatric community than the psychoanalytic one” (Kuriloff, 2002,
p. 306). Levenson (1992) notes that his thinking was not psychoanalytic in itself, but
that:
…his essentially open-ended postulates—which he scrupulously defined as
Interpersonal Psychiatry —can be, and were, extended into a contemporary
interpersonal Psychoanalysis. I really do not believe this was Sullivan's doing
per se but rather, was the result of the merging of his American pragmatic
psychiatry with European psychoanalysis through the contributions of his
colleagues, especially Thompson, Horney and Fromm (p. 451)
And so his thinking came to be associated with the group later dubbed culturalist within
psychoanalysis, which included figures like Karen Horney and Erich Fromm (Mitchell
& Black, 1995, p. 259). Clara Thompson (1979) confirms that: “the contributions of
Sullivan and Fromm have come to be called the "cultural school, " because of the great
emphasis of both on the interpersonal factors in personality formation and personal
difficulties and the relative lack of emphasis on the more biologic drives as dynamic
factors” (p. 200). This represents a clear departure from Freud’s emphasis on biological
explanations. However, it is also important to notice that it maintains a significant
theoretical distance from object relation approaches. In the development of relational
10
psychoanalysis, Sullivan’s focus on interpersonal interaction will offer the
complementary balance to the analysis of interiority presented by object relations.
Although one is pressed to find an outright rejection of an inner-world in
Sullivan’s theorizing, there certainly is a determinate and almost exclusive focus on
interpersonal phenomena. However, it seems helpful to heed Mitchell ‘s (1988) advice
that understanding Sullivan involves readjusting our basic concepts of the intrapsychic
and the interpersonal:
At first glance, it might seem apparent what is meant by “intrapsychic” and
“interpersonal,” the former referring to processes within the mind, the latter
referring to processes between persons. These are serviceable working
definitions, but they don't take us very far if we are trying to distinguish
Sullivan's position from classical psychoanalysis, since they clearly do not do
justice to either mode of theorizing” (p. 473)
Mitchell (1988) maintains that these concepts have been used as quasi-political
banners that obscure similarities and polarize different theoretical positions (p. 473). He
notes that he sees no outright rejection of social influence in classical psychoanalysis,
just like there is no rejection of intrapsychic dimensions in a Sullivanian approach.
Instead, there is a disagreement about how primordial each pole really is in explaining
human behavior. So while Sullivan can acknowledge that interpersonal interaction
unavoidably involves the subjectivity of the individual, he will not make it a focus in
11
and of itself. In its place, the starting point for understanding human behavior is not the
individual mind but the interpersonal field:
For Sullivan, situations are not outside the individual but inclusive of the
subjective and behavioral activities of all participants. The arena of relevance is
not behavioral but expanded to include a circuit of continuous interchange,
permeating boundaries between the subjective "inner" and behavioral "outer."
That intimate connection between them is what makes it possible to draw
inferences about the subjective even though it cannot be directly observed…
Thus personality is seen as a somewhat open system, inevitably engaged in the
more inclusive social fields through which one moves in the course of living,
beyond Freud's term of early childhood (Grey, 1988, p. 556).
Commenting on the origin of this concept in Sullivan’s approach, Siegel (1987)
notes that: “…using Kurt Lewin's (1951) concept of field theory, Sullivan tried to shift
the focus in psychiatric and psychoanalytic thinking from the intrapsychic to the
interpersonal field.” (p274). Lewin, a German exile who eventually led the Research
Center for Group Dynamics at MIT, introduced field theory as a “corrective to earlier
systems of thought” that were too individualistic (Viney, 1993, p. 368). Sullivan
appropriated this notion of a field as a basic unit of analysis and introduces it to
psychiatry. An interpersonal field can be seen as analogous to the system in family
therapy, where the whole has an interactive force that shapes individual participation.
The concept of an interpersonal field is central for Sullivan (Bromberg, 1980, p. 240)
12
and it will take up a central role in relational psychoanalytic approaches as well (TubertOklander, 2007, p. 115).
Sullivan defines the self as: “…a system or organization of interpersonal
processes which are an embodiment or reflection … of selected attitudes of the culture
acquired through contact with the significant people” (Thompson, 1978, p. 498). Rather
than thinking of the self as a self-contained entity, Sullivan defines it as a structured set
of interpersonal processes. Thinking of the self as a co-constituted phenomenon defies
traditional definitions that attribute uniqueness and individuality to it. In fact, Sullivan
does not leave much room for creative expression and uniqueness as usually understood
(Klenbort, 1978). Yet, even though he appears intent on dismantling notions of personal
uniqueness, Sullivan acknowledges the role of subjective experience in motivation.
However, he departs from Freud’s focus on internal phenomena by substituting
interpersonal needs in place of libidinal instinct as the motor for behavior:
…while Freud sees the child's development as going on inevitably in terms of
the child's sexual development and his libido, Sullivan's child is a product of his
interaction with significant people. He assumes that the need for security is even
stronger in the human being than the need for instinctual gratification or
satisfaction and that these latter become problems only when they conflict with
the need for security. Since man is the least instinct-dominated of all the
animals, it behooves us according to Sullivan to concern ourselves chiefly with
13
the forces which do dominate man, and they are the social forces. (Thompson,
1978, p. 495)
Thompson identifies the central difference between their approaches by noting
that Sullivan completely dismisses a hedonistic principle in explaining motivation.
Sullivan views two sets of motivating factors in humans: needs and anxiety (Grey,
1988, p. 556). Needs are biological urges such as hunger, thirst and the like. Sullivan,
like Freud, acknowledges the role of biology in influencing human behavior. However,
Sullivan speaks of needs as and their satisfaction as a way of drawing people together
and ensuring the survival of the individual and the species. For him, biology sets us up
in a sort of collaborative harmony from the starting point. Furthermore, our needs are
plastically shaped by culture, which defines the ways in which satisfaction can be met
(Grey, 1988, p. 557).
The other pole that explains human behavior for Sullivan is anxiety. He views it
as a pathological phenomenon that regulates interpersonal functioning. Anxiety emerges
from a threat to the individual’s security needs, an intrinsic human desire found in
interpersonal approval (Grey, 1988, p. 557). It represents more than just subjective
discomfort, but rather “an experience of such catastrophic dimensions, so utterly
disorganizing, that the patient will do almost anything to avoid it” (Levenson, 1992, p.
452). In fact, the devastation that anxiety brings about causes us to systematically
ignore or disavow those interpersonal experiences that can trigger it. Sullivan calls
those instances of systematic inattention, along with other defensive maneuvers that
14
manage to stay out of awareness, security operations. The experiences associated with
anxious affect are so distressing as to become dissociated from our sense of personal
identity.
According to Sullivan, people are shaped by the effect of anxiety, which is
present and absorbed within an interpersonal field. Indeed, the child comes to
understand which experiences should trigger anxiety because affect is contagious in the
first place: “…Sullivan termed this contagious spread of mood from caregivers to
babies the empathic linkage” (Mitchell & Black, 1995, p. 67). Certainly, therapists
sitting next to a very anxious patient for a significant period of time can attest to the
infectious nature of the state of mind. As the seed of motivation, anxiety is the affective
state that the therapist must be intensely attentive to. But because it spreads within the
interpersonal field, they should attend to it not only in their clients but also in
themselves. Indeed, Sullivan believes therapists cannot fully extricate themselves from
the therapeutic encounter, an idea that finds expression in another of Sullivan’s
concepts: that of participant-observation.
Interpersonal Psychoanalysis in Practice
Sullivan introduced the concept of participant-observation in psychiatry and it
was later incorporated into psychoanalysis:
In 1939, in his first lecture on Conceptions of Modern Psychiatry, Harry Stack
Sullivan referred to participant observation as, "the root premise of psychiatric
methodology" (Sullivan, 1940), for the theory which had emerged at the
15
beginning of his career as research psychiatrist. It arose out of thrashing
discontent with how psychiatrists were functioning in regard to schizophrenic
patients. (Spiegel, 1977, p. 372)
Like other Sullivanian concepts, it seems easier to grasp intellectually than to practice
clinically. Green (1977) succinctly captures the essence of his idea when he notes that:
“in all his teaching and writing, [Sullivan] assumed that the psychiatrist is inextricably
and inescapably involved with all that is going on in the session” (p. 258). Part of
Sullivan’s retreat from Freudian theory, which he considered too speculative, involved
developing simple concepts that originate from clinical practice instead of speculative
reconstruction (Hirsch, 2003, p. 222). This does not mean, however, that Sullivan is
purely pragmatic and/or theoretically blank. He developed theoretical contributions that
he believed derived from a firm experiential grasp of psychopathology and personhood.
The use of participant-observation is an example of this practical simplicity paired with
concrete theoretical direction.
Distinguishing Sullivanian from classical models of analytic technique, Bruch
(1977) observes that in the traditional model: “…the psychoanalyst was like a blank
mirror onto whom the patient transferred his libidinal attachments”, while “…Sullivan's
concept of the psychiatrist's role as participant observer stands in opposition to this
passive image” (p. 348). In Sullivan’s view, the psychiatrist cannot stand back and offer
interpretations at appropriate moments while the transference takes place. On the
contrary, he actively engages the client and her perspective in a joint inquiry into the
16
areas of her interpersonal functioning which stand out as problematic. In one sense, the
role of the analyst is actively participative because “…the only way for the analyst to
know what the patient is really talking about is to ask detailed questions” (Mitchell &
Black, 1995, p. 72). However, the therapist participates in the clinical encounter in a
deeper sense by joining and co-creating a new interpersonal field. For Sullivan, the
analyst is embroiled with the client so that the analyst’s reactions to what is going on in
the room, the countertransference in classical terms, becomes an important data point.
As a matter of fact, he believes that clients will unavoidably reenact their interpersonal
patterns of relatedness in the therapy session, and that the role of the therapist is to
understand these and facilitate the development of insight in the patient through careful
questioning. This process is mired by complexity and requires careful detail to the
moment to moment exchange. Sullivan (1953) writes that “…when we talk
professionally with a person—whom I shall now call the patient—the speech behavior
occurs in a situation including the two of us and an indefinite and shifting group of
illusions and impressions as to each other.” (p. 45). He illustrates his point when
discussing the treatment approach of a schizophrenic who: “…hated to have people
stare at him, so he stayed at home. Why did people stare at him? He does not know—
and is obviously and keenly uncomfortable…I comment looking at him that I see no
reason to stare at him.” (1953, p. 46). In his response to the patient’s presentation of his
problem, Sullivan engages the patient by communicating to him that he believes there is
no reason why the patient should be stared at. Moreover, he phrases the question
17
directly, allowing the patient to feel trusted in his experience as opposed to challenged
or kept at a distance:
Consider in our example the substitution of “Did people stare at you” or “What
made you think that people were staring at you.” The first is thoroughly
disconcerting, thoroughly disorganizing to the direction of inquiry. Suppose I
ask you your age, and, having been told, ask if it is so. The patient has clearly
shown his belief—or his intention that I shall understand—that people stared at
him. I am in no position to contradict this, even if I wished to do so. (p. 46)
This ability to meeting the patient where he is, taking him at face value, allows him to
remain involved in the interpersonal field because he can understand where the
conversation is going. It may seem paradoxical when Sullivan states: “The patient is a
stranger and is to be treated as a stranger” (p. 46), given his idea that we are always in
relation to the other. However, what this statement means is that we should treat the
patient as we would any other person that we meet for the first time, without making
assumptions about who they are, especially about their capacity for judging a situation
accurately. According to Sullivan, this openness to the other in participation and
attentive listening establishes the manner of access to the interpersonal patterns of the
patient, and with that an opportunity to examine what has remain conspicuously unseen
in his retreat from anxiety. Understanding the involvement of the analyst in this sense is
congruent with Sullivan’s consideration of the interpersonal field as an indissoluble unit
18
of analysis. There is a significant degree of consistency between his general theory of
personhood and his clinical theory:
This formulation of the therapeutic interaction is closely linked to Sullivan's
theoretical considerations. Sullivan was first and foremost a clinician and the
need for theoretical reformulation arose from his therapeutic experiences with
schizophrenics and obsessives. (Bruch, 1977 p. 348-349)
Arguably, this anticipates a “two-person psychology” (Silverman, 1996, p. 267)
in which both members of the therapeutic dyad are seen as having an effect on the
other. Mitchell (1988) sees this concept as the sine-qua-non of a relational approach to
psychoanalysis. Hirsch (2003) agrees with this noting that: “…the relational turn in
psychoanalysis began with Sullivan's (1953) shift in emphasis from a biologically or
instinctually dominated theory of the mind to one emphasizing exclusively the study of
interpersonal relationships as building blocks of the mind” (p. 224). However, it is
important to notice that Sullivan does not focus on the relationship, but on the patient’s
functioning. Relational psychoanalysis attempts to articulate what is going on between
the therapist and the patient, considering their relative contributions. Although this can
be characterized as an extension of Sullivan’s interpersonal psychiatry, is certainly
moves beyond its parameters. As such, Sullivan remains an influence that, although
shaped relational approaches significantly, cannot be simply equated with them. The
emphasis on the exploration of a joint subjective experience in relational psychoanalysis
19
likely owes to the influence of object relations approaches and their focus on subjective
experience.
Object Relations Theory
As early as 1981, Stephen Mitchell noted that: “object relations theory has
become one of the ubiquitous phrases within contemporary psychoanalytic literature”
(p. 374). Along the same lines, Ogden (1985) observed that: “…object relations theory
is not comprised of a discrete collection of principles; rather, it represents a diverse
collection of contributions that, in my opinion, have been developed in the context of
one of the most intense and fruitful of psychoanalytic dialogues” (p. 347). In this
regard, the development of relational approaches mirrors this phenomenon. Again, a
complete survey of object relations theory is beyond the scope of this work. Given that
the purpose is to illustrate the influence of object relations on relational psychoanalysis,
this work will follow Mitchell (1981, p. 375), and Mitchell & Black (1995, p. 112) who
identify W. R. D. Fairbairn, and D. W. Winnicott as central influences in object
relations theory. However, Mitchell and Black (1995) also note that: “…Melanie
Klein…provided the conceptual bridge between Freud and modern British object
relations theories” (p. 113). As such, a brief introduction to some of her concepts is in
order.
Melanie Klein
By most standards, Klein was a controversial figure whose thinking departed
considerably from Freud's, yet influenced psychoanalysis substantially. In fact, Mitchell
20
and Black (1995), note that: “Melanie Klein has had more impact on contemporary
psychoanalysis than any other psychoanalytic writer since Freud” (p. 85). Although her
contributions are lengthy and complex, her most significant contribution to the
development of a relational perspective is her expansion of the role of the object in
mental life. In this regard, Green (2000) comments that:
In the history of psychoanalysis, there was a turning point after which the object
left behind its status of referential exteriority. From then on, one was no longer
dealing simply with a phantasy object as in Freud, but with what Klein called
the internal object. It was no longer simply an object that could be seen from the
angle of phantasy, but an object forming the basis of the subject's internal
world… (p. 13)
Although Klein does not abandon Freudian metapsychology, she reconfigures it
in an important way. Green identifies at least two significant moves that take place in
Klein’s reconfiguration: the first is the internalization of the object. For Freud the object
is an external figure towards which the drive aims. Klein (1932), on the other hand, uses
the term object with a dual meaning, referring both to an external figure and to its
internalized psychic representation: “As far as can be seen, there exists in the small
child, side by side with its relations to real objects but on a different plane as it were,
relations which are based on its relations to its unreal imagos both as excessively good
and excessively bad figures. Ordinarily, these two kinds of object-relations intermingle
and colour each other to an ever increasing extent.” (p. 213). Guntrip (1965), concurring
21
with the importance of this transition, noted that: “It is this conception of human beings
living in two worlds at the same time, inner and outer, with mutual interference, that
makes Klein's work of such momentous importance…” (p. 258).
However, is it worth remembering, Ogden’s (2002) argument that the seeds of
this line of thought, indeed of the school of object relations itself, can be traced to
Freud’s developments in “Mourning and Melancholia” (p. 767). Mitchell (1981) lends
support to this view when he notes that: “…although he never employed the term
"internal object" as such, Freud, from the beginning of his work, had described clinical
phenomena involving internal "voices, " images, parental values, etc.” (p. 375).
Nevertheless, Klein’s contribution is her utilization of the object as an organizing
referent for the individual’s entire psychic life, which is Green’s second point in the
quote above. Klein is introducing an object not only as a form of mental content, but as
a structuring force in subjective experience. This development served as material for
Fairbairn’s work (Mitchel, 1981, p. 385), which nicely illustrates the way in which both
continuity and innovation occur as psychoanalytic theory unfolds through history.
Fairbairn, of course, would present a more radical challenge to the Freudian
metapsychology that Klein would not abandon.
W. R. D. Fairbairn
While Klein herself described her contributions as an extension of Freudian
metapsychology, Fairbairn departs from classical thinking more markedly:
“…Fairbairn's rejection of Freud's tripartite division of the psyche into ego, id, and
22
superego, and replacement of it with a theory of endopsychic structure based directly on
the vicissitudes of human object relatedness…is the crowning culmination of Fairbairn's
thinking” (Rubens, 1984, p. 429). This culmination rests on a general reworking of the
theory of the drives, and consequently a departure from Freud’s theory of motivation
(Mitchell & Black, 1995, p. 114). Beattie (2003) describes this theoretical shift by
noting that Freud held excitatory discharge motivated our behavior, while Fairbairn
believed that our intrinsic need for connection to others motivates us (p. 1172).
To understand this transition it is necessary to grasp Fairbairn and Freud’s
different views of the relationship between drives and objects. For Freud, our instinctual
life is centered on the pursuit of pleasure, which he defined as the discharge of
stimulation. According to Freud, we are organismically designed to discharge the build
up of excessive stimulation that creates a sensation of discomfort or pain. The object of
the instinct in this picture becomes secondary, acting solely as a means to the end of
pleasure seeking. In other words, I seek out other people so that I can regulate the way I
feel internally, but seeking out others is not considered an end in itself (Scharff &
Birtles, 1997, p. 1086). Fairbairn argues that the reverse is true and that Freud is
mistaken because he separates instinctual energy from the object it engages. He claims
instead that from the very beginning our instinct is to seek objects rather than pleasure
itself:
Fairbairn understood Freud's position to be a direct consequence of his divorcing
of energy from structure, for what goal could there be for structureless,
23
directionless energy other than indiscriminate discharge for the purpose of
homeostasis. For Fairbairn, having initially postulated the inseparability of
energy and structure, it followed that the goal (or aim) of self-expression could
no longer be viewed as mere tension reduction (the discharge of energy, ending
the 'unpleasure' of excitation and thereby definitionally resulting in pleasure)
with little or no reference to the object by means of which this discharge is
accomplished. Rather he completely inverted Freud's position, maintaining that
the relationship with the object was itself the goal, and that the pleasure involved
was a secondary consequence. (Rubens, 1984, p. 430)
As Mitchell (1981) notes, Fairbairn claims that we are constitutionally designed
to seek other people, and that: “…the main characteristic of libidinal energy is its
object-seeking quality”, adding that “…pleasure is not the end goal of the impulse, but a
means to its real end, relations with others.” (p. 386). This change speaks to the core of
a relational orientation in psychoanalysis in describing the individual as inherently
other-directed.
In spite of its significant influence on relational approaches, Fairbairn’s view of
intrapsychic life is not entirely equivalent with current relational thinking. He believed
that internal objects only arise as compensatory structures as a result of faulty parenting
(Carveth, 1996, p. 344). The child, in response to frustrating experiences with parents,
fantasizes about good objects that she cannot encounter in the real world. These
imagined others, or rather re-imagined others, are endopsychic structures split off from
24
the self that become necessary for maintaining a sense of connection with the frustrating
parent. On the other hand, when things are going well the child is outward directed
because it has no reason to create an internal replacement for an external object with
which she maintains a satisfying connection. However, as Rubens (1984), points out:
“…internal structural differentiation is a clearly pathological, albeit unavoidable,
schizoid phenomenon which, to varying extents, diminishes the functioning of all
human beings” (p. 434). According to Fairbairn, we all develop endopsychic structures
because, to one degree or another, we all experience frustration and suffering as part of
the human condition. But what about the internalization of good experiences with
others? If no endopsychic structure is formed in these cases, how does Fairbairn believe
that we internalize those structures? Apparently, Fairbairn did not elaborate on healthy
development as much as he did on pathology, but he does argue that the internalization
of good objects becomes part of an idealized object that is consciously integrated into
the self (Rubens, 1984, p. 435). This dimension of his theory remained somewhat
underdeveloped. Nevertheless, experiences with others, whether healthy or not, become
the foundation of a person’s internal life and act as the basis for all motivation and
behavior. For Fairbairn, relationships with others are the structuring blocks of
subjective and interpersonal life.
D. W. Winnicott
Winnicott is widely regarded as a deeply original contributor to psychoanalysis
whose clinical style, as Ogden (2001) remarked, was mirrored in his writing style, itself
25
permeated by paradox and play (p. 299; Modell, 1985, p. 113). It is challenging to
present a systematic account of his work because his thinking is elusive at times. As
Kwawer (1998) points out: “Winnicott's writing always lends itself, in my experience,
to adoption by readers of various persuasions; like ambiguous cloud formations in the
summer sky” (p. 389). From the vantage point of examining his influence on relational
approaches, there are a number of concepts that become relevant. Among them,
Winnicott’s emphasis on subjectivity and the mother-infant dyad appear most relevant
because of their direct association with relational ideas.
In many ways prefiguring self-psychology (Bodin, 1994, p. 41), Winnicott
utilizes the concept of self as one central axis in his work. In his view, the possibility of
developing a healthy self is mediated by an appropriate developmental process, which
involves the mother's capacity to establish a responsive attunement to the child’s needs
(Bodin, 1994, p. 45). According to Winnicott, the infant initially exists in a space of
subjective omnipotence where there is no discontinuity between needs and their
satisfaction. For example, when a baby cries in hunger the mother immediately satisfies
this need and as a result the baby experiences herself as omnipotent. In order for this to
work, the mother renounces her subjectivity to concern herself only, or at least
primarily, with her infant’s needs: “In Winnicott’s view, the mother is not in her right
mind. The state of primary maternal preoccupation is a constructive kind of temporary
madness that enables the mother to suspend her own subjectivity to become the medium
for the development of the subjectivity of the infant” (Mitchell & Black, 1995, p. 126).
26
As a result, the baby cannot be considered an independent entity with its own mind in
this stage of development. Ogden (2001) notes that: “The baby ‘does not mind’ because
the mother is there “minding” him (taking care of him)” (p. 309-310). This is the reason
behind Winnicott’s (1975) radical assertion that there is no baby in isolation, only a
baby-mother dyad (p. xxxvii). Of course this assertion presupposes the concept of a
relational space or joint subjectivity that a self-other dyad occupies, a concept that will
influence relational approaches. However, for Winnicott this initial enmeshment gives
place, in healthy development, to a process of individuation that ends when one is able
to be alone. As Ogden (1985) notes, this process takes place through the gradual
introduction of frustrations that allow the infant to have desires for what is not readily
available: “The delaying of the infant's awareness of separateness is achieved in large
part by means of the mother's meeting of the infant's need before need becomes desire.
The infant without desire is neither a subject nor an object: there is not yet an infant” (p.
350-351). When the infant begins to notice the rupture between need and fulfillment
introduced by gradual frustrations, this need becomes a desire and the infant gradually
becomes a subject confronted by an object over which it does not have omnipotent
control.
Through this process of frustrations, the child learns to inhabit the objective
world after passing through a transitional period. Gradually the infant is pushed by the
mother’s normal imperfections to acknowledge the reality of others. However, this
movement is not merely one “…from dependence to independence, but the transition
27
between two different patterns of positioning the self in relation to others” (Mitchell &
Black, 1995, p. 128). In spite of this growth towards individuation, the healthy adult
never fully abandons a sense of core omnipotence and fantastic fusion with the maternal
image. This core sense acts as a reservoir of coping resources to which she returns in
period of stress that require creative adaptation to new situations. Within relational
approaches, Mitchell shares this view of a core self that anchors identity and underlies
the changing self in development across the lifespan. According to Winnicott, however,
the healthy self is able to fluctuate between a fused and individuated positions but does
not rigidly adheres to either one (Mitchell & Black, 1995, p. 128).
What remains somewhat unclear in Winnicott is his definition of an internal
object and intrapsychic life. Whereas Fairbairn delineates what he means by
endopsychic structures and ideal objects, it is not clear in Winnicott whether there is
such a precise process of internal formation of the self. Kwawer (1998) suggests that
Winnicott’s concept of object use provides a platform to understand his thinking in this
area:
Winnicott had written hintingly about this elusive concept of object use several
years earlier, offering the provocative and foretelling idea that there is a stage of
personal development beyond object relating, calling this the stage of “object
use”; he notes that the question of what the appropriate environmental provision
is during the stage of object usage is not yet clearly understood. In proposing the
notion of “object use,” Winnicott is beginning to find his own voice, apart the
28
focus on an object-relations analysis (or in other words, the analysis of
transference as a subjective phenomenon created by the patient). If this sounds
like the conceptual shift from thinking about the transference relationship to one
that encompasses the real relationship…(p394-395)
If Kwawer suggestion is correct and Winnicott thinks about a stage beyond
internal object relating into real object relating, then this would align him more closely
to the interpersonal tradition of Harry Stack Sullivan. Kuriloff (1988) argues for such an
affinity stating that: “Both Winnicott and Sullivan, if viewed through a particular lens,
help the patient to renounce omnipotence, to tolerate subjectivity, to bear what the
family has made toxic, unbearable, split off, distorted, because the therapist is willing to
act in ways that illustrate and generate tolerance and survival, paving the way for him to
be ‘used’ and used well” (p. 388). However, he adds that there are differences as well
between Sullivan and Winnicott’s goals wherein the former tries to help the patient gain
awareness of interpersonal patterns of relatedness and the latter: “hopes to aid in the
creative apperception of the world, so that the place between what is real and illusory
becomes a lively and creative experience” (p. 380). The blurred distinction between real
and illusion remains an important concept in relational psychoanalysis, particularly its
postmodern variants. Indeed, most relational thinking would take issue with Sullivan’s
concept of an objective world that the analyst helps the patient see. Instead, something
like a Winnicottian view of internal subjectivity ends up winning out in relational
perspectives.
29
Winnicott’s characterization of a true self that originates in the child’s
spontaneity helps elucidate how he thinks of intrapsychic experience. He notes that
when the mother appropriately meets this spontaneity of gesture, the child is allowed
the illusion of omnipotence. In time this illusion is given up, yet it always remains as
the basis for a generative creativity that underlies healthy experience. For Winnicott,
illusion appears to be the ability to conceive of something as what it is not, without
letting go completely of what it is. This core or true self cannot be a composite of
internal objects, but rather a way of relating to others and the world at large. Winnicott
does not abandon, however, a more classic idea of the intrapsychic as an internal
subjective space distinct from an external world. He maintains that there is a private self
that we can never fully access:
Winnicott here puts forward the view that in every human being, at the core of
every person there is a secret self, an 'incommunicado element' which is for ever
silent. He assumes that even in the healthy individual there is a core of
personality which never communicates with the objectively perceived objects
and, further, that the individual person knows that there can never be a
communicating with this core and that it will also have to remain unreachable by
external reality. (Schacht, 1988, p. 527)
This private self remains at the core inaccessible to objects and remains a
somewhat mysterious element of his theorizing, which seems to be incongruent with a
relational approach.
30
However, Winnicott’s dramatic attunement to the needs of the client, his ability
to be deeply engrossed and participate in the subjectivity of the client, is an important
area of resonance he shares with relational approaches. Additionally, his notion of a
position that structures the relationships of the self is consistent with relational notions
of internalized relational configurations. Perhaps most importantly, Winnicott
designates the ability to truly recognize the other in their objective existence as a marker
of healthy development. This is a radical acknowledgement of a two-person approach to
psychology that underlies relational views.
Therapeutic dimensions of Fairbairn and Winnicott
Harry Guntrip is another important theorist closely associated with the object
relations movement (Sutherland, 1980). In addition to the contributions he made to this
psychoanalytic approach, another claim to fame he possessed is having been analyzed
by both Winnicott and Fairbairn (Guntrip, 1996; Hazell, 1991). In a paper entitled My
Experience Of Analysis With Fairbairn And Winnicott: (How Complete A Result Does
Psychoanalytic Therapy Achieve?), Guntrip details his experiences as an analysand with
both clinicians: “I had just over 1,000 sessions with Fairbairn in the 1950s and just over
150 with Winnicott in the 1960s. For my own benefit I kept detailed records of every
session with both of them, and all their correspondence.” (Guntrip, 1996, p. 740). This
presents a unique platform from which to explore the therapeutic technique of Fairbairn
and Winnicott. In addition, it allows an opportunity to investigate the relationship of
their theory and clinical practice. However, given the complexity of these questions,
31
what follows should be considered an initial direction for research rather than a
systematic account.
Guntrip (1996) observes that he came to analysis already knowing Freud’s work
intimately and having abandoned what he termed Freud’s “psychobiology of instincts”
(p. 748) to focus on his theory of psychopathology. In spite of his scholarly interest in
psychoanalysis, Guntrip’s (1996) interest in psychoanalytic treatment was to gain relief
from personal suffering rather than to develop new theoretical avenues. From Guntrip’s
(1996) point of view, however, this distinction might not be valid given his view of the
relationship between theory and practice: “…on the difficult question of the sources of
theory, it seems that our theory must be rooted in our psychopathology.” (p. 753).
Furthermore, he notes that: “…theory does not seem to me to be the major concern. It is
a useful servant but a bad master, liable to produce orthodox defenders of every variety
of the faith.” (p. 739). Guntrip is comfortable viewing and presenting himself as a
patient because he does not find that this role conflicts with being a therapist.
Guntrip arrives to psychoanalytic treatment complaining of suffering from a
recurring debilitating illness that is triggered by experiences of death or abandonment.
This, he observes, originated from an early childhood experience:
…at 3½ I walked into a room and saw Percy lying naked and dead on her lap. I
rushed up and grabbed him and said: ‘Don't let him go. You'll never get him
back!’ She sent me out of the room and I fell mysteriously ill and was thought to
be dying. Her doctor said: ‘He's dying of grief for his brother. If your mother wit
32
can't save him, I can't’, so she took me to a maternal aunt who had a family, and
there I recovered. (p. 746)
Noting that he is amnesic for these events, he tells us that he learned about this
incident from his mother’s report. Guntrip also comments that his mother was often
aggressive and withdrawn with him. Her relationship with her sons was so problematic
that his young brother died because she refused to breast-feed him. Later in life, Guntrip
adds, his mother would complain of regretting having had children at all.
These are the themes that Guntrip explores in his therapy with Fairbairn, and his
description of their work together is rich and telling. Guntrip often characterizes
Fairbairn as intent on providing “his very intellectually precise interpretations” about
the dynamics with his mother and brother (p. 744). Contact of a more personal nature,
however, was reserved for extra-analytic activities: “…after sessions we could discuss
and I could find the natural warm-hearted human being behind the exact interpreting
analyst.” (p. 745). Guntrip presents Fairbairn as an orthodox therapist who does not
work directly on building a relationship. This, Guntrip comments, is incompatible with
Fairbairn’s theoretical beliefs, as he explicitly stated that the relationship is a central
ingredient in treatment. Guntrip writes about Fairbairn that “…on another occasion he
said: ‘You can go on analysing for ever and get no- where. It's the personal relation that
is therapeutic’” and that “…he held that psychoanalytic interpretation is not therapeutic
per se, but only as it expresses a personal relationship of genuine understanding.” (p.
741). Mitchell and Black (1995) also report that Fairbairn believed developing a new
33
form of relatedness, not a set of insights, was the motor for change in the patient (p.
122). Yet Guntrip experienced Fairbairn as a technical interpreter, and even though he
indicated feeling conceptually understood at times, he complained of lacking a lived
sense of an open and personal relationship. His account of their last session certainly
gives the impression that their intimacy was restrained: “As I was finally leaving
Fairbairn after the last session, I suddenly realized that in all that long period we had
never once shaken hands, and he was letting me leave without that friendly gesture. I
put out my hand and at once he took it, and I suddenly saw a few tears trickle down his
face.” (p. 745). Such a moving account of their termination speaks to a depth of feeling
in Fairbairn that was not expressed or acknowledged before. This suggests that there is
an incongruity between Fairbairn’s therapeutics and his theory. Indeed, Crastnopol
(2001) confirms that Guntrip: “…was deeply frustrated and injured by his analyst's
communicative style, which was indeed quite restrained and at times somewhat
mechanical, notwithstanding the fact that Fairbairn had written about and must have
believed in the theoretical importance of the analyst providing the patient with a good,
warm personal relationship.” (p. 128).
It is not clear how to resolve this tension between Fairbairn’s writing and his
disposition in analysis with Guntrip. Mitchell and Black (1995) suggest a plausible
answer when they note that Fairbairn was not specific about the process through which
the patient changes the way she experiences the analyst from a bad object to a healthy
one (p. 122). Fairbairn’s idea that genuine understanding should be conveyed in the
34
interpreting process suggests that perhaps he believed interpretation was the primary
medium for building relationships with patients. In spite of his emphasis on the
relationship as a therapeutic agent, he still resorts to interpretation as a primary tool.
Perhaps this illustrates how the pull for continuity with our tradition and influences can
sometimes overpower our push for innovation. Undoubtedly, Guntrip’s analysis with
Fairbairn demonstrates that we don’t always find an unproblematic relationship between
theory and practice in which one wholly encapsulates and expresses the other.
Recognizing the incompleteness in this relationship can provide the clinician with a
useful corrective for theoretical dogmatism or pragmatic naiveté.
In addition to complaining about his lack of personal warmth, Guntrip (1996)
also took issue with Fairbairn’s theoretical approach in their work. Guntrip
acknowledged that Fairbairn helped him work through the internalized bad objects that
he developed from the trauma with his mother. However, he also felt that beneath these
difficulties lay another deeper issue which Winnicott was able to access because of his
wider theoretical horizon: “…I had had a radical analysis with Fairbairn of the
‘internalised bad-object defences’ I had built up against that, but we had not got down
to what I felt was my basic problem, not the actively bad-object mother of later
childhood, but the earlier mother who failed to relate at all” (p. 747). In this regard,
Winnicott’s theory opened a therapeutic region that was not available to Fairbairn.
Guntrip credits Winnicott with the theoretical insight that his trauma occurred
before his brother’s death, dating back to his mother’s initial inability to relate to him or
35
his brother. Guntrip believed that Winnicott’s willingness to let him regress to the stage
of that trauma allowed him to work through those issues and internalize a good object.
According to Guntrip, Winnicott facilitated this experience because he found:
“…content and interpretations were nearly irrelevant…what was crucial was experience
of the self in relation to the other” (Mitchell & Black, 1995, p. 134). On this basis,
Winnicott attempts to provide an environment in which the patient’s subjectivity can be
regenerated. As a result, Guntrip can transform his sense of internal deadness through
Winnicott’s warm and protective relationship, which he had lacked from Fairbairn.
Among many things, Guntrip’s description of his work with Winnicott
illustrates that practice is not always the unimpeded expression of theoretical principles.
Guntrip notices that Fairbairn was: “…more orthodox in practice than in theory while
Winnicott was more revolutionary in practice than in theory.” (p. 742). This suggests it
is possible to be clinically competent without theoretically lucid. Kwawer (1998) lends
support to this view by arguing that Winnicott’s originality was not fully captured in his
theoretical writing:
‘Winnicott’, I always find myself wondering, ‘why do you have to speak Freud
or Klein? You're always more engaging to me and more clinically relevant when
you speak in your own voice.’ Indeed, I think Winnicott was engaged in a
lifelong and largely unsuccessful struggle to free himself from the powerful
emotional, political, and probably economic constraints of orthodoxy, both
Freudian and Kleinian. (p. 394)
36
All the richness of a therapeutic encounter can potentially remain inarticulate, or
worse, misinterpreted, if there is no appropriate language to express it. However, the
reverse is also true given that clinical practice can be misguided without a conceptual
framework to organize and understand clinical phenomena. Kohut (1977) argued as
much when he introduced theoretical developments that, in his view, responded to a
need to appropriately grasp the phenomenon of narcissism.
Self-Psychology
Kernberg (1997) sustains that Kohut’s developments provided an important
basis for the emergence of a relational approach:
Parallel to what I have characterized as the “mainstream” development, there
has been (especially in the United States) a rapprochement between approaches
derived from self psychology on one hand and the culturalist psychoanalytic
tradition expressed in contemporary interpersonal psychoanalysis on the other.
(p. 99)
Kernberg then argues that the shift away from classical analytic concepts owes
much to Kohut’s emphasis on the self-object transferences as a focus of treatment (p.
99). In this framework, the function of the analyst becomes providing the right kind of
experience, then internalized by the patient, by being carefully emotionally attuned to
the patient. Certainly the intersubjective school of relational psychoanalysis headed by
Stolorow, Atwood, and Orange (1999), argues the same when they intend to “paint a
portrait of Heinz Kohut as a pivotal transitional figure in the development of a post37
Cartesian, fully contextual psychoanalytic psychology that recognizes the constitutive
role of relatedness in the making of all experience.” (p. 381). Agreeing with Kernberg,
they note that Kohut’s emphasizes on subjective experience led them to a contextual
view of treatment and personhood (p. 381). Goldberg (2002) also notes self-psychology
in its ongoing evolution has played a role in “other psychoanalytic excursions such as
seen in interpersonal and social constructivist concepts” (p. 2).
In spite of the centrality of his role in contemporary psychoanalytic developments,
Kohut trained as a traditional psychoanalyst, even presenting his initial findings in the
context of official psychoanalytic circles (Meronen, 1999, p. 211). Furthermore, his
early work presented empathic observation as an addition to classical approaches, not
as a replacement. Kohut did not present empathy as a replacement psychoanalytic
methodology, and he noted Freud himself was a pioneer in the use of empathy, thus
establishing a sense of continuity with the tradition (Kohut, 1959, p. 463-464).
Eventually, Grotstein (1999) argues, Kohut would become the profession’s Luther
spearheading a reformation with empathy as its main thesis (p. 123). Indeed, Kohut
(1979) presents his approach, which he calls a “psychoanalytic psychology of the self”
(p. 3), as an alternative to classical analysis. Ultimately, his later work provided deep
theoretical revisions centering on a transfiguration of the role of narcissism in
development and of the view of personhood in general.
38
In his paper Thoughts on Narcissism and Narcissistic Rage, Kohut (1972) outlines
the basic tenets of his theory. Glassman (1988) states that Kohut viewed childhood
narcissism as a normal developmental stage that requires an “affirmative attitude” from
the analyst—both clinically and theoretically-- because it grounds the possibility for
maturity and growth. When the child—and the also the narcissistic patient—is not
provided with experiences of empathic attunement that gratify her narcissistic needs,
then the self becomes fragmented leading to experiences of emptiness and impoverished
subjectivity. But appropriate empathic responses facilitate healthy development: “In
order to relieve feelings of helplessness, the infant requires the parent to serve as a
"selfobject," i.e., an object that can perform psychological tasks such as tension
management and self-esteem regulation that the infant is unable to perform for itself.”
(p. 601).
In this model, caregivers are self-objects, extensions of the child’s self that perform
certain functions that the child is unable to do. Self-objects are like appropriate
scaffolding on which developmental experiences rests. The primary function of the selfobject is to be empathically attuned to the growing infant thus allowing feelings of
grandiosity and merger to “ward off the threat of disorganization in the face of
helplessness.” (Glassman, 1988, p. 601). Consequently, a child without these
developmental experiences remains fragmented and unable to manage distressing and
disorganizing affect. The healthy individual has been afforded the opportunity to
39
internalize good self-object experiences and thus grow into an autonomous maturity. In
Kohut’s (1972) own words:
…the experiences during the period of the formation of the self become the
prototype of the specific forms of our later vulnerability and security in the
narcissistic realm: of the ups and downs in our self-esteem; of our lesser or
greater need for praise, for merger into idealized figures, and for other forms of
narcissistic sustenance; and of the greater or lesser cohesion of our self during
periods of transition, whether in the transition to latency, in early or late
adolescence, in maturity, or in old age. (p. 369)
These changes eventually led Kohut to reconfigure even the most central of
psychoanalytic concepts, the oedipal conflict. First of all, Kohut (1982) diminishes the
centrality of the oedipal stage—which he differentiates from oedipal conflict-- as “only
a link, and not the deepest one at that, in a causal chain” in development (p. 402). But
more importantly, he challenges the idea that the oedipal conflict is normative. He
posits instead that: “pathological 'Oedipus complex' (as distinguished from the normal
'oedipal stage' of development) refers not to the essence of man but, that they are
deviations from the normal, however frequently they may occur…” (p. 402). Normal
experience involves not intergenerational strife but collaborative maturation. For Kohut,
the basis of his disagreement with Freud rests on holding radically different concepts of
what a human being is. According to Kohut, Freud introduces a “Guilty Man”; an
40
individual eternally conflicted by tensions between his biology and the limitations of
reality, a view grounded in a naturalistic view of personhood. Kohut argues instead that
man is a tragic figure, marred by his difficulty fulfilling the promise of early
developmental experiences. Kohut (1982) believes that man is a “homo psychologicus”,
and not “homo natura” like Freud suggests (p. 402).
Self-Psychology and Clinical Practice
In 1979, Kohut published The Two analysis of Mr. Z, a vivid portrayal of the
differences that theoretical approaches can have on therapeutic conceptualization,
technique, and outcome. This work illustrates the differences between his approach and
the traditional psychoanalytic framework. In doing so, he utilizes an underlying view
about the relationship between theory and practice in psychoanalysis that is worth
articulating. To put it briefly, he believes that a theoretical approach allows us to let
relevant material call our attention. In this sense, a theory provides us with the right
kind of seeing, and also the corresponding appropriate response to what is manifest. In
turn, clinical practice challenges our theoretical framework and can reformulate it,
albeit only if we let it. This reciprocal movement is illustrated in Kohut’s description of
his analytic work.
Mr. Z is a young graduate student who presents with somatic complaints,
feelings of social isolation, and inability to establish relationships with women. In spite
of these difficulties, he had managed to achieve a certain balance in his life through his
relationship with his mother and a close friend. However, this equilibrium was disrupted
41
when his friend began a relationship with an older woman, prompting Mr. Z to seek
treatment. In addition to his initial presentation, Mr. Z’s history is significant because
his father left when he was 3 years old to be with another woman, but returned home
approximately 2 years later. Lastly, Kohut mentions almost in passing, a camp
counselor sexually abused Mr. Z at age 11 and this relationship was maintained for a
period of 2 years. It is worth noting that the slight attention this last event receives in
Kohut's paper also reveals the effect a theoretical framework has on treatment approach.
Kohut notes that initially during therapy, Mr. Z often brought up feelings of
entitlement and moments of palpable rage:
He blew up in rages against me, time after time—indeed the picture he presented
during the first year and a half of the analysis was dominated by his rage. These
attacks arose either in response to my interpretations concerning his narcissistic
demands and his arrogant feelings of 'entitlement' or because of such
unavoidable frustrations as weekend interruptions, occasional irregularities in
the schedule, or, especially, my vacations. (p. 5)
Kohut interpreted this dynamic as Mr. Z’s attempt to return to a pre-oedipal
fusion with the mother in which he held and expected her attention exclusively:
“Formulated in the traditional terms of early object relations, we would say that this
phase of the analysis revived the conditions of the period when, in early childhood, he
had been alone with his mother, who was ready to provide him with the bliss of
narcissistic fulfillment at all times.” (p. 14). This childhood experience was a form of
42
“overgratification” (p. 14) that instilled in Mr. Z a sense of entitlement and a fixation on
this stage. In this narrative, the return of the father represents a challenge, and
eventually a defeat, from which he defended himself by retreating into the illusion of
his narcissism: “…I interpreted the persistence of defensive narcissism as it protected
him against the painful awareness of the powerful rival who possessed his mother
sexually and against the castration anxiety to which an awareness of his own
competitive and hostile impulses towards the rival would have exposed him.” (p. 6). As
a result of this classic conceptualization, the therapist role is to help the patient
relinquish this narcissistic defense by means of insight oriented interpretations and
working through the resistance, so that repressed oedipal wished can come to the fore.
Kohut reports that he accomplished this and Mr. Z’s rages diminished while his
capacity to sustain relationships with women improved, and this marked the ending of
the first analysis of Mr. Z. All the pieces of this analysis fit together with “logical
cohesiveness” and “seemed impeccable”, completely consistent with the “precepts that
were then firmly established in me as almost unquestionable inner guidelines in
conducting my therapeutic work.” (p. 9). But in the face of such rotund clinicaltheoretical success, Kohut felt dissatisfied with an aspect of the termination. Mr. Z had
failed to show emotional depth through termination, which stood in stark contrast with
the rest of his emotional experience through the analysis. Curiously, Kohut found this
difficult to articulate at that point: “What was wrong at that time was much harder to
43
describe than what seemed to be right” (p. 9). It is as if the theory was telling him that
they were done yet their experience did not reflect that.
Indeed, Mr. Z contacted Kohut several years later and began the second analysis
that would follow a different set of guidelines. Mr. Z returned to analysis complaining
of a lack of satisfaction with his life: his relationships were shallow and he could not
derive pleasure from his work in spite of his success. Exploring his current situation led
to an analysis of Mr. Z’s relationship with his mother, who turned out to have a serious
personality disturbance of her own. Mr. Z’s difficult childhood experiences of being
dominated and controlled by his mother had left him with a chronic feeling of
depression and hopelessness, something the oedipal narrative failed to pick up: “…this
traditional pattern of explanations fails to do justice to… an underlying chronic despair
which could often be felt side by side with the arrogance of his demandingness” (p. 14).
According to Kohut, Mr. Z’s depression resulted from a lack of developmental
experiences in which his autonomy was facilitated. Instead, his mother’s need for
control turned him into an extension of her, and her love for him was always conditional
on his willingness to play this role. However, it wasn’t the desire to perpetuate this
pattern that rooted his pathology—as classical psychoanalysis would hold. These
experiences, and the developmental arrest that they afforded, were pathological in
themselves. The analysis provided a restorative space where these could be discussed
and eventually opened up the possibility of Mr. Z identifying with his father through the
recollection of positive memories of them. The narrative structuring the analysis is
44
radically different than the previous one. Whereas the expectation before was to help
the patient face a painful reality, Kohut now sees his role as providing empathic
attunement as a catalyst for growth:
I relinquished the health- and maturity-morality that had formerly motivated me,
and restricted myself to the task of reconstructing the early stages of his
experiences, particularly as they concerned his enmeshment with the
pathological personality of the mother. And when we now contemplated the
patient's self in the rudimentary state in which it came to view in the
transference, we no longer saw it as resisting change or as opposing maturation
because it did not want to relinquish its childish gratifications, but, on the
contrary, as desperately—and often hopelessly—struggling to disentangle itself
from the noxious selfobject, to delimit itself, to grow, to become independent.
(p. 12)
Furthermore, with the classical theoretical framework came a certain disposition
towards Mr. Z: “I can still remember the slightly ironical tone of my voice, meant to
assist him in overcoming his childish grandiosity…” (Kohut, 1979, p. 14). In the first
analysis, these interventions were met with instances of rage. Yet Mr. Z noted that,
during the first analysis itself, he was able to overcome his feelings of rage when Kohut
provided the following interpretation: “Of course, it hurts when one is not given what
one assumes to be one's due” (p. 5).
45
Within this different therapeutic horizon, Mr. Z was able to achieve a sense of
independence and full self-hood. The marker for therapeutic success in the second
analysis became Mr. Z’s greater capacity for understanding and compassion, not the
logical coherence of the approach from a theoretical perspective.
The preceding paragraphs explore Kohut’s self-psychology in clinical practice
in contradistinction to a classical approach. We can observe the way in which the
therapeutic interaction is guided by a theoretical principle in each analysis, and how
they lead to different paths. But Kohut does not articulate explicitly the way theory and
practice relate to each other. Nevertheless, he does present useful case information
from which to make inferences about this relationship. Upon reflecting on the first
analysis, from the vantage point of having finished the second, Kohut recognizes that:
“Crucial material…had indeed appeared, but…it had failed to claim our attention”
(Kohut, 1979, p. 15). What Kohut appears to be saying is that what counted as crucial
was different in the first analysis, and as a result the important material remained
unexplored. Thus, having a background understanding of what counts as relevant, and
what is peripheral, is what permits clinical phenomena to “claim our attention”. It is
also telling that he does not speak of the clinician intentionally directing her attention,
but rather about the conditions that make it possible for clinicians to be called by the
appropriate phenomena. But this begs the question of how we are ever able to shift from
one theoretical horizon to the next, if they are so determinative of what appears as
46
relevant clinical phenomena. Indeed, Kohut claims to have been able to change
paradigms, so on what basis was he able to do so?
Kohut’s dissatisfaction with the ending of the first analysis provides a telling
clue. As mentioned above, even though everything about the analysis made sense from
a theoretical perspective, his experience of Mr. Z’s emotional thinness during
termination left him perplexed. Somehow this datum was claiming his attention, even if
his background theoretical understanding was not flagging it as relevant. From this it
follows that theory need not exhaust nor determine the interpretive possibilities present
before us. The therapeutic encounter, however guided by theory, does not have to
remain within its confines, and often it does not. This is precisely what permits Kohut to
work beyond classical interpretations by remaining open to the experience of the
therapeutic encounter. We can see evidence of this concrete openness in the following
paragraph, when he details how he shifts interpretive strategies when the client
repeatedly asks personal information about him:
…I did concede that, after listening to him further and watching his reactions, I
had to agree with him that the term 'curiosity' that I had been using had not been
right—that what he was experiencing now was not a revival of sexual voyeurism
of childhood but some different need. And I finally ventured the guess that it
was his need for a strong father that lay behind his questions, that he wanted to
know whether I, too, was weak—subdued in intercourse by my wife, unable to
be the idealizable emotional support of a son” (Kohut, 1979, p. 15).
47
Only after “listening” and “watching his reactions” was Kohut able to provide
an account that made sense to both himself and his client. What Kohut does not seem to
grasp is that, because of the openness that permitted this revision, this interpretation
itself is subject to further revisions given the right circumstances. Instead, Kohut
dismantles classical orthodoxy to quickly assemble his own. But his account of the
movement from one to the other helps understand how theory and practice coexist in a
dialogical and mutually constitutive relationship.
48
Chapter 2: Relational Psychoanalysis
Introduction
Ghent (1992) identifies the series of events that shaped the relational perspective
and allowed it to emerge concretely from the matrix of its influences. First, he notes that
the brewing ground for this thinking occurred in the NYU Doctoral Program in Clinical
Psychology where: “the academic values of scholarship, diversity of thinking, efforts at
integration and synthesis, and, above all, open discourse” were fostered (p. xv). Within
this openness, Ghent sees two important works that stimulated integrative discussion
around the concept of relationality. One was Merton Gill’s (1983) paper: The point of
view in psychoanalysis: Energy discharge or person?, in which he introduces the
concept of a “person point of view” that incorporates insights from interpersonal and
self-psychology traditions (p. xv). The second is Greenberg and Mitchell’s (1983) book:
Object Relations in Psychoanalytic Theory, which also attempted to survey and
integrate different approaches around ideas of relationality. Finally, Ghent notes, the
development of a relational track in the aforementioned postdoctoral program, and the
founding of the journal Psychoanalytic Dialogues: A Journal of Relational Perspective,
gave more institutional substance to the burgeoning movement. However, defining with
precision just what relational psychoanalysis is proves more difficult than tracking its
development and influences.
As mentioned before, rather than a coherent approach to psychoanalytic theory
and practice, relational psychoanalysis is a:
49
…tradition (that) has emerged within American psychoanalysis with a
particular set of concerns, concepts, approaches, and sensibilities. It
operates as a shared subculture within the more general psychoanalytic
culture, not by design, but because it has struck deep, common chords
among current clinical practitioners and theorists in this country
(Mitchell & Aron, 1999, p. xii).
This tradition is composed of various psychoanalytic subgroups that emphasize
the importance that relationships and social context have in the constitution of the
psyche. In the quote above, Mitchell and Aron suggest that there was no design in the
development of this movement, but rather a recognition of similar goals as an organic
process throughout various camps (p. x). Berman (1997) notes that: "Relational
psychoanalysis is not a new school, but rather a broad integrative orientation focusing
on Self and Other” (p. 185). This leaves room for ample heterogeneity and
disagreement within the relational psychoanalytic movement, which consequently spans
various fields including postmodernism, intersubjectivity, and gender theorizing, among
others.
As previously mentioned, in spite of the decentralized character of the
movement, Stephen Mitchell is generally recognized as its informal leader. In his early
work with Greenberg (1983) they first proposed the categorization of psychoanalytic
theorizing into two camps: those models that emphasize the drives as the building
blocks of the psyche, and those that recognized the primacy of human relationships in
50
the constitution of mind. Admittedly, there are some limitations with such a dichotomy
as it risks falling into simplistic and crass categorizing. Mitchell’s success, however,
lies in his ability to name a real phenomenon in the unfolding of psychoanalytic
theorizing. In this respect, Eagle and Wolitzky (in Freedheim, 1992) comment that:
To a significant extent, the history of theoretical developments in
psychoanalysis can be understood as a series of successive reactions to
Freudian drive theory, with its emphasis on libidinal and aggressive
wishes as the primary motives for behavior. Thus, following Pine (1990),
the main foci of theorizing in psychoanalysis subsequent to drive
theory—ego, object, and self—can be meaningfully viewed as entailing
modification or abandonment of that drive theory. These theoretical
developments gave greater primacy to interpersonal and social
determinants of personality development and psychopathology (p. 105).
Mitchell’s contribution rests in his recognition of this trend, but extends beyond
this, because he challenged, developed, and integrated pivotal notions within it.
Consequently, an account of relational psychoanalysis requires a presentation of
Mitchell’s views.
Nevertheless, the heterogeneity of the movement does not allow one to present
only Mitchell’s views. There are others contributors to a relational perspective, whose
views don’t always agree with Mitchell’s own. As he points out, the term relational
“grew and began to accrue to itself many other influences and developments: later
51
advances of self psychology, particularly intersubjectivity theory; social constructivism
in its various forms; certain currents within contemporary psychoanalytic hermeneutics;
more recent developments in gender theorizing…” (Mitchell & Aron 1999, p. xi). A
systematic exposition of all these views lies well beyond the scope of this work. In
order to present shared assumptions and theoretical diversity in the relational approach,
two other camps--selected for their potential to widen and pose interesting challenges to
Mitchell’s approach--will be explored, following a more lengthy exposition of
Mitchell’s own work.
The intersubjective approach of Stolorow (1995) and colleagues stands out as a
significant contribution. Trained in the Kohutian School of self-psychology, these
theorists have proposed a widening of psychoanalytic conceptions based on the
continental philosophy of Martin Heidegger and others. Their main concern resides in
overcoming the Cartesian heritage of psychoanalytic conceptions of mind. On another
end of the spectrum, psychoanalytic gender theorizing also surfaces as an important
subgroup of the relational approach. The social constructionist bent of their specific
views at times collides with Mitchell’s position, but the emphasis on the social
construction of the self—particularly our notions of gender identity—constitute
important examples of relationality in psychoanalysis. Within gender theorists, Nancy
Chodorow and Lynne Layton are particularly relevant for their attempt to integrate
postmodern thinking with clinical practice and relational theory (Dimen & Goldner,
2002).
52
All these thinkers share an understanding of the inadequacy of the Freudian
drive model. They read Freud as defending that endogenous forces shape the mind
almost exclusively. According to them, Freud holds that the determining character of
our biological make up pushes from the inside out and finds fulfillment in an external
social world. Mitchell (1988) notes relationships are not considered to be direct
causative factors of mental structure in Freud’s model, being at best a catalyst for the
expression of internal drives. Mitchell (1999) sees in this a problematic
decontextualization of the nature of desire and the development of the mind. Congruent
with this critique, Gender theorists often complain about Freud’s essentialism, which
reifies socially constructed gender stereotypes into natural categories. Finally, the
intersubjectivists argue that Freud’s drive model is a direct extension of Cartesian
postulates, which brings with it the ensuing problems of presenting the mind as isolated
and separate from an external world. Each view is a variation on a common theme: a
rejection of Freud’s drive model as reductive and distorting of the inextricable social
nature of selfhood. However, there are also notable differences between these positions
which, if brought into dialogue, can possibly bring about important theoretical crossfertilization.
What follows then is an exposition of these three views, with some
consideration for their origins, points of contacts, and disagreements. This analysis will
serve to represent some of the basic contributions of relational psychoanalysis as a
group, but also to understand important differences between these positions in order to
53
open up a dialogue aiming to refine them. Ultimately, it will be argued that their best
insights can be properly grasped and integrated by attending to a wider philosophical
horizon. Certain points of contact between the work of relational psychoanalysis and the
theoretical psychology of Martin and Sugarman constitute helpful and important
stepping-stones towards a wider integrating vision.
Mitchell and the Development of Relational Psychoanalysis
As mentioned above, Stephen Mitchell sees his work as an integrative effort to
“bridge the traditions” within psychoanalysis that already shared some common ground
(Mitchell & Aron, 1999, p. xi). From these schools Mitchell would derive certain
elements of what he later termed the relational matrix, a construct meant to widen the
unit of study in psychoanalysis from the individual, to the relationships that constitute
him. Mitchell developed the concept in his 1988 book Relational Concepts in
Psychoanalysis: An Integration, and assigned to it three different poles: “The basic
relational configurations have, by definition, three dimensions—the self, the other, and
the space between the two.” (p. 33). These poles are mutually constitutive, requiring
each other for their coming into being: there are no objects without a self that
internalizes them, no self without a matrix of relationships, and neither self nor object
can exist without the psychic space in which they fulfill their transactions. Mitchell
notes that the object dimension in this configuration has been largely explored by the
object relations school, while the concept of the self has been developed by other
sources, particularly the work of Kohut and Winnicott. Finally, the concept of a psychic
54
space, a bridge between “subjective experience and psychological world” of objects,
has been studied by developmental theorists like Stern, and the interpersonal school of
Sullivan, both of whom are concerned with the transactions between self and others (p.
33).
The “relational matrix” replaces the drive’s role in motivating human behavior,
because it presents human beings as perpetually struggling to maintain their relational
configurations: “There is a powerful need to preserve an abiding sense of oneself as
associated with, positioned in terms of, related to, a matrix of other people, in terms of
actual transactions as well as internal presences” (p. 33). According to Mitchell,
individuals seek to maintain coherence and continuity in both their interior life and in
their relationship to others, creating a dialectic between interpersonal and intrapsychic
life that “sometimes enhance each other and sometimes are at odd with each other,
forming the basis for powerful conflicts” (p. 35). By definition, the relational matrix
includes both interpersonal and intrapsychic elements in its formulation.
With the relational matrix Mitchell presents a new unit of study, inherited from
Sullivan, and a new theory of motivation. Mitchell (Mitchell and Aron, 1999) views his
theoretical contribution as an attempt to navigate the perceived demise of Freud’s
metapsychology: “…we were struggling to break free of a ‘classical’ metapsychology
and technique that many of us experienced as extremely deadening, both for the new
generation of ideas and in trying to grasp what is at stake in the clinical process” (p. xii).
This navigation demanded a twofold task: differentiating himself from other positions,
55
while integrating new burgeoning approaches into a wider framework that
acknowledged their best insights.
One of Mitchell’s initial attempts to differentiate his position is found in his
article: The Wings of Icarus: Illusion and the Problem of Narcissism (1986). This is one
of Mitchell’s early works in which he develops some of the conceptual foundation that
would later house his formulated ideas about relational psychoanalysis. In order to
advance an understanding of the psyche as constituted by human relationships,
Mitchell contrasts three views on the role of illusion in the treatment of narcissistic
neurosis: Kernberg’s, Kohut’s and his own, demonstrating that each therapeutic method
grows out of a theory of mind with which the approach is congruent.
Mitchell (1986) notes that Kernberg believes that: “transferential illusions
concerning the self or the analyst must be interpreted quickly and vigorously, their
unreality pointed out, their defensive purpose defined” (p. 110). Mitchell also observes
that “This traditional emphasis on aggressive interpretation of narcissistic phenomena
derives in part from the original view of ‘narcissistic neurosis’ as unanalyzable, and
narcissistic defenses as generating the most recalcitrant resistances to the analytic
process” (p. 111). As a result, the patient must be rapidly confronted, challenging his
narcissistic illusions in order to make way for therapeutic gain. According to Mitchell,
this prohibitive view of narcissistic illusion owes much to Freud’s drive theory, which
sees narcissistic investment as a libidinal cathexis of the ego that must be redirected
towards objects again in order to respond to the reality principle.
56
In contrast to what he deems a draconian view of narcissistic illusion, Mitchell
(1986) presents Kohut as an alternative model in which “narcissistic illusion…[is] the
core of the self and the deepest source of creativity” (p. 114). The concordant
therapeutic approach is to treat kindly “the appearance of narcissistic illusions within
the analytic situation”, because they “represent the patient’s attempt to establish crucial
developmental opportunities…”(p. 116). As a result, and standing in profound contrast
with the previous view, the therapist must respond with complete warmth and empathy:
“Anything short of a warm acceptance of narcissistic illusions concerning both the self
and the analyst runs the risk of closing off the delicate, pristine narcissistic longings and
thereby eliminating the possibility of the reemergence of healthy self-development” (p.
116).
Kohut’s emphasis on pre-oedipal stages of development as foundation for
healthy psychological life grounds his project of rebuilding a self through experiences
of empathy. Since the aim is no longer a direct accommodation to reality, but rather an
authentic engagement with the world based on the creativity of infantile narcissism, this
condition in the adult is not an obstacle to be surmounted but rather the path towards
growth. The result is that narcissistic illusion needs to be acknowledged and embraced.
However, Mitchell disagrees with both positions and presents a third way
beyond these opposing alternatives by using the myth of Icarus as a structuring parable:
Daedalus, the builder of the Labyrinth, constructs wings of feathers and
wax, so he and his son can escape their island prison. The use of such
57
wings requires a true sense of Nietzsche’s dialectical balance; flying too
high risks a melting of the wings by the sun; flying too low risks a
weighing down of the wings from the dampness of the ocean…(p. 122).
According to Mitchell, Narcissistic illusion operates under the same constraints
of Icarus: it can be neither fly too high nor too low in order to allow for healthy living.
If a person is overrun by narcissistic illusion he lives a restricted life marked by
grandiosity, but if he has none then he falls prey to idealization and passivity. Balancing
the levels of illusion is the task of the therapist, who should neither aggressively
shortstop nor passively embrace the illusion of the narcissistic patient. The therapist
must instead view the patient’s grandiosity or idealization as an invitation to participate
in the analysand’s world, an invitation that must be both accepted and questioned:
…the most useful response entails a subtle dialectic between joining the
patient in the narcissistic integration and also simultaneously questioning
the nature and purpose of that integration, both a playful participation in
the patient’s illusions and a puzzled curiosity about how and why they
came to be the sine qua non of the analysand’s sense of security and
involvement with others (p. 125).
The acceptance of the patient’s illusions allows him to engage with the therapist
in his usual way of relating with others. In turn, helped by the therapist’s subtle
questioning, this allowance reveals the patient’s way of relatedness as an option and not
the only way of being with others. This is a fundamental point of departure for Mitchell
58
(1986) because he establishes that narcissism cannot be effectively conceptualized
primarily as an internal phenomenon, be it libidinal cathexis or creative flourishing, but
rather as “a form of participation with others” (p. 124). Both Kernberg and Kohut think
of narcissism as a manifestation of internal pressures and tend to ignore how it functions
as a mode of relating to others.
The theoretical revision and the clinical approach presented in this paper
established fundamental concepts of Mitchell’s relational psychoanalysis. However,
although he continued to differentiate his approach from other systems, his later work
was characterized by an impetus to find new integrative schemes that would bring
together related but distinct models of human functioning. In Relationality: From
Attachment to Intersubjectivity (2000), Mitchell presents his final integrating vision
based on a reading of Hans Loewald’s work: he introduces a developmental theory of
intersubjectivity which he calls an “interactional hierarchy” (p. 53). The theory has four
modes or stages that occur sequentially in our development, but that also continue to
operate “in dialectical tension with each other throughout the life cycle” (p. 58). Each
mode is an “interactional dimension… through which relationality operates” (p. 58).
The first two modes describe phenomena in which the connectedness of the
human condition is most evident: our behavior and our affect. Mitchell explains how
pre-symbolic and non-reflective behavior shapes the responses of those around us, and
vice-versa, creating a mutually regulating interactional field. On a more sophisticated
developmental level, human beings also bond over the contagiousness of affect that
59
permeates through the individuals creating an intense affective connection. What is
characteristic of the first two modes, Mitchell notes, is the inability to firmly distinguish
between the self and the other. In the case of non-reflective behavior, the interactional
behavioral cueing occurs in joint movement, like dance partners whose synchronization
allows them to feel a continuity between their bodies marked by a sense of
undifferentiation. In the experience of shared affects there is also a similar sense of
boundless union that cannot be appropriately traced to the individuality of each
participant. In romantic love for example, two people are said to be ‘in’ love precisely
because it is an affective experience that transcends them as individuals. In these first
two modes of development, behavioral and affective, it is also impossible to firmly
distinguish between an I and a you, it is rather the I-you dyad that is experienced:
powerful emotional experiences are registered in a fashion in which what I am
feeling and what you are feeling are not sorted out independently , but rather
form a unity, the totality of which I experience as me…[and]…actions and
interactions function without an organized conceptualization of self and other.
On this level, the question, Who started it? Is meaningless, because the actions
of each participant have evolved, through microadaptations, in complementarity
to those of others. (p. 62)
Once the individual reaches the third mode of development, he is able to
symbolize the other, but this recognition of the other remains predicated on a
relationship to the self. Mitchell speaks here of the internalization of self-other
60
configurations, or internalized representations of my relationships with others. Thus, my
relationship with my father leaves me with a sense of who I am that becomes enacted in
other moment of my life, consciously or not. But the other continues to be recognized
only in relation to the self, revealing an inability for true recognition : “in each of these
three modes, others are not organized and experienced as independent subjects in their
own right…only in mode 4 are others organized as distinct subjects” (p. 63).
In Mitchell’s framework, the fourth mode constitutes the pinnacle of our
development potential for relationality because this is when we are finally able to
recognize the subjectivity of the other person. For Mitchell, this is important for cultural
reasons given that: “being fully human (in Western culture) entails being recognized as
a subject by another human subject” (p. 64). Recognizing the subjectivity of the other
involves an understanding of self and others as agents, that is, as individuals with both
“self-reflective intentionality” and “dependency”, both the ability to sustain individual
intentions, and the necessity of others for their completion (p. 64). Inevitably, according
to Mitchell, this creates a tension: “between our efforts to have our own way, as an
expression of our own subjectivity, and our dependence on the other, as a subject in her
own right, to grant us the recognition we require” (p. 64). But this struggle is reflective
of our highest potential for human relatedness fulfilled in an intersubjectivity that
requires we mutually acknowledge each other’s humanity. Mitchell illustrates his
position through a description of the act of declaring one’s love to a romantic partner.
This event takes place in mode 4 because it requires an important level of self-reflection
61
and self-definition, at the same time that it seeks the recognition from the other partner.
Mode 4 events are marked by a reflective intentionality that seeks recognition from the
other.
Mitchell notes that, in spite of being developmental stages, all four modes
remain operative in our interactions with others. I can simultaneously be influenced by
mutually constituted behavioral patterns, intense affective experiences, self-other
configurations, and intersubjective relationships. By revealing different dimensions of
our relatedness the framework also orients the clinician in the therapeutic process.
Sometimes the therapeutic relationship must be addressed on the basis of what
behaviors are shaping it, whereas at other times it is more helpful to discuss the nature
of the shared affective experience. However, Mitchell’s developmental account seems
to imply that intersubjectivity remains at the helm of these dimensions by guiding the
process with self-reflection, intention, and sought-for recognition. Within this
intersubjectivity, we learn “to contain in dialectical tensions different mutually
enriching forms of relatedness” (p. 101). The goal of therapy would be to help achieve
or sustain an intersubjectivity in which experiences of the other modes, which
sometimes challenge a defined and clear sense of self versus other, are contained and
understood.
Given that intersubjectivity is a shared process that involves mutual recognition,
the analyst’s subjectivity is crucial to the therapeutic process because it helps define the
subjectivity of the client himself. The formative experiences that occur in therapy
62
require that the therapist recognize the subjectivity of the client, always from his own
subjectivity. But because the therapist is embedded in a relationship, the therapist also
seeks the recognition of his subjectivity by the client. As a result, the analytic
relationship cuts both way and also defines the therapist in the process. Mitchell (2000)
presents a compelling illustration of this phenomenon when narrating an episode of a
client who challenged his impersonal way of greeting her when inviting her into the
office. Mitchell changed his impersonal demeanor with that client seeing important
therapeutic improvement. What's more, he also began changing the way he greeted
other patients in the waiting room (p. 97).
In addition to providing a clinical guide, the modes are also intended to be
theoretically integrative by accommodating different relational theorists into a typology
according to the emphasis each gives to the phenomenon described in each stage:
Thus, for example, Bowlby was most interested in behavior: what
mothers and children actually do with each other…Fairbairn was most
interested in self-other configurations…Benjamin is most interested in
intersubjectivity…(p. 82)
This does not entail that these thinkers operate exclusively within that mode, but
rather take it up as an area of emphasis. What is more, Mitchell proposes his
developmental model in order to integrate approaches and guide clinical practice, but he
“does not claim to carve nature at its joints” (p. 59).
63
Mitchell’s work stands as the foremost proponent of a relational psychoanalysis
that attempts to transcend Freud’s emphasis on the individual mind. His work rests on
the assumption that the mind is thoroughly constituted by interpersonal experience and
its internalization, not by the outward expression of internal mechanical forces. The idea
of the human being as acorn, naturally developing out of its own internal plan, given
certain environmental conditions, is replaced with that of an intersubjectively engaged
agent who learns to be who he is in the context of his relationships..
Mitchell (2000), however, suggests at times that culture operates within the
possibilities of our bodily condition. He notes that speaking of culture assumes
“relationality as universal and fundamental feature of human development”, because it
is on the basis of our relatedness that we are cultural to begin with (p. xii), presenting
relationality as a fundamental characteristic of human nature. Although he falls short of
grounding it in biology, like Bowlby does, he does speak of what he calls the
“materiality of the body and its attributes” and of humans being “constrained by our
materiality and the weight imparted by psychodynamic continuity” (Mitchell & Aron,
1999, p. xvi). Furthermore, Mitchell continues to speak in the language of interiority he
sometimes criticizes in Freud by using concepts like inner-world, intrapsychic, and
internalization. Stolorow, Orange, and Atwood (2001), primary representatives of an
intersubjective approach, have criticized him for retaining Cartesian notions of mind.
Social constructivist feminist thinkers on the other hand, criticize him for risking a
retreat into essentialist biologism. An outline of these views is presented in what
64
follows in order to consider theoretical challenges to Mitchell’s and their own
approaches.
Worlds of Experience: Stolorow, Atwood, and Orange
The term intersubjective has been appropriated by the psychoanalytic tradition
in various and sometimes contrasting ways (Stolorow, Atwood, & Orange, 2002):
…developmentalists such as D.N. Stern (1985) have used the term
intersubjective relatedness to refer to the developmental capacity to
recognize the other person as a separate subject. In a similar vein,
Benjamin (1995)…has defined intersubjectivity as mutual recognition.
Ogden, by contrast, seems to have equated intersubjectivity with…a
domain of shared experience that is prereflective and largely bodily. (p.
85)
Stolorow, Orange, and Atwood (2001), the theorists considered here, define the
term intersubjective more inclusively as a “relational context in which all
experience…takes form” (p. 474). This relational context is a field in which the
personal worlds of subjects come together and mutually influence each other (Stolorow,
Atwood, & Orange, 2002). At least two features are of central import to this view: first
the notion that the unit of study must be enlarged from an interactive dyad (Mitchell &
Aron 1999), to the very world the subject inhabits. Based on Martin Heidegger’s notion
of being-in-the world, the intersubjective approach sustains that the subject cannot be
grasped without understanding the world to which he belongs: “…the experiential
65
world seems to be both inhabited by and inhabiting of the human being” (Stolorow,
Atwood, & Orange, 2002, p. 34). The complete interpenetrability of self and world
renders these poles inseparable and mutually constitutive. In this view, the subject is his
world, the context in which his experience takes shape and meaning.
The second feature central to an intersubjective approach, also derived form
Heidegger’s philosophy, is the centrality of affective experience: “…affect—that is,
subjective emotional experience—has become a centerpiece of our psychoanalytic
framework” (Stolorow, Atwood, & Orange, 2002, p. 10). Shifting the emphasis from
drives to the primacy of affective experience allows Stolorow and colleagues to
underscore the phenomenology of psychological life, which is deeply intertwined with
the world. Affectivity, when properly understood, is a concept that reveals the
inextricable relationship between subject and world and obliterates any sharp separation
of these two poles.
According to Stolorow and his colleagues, the development of the concept of
experiential world, with its emphasis on affective encounter, evolved from a detailed
and extensive criticism of the Cartesian heritage. With remarkable succinctness and
philosophical breadth, Stolorow, Atwood, and Orange (2002), point out eight
assumptions about the mind inherited form the Cartesian tradition and present in most
psychoanalytic thinking (pp. 21-38). Many of these concepts require further
philosophical elaboration that will be taken up later in this work.
66
The first assumption is a view of mind as self-enclosed and isolated, separate
from any social constitutive context. Second, and underlying this view of mind, is the
subject-object split, a belief that reality is composed of two separate kinds of
substances: objects—or extended things--, and minds—or thinking things. Third, and
also related to the subject object split, is a distinction between an inner and outer
reality, where the external is real independently of our perceptions, and the inner is
subjectivity acting as a container of representations. The fourth and fifth attributes of
the Cartesian mind are the object and method of Cartesian inquiry respectively: a) the
search for a certain foundation b) through the rigor of logic and rational thought. The
sixth inherited assumption is the view of mind as atemporal, abstracted from the
influence of the past and the future and always present as an enduring object in the hereand-now. The seventh assumption is the representational view of mind and the
correspondence theory of truth. Finally, the last Cartesian assumption about mental
functioning they describe is the view of mind as a substance. This produces a reification
and reduction of mental phenomena to the category of a thing, a philosophical mistake
that permeates much of Freud’s metapsychological postulates.
This detailed critique of a Cartesian view of mind is meant to challenge many of
our unspoken assumptions as Western thinkers. It also serves as a prelude and
justification for the introduction of a contextualist position that they believe transcends
many of these problems and confusions. To what extent their approach is successful,
even by their own standards, is an open question which will be analyzed later as part of
67
my thesis. Nevertheless their appeal to a wider philosophical horizon brings some
apparent problems with Mitchell’s view into relief.
Stolorow, Orange and Atwood (2001) claim, for example, that the notion of
projective identification implicitly used by Mitchell’s accounts of therapists enacting
the client’s maladaptive patterns assumes two separate minds that emit and receive
thoughts onto each other (p. 476). Based on Schafer’s work (1972), Stolorow, Orange
and Atwood (2001) point out that the idea of projecting thoughts involves a confusion
of spatial notions of interiority and exteriority with subjective—non-spatial—concepts
of mind (p. 476). Minds, they claim, do not have an inside or an outside, they are
“pictured as an emergent property of the person-environment system, not as a Cartesian
entity located inside the cranium” (p. 480). The phenomenon in which a client evokes
affective responses in the therapist which he himself is feeling, would not be understood
as a projection of mental content between two separate minds, but as a shared affective
experience that emerges as a property of an intersubjective system.
The intersubjectivists challenge an assumption deeply held by Mitchell: his
allegiance to a distinction between real interpersonal relations and internalized selfother configurations. According to Stolorow and colleagues, such distinction mirrors a
dramatic split between external and internal reality predominant in Cartesian thinking.
This separation seems to originate from his attempt to integrate an interpersonal and an
object relations perspective, which contain the Cartesian assumption of separate
inner/outer realms. Mitchell considers that the integration of intrapsychic and
68
interpersonal realms provides a full account of human subjectivity that each side alone
misses. According to the intersubjectivists, however, any conservative strategy would
betray a lack of philosophical sophistication because: “persisting dichotomies between
the intrapsychic and the interpersonal, between a one and two-person psychologies, are
obsolete—reified, absolutized relics of the Cartesian bifurcation” (Stolorow, Orange, &
Atwood, 2001, p. 481). Retaining this dichotomy inevitably presents the mind as
separate form the world, as a container within the subject and not as an emergent system
between the subject and his environment, as intersubjectivists argue.
The intersubjective approach presents an important challenge to relational
psychoanalysis by questioning its Cartesian assumptions. Their challenge pushes
relational psychoanalysis to widen its unit of study and become more relational in the
process. Stolorow, Orange, and Atwood are able to pose this challenge and provide an
interesting answer because they appeal to a wider philosophical horizon that both
informs their work and illuminates their clinical practice. Their approach, for example,
criticizes the ethic of personal disclosure that relational psychoanalysis foments by their
focus on “present moment thinking” (Stolorow, Orange, & Atwood 2001, p. 472). From
an intersubjective approach, this atemporal understanding of therapy overlooks the
influence of the patient’s history and perception of his future. In addition, by focusing
primarily on the therapeutic relationship, the therapist might be oblivious to other
contexts of relatedness that the client inhabits most of the time. This is why Stolorow,
Orange and Atwood prescribe a widening of the therapeutic dyad as a unit of study to
69
include the entire world of the subject. In spite of its clinical and theoretical sagacity,
the question of how well intersubjectivity lives up to its own philosophical insights
remains open and will be considered later.
Intersubjectivity attempts to differentiate itself sharply from postmodern
approaches in psychoanalysis noting that: “contextualism in psychoanalysis should not
be confused with postmodernist nihilism or relativism” and that “Relativity to context is
not the same thing as a relativism” (p. 482). However, what they do share with
postmodern gender theorists, who will be considered next, is the belief in the deep interpenetrability, if not the identification, of the mind and its context. To use Mitchell and
Aron’s (1999) term, the “radical forms of constructivism” accept as true the complete
social construction of the mind following the postmodern thinking of philosophers like
Foucault and Derrida (p. xv). But Mitchell and Aron (1999) present an important
challenge to theorists that grant an exhaustive priority to the social: “…from our point
of view, constructivism in political and gender theory, in its dialectical swing away
from essentialism, often becomes too airy and ungrounded, missing the way in which
the past, the inner world, developmental continuities, all have claims on our present
experience” (p. xvi).
This question also challenges the intersubjective approach by proxy, given its
emphasis on abandoning any form of biological grounding or interior private
experience. If the mind arises out of a person-environment system, then how does the
subjectivity of the individual become differentiated from the world itself? Mitchell
70
seems to be asking whether we are obliterating the individual and his real corporeal
existence if we conceptualize him as completely undistinguishable from his world and
its constructions. What follows then is a brief exposition of the constructivist
perspective in psychoanalysis with a consideration of Mitchell’s criticism of ignoring
intrapsychic and bodily dimensions.
Social Constructionist Perspectives in Psychoanalysis
Like the relational tradition itself, postmodern influences within it are varied and
complex (Dimen & Goldner, 2002), and a detailed exposition of all its views is beyond
the scope of this work. Leffert (2007, p.177) notes that postmodern approaches within
psychoanalysis are related to, but should not be entirely conflated with, intersubjective
and relational perspectives. Furthermore, he notes that there is ample heterogeneity
within postmodern psychoanalytic thinking, and that integrative work is on order. A
representative overview of thinkers in this position is offered by Fairfield, Layton and
Stack (2002), who note the heterogeneity in the movement but recognize there is
important common ground. The dialogue between psychoanalysis, feminism, and
postmodern philosophy is one crucial shared goal, if not the unifying platform, for
many of these theorists (Flax, 1990, Fairfield, 2001, Layton, 1998). From within this
interdisciplinary crossroads, several thinkers welcome the philosophical influence of
Foucault and Derrida, while others tentatively explore the tensions between their
philosophy and the realities of clinical practice.
71
Derrida and Foucault’s influence is most noticeable in several projects that
challenge prevailing notions of gender. Butler, Corbett, Dimen, and Goldner (in Dimen
& Goldner, 2002) write excellent examples of this line of scholarship, in which cultural
understandings of gender are analyzed in light of language and power dynamics.
Specifically, they question the customary dichotomizing of gender into opposite poles
(male/female), which are usually construed as natural categories. In their view, such an
analysis subverts the power structure maintained by those constructs. In the words of
Goldner (2002):
I argue that dichotomous gender categories, precisely because they are
essentialized, mutually exclusive, and unequally valued, can be used for
magical ends in the psyche, in the family, and, as we have already seen,
in the culture to carry, solve, or exploit existential oppositions and
dilemmas. (p. 75)
Underlying this project we find a set of assumptions about the nature of reality
that guides the inquiry. There is, for example, a Foucaultian (1978) view of knowledge,
personal and academic, as a form of discourse that is culturally enacted to sustain power
relations. In addition, we find Derrida’s position on language as an instrument of this
polarization and domination (Fairfield, Layton, & Stack, 2002, p. 2). These theorists
hold that all our concepts, including our understanding of selfhood, are not natural
categories but socio-political constructions sustained by linguistic practices (Mitchell &
Black, 1995, p. 198). As Jones (2003) notes: “the ‘intrapsychic’ is actually a mode of
72
the interpersonal or even the cultural” (p. 171) in postmodern views, because, as
Fairfield (2001) explains: “They enact it, reiterate it performatively, within a cultural
setting that allows for the legibility of that construct” (p. 228).
In spite of a general acceptance of these premises, some psychoanalytic gender
theorists raise questions about the relationship between feminist psychoanalysis and
postmodern philosophy. Nancy Chodorow (1991), for instance, advocates a formulation
of postmodern thinking that rejects essentialism but includes the role of individual
psychology in the creation of meaning: “gender difference is not absolute, abstract, or
irreducible; it does not involve an essence of gender. Gender differences, and the
experience of difference, like differences among women, are socially and
psychologically created and situated” (p. 100). This appropriation seems to stem from
recognizing the problems inherent in ignoring individual psychology in favor of cultural
practices:
In this view, meanings are imposed as cultural categories rather than
created in contingent individual ways. According to this hegemonic
feminist viewpoint, cultural order takes precedence over a more nuanced
and variable individual personal meaning, and the psyche is entirely
linguistic (Chodorow, 1999, p. 70).
This quote poignantly illustrates Chodorow’s discomfort with cultural
explanations completely displacing individual experience. According to her, the
linguistic constitution of the psyche cannot explain the profound variability in human
73
experience without appealing to a psychological dimension. She notes that it is “not
only that people create individualized cultural or linguistic versions of meaning by
drawing on the cultural or linguistic categories at hand. Rather perception and the
creation of meaning are psychologically constituted” (p. 71). In her view, although the
self is embedded in social contexts, experiencing them is intensely personal colored
through affectivity and fantasy, such that cultural categories can neither exhaust nor
determine the possibilities of individual life.
Lynne Layton (1998), another gender theorist who recognizes the role of
individual psychology in the creation of meaning, places Chodorow’s protest within a
general “tension between individual specificity and cultural processes [that] has been
much discussed among clinicians who are also gender theorists” (p. 9). She attributes
this dialectic to the philosophical blindness of defenders of individuality on one hand
and social construction on the other, who both miss each others claims. Her recipe for
the successful integration of individual and postmodern approaches is the recognition
that “the cultural is psychologically constructed, and the psychological is cultural” (p.
10). She argues that understanding would permit retaining a sensitivity to the reality of
individual experience as well as its interconnectedness with the social contexts to which
it belongs. As a result: “the way a black middle-class girl construes a gender identity at
any particular historical moment , the way she puts together the possibilities that
circulate in her family and culture, in turn contributes to constructing the set of cultural
practices that will define ‘black middle-class female’” (p. 10).
74
It seems, however, that both Layton’s and Chodorow’s strategies raise many
questions about the interaction between personal and social reality. For example, we are
left wondering on what basis the individual can “put together…the possibilities that
circulate” (Layton, 1998, p. 63) in her context, without appealing to cultural values and
ideas that inform those choices. This is problematic because if the criterion for personal
choice is itself cultural, then individuality seems to become undistinguishable from
culture. Chodorow suggests that our psychology differentiates us from culture and
allows us to appropriate it individually. She rejects the notion that culture simply
provides meaning, positing instead that meaning and perception are actively constructed
through affect and fantasy. However, in attributing such constitutive strength to the
psyche she displaces the role of culture. We are left wondering again on what basis
affective and fantasy create individual meaning if not from cultural constructs. An
appeal to naturalistic view of affective life is, of course, also precluded if Chodorow
wants to avoid charges of retreating into essentialism.
Chodorow and Layton both navigate what Dimen and Goldner (2002) describe
as “ensuring that we neither essentialize gender nor dematerialize it” (p. xvii). On the
one hand, postmodernists who emphasize the role of social forces in constructing the
self escape naturalism and essentialism with all its trappings. By contrast, thinkers who
retain notions of psychological experience as co-constructor of selfhood avoid the
“dematerialization” of the individual into social structures. But this dialectic places
either position into an uneasy theoretical tension.
75
Mitchell and Aron (1999) effectively identified the “dematerialization” of
individuality that radical social constructivists face. He criticizes them for ignoring the
claims that the intrapsychic and the “materiality of the body” make on an individual’s
life (p. xvi). According to him, even tough the self is socially constructed, the elements
out of which it is built must count. Discursive practices risk being too “airy and
ungrounded” as the self’s only building blocks, so we need to acknowledge the impact
of body and psyche as particular realities in the construction of the self (p. xvi). This is a
challenging critique that resonates with Chodorow and Layton’s defense of individual
meaning making. Like them, Mitchell embraces the intrapsychic role in the formation of
meaning. Also like them, it is not clear that he succeeds in retaining a notion of
individuality that does not fade into the cultural practices that constitute it. Mitchell’s
intrapsychic life is ultimately constituted by interpersonal transactions, which again
raises the question of what this psychology is based on if it is not equivalent to culture.
Mitchell appeals to the reality of the body as a grounding principle in the social
construction of the individual, yet “any ways in which those bodily attributes are
described are themselves social constructions” (1999). If the body also must be
interpreted in and through culture, it is not clear that it can ground any sense of selfhood
above and beyond the cultural practices that constitute it.
These theorists embody a profound tension between privileging individuality or
social construction in understanding selfhood. If they hold on to a personal psychology
then they must explain how it develops as something different than culture, and if they
76
embrace the cultural constitution of the self then they must face the risk of
“dematerializing” our phenomenological sense of personhood. This is a dilemma that
Jack Martin and Jeff Sugarman have identified as confronting a “Hobson’s choice
between scientism or relativism” (1999, p. 41), “between modern foundationalism and
postmodern radical arbitrariness” (2000, p. 402) and between “modern essentialism and
postmodern antisubjectivism” (2000, p. 403). Their work attempts to provide a solution
from the perspective of theoretical psychology. Understanding how they frame this
difficulty that plagues modern psychology, including relational psychoanalysis, should
clarify the issues at stake in and facilitate a path towards a better answer.
Relational Psychoanalysis in Clinical Practice
Having explored the theoretical underpinnings of these three schools of
relational psychoanalysis, it is important to also note how their theoretical departure
from classical precepts informs their clinical practice. Just like in theory, there are both
differences and shared ground between these approaches in clinical practice. Possibly
the characteristic these approaches share most clearly is their belief in never privileging
the subjectivity of the analyst over that of the client. This view derives from the
assumption that the therapist is an active participant in a shared relational process. As a
result, she is never in a position to somehow stand outside of the therapeutic
relationship to provide neutral—and thus more objectively real—interpretations.
In an early work entitled The Psychoanalytic Treatment of Homosexuality: Some
Technical Considerations (1981), Mitchell illustrates the insidious way in which
77
unrecognized analytic authority can be abused to distort what is happening between the
patient and the analyst. He brings up the now outdated issue, at least in psychoanalytic
circles, of considering homosexuality as an illness that needs to be treated by suggestive
techniques (p. 65). The oppressive dimensions of this approach are now readily
apparent to the contemporary reader, but what is more interesting and still relevant for
current practice is Mitchell’s discussion of the use of interpretation as a way to conceal
the influence of the analyst. Mitchell references the following clinical vignette
originally presented by Ovesey (1969):
This example involves patient 2, who, after much pressure from the analyst,
goes to bed with a prostitute and that night dreams: 'He was in the woods. He
was a male fox among many others and one of the foxes inserted anally into
him. Then all the foxes, including the patient, changed into men' (p. 140). This
dream is interpreted as a flight from heterosexuality to a 'magical repair through
homosexual contacts' (p. 141). Ovesey doesn't consider the possibility that the
dream represents the patient's experience of being dominated and overpowered
by the therapist, who had pressured the patient into the heterosexual situation.
The therapist's interpretation of the dream, in fact, seems to have been
experienced as a further domination and control. (p. 69)
The analyst couches his suggestion—perhaps unconsciously—in a plausible
interpretation. This has the double effect of concealing the real message being
transmitted—avoid homosexual behavior—and disassociating it from its author by
78
appealing to its neutrality and theoretical correctness. The subjectivity of the analyst,
the guiding set of concerns, expectations, and dispositions that structure this
intervention remains wholly unacknowledged and anonymously dominant.
In a relational model all interaction must account for the participation of the
therapist. Interpretations of their process are not accounts of something the patient does
independently over there, but rather an account of what the therapist-patient dyad
participate in together. In postmodern perspectives that approach is accompanied by
refined sensibility towards the workings of power in theoretical constructs. Stack (1999)
notes that:
As long as psychoanalysis promulgates the concept of “penis envy,” as long as
we use this image no matter how we understand its symbolic meaning, we reify
the phallocentric narrative that men have/ are the desired object that women
lack. This heterosexist trope of desire rambles through our personal lives, our
work with patients, and our professional relations, reinforcing and reenacting its
belief in itself each time it shows up (p. 77).
As such, when she listens to repeated presentations at a conference of male
analysts struggling with the erotic transference of a female patient, she sees both the
enactment and reinforcement of this narrative. For Stack it isn’t only the thoughts and
feelings of the analysts we need to worry about, but also how these are structured—and
sometimes concealed—by theoretical constructions grounded in dominant forms of
discourse. Postmodern relationalists introduce the social shared background, with its
79
concomitant power differentials, into the room along with the subjectivity of the analyst
and patient. They see these practices as deeply constitutive of subjectivity to begin with,
and as such they will unavoidably inform the therapeutic interaction. But, if “all of the
content that arises in the analytic situation is generated from the mind of the patient”
(Mitchell & Black, 1995, p. 234) as classical theory would have it, then whatever role
the analyst has in bringing about an erotic transference or in enacting cultural constructs
remains completely concealed. Postmodern clinical practice expects the analyst to
always question their stance in the room instead, to “put their own assumptions into
question” as a sine qua non for belonging to the “postmodern episteme.” (Fairfield,
Layton, & Stack, 2002, p. 4).
But admitting that the analyst has an active role in the room and that her
subjectivity needs to be recognized is not enough; these factors should be considered
constitutive for an analytic relationship to take place. In other words, it is not that
recognizing the influence of subjectivity places us in a better position to achieve
neutrality, but rather the criticism places subjectivity at the core of a therapeutic
relationship. In classical models, for example, countertransference needs to be
neutralized, while in relational approaches it is often meant to be disclosed: “What is it
to be done with the therapists feelings? Probably the most important dividing line in
current approaches to using countertransference is around the question of whether the
analyst’s reactions ought to be in any way divulged to the patient.” (Mitchell & Black,
1995, p. 247). And even though, as Stepansky (2002) suggests, the “surgical metaphor”
80
of cold detachment and acting upon the patient was questioned by Freud himself,
certainly the idea of analytic neutrality remains a viable construct in many circles, one
that urges restraint on the part of the therapist (p. 500).
For the intersubjectivists (Orange & Stolorow, 1998) the issue of disclosure is
not whether one discloses or not, but rather how one chooses to do so: “Intersubjectivity
theory is even more radical on this topic. It recognizes that within any particular
psychoanalytic situation or intersubjective field, two subjective worlds are continually
self-revealing and attempting to hide. Even withholding is a form of communication.”
(p. 532). From this perspective, the dilemma of communicating or withholding is a
pseudo issue because we are always conveying a message in the process whether we do
so or not. The more interesting question becomes how and when do we speak. Orange
and Stolorow (1998) present a clinical vignette in which disclosure played an important
role in advancing towards significant material:
Once Erica settled into treatment and began to feel understood, a curious pattern
developed. At the beginning of each session she would ask how the analyst's
weekend had been, or how she was…Erica would ask more, or wait for more
response, before she seemed able to move on…She was reluctant to point the
pattern out, imagining Erica would feel shamed. Yet the merely polite responses
were evidently also problematic…Perhaps, the analyst thought, Erica needed her
analyst to talk about herself. So, one Monday, when asked what she had done on
the weekend, the analyst responded that she'd mostly done chores, had done
81
some reading, and had been to a concert. Since then, they have tended to “chat”
for about three minutes at the beginning of each session. Erica has come to
know a fair number of details about her analyst's interests and activities. (p.
536).
Eventually, while discussing the meaning of this changed interaction, the patient
discovered that the function of this initial dialogue had been first to test the authenticity
of the analyst, and then to also check her emotional state to see if she was healthy
enough to trust her with her own psychological burden. One can imagine this same
issue being address in a more restrictive frame and also being resolved. But without the
accessibility of the therapist in that act of self-disclosure, it is also possible that the
patient will leave with a different message about how to negotiate relationships outside
the session.
82
Chapter 3: Beyond the Intrapsychic vs. Interpersonal Dualism
Differing Concepts of Personhood
So far this work has had three aims: 1) to highlight a point of theoretical tension
within relational psychoanalysis regarding concepts of selfhood by bringing some of its
variants into dialogue, 2) to present these relational schools in the context of their
influences, and 3) to present ideas about the relationship between theory and practice in
psychoanalysis. A more careful presentation of the praxis/theory relationship requires
reviewing concepts that will be presented in the following chapter, and thus that line of
investigation will be held until then. However, in order to address the problematic
tension within relational schools introduced earlier, it would be helpful to articulate it in
more detail.
As mentioned before, relational psychoanalysis is unified by a series of critiques
of traditional concepts of self in psychoanalysis. The three positions outlined above-Mitchell, the intersubjective school, and postmodern psychoanalysis—all present
related but subtly different critiques of traditional psychoanalytic notions of selfhood.
Mitchell contends that classical psychoanalysis conceptualizes human beings too
narrowly by viewing interpersonal relationships as merely epiphenomenal and innate
drives as constitutional. In this view, intrapsychic conflict determines our behavior
while other people and the world we occupy are the actors and stage that instantiate an
internal script. This represents a one-person view of psychological life, according to
Mitchell, which fails to consider the constitutive role of relationships in personhood.
83
Mitchell could be described as criticizing the individualistic tendencies of Freudian
theory.
The intersubjective approach criticizes traditional psychoanalysis from a
different front by questioning the very concept of an internal private world. This
constitutes a direct attack on notions of personal intrapsychic life. They propose instead
that people have experiential-worlds, webs of meanings and relationships with others
that constitute their identity. In this framework, subjectivity is constituted by the
relationship with other subjectivities and their corresponding matrix of meanings, each
from their own perspective. According to Stolorow, Atwood, and Orange (2002), the
self is inherently intersubjective because there is no self without the subjectivity of the
other. Intersubjectivists can be seen as primarily criticizing the cartesianism of Freudian
theory—its notion of a private and separate subjectivity. Postmodern psychoanalysts
focus their critique on Freud’s essentialism, the idea that human beings have an
unchanging underlying core. They present instead a radically different view of selfhood,
derived from poststructuralist philosophy,that denies it is possible to understand any
phenomena in terms of unchanging and universal structures, like those provided by
natural science. In its place, human beings are seen as constituted by language, which is
itself always constrained by historical context. In this view, psychological life is
constructed socially as a form of discourse, a consensual way of speaking about reality.
As a result, the subject becomes de-centered, there is no core or center of selfhood but
rather a multiplicity of selves that we enact in everyday life through our different roles.
84
All three critical themes, individualism, cartesianism, and essentialism, reflect
similar concerns with the decontextualization of the self from the world. However,
while Mitchell is sympathetic to the importance of contextualizing the self, he wants to
retain notions of interiority and biological givens, and this puts him at odds with
intersubjectivists and postmodern psychoanalysts. But if the other two groups are
correct, retaining ideas of a private subjectivity and/or biological givens results in
decontextualizing the self from social reality. Conversely, Mitchell poignantly asks if
the self disappears into thin air if it is so thoroughly contextualized, wondering what
happens to our mind and our body when it is so indistinguishable from that of others.
As Ghent (in Skolnick & Warshaw, 1992) so lucidly articulates, it is possible that “The
self as a center of activity and agency has somehow been neglected by placing the
emphasis so firmly on a two-person psychology.” (p. xxi).
It seems then that relational approaches defend what could be described as thin
accounts of personhood: theories that emphasize the self’s constitutive engagement
with a social realm, plural and discontinuous character, discursive structure, and
perpectival access to reality. These characteristics are prominently found in postmodern
critiques of selfhood. On the other hand, some voices within relational psychoanalysis
want to preserve aspects of what could be termed thick accounts of personhood: those
that present the self as unitary and continuous, with a substantive and unchanging core,
primarily engaged with mental contents, and biologically grounded. These are
characteristics usually associated with a modern view of selfhood. Relational
85
psychoanalysis seems to occupy a tense space between these two positions, often
oscillating between them. When one of its voices thins out personhood, another asks
about the disappearance of a substantive self.
Martin and Sugarman
Martin and Sugarman (1999, 2000) tackle the problematic introduced in this
work in a related yet different context. Their aim is wider in that they target the social
sciences at large and tackle philosophical questions about agency and the capacity for
choice. However, the phenomenon they describe is quite similar to the one present in
relational psychoanalysis--this push and pull between thin and thick accounts of
personhood—thus making their thinking potentially beneficial for the issues at hand.
From their wider optic, Martin and Sugarman note that in recent decades the social
sciences and psychology have come under heavy attack for presupposing and operating
within characteristically modern views of human agency and the self. Cushman (1990,
p. 604) notes that the social sciences operate under a modern view of selfhood as a
"bounded, masterful self," that "is expected to function in a highly autonomous, isolated
way" and "to be self-soothing, self-loving, and self-sufficient." Regrettably, Cushman
argues, this inflated and overly autonomous modern self transforms into an "empty
self," characterized by feelings of fragility, emptiness, and an emotional that oscillates
between feelings of grandiosity and worthlessness (Richardson, Fowers, & Guignon,
1999). Likewise, Gergen (2001), takes psychology to task for being “essentially a byproduct of what is often called cultural modernism”, characterized by “three modernist
86
themes—emphasis on the individual mind, an objectively knowable world, and
language as carrier of truth” (p. 803). Instead, Gergen argues, we should move “from
individual reason to communal rhetoric”, “from an objective to a socially constructed
world”, and in language “from truthful picture to pragmatic practice” (p. 805).
Like in psychoanalysis, many influential postmodern thinkers in contemporary
psychology (Gergen, 1985, 1994; Slife & Williams, 1997; Giorgi, 1970) have sharply
critiqued the modern overly atomistic conception of the self, one that seems abstracted
or detached from any meaningful social context. In its radical variants, these criticisms
insist on the social construction of the self and human identity and usually argue for an
epistemological perspectivism that appears to be potentially liberating for postmodern
selves (Richardson, Fowers, & Guignon, 1999). Although a minority standpoint in
psychology and psychoanalysis, the postmodern/social constructionist influence has
grown considerably in recent years. However, it has sustained a number of criticisms.
Smith (1994) contends that the postmodern “flow of discourse leaves us bereft of
anchors to stabilize a view of self and world”, leaving psychology with an “extreme
version of antiscientific relativism” that “is gaining prominence at the margins of
mainstream psychology.” (p. 408). Parker (1998) noted that reactions to postmodernism
in psychology have centered on defenses of realism and scientific explanation, adding
that postmodernism is “particularly pernicious in its embrace of relativism and
amoralism” (p. 622). Eagle (2003) expresses his concern over the excesses of
postmodernism, noting that:
87
…legitimate criticisms of some traditional psychoanalytic views have been
transformed into untenable philosophical positions that do not constitute an
adequate basis for psychoanalytic theory or practice. For example, skepticism
toward the therapeutic value of insight and self-knowledge has been transformed
into a philosophical position that rules out the very possibility of discovering
truths about the mind. (p. 411)
A number of voices within psychology find considerable fault with both modern
scientistic and relativistic postmodern approaches to understanding human life. These
critics speak in various ways of a need to move beyond the dualism of scientism and
constructionism (Zeddies & Richardson, 1999; Richardson, et al., 1999). These
critiques owe much to the work of Richard Bernstein, who in his book Beyond
Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (1983) notes that:
There is an uneasiness that has spread throughout intellectual and cultural life. It
affects almost every discipline and every aspect of our lives. This uneasiness is
expressed by the opposition between objectivism and relativism, but there are a
variety of other contrasts that indicate the same underlying anxiety: rationality
vs. irrationality, objectivity vs. subjectivity, realism vs. antirealism.
Contemporary thinking has moved between these and other related extremes.
Even the attempts that some have made to break out of this framework of
thinking have all too frequently been assimilated to these standard oppositions.
(p. 1)
88
Bernstein’s recognition of this academic and cultural malaise is now over 20
years old yet thinkers who continue to point out this problematic are anything but
anachronistic. This phenomenon certainly speaks to the force and endurance of these
opposing contrasts, which Bernstein acknowledges. Certainly Martin and Sugarman are
deeply aligned with such a critique and articulate its problematic very lucidly as it
pertains to social science. What follows then is a preliminary analysis of their account
of human agency and selfhood. Stating their view of the current problematic facing the
social sciences will help frame the dilemma facing relational psychoanalysis in a new
light.
Beyond Modern and Postmodern Selves
In their book The Psychology of Human Possibility and Constrain (1999),
Martin and Sugarman begin their investigation by responding to what they consider an
important limitation of some variants of postmodern thought: the eradication of
personhood as an ontological category. Against postmodern criticism they ask: “Is there
nothing of value to be gained by retaining something of the individual psychology
against the ever-present sociocultural fabric of human existence?” (1999, p. 3).
However, their question does not represent a complete rejection of postmodernism, the
authors claim, for it has provided useful critiques of atomistic views of selfhood. Martin
and Sugarman acknowledge that challenging the idea that people can be understood
separated from their history and surroundings, is a timely and invaluable notion which
helps us understand personhood in a richer light. They also recognize that there is
89
important heterogeneity within social constructionist approaches, and that some place
significant emphasis on the reality of individual experience. Nevertheless, they note,
“more radical versions of postmodern social constructionism seem to us…to erase both
the psychological agent and the possibility of warranted psychological understanding.”
(Martin & Sugarman, 2000, p. 399). In other words, radical postmodernists usually take
their claims further than the phenomena requires. Martin and Sugarman also qualify this
claim about radical postmodernists saying that: “it may be possible to interpret the
strong version of postmodern social constructionism as advocating only a social
relational constitution of the psychological agent”, although they do find indications
that these radical perspectives tend to be reductive (p. 399). Although this is a topic
worthy of discussion in itself, it is not important whether Martin and Sugarman
accurately depict all variants of constructionist approaches but rather that they clearly
delimit the positions they are arguing against. If it turns out that some postmodern
variants can successfully defend a socially constructed self that does not loose its
personhood, then that would be a type of postmodernism that Martin and Sugarman
would likely embrace.
In sum, the problem as Martin and Sugarman (1999) see it is that a radical social
constructionist view collapses psychological individuality with the social background
from which it develops: “we believe that there is an important sense in which these
various proposals conflate individual psychological experience with plausible
sociocultural explanations for such experience.” (p.3). According to them, the
90
sociocultural level of explanation is not incorrect, but taken as the sole perspective it
occludes the individual experience that a psychology of personhood tries to capture.
Furthermore, when selfhood is understood solely from a social perspective a number of
philosophical, and ultimately practical, problems ensue. For example, in such a system
there is no room for the phenomenal experience of ourselves as individuals making
meaningful choices within a social and cultural context. The social context becomes
undifferentiated from the individual in such a way that making choices is impossible.
However important the re-embedding of the subject in a historical and cultural lifeworld might be, we are throwing the baby with the bath water when we weave them
into the world to the point of virtual extinction. Martin and Sugarman respond to this
problem by providing a fresh account--one that in its own way tries to move beyond
tired and rigid dualisms--of how we develop and function as human agents in our social
universe.
Social Constructionism and Cognitive Constructivism
According to Martin and Sugarman (1999) the entire discussion about the nature
of the self and its relation to society in the human sciences, and elsewhere, is deeply
affected by a problematic dualism. At one pole of this dualism we find social
constructionists, who claim that the self is constructed out of or largely the product of
social interactions. The individual, through its immersion in conversational practices,
learns to organize thought and experience into a meaningful framework. Society
provides individuals with both the cognitive tools and the symbolic content that
91
constitutes their identity. The primary focus of explanation is at the social level. On the
other pole, cognitive constructivism holds a more traditional conception of the self. This
view posits that learning occurs through a series of innate mechanisms triggered in the
individual through its interaction with the environment. As a child grows, he passes
through several stages of cognitive development that regulate his thinking and
experience of the world. The focus of explanation is at the individual level.
Each of these opposing views, according to Martin and Sugarman (1999), say
something illuminating about personhood and society. Social contructionists point out
how identity originates from society by means of the internalization of pre-existing
social orders. But they have great difficulty explaining two phenomena. The first is the
existence of novelty or originality. The second is the phenomenological experience of
individuality and choice. If individuals are constituted by the social through and
through, where do new ideas come from? In addition, if the category of the social
suffices to explain psychological phenomena, what do we make of our rich individual
experience of the world as we make choices and, often arduously, sort through a
plurality of meanings in the process?
Cognitive constructivists, on the other hand, are able to account for at least some
of the generation of novelty by the individual as well as the experience of meaningful
encounter that each individual has with the world. Nevertheless, they have a difficult
time explaining how is it that we manage to communicate and cooperate so well with
other people. It seems then that both poles reveal aspects of human existence that are
92
truthful: one emphasizes our personal encounter with the world while the other
illuminates the shared nature of our identity. And so Martin and Sugarman (1999)
observe that:
With social constructionists such as Vygotsky (1934/1986), Mead (1934),
Gergen (1985), and Shotter (1993), we contend that the individual arises from
the sociocultural. However, concurring partially with the contrasting view, as
represented by cognitive constructivists such as Bartlett (1932), Piaget (1954),
Kelly (1955), and Mahoney (1990), we also contend that the individual is not
isomorphic with, nor educible to, the sociocultural. (p. 5)
However, they don’t consider this statement to be a conclusion, but rather the
starting point of an integrative effort that needs to justify how to bridge concretely these
apparently discrepant perspectives. The reason why this has been difficult, Martin and
Sugarman tell us, does not reside in some important difference between these views, but
rather in an important assumption they actually share. Both treat their central categories
as closed fixed entities. What is required, the authors say, is a conceptualization that
understands the social and the individual as mutable and mutually constitutive
processes: “…the real problem with sociocultural-psychological dualism has less to do
with the drawing of a divide between societal-cultural phenomena and individualpsychological phenomena, than it has to do with treating that which is on either side of
this divide, and the divide itself, as fixed and immutable.” (1999, p. 6).
The Metaphysics of Dynamic Interactionism
93
For Martin and Sugarman, if we operate under the assumption that the social and
the individual are fixed and immutable entities, then we are forced to see them as
mutually exclusive explanatory frameworks. If we consider the category of the social as
something closed, fixed, and thus complete unto itself, then by necessity this category
co-opts any explanatory power that we could find at the individual level. Of course, the
reverse is also true. If cognitive constructivists assume that individuality is a closed
category, they are forced to consider the social as nothing more than a derivative
phenomenon. This underlying assumption of fixedness prevents each pole from
understanding its relationship to the other. Martin and Sugarman argue that this
assumption blocks each side from being receptive to the partly valid claims of the other.
For the cognitive constructivist, it displaces the centrality of social contributions in the
formation of individuality. In the case of social constructionists, it leads them to
downplay—or outright ignore—the experience of agency and the individual’s encounter
with the world.
Clearly, rejecting one pole in order to favor the other is an incomplete solution,
but simply adding them together creates more questions than answers. How is it that we
are constituted by social forces yet not determined by them? If individuality is
something more than its sociocultural origins, from where does it get it? To answer
these questions, Martin and Sugarman argue, we need to first challenge the assumption
of fixedness that frames this dualism. Once we allow ourselves to think about
alternatives to this assumption, we can begin to work out a better account of
94
personhood, culture, and their relationship: “the key to this bridging of atomism and
holism is to treat societies and cultures not as things with effective causal powers, but as
dynamic interrelational processes through which social and psychological practices are
ordered over time.” (1999, p. 13).
Martin and Sugarman utilize Gidden’s (1984) theory of structuration to explain
the interrelated process of individuals and social co-constitution. In this view, social
structures have a regulatory function in the lives of individuals; they dictate parameters
for action and meaning in societies. For example, the organization of the US
government stipulates that no one should take hold of office by force. The democratic
process gives its members a degree of power over the collective norms that rule their
lives. However, this political structure requires the participation of individuals to breath
life into it. In other words, there can be no democracy without a group of democratic
individuals, but we cannot be democratic individuals without a democracy to constitute
us as such. Society and individuals need each other to exist. Additionally, this
relationship is not static. The structures do not rigidly determine individual behavior
any more than the reverse occurs. Once within a structure, individuals re-work their
beliefs and values in light of new situations and experiences. As a result, individuals
have a historical effect on shaping the form and nature of these institutions as much as
the institutions have an effect on shaping its members. Society and individuals are
dynamically interactive and mutable.
95
Martin and Sugarman hold that change in societies arises through psychological
individuality, yet they are enabled and constrained by the sociohistorical structures that
they inhabit. In their discussion of dynamic interactionism, the theory they propose as a
bridge between social and individual explanatory frameworks, they state that:
An ineluctable condition of human existence is that at birth, humans are thrown
into already existing societies and cultures that have evolved in a real physical
world. As biological organisms equipped with rudimentary physical and
perceptual activity, human infants are capable of prereflective embodied
experience. (p. 17)
In their view, before we develop reflexive agency our capacity to understand is
grounded in a precarious sensory and perceptual apparatus. This embodiment is an
existential given that predates the existence of anything like a mind. However, as we
become exposed to language and other symbolic mediation processes present in culture,
we learn to organize our experience in a way that makes reflexivity emerge. We shift
from an unmediated direct perception of the world as biological entities to a reflexive
understanding of the world mediated by what these authors call theories of ourselves
and the world. Once we develop the cognitive capacities of imagination and memory,
we have the ability to hold such theories about ourselves and the world. This capacity to
cognitively theorize about the world, the authors argue, is what gives us enough
distance from the sociocultural and biological to make innovative decisions. Theories of
96
self and the world create enough of a separation between the individual and society to
create new imagined possibilities:
In our ontology of human existential givens, we rejected the idea of an initial
separation of human psychology from its sociocultural context, but subsequently
we argued strongly for possibilities of sociocultural innovation and change
resident in an emergent, dynamic dualism, one that acknowledges a gradual and
graduated separation of individual psychology from its largely sociocultural
determinant. (pp. 130-131)
Without this separation and emergent reflexivity, Martin and Sugarman tell us,
there is no change and there certainly is no agency. People are initially originated by
sociocultural structures and biological conditions, but at a given point individuals
develop the capacity to transcend their sociocultural and biological origins. They are
able to do so when they have become psychologically constituted. After internalizing
societies interpretive practices, individuals develop the capacity to interpret themselves
as meaningful actors in a social context. They form personal theories about themselves
and the world, which allows them to influence their surroundings in an self-reflexive
way. When this occurs, Martin and Sugarman tell us, the psychological has emerged.
Once we are constituted as psychological beings, we develop the capacity to make
choices, we become agents.
Free Will and Determinism
97
Martin and Sugarman note that an important philosophical consequence of
accepting radical social-constructionism, is the idea that we are fully determined by our
environment. Society both originates and regulates the individual in its totality. As a
result, the individual is never in a position to diverge from a given social structure, he is
determined by it. Within the philosophical debate about freedom and determinism,
radical social constructionists fall under the category of hard determinists. In stark
contrast to this position, those who hold we posses free will believe we are able to make
choices that transcend the situations that they are made in. People in this camp sustain
that the individual is completely free to choose his own fate, regardless of the
environment. There is also a third alternative to these two positions called
compatibilism., which holds that an individual can be both determined and free.
There are a variety of forms that compatibilism can take, but Martin and
Sugarman identify one which in their view provides part of the basis for a sound theory
of embedded agency. Their form of compatibilism states that individuals are both
determined and free because their beliefs and desires are included as a variable in the
causal process. If my desires and beliefs are also taken into account in the explanation
of the causal chain, then I have made a free choice. For example, imagine you have
been socialized to become a civil member of society and you hold civility as a belief
and desire. Whenever you act from this belief, you are making a free choice even if the
belief itself originates from your upbringing. Freedom in this sense requires congruence
between your beliefs and your actions. In essence, once the self becomes part of the
98
determinant of behavior, then the individual is both determined and free. The trick is
that the self, according to Martin and Sugarman, is “underdetermined” by social forces.
Underdetermination is a thesis that Martin and Sugarman’s propose in their new
metaphysics of the self. It holds that fundamental dimensions of human existence, such
as biology and society, have an impact in determining the self but cannot wholly shape
it. These forces underdetermine the self, which in turn opens up a space for selfdetermination. This self-determination does not occur in a vacuum, however, like many
free will defenders claim. According to Martin and Sugarman, it is conditioned by
social and biological realities. So, for example, as a member of modern society I can
choose to be employed in a variety of professions, but I cannot choose to be a sixteenth
century Italian poet, or a phrenologist. To put it another way, I can choose to run instead
of walk, but I can’t choose to fly.
Limitations of Martin and Sugarman’s approach
Martin and Sugarman present a persuasive account of how an individual
psychology emerges from the social, and how subsequently these two forces in turn
shape or constitute each other. In the process, they also take a compatibilist position on
the question of free will and human agency, which attempts to integrate our biological
and social embeddedness with our experience of ourselves as the agents of our lives.
Their view is compelling in many ways, and I take it to be more theoretically
sophisticated than the conventional alternatives they discuss.
99
However, their account of what it means to be an individual that remains
embedded in culture contains unexamined assumptions that need to be brought to light
and critically examined. Ultimately, their solution invokes notions that run counter to
some of its own tenets. For example, when they speak of the internalization of sociocultural practices they assume an idea of the mind as an inner-space that contains
mental representations that mediate our experience with an external world.
Additionally, they locate the source of individuality and free choice in cognitive
faculties that allows the self to create a theoretical sphere of distance from the world.
Lastly, they assume that psychology must be explained within the framework of a
natural scientific paradigm. From a Heideggerian (1962) perspective, a source that these
authors claim as an influence, their view of selfhood does not transcend the
individual/society dualism that it attempts to move beyond. It seems that in their effort
to retain an idea of selfhood they revert to the modern Cartesian self that they so
thoroughly criticize.
I am suggesting that Martin and Sugarman might want to develop the
hermeneutic (Gadamer, 1977, 1984, 2000) dimension of their thought more fully, in
order to better accomplish their aim of finding a way that truly goes beyond
postmodernism and cognitive constructivism. Such development may be required if
Martin and Sugarman’s account of selfhood and agency is to escape the theoretical dead
ends and untoward practical consequences of postmodernism and cognitive
constructivism that they so richly document for us.
100
Consider, for example, the question of free will and embeddedness touched
upon briefly earlier in this work. Martin and Sugarman adopt a version of
compatibilism, but Kane (1996) and Richardson and Bishop (2002) present strong
arguments against this view. They point out that a careful analysis of compatibilism
shows that it dissolves rather than preserves genuine freedom and agency. If our desires
and choices are really just links in law-governed chains of efficient causes and their
effects, they do not represent genuine freedom or agency but are quite determined by
past or current events. If they do represent genuine freedom or agency, it would appear
they can do so only as mysterious, unexplainable interventions from beyond the
ordinary world and the events in it. The implication of their criticism is that when
human beings are seen as another entity in the natural world of physics, the determinism
in this perspective does not leave any room for the phenomenon of freedom as
experiences in everyday life. However, according to Richardson and Bishop (2002), the
pursuit of science relies on the ability to detach from the values and meanings of
everyday life. That position "regards the world as it is independently of the meanings it
might have for human subjects, or of how it figures in their experience” (p. 438).
It seems that the problems with the individual/social dualism is not that we need
to find a novel way to recombine these poles; we need to examine first how each of
these categories are defined from the beginning as they carry over assumptions that
render any kind of theorizing problematic. Their inability to provide a sustainable
solution is didactic. It tells us that without a critical consideration of the concepts we
101
inherit we run the risk of repeating the problems we attempt to overcome in our
theories. By that light, any additive solution of internal and external poles proposed in
relational psychoanalysis that does not first engage directly the problems with
individuality as defined by Freud—and ultimately by the Western tradition—will likely
repeat the individualism that it criticizes. Of course, the issues discussed here about
Martin and Sugarman also apply to the problems faced by relational psychoanalysis. To
the extent that relational approaches continue to appeal to biology, as Mitchell does in
response to postmodern approaches, or to the active role of the mind in constructing
reality, as Chodorow does when supporting an individuated process of social
construction, they revert to ideas of a separate subject.
102
Chapter 4: Rethinking Selfhood
Introduction
Throughout this work, relational psychoanalysis has been characterized as an
amalgamation of interpersonal and intrapsychic views that can sometimes be at odds
with each other. Postmodern psychoanalysis, for example, views the individual as an
expression of a socially constructed reality. Instead of a singular self, there are multiple
selves constituted by socially dictated roles. Mitchell (2000), though agreeing that we
are essentially relational and socially constructed, suggests that an authentic core must
remain beneath all social participation as the condition for the possibility of genuine
expression of selfhood. According to him, a multiple self can't explain the continuity of
self-experience that is manifested in everyday life. As a result, Reis (2005) notes:
“relational psychoanalysis shows itself to be rather tentative in its embrace of
postmodernism…there is no fragmented incoherence of subjectivity here, no slip into
merged mindlessness where one can no longer tell who is who” (p. 88). In appealing to
an underlying core, an essence that is subjacent to all transformation, Mitchell has been
criticized for falling back into an individualism that resists being shaped by cultural
forces. In this light, Reis (2005) points out that Mitchell’s project remains at least in
part “modernist”, in spite of his allegiance to a social construction paradigm (p. 88).
This modern vs. postmodern dialectic in relational approaches reveals a problem: how
103
do we explain both the contextual and the individual character of human experience?
How can the self be characterized as fundamentally relational while acknowledging
uniqueness and individuality? Stern (2000) aptly summarizes the dilemma relational
psychoanalysis faces in the following way: “The problem is to maintain some kernel of
psychic life that cannot be completely dissolved in social relations, and to accomplish
that without having to posit essences” (p. 762). Pressing for answers, these issues are
not just academic given that clinicians, at least in part, rely on theoretical frameworks to
structure and direct the therapeutic encounter.
To make matters worse, attempts to overcome this dualism are fraught with
conceptual difficulties that appear deeply problematic, if not completely
insurmountable. Martin and Sugarman (1999, 2000) proposed a metaphysics of
dynamic interactionism, in which individual psychology emerges from sociocultural
and biological origins but then transcends its constraints by means of cognitive faculties
like memory and imagination. Although it stands as a sophisticated proposal, their
appeal to a cognitive distance that frees the individual from the impingement of a
tradition is characteristically modern. It is worrisome that even after attempting to
critically look at their assumptions, refined theorists like Martin and Sugarman fall back
into positions they try to avoid. Taylor (2003) recognizes the perniciously adhesive
quality of these ideas we struggle to bring into question. He notes that we have been
spellbound by a set of assumptions about the nature of the self, and that “just saying
you've abandoned them, and then not giving them any further thought…is a sure recipe
104
for remaining in their thrall” (p. 158). The reason for this, Taylor argues, is that “just
saying that you reject a concept is not necessarily climbing out of the picture that
embeds it. You also have to explore and bring to awareness how that picture holds you
captive. Just walking away avoids doing this” (p. 168). Martin Heidegger (1993, 1996,
2001) spent most of his life trying to spell out the “picture that embeds” (Taylor, 2003,
p. 168) the dualism of intrapsychic vs. interpersonal, which he identified as Cartesian
dualism. Heidegger’s philosophy provides a fertile ground to explore our tendency to
remain engrossed in this picture.
Martin Heidegger’s influence has extended beyond the confines of philosophy.
Hubert Dreyfus (2002) writes that: “his work has been appropriated by scholars in fields
as diverse as philosophy, classics, psychology, literature, history, sociology,
anthropology, political science, religious studies, and cultural studies” (p. vii). This farreaching influence owes much to his innovative way of thinking about the nature of
selfhood and its relationship to the world. Hans-Georg Gadamer (1989, 1993, 2000), a
student of Heidegger, incisively explored the phenomenon of human understanding as it
presents itself in art and history, offering concrete insight into how human beings can be
both relational and individual. Charles Guignon (2002, 2004), a contemporary
continental philosopher, approaches these questions considering how they intersect with
psychotherapy and modern culture. Together, these sources frame the aforementioned
theoretical problems in a new light, suggesting plausible ways to rethink the dualism
that Martin and Sugarman identify and that pervades relational psychoanalysis.
105
Martin and Sugarman (1999, 2000) already draw extensively on the ideas of
hermeneutic philosophy (Heidegger, 1996, 1993, 1996; Gadamer, 1974, 1989) in
outlining their theory. Relational approaches, particularly those of the intersubjective
school (Stolorow, Atwood, & Orange, 2002), also draw on Heidegger and hermeneutics
to articulate aspects of their position. However, I would like to argue that these
approaches do not do full justice to their sources. From a Heideggerian perspective, the
risk of dematerializing the self in the process of contextualizing it only presents itself
because the definitions of self and culture we utilize are not engaged critically enough.
As a result, the question of the relationship between the individual and culture arrives
too late and with too much baggage. What is required is a careful exploration of the
underlying assumptions given in these concepts and how we could move beyond them.
Martin Heidegger: Theory and Everyday life
Heidegger is well known, among many reasons, for his relentless criticism of
the influence of the Cartesian heritage in modern thought. Although his primary area of
philosophical research was ontology, the branch of philosophy that inquires about the
meaning of being, he developed useful insights about the nature of selfhood in the
process of addressing those wider questions. Throughout his work, Heidegger claims
that the Western tradition provided us with a misleading way of thinking about who we
are that obscures some essential aspects of our day-to-day experience. Under the
106
influence of Descartes, the “revered father of modern philosophy” (Cottingham, 1998,
p. 1), we have learned to interpret ourselves as a “thinking, non-extended thing”
(Descartes, 1988, p. 116), minds divorced from an external world of meaningless
objects onto which we project meaning. Guignon (2004) argues that to be a person in
this view: “…is to be a self-contained, bounded individual, a center of experience and
will, with no essential or defining relations to anything or anyone outside oneself” (p.
108). He adds that contemporary philosophers called this view of selfhood the “modern
subject” (Guignon, 2004, p. 108), which is characterized by a number of defining
features.
Perhaps the most significant is that the subject is endowed with a mind, an
internal region that holds the sensations, perceptions, thoughts, and feelings that inform
our experience of an external world. Heil (2003, p. 16) explains that the Cartesian mind
is a non-spatial center of experience to which we have unmediated and private access.
Although it seems like we experience things in space, in the Cartesian model of mind all
of our experiences are non-spatial, as illustrated by the following:
Consider the phenomenon of 'phantom pain', a phenomenon well known to
Descartes and his contemporaries. Amputees often seem to undergo experiences
of pains in their amputated limbs. Your big toe could be amputated, yet you still
might continue to experience the very same kind of throbbing pain you
experienced prior to its amputation, and this pain might seem to you to be in a
region at the end of your foot formerly occupied by your big toe. This suggests
107
that although we experience pains and other sensations as occurring in various
bodily locations, it need not follow that experiences occur at those locations.
(Heil, 2003, p. 17)
A consequence of this view is that we don’t actually experience external events,
but only our representation of them. Of course, Descartes (1988) does not think that the
mind arbitrarily formulates our experience without any correspondence to outside
events. Its function is to represent what goes on externally. Rorty (1979) explains that
this picture presents the “mind as a great mirror containing various representations” (p.
12), of an external word composed of objects. Blackburn (1994) defines this position,
called representationalism, as “the doctrine that the mind works on representations of
the things and features of things that we perceive or think about”, acting as a “container
for ideas” (pp. 328-329). Although the Cartesian mind is what makes us different from
other types of entities in the universe, we also have an extended body that is a part of
the extended world of objects. Cartesian dualism assumes this mechanistic worldview
that gained prominence during the enlightenment (Taylor, 1995). Taylor (1995) notes
that there is a “link between this representational conception and the new, mechanistic
science of the seventeenth century”, which “undermined the previously dominant
understanding of knowledge and thus paved the way for the modern view” (p. 1).
Richardson, Fowers, and Guignon (1999), note that “the early scientists could describe
the world as a vast collection of objects on hand for our theorizing and technological
control”, and “from this perspective, humans are seen as knowing subjects registering
108
input from the external world, processing the data according to rational procedures, and
striving to devise a correct representation of reality” (p. 240). This mechanistic view of
the world continues to animate the project of modern natural science as the most basic
description of the world (Matthews, 1989, p. 133).
But even if Descartes project fit well with the emergence of a mechanistic
worldview, his aim was more ambitious. Bernstein (1983) tells us that Descartes was
seeking a unyielding ground for new knowledge “…that could serve as a foundation
upon which we could construct a ‘firm and permanent structure in the sciences’…”, one
that…“should not rely on unfounded opinions, prejudices, tradition, or external
authority, but only upon the authority of reason itself” (p. 17). However, radical doubt
deprives Descartes of an external departure point for reasoning, for he can trust none,
and thus he is only left with the certainty of self-reflective clarity. Taylor (1995)
explains that Descartes undertakes a “reflexive turn, where instead of simply trusting
the opinions one has acquired through one’s upbringing, one examines their foundation,
which is ultimately to be found in one’s own mind. “ (p. 3). Furthermore, Descartes
does not only intend to find a secure foundation for the sciences, his project is also “the
quest for some fixed point, some stable rock upon which we can secure our lives against
the vicissitudes that constantly threaten us” (Bernstein. 1983, p. 18). According to
Descartes, disengaged and self-reflective reason provides a foundation for a life that
liberates individuals from the errors of prejudice.
109
Many of these characteristics may sound intuitively correct to a contemporary
reader. Yet Heidegger (1996) believes that their obviousness obscures our ability to see
the ways in which we are most unlike a Cartesian subject in everyday life. In short,
Heidegger thinks that this story about who we are keeps us from seeing how our
identity is defined by the relationship we hold to the world, not by our ability to
rationally detach from it. Relational psychoanalysis is clearly sympathetic to the
Heideggerian critique of the subject given their emphasis on the embedded nature of
selfhood. However, I would like to argue that ultimately, relational approaches do not
understand it properly and successfully incorporate it.
In an attempt to shake the tight hold that traditional thinking has on us, Heidegger
introduces a radically different view of human existence, which he terms Dasein. His
work offers a fresh perspective on the relationship between self and world that
transcends the internal/external dualism that plagues modern thought, including the
work of Martin and Sugarman (1999) and relational psychoanalysis.
Dasein as human existence
Polt (1999) writes that the word Dasein is a German expression that “parallels
our word ‘existence’” (p. 29). Heidegger (1996) uses the term to “denote…this entity
which each of us is himself” (p. 27), meaning that he intends to discuss human beings.
Why choose a new term for such an old subject? Polt (1999) explains that “Heidegger
110
doubtlessly wants to avoid the tired old term “man” and invent a new usage, in order to
get to look at ourselves with fresh eyes” (p. 29). Perhaps because of its departure from
previous thought, Heidegger’s subtle vision of selfhood can lend itself to
misinterpretation. As a result, it is useful to consider in a preliminary way how his
understanding of Dasein can be misconstrued. One of the most common errors is to
think of Dasein as a conscious subject. As Dreyfus (1991) explains, Dasein is not a
replacement for the term consciousness, but instead “must be understood to be more
basic than mental states” (p. 13). Dasein is not a mind that contains internal
representations, but, conversely, it is nothing like an object we can encounter in the
world: a kind of thing-like entity with properties. It is very important for Heidegger that
we avoid interpreting Dasein as a mind or a thing, a subject or an object. In fact,
Heidegger introduces the term Dasein precisely to stimulate reflection about who we are
beyond these alternatives presented by the Western tradition.
But if we are neither mind nor thing, what are we from Heidegger’s perspective?
According to him, that question is loaded because it seeks a ‘what’ in terms of which to
define our nature. Unfortunately, the bias of this question is deep-seated since we have
interpreted human nature as a type of persisting substance, a core that lies beneath all
changes, from the beginnings of Western thought (Guignon, 2004, p. 119). Simply
stated, Heidegger’s solution is to shift the question from a ‘what’ to a ‘how’, from
asking about what type of substance we are, to pondering about our way of being. His
answer to this question comprises most of his major work Being and Time (1996), and
111
although an in-depth analysis of it lies beyond the scope of this work, it is possible to
present briefly some of its major concepts.
Heidegger (1993) claims that Dasein has two defining features that make it
different from minds and objects; the first is that Dasein cares about its own being:
“Dasein is a being that does not simply occur among other beings. Rather it
is…distinguished by the fact that in its Being this being is concerned about its very
Being” (p. 54). Unlike rocks, computers, or even dogs, we are capable of caring about
who we are and what happens to us. Heidegger does not mean by this that we are
concerned with our survival, or that we are driven to avoid pain and seek pleasure. He
means that we have the possibility of caring about what kind of person we are and about
the choices we make in our lives. As Melchert (2006) explains:
This feature of Dasein is so central that Heidegger points to it as the essence of
Dasein. In each case—yours, mine—Dasein “has its Being to be” (BT, 33). It is
as though Dasein can’t just be (the way spiders are, for example); Dasein has to
decide about its Being. How it will be is an issue; its Being, for Dasein, is a
problem to be solved; but it cannot be solved in a disinterested way; it is solved
only by living—by existing. (p. 599).
Because being is an issue for Dasein, it is always faced with the task of taking a
stand for what he or she values in life, even if those choices are not thought about
explicitly. For Heidegger, this is an ineludible aspect of our existence: the possibilities
112
we seize or avoid define who we become. As Polt (1999) explains: “ …my own
existence is an issue for me: I am assigned the task of being someone, and the way in
which I deal with the possibilities open to me will determine who I am” (p. 78).
The second defining characteristic of Dasein, closely related to the first, is that:
“The being which this being is concerned about in its being is always my own”
(Heidegger, 1996, p. 40). In other words, Dasein needs to be understood in the firstperson, not as an abstract speculation about human nature but as the living out of one’s
life. Dasein is always concretely you or me: “In accordance with the character of
always-being-my-own-being, when we speak of Dasein, we must always use the
personal pronoun along with whatever we say” (p. 40). In other words, as I am involved
in the process of making decisions and sorting out the meanings in my life, I cannot talk
about my existence as an abstract category. Heidegger seems to point out that there is an
inescapable mineness to our existence, what he calls Jemeinigkeit, which makes it
possible for us to be concerned about our being. Whether we like it or not, we always
have ourselves to be, always remain accompanied by ourselves, even when we attempt
to escape or avoid who we are:
Because Dasein is in each case essentially its own possibility, it can, in its very
Being, ‘choose’ itself and win itself; it can also lose itself and never win itself;
or only ‘seem’ to do so. But only insofar as it is essentially something which can
be authentic - that is, something of its own - can it have lost itself and not yet
won itself. As modes of Being, authenticity and inauthenticity. . . are both
113
grounded in the fact that any Dasein whatsoever is characterized by mineness.
(Heidegger, 1996, p. 68)
In this passage Heidegger introduces the notion of authenticity, a concept that
explains in his view how human beings are deeply embedded in traditions and a shared
world of practices, yet are also able to achieve a form of individuation on the basis of
this context. In the original German, the term authenticity, eigentlichkeit, is
etymologically related to the word “own”, much in the way that the English word
“authentic” derives from the Greek term authentes, which means “one who acted for
himself” (Shipley, 1945, p. 34). In both languages the word points towards the idea of
owning up to the choices we make and how they define who we are. Authenticity is a
central concept for Heidegger, on the basis of which he explains how one can lead a
truly individuated life that (Guignon, 2004). But before exploring its implications, it is
necessary to understand Heidegger’s notion of Dasein more fully.
Dreyfus (1991) points out that mineness needs to be clearly distinguished from
the Cartesian self: “…it cannot mean that each Dasein has a private world of
experience” (p. 25). Mineness does not refer back to a private “I” that is distinct from
the world. Mineness means always having a personal stake regarding what happens
because of one’s participation in a shared world. In fact, Heidegger strongly argues that
Dasein always dwells in a public world of shared meanings and actions. Dasein,
Heidegger (1996) argues, is “being-in-the-world” (p. 12). The hyphenation of the term
emphasizes that our being, our engaged activity of sorting through our possibilities and
114
commitments in everyday living, only makes sense in the context of the world in which
we make those choices. In Heidegger’s (1996) words: “the compound expression
‘being-in-the-world’ indicates…that it stands for a unified phenomenon” (p. 49). Dasein
cannot be understood separately from the world in which it acts. Its relationship to the
world is constitutive of its identity such that there is no Dasein without a world in which
it dwells.
However, Dreyfus (1991) remarks, Dasein is in the world in an entirely different
way than a stone is in the river: “in English we…distinguish between two senses of ‘in’:
a spatial sense (‘in the box’) and an existential sense (‘in the army’, ‘in love’). The first
use expresses inclusion, the second conveys involvement…Being-in as being involved
is definitive of Dasein” (p. 43). Dasein relates to its “there” in an entirely different way
than objects occupy space. Dreyfus’ use of the word involvement indicates that Dasein
maintains an open relationship to places, not merely occupying space but belonging, or
failing to belong, to them. When we ask someone where they are from, for example, we
are not merely curious about the physical location of their birth, but rather about the
influences that define at least part of their identity. The reader might wonder whether
there is anything special or noteworthy about this observation, because obviously
people are different than objects by virtue of being conscious. From Heidegger’s
perspective, this rebuttal entirely misses the experience of what it is like to be involved
in the world. The dominant scientific interpretation of the self as physical organisms
with minds entirely passes over this phenomenon. As a result, being-in-the-world is
115
reduced to having internal ideas about external objects. If Heidegger is right, being
involved is nothing like holding internal representations, but more like having an
inarticulate sense of how and why things matter to us, which he calls having an
understanding of being.
Polt notes (1999) that: “…we have a ‘there’ as no other entity does, because for
us, the world is understandable” (p. 30). For Heidegger, our having a “there” relies on a
background intelligibility that he calls a “vague and average understanding of being”
(1996, p. 4). But for Heidegger, this type of understanding is not an intellectual grasp of
a fact, but rather an ability to cope practically with a situation. Grodin (2002) observes
that:
In this regard, one who “understands” something is not so much someone
endowed with a specific knowledge, but someone who can exercise a practical
skill. A good cook, a good teacher, a good soccer player is not necessarily an apt
theoretician of his trade, but he “knows” his trade, as the English locution puts
it. This “knowing” is, of course, less cognitive than practical, as one “knows”
how to swim. So it is with the basic understanding on which we thrive and by
way of which we sort our way through life. (p. 38)
Understanding for Heidegger, is first and foremost a lived grasp of a situation
on the basis of concrete possibilities of Dasein. As we go about our daily business, we
have a lived understanding of what things mean and how we have to deal with them.
For example, responsible driving requires knowing how to seamlessly operate the
116
vehicle, understanding the rules that govern being on a shared road, and maintaining a
vigilant awareness of changing conditions in the environment. But driving expertise is
not a cognitively explicit grasp of these realities, but rather a situated and lived
understanding that allows someone to respond appropriately and skillfully to a given
situation. We rely on this background familiarity and coping ability, for example, when
we have to break to avoid an accident. An intellectual grasp of the car’s manual and
traffic rules does not make an expert driver. When we need to break in a mere instant,
there is no time to form mental representations that serve as a directive for action. If we
had to become cognitively aware of the situation before making the decision to break, it
would get in the way of our ability to cope skillfully with a potential accident. Before
we engage in any act of thematic cognitive reflection, we already have an inarticulate
sense of what things are and how they matter in the world. According to Heidegger, this
background sense of what is real precedes any thought process and provides the
condition for the very possibility for its existence. To oversimplify, Heidegger is saying
that being precedes and grounds thinking, thus deliberately reversing the well-known
Cartesian dictum cogito ergo sum.
Clearly, there are times when we can and do abstract away from our lived
understanding of the world for certain purposes, as in the case of scientific
experimentation. Scientists keep the object they study at a personal distance in order to
develop theories that describe it a way that is detached from everyday opinions and
attitudes. They are trained to conduct randomized clinical trials, for example, to
117
eliminate the possibility of affecting the results through experimenter bias. Certainly
this is appropriate when evaluating the effectiveness of a new drug in cancer treatment.
How the physician feels about the drug, whether she has a family member who is in the
late stages of the disease, or whether a pharmaceutical company whose success depends
on a positive outcome funds her, cannot enter into the equation. But that attitude of
neutrality and indifference is only a modification, a temporary one, of an engaged
understanding we maintain in our everyday dealings with things. This becomes evident,
for example, when the results of the research provide a favorable outcome and the
researcher meets this with marked enthusiasm. As Mulhall (1996) notes, Heidegger:
…begins by pointing out that our dealings with the world typically absorb or
fascinate us; our tasks, and so the various entities we employ in carrying them
out, preoccupy us. Theoretical cognition of entities…should therefore be
understood as a modification of such concern, as an emergence from this
familiar absorption into a very different sort of attitude. (p. 43)
Heidegger is saying that explicit theoretical representation is not the most basic
way in which we relate to the world. The average and most familiar way in which we
are in the world, he tells us, is concerned involvement. By being engrossed and
occupied in the activities of daily living we take up certain possibilities that define who
we are. We are always engaged in practical coping, dealing with this or that possibility,
in a shared context of significance. Even when we choose to turn away from our
everyday dealings with things to become an objective observer, the attitude of
118
indifferent detachment is itself a mode of relating to things for certain purposes in a
determinate context.
In this light, the idea that our individuality might arise from cognitive abilities,
or from an internal psychological space, becomes suspect. Rather, this idea seems very
close to the Cartesian view of personhood that Heidegger, and often Martin and
Sugarman themselves, criticize. The Cartesian subject comes into its own precisely by
separating itself from its surroundings and traditions, seeking always to represent them
in neutral and objective ways. Charles Taylor (1993) explains that such a “disengaged
perspective” is actually “a rare and regional achievement of a knowing agent whose
normal stance [is] engaged” (p. 323). Our more fundamental “implicit understanding”
or what Heidegger calls “pre-understanding is “not a matter of representation” It
involves a “background sense of reality” that is “nonrepresentational, because it is
something we possess in--that is inseparable from--our actual dealings with things” (p.
327). Only occasionally and for a time do we actually hold explicit theories about the
world, and then only in the context of a lived understanding of the possibilities that our
culture and traditions offer us as participants in them.
Likewise, the idea that we relate to others by reenacting internalized
representations of relational patterns also becomes suspect. It seems more appropriate to
speak of our way of being with others, where relationships are neither inside a mind nor
objectively present in an external reality, like a fully formed object waiting to be
discovered. Relationships, and cultural participation for that matter, carry us forward
119
through shared practices and common meanings in a way that is not captured by talk of
subjective or even intersubjective experience. That way of interpreting who we are
presupposes that meaning resides in the subject and then becomes outwardly projected
onto a neutral reality. If Heidegger is right, the relational matrix that relational
psychoanalyst describe cannot originate from a mind or even from a communion of
minds. Relationships would precede any kind of mental representation of them.
Furthermore, locating them in the individual as a projection of meaning, even if it is
mutual, interactive, and negotiated, attributes to people an unreasonable level of control
over their relationships’ direction and shape. Intersubjective space cannot be
appropriately grasped as a combination of separate individuals, however egalitarian.
Vessey (2005), addressing Gadamer’s (2000) ideas on dialogue, comments that
current discussions of intersubjectivity derive, or at least parallel, Martin Buber’s
concept of an I-Thou relationship. According to Vessey this is problematic because: “IThou relations embody a mystifying substantialization”, and we should look instead at
“dialogical approaches”, which “invoke "the between" as the space of the encounter
between I and Thou; a space that cannot be grasped intellectually” (p. 62). This inbetweenness, for lack of a better term, cannot be grasped as a mixture of two positions,
but rather as a space within which positions come to be expressed and understood. In
other words, I can share my point of view with someone only because there is a prior
shared engagement that makes this possible and intelligible.
120
Here, Gadamer’s (1975) reflections on our participation in history are applicable
to our participation in relationships as well:
In fact history does not belong to us; we belong to it. Long before we understand
ourselves through the process of self-examination, we understand ourselves in a
self-evident way in the family, society, and state in which we live. The focus of
subjectivity is a distorting mirror. The self-awareness of the individual is only a
flickering in the closed circuits of historical life. (p. 278).
Gadamer is indirectly referring here to a feature of human existence that
Heidegger (1996) calls our “thrownness” (p. 174), the fact that we always find
ourselves in a situation with its set of constraints and available meanings, inherited from
our past. In its most radical sense, Heidegger means that we are thrown into the world,
without having chosen our gender, race, religion, place of origin, and all other
constitutive conditions that we are born into. But also in everyday life, as we navigate
the challenges of any given moment, being thrown means that we arrive at that moment
from a past that gives it a determinate shape with its set of conditions and possibilities.
In other words, Heidegger is saying that at any given moment, we never have the option
of jumping out of our own skins. As Dreyfus (1991) puts it: “I am always already
surrounded by objects that matter in some specific way. Dasein is thus always already
given and then needs to take a stand on what it is. It is a self-interpreting foundness.
Heidegger calls this foundness or givenness thrownness” (p. 173).
121
Our thrownness becomes intelligible to us, according to Heidegger, through our
moods. However, far from being an intrapsychic phenomenon, he thinks that moods are
a way of being attuned to our situation. Again, Heidegger cleverly uses his native
language to make his point, as the German word for mood, Stimmung, also means to
tune an instrument (Inwood, 2000, p. 41). Instead of a type of mental content,
Heidegger sees in moods a disclosive relationship to our situation. Moods bring our
involvement in situations into relief. In contrast to emotions, that have a specific object
towards which they are directed, moods reflect the whole of our experience at a given
time. For example, when one is in a depressed mood everything appears as negative or
defeating. As Beck (1979) has persuasively argued in his approach, a depressive state
colors the whole structure of our thinking. For Heidegger, however, a depressed mood
does not represent a failing or distortion on our part, but rather it reflects our ongoing
attunement to our situation. And situations, according to Heidegger, are always already
meaningfully given to us from a past from which we are thrown. We always arrive to
situations as having already been somewhere before. Hence, when we come across an
acquaintance that is visibly upset, we immediately ask what happened to them to cause
them to feel that way.
Although our relationship to a past informs the meanings that are available at a
given time, Heidegger (1996) finds that having a future is a more important dimension
of human existence. As Inwood (2000) explains: “Dasein's potentiality or possibility is
prior to its actuality: Dasein is not a definite actual thing, but the possibility of various
122
ways of being” (p. 23). Because Dasein is its agentic involvement in the world, and not
a fully formed thing located in the present, having future possibilities is its defining
characteristic. As initially stated, being concerned with its own being is what makes
Dasein different than other entities. For Heidegger, being human entails that we are
always confronted with the need to make a choice and projecting ourselves towards a
future. Of course, the range of one’s possibilities is always constrained by the past.
Heidegger does not believe we are pure choice detached from our history. As Warnke
(1987) explains: “the way in which we have understood the past and the way our
ancestors have projected the future determines our own range of possibilities” (p. 39).
At the same time, Warnke (1987) notes that “the way in which we anticipate the future
defines the meaning the past can have for us” (p. 39). This indicates that we are not
constituted by the accruing weight of past circumstances; rather the very meaning of our
past events depends on the possibilities that I am pursuing. For example, a person
training to become a professional violinist who looses a pinky finger might be more
affected than another individual who looses a hand.
As a result of having both a past and a future, Dasein is always already ahead of
itself and being carried forward by projects, explicit or implicitly pursued, that become
possible by drawing on its past. Dasein is not only thrown into a past, but also throws
itself into a future; he or she is not only embedded in a tradition but is also being carried
forward by motives and projects. As Dreyfus (1991) notes: “Dasein is thus already in,
ahead of itself, and amidst” (p. 244). Dasein always finds itself always caught in this
123
ongoing embedded projecting within which the meaning of a situation becomes
apparent. In other words, things matter to us because we have a past and a future, and of
course a present in which their significance opens up to us. For Heidegger, time is the
basis on which things matter for us, the ground upon which we are concernfully
involved in the world. However, when Heidegger identifies Dasein with its situated
involvement, he is not saying that it needs to be reduced to the actualities that surround
him at the present time. Quite the opposite, Dasein can only be present in a situation
insofar as it is already pressing forward into a future on the basis of a past. Guignon
(2002) explains that, for Heidegger: “to be in a situation…is to be part of an unfolding
story with a distinctive temporal structure”, and as a result “the I is historical” (p. 83).
Consequently, the Heideggerian self needs to be grasped as an unfolding event rather
than a kind of enduring substance, like the tradition has typically defined it. Guignon
(2002) fleshes out this embedded view of selfhood, so inextricably tied to situations, by
exploring Heidegger’s account of a climber reaching the summit of a mountain:
…watching the sunrise at the top of the mountain, I experience myself not as a
subject having experiences, and certainly not as an organism functioning in a
geographical location. Instead, I experience myself as the climber who prepared
for days, who rose before sunrise, who braved the cold, who reached the summit
after a difficult climb, and who is now in touch with the beauty of nature. Far
from being one item among others in this scene, my identity as a human is
124
constituted by the entire lived context that makes up my dwelling in the world.
(p. 84).
Guignon (2002) illustrates how the self is, in its very essence, defined by its
lived relationship to the situation in which it participates. Looking for an underlying
substantial self that is separate from its situation, that then somehow internalizes it,
misses the way we actually live through those experiences. Additionally, Guignon
(2002) also explains Heidegger’s (1996) point that our ability to be engaged and open to
the world is only possible on the basis of our relationship to time. In other words, we
can be part of the world because we have a past where we come from, a future towards
which we head, and a present with which we are concerned. As Mulhall (1996)
explains: “for Dasein to disclose entities is for it to manifest a present concern for them,
that grows from its having taken on a project and being oriented towards its future
realization” (p. 155). Heidegger holds that having this relationship to the three temporal
structures, what he calls being historical, allows us to be involved in the world.
However, Heidegger (1996) criticizes our usual definition of time for being too
focused on the present, claiming that we understand it as “a continuous stream of nows”
(p. 463). Scharff (1971) notes that, according to Heidegger, “everyday common sense is
perfectly well satisfied to think of time as an objective structure through whose phases
things, others, and oneself ‘pass,’ moment by moment” (p. 28). In contrast, Heidegger
proposes that we reverse our focus on the present to recognize that our moment-tomoment involvements are only possible on the basis of having a relationship to the past
125
and the future. In other words, my being concerned with an ongoing activity at a given
time point is dependent on having already been engaged on a preceding activity that
continues to be directed on the basis of a concrete possibility. As a result, time is
understood as an unfolding event or trajectory, which has a ‘from’, a ‘towards’, and a
‘here’—past, future, and present—as opposed to a series of linear time points that
stretch infinitely and homogeneously backward and forward. Existential time, as
Heidegger (1996) calls it, is what makes it possible to be engaged actors in an unfolding
meaningful life drama, because it allows us to have a temporal orientation: a specific
relationship to our tradition, our future possibilities, and our present involvement. In
turn, this constitutes the basis of our identity that, according to Heidegger, is itself the
unfolding plot of our life.
Ultimately, Heidegger (1996) can be seen as radicalizing the insights of a
relational approach by stating that Dasein is an unfolding relationship to the world.
However, he contextualizes a relational insight within a critique of traditional Western
philosophy, allowing him to understand the self as an ongoing unfolding event rather
than an enduring fixed core. In this picture, the “core” of Dasein has the unity of a story
unfolding from birth to death. Although selfhood has a narrative structure, it is not a
text like postmodernists claim at times. Rather, selfhood is a happening that has the
structure of a story as an unfolding occurrence with meaning and continuity. We can
and often do stop to articulate our life trajectory explicitly, enriching its meaning and
126
clarifying its direction. At these times we confront ourselves, and often reevaluate who
we are, as we articulate our experiences on the basis of who we want to be.
Psychotherapy is a specific form of that explicit articulation of one’s aims and
participation in life, an activity that can be seen as an exercise in self-understanding.
This type of reflective activity is not circumscribed to psychological self-examination;
one often takes stock of one’s life in several contexts, like civic engagement, religion,
and more pervasively in open dialogue with our immediate family and friends. What is
common to all these experiences is the act of self-examination, so well captured in the
expression taking stock of one’s life, which refers to a careful assessment of the
cumulative meaning of life in light of what needs renewal, replenishing, or change.
Unfortunately, Heidegger (1996) claims, in modern times our ability to pause to
take stock of one’s life has become increasingly difficult for a number of reasons. First
of all, we often find ourselves having no time because of the endless stream of ongoing
engagements that claim our attention and dispose us in constant hurried busyness.
Ironically, the very engrossing business of everyday living prevents us from reflecting
on the ultimate aims of our activities in light of our life as a whole. Equally perplexing,
Heidegger notes, is that the cultural meanings on the basis of which we need to evaluate
our life as a whole have been de-legitimized by enlightenment critiques and scientific
thinking. In the current cultural ethos, meaning and values are seen as either objectively
real or subjectively created (Taylor, 1989). As a result, we are left with no recourse but
to either accept the traditional values as given or to reject them as arbitrary and create
127
our own. Of course, either option is problematic, especially in the context of
psychoanalysis where the explicit aim of treatment is to achieve change that is grounded
in a reworking of meanings rather than passive acceptance or wholesale rejection of
them.
Yet the modern condition leaves little room for a middle road, because as a
series of fully formed moments in a deterministic chain of cause and effects, “the role of
culture and language always threatens either to engulf life in simple determinism, as in
Western science, or else leave us with little to do except continually engage in a vigilant
‘decentering’ or ‘deferring’ of whatever is just now being said” (Scharff, 1997, p. 4).
The second alternative references postmodern appeals to embrace a vigilant and ironic
detachment from our traditions, which become materials for a project of individualistic
self-construction. The problem with this approach, Zimmerman (2000) tells us, is that it
leaves us feeling empty once the exhilarating openness of boundless possibilities turns
into disorientation and shallow overstimulation: “many people find themselves
confronted with captivating, seductive, and expansive options that allow people readily
to exchange one identity for another, such as Internet chat rooms…despite all the
excitement, some people report feeling disintegrated, superficial, even dehumanized”
(p. 123).
Gilles Lipovetsky (2005), echoing Heidegger, notes that postmodernism brought
“the concomitant triumph of consumerist norms centered on living in the present”,
which “indicated the advent of an unprecedented social temporality marked by the
128
primacy of the here-and-now” (p. 29). This presentism promotes an asphyxiating
absorption into the tasks of the modern moment, leaving no time for reflections about
origins and purposes. In this light, Heidegger’s appeal to open up to a different temporal
orientation, one in which there is a sense of unfolding continuity with a tradition that is
meaningfully retrieved in light of current concerns, becomes poignantly appealing.
Heidegger will call this type of historical orientation an authentic one, which leads to
the emergence of an authentic self.
Authentic selfhood
According to Guignon (2004), Heidegger (1962) views selfhood as “an
unfolding event or happening that is so thoroughly enmeshed in a shared lifeworld that
there is no way to draw a sharp line between either self and world or self and others” (p.
120). However, Guignon observes that Heidegger also speaks of an authentic self that
provides cohesiveness to the multiplicity of our social and worldly involvements, which
seems to clash with his other account of a socially enmeshed self. Guignon’s
examination reveals a tension between individual and social accounts of selfhood that
echoes the conceptual problems of relational approaches. However, unlike relational
psychoanalysis, Heidegger is not concerned with defending some form of intrapsychic
reality as the basis for individuality. Heidegger’s (1962) authentic self is not a
psychological substance but nevertheless has the “constancy” (p. 166) and
“selfsameness” (p. 168) of individual identity while remaining part of a shared world. In
129
Heidegger’s view, authentic individuality is not a way of transcending our ties to
society in the name of self-realization, but a way of existing within it.
Everyday life is only possible, Heidegger (1996) tells us, because of public
meanings and activities. Even being alone is possible only because we are temporarily
withdrawing from a shared world, and even when we are unaccompanied we can’t
escape into a private language or culture. As Guignon (2004) notes, the “ongoing
happening of our lives never exists in isolation from the wider context of the world” (p.
123). Daily interaction requires this public horizon of conventions and interlocking
goals through which we can reach an understanding. However, as noted before,
Heidegger is critical of the way in which our engrossed participation in the modern
world engenders a presentism that prevents us from reflecting on life purposes and the
basis for our decisions. In this sense, the social world is a double-edged sword because:
“in the complacency of worldly existence we become so absorbed in the things that
show up on the current scene” that we become “assured that everything has already
been worked out and nothing really calls for a decision” (Guignon, 1993, p. 30).
Heidegger (1962) holds that certain experiences help us break out of our
quotidian contentment. Although he initially identified anxiety in the face of death as
the most important of those experiences, in his later thinking he gave equal weight to
other ones such as profound dissatisfaction, joyous elation, and serene reflection
(Pattison, 2000). The importance of those moments rests on their power to shift our
attention from the things in the world to our responsibility for our existence. Heidegger
130
(1962) calls that change in focus a “moment of vision” (p. 376) in which we face up to
the task of living, because we grasp our existence as a “story unfolding ‘between life
and death’” (Guignon, 1993, p. 8) in which decisions must be made and not everything
is possible. Within this orientation, “the overall shape our lives take is an issue for us”
(Guignon, 2004, p. 127) and what really matters stands in sharp relief, granting a degree
of clarity to our choices without rendering them easy or simplistic. Heidegger argues
that this committed examination of our life as a whole builds an enduring selfhood that
is based on how we live, not on what we are.
Heidegger’s authentic selfhood rests on understanding our mortality as the
contour within which life can be grasped as a whole thus making our choices
meaningful. Yet according to Gadamer (2000), Heidegger’s appeal to mortality
personalizes our experience of finitude at the expense of minimizing the inherently
dialogical nature of self-understanding. For Gadamer, the unfolding story that
constitutes selfhood is not a monologue but a conversation within which we understand
what is most important and make our decisions. In his view, our being comes into relief
only in dialogue because “I experience my own limitation through the encounter with
the Other” (Gadamer, 2000, p. 285). As a result, dialogue provides the contours within
which our life gains coherence. As Vessey (2002) argues:
For Gadamer we exist in conversation or in dialogue with one another and it is
through these conversations that we fully come to realize our limitations.
131
Dialogue is an irreplaceable means for self-understanding. There are insights
about ourselves attainable through dialogue that we would not be able to attain
any other way. This view, if true, would undermine Heidegger's argument that
authenticity is attained only by turning away from others and finding the one
thing that will definitively individuate us. Instead authenticity requires turning
toward others and engaging others in dialogue. (para. 3)
In this light, selfhood is understood as inescapably relational because it emerges
and endures by participating in an ongoing cultural conversation (Taylor, 1994, p. 32).
Gadamer enriches Heidegger’s authentic individual by making its struggle to define its
identity a shared pursuit rather than the individual commitment prevalent in
Heidegger’s early thought (Pattison, 2000). Later in his work, Heidegger (1968, 1971)
would focus on the role of language and our participation in history in taking up our
existence authentically. Gadamer’s account of dialogical understanding can be
construed in part as a continuation of this thinking.
Gadamer and understanding
Within academic circles, Gadamer (1975) is well known for his development of
philosophical hermeneutics, an approach aimed in part at challenging prevailing ideas
about the role of method in the humanities and social sciences. As Warnke (1987)
notes: “his ideas on understanding and interpretation have been applied to a wide132
ranging series of discussions: to questions of interpretation in the study of art and
literature, to issues of knowledge and objectivity in the social sciences; to related
debates in such disciplines as theology and jurisprudence; and even to re-evaluations of
the project of philosophy itself” (p. ix).
Gadamer’s principal aim, however, was to develop a philosophy of human
understanding that builds on Heidegger’s insights regarding the inevitable influence of
tradition and its impact and self-understanding. Blackburn (1994) defines hermeneutics
as “the method of interpretation first of texts, and secondly of the whole social,
historical, and psychological world” (p. 172). This definition is faithful to the origins of
hermeneutics as a method for the interpretation of biblical writings, and later as a
general theory of interpretation that rests on correct utilization of methodology
(Warnke, 1987, p. 1-6). But for Gadamer, hermeneutics is not a methodological
discipline but a philosophical exploration into the conditions for the possibility of
understanding in general.
The heart of Gadamer’s (1975) hermeneutics is reflected in his effort to subvert
the modern meaning of the term prejudice as an undesirable bias: “…if we want to do
justice to man’s finite, historical mode of being, it is necessary to fundamentally
rehabilitate the concept of prejudice and acknowledge the fact that there are legitimate
prejudices” (p. 277). For Gadamer, prejudice is the condition for the possibility of any
understanding, because in order to make sense of our experiences we need to have a
certain ground from which to begin to grasp what addresses us. In other words,
133
understanding is not the imprinting of a external piece of information into a mental
blank slate, but the dialogue between our background sense of reality and the matter
that addresses us in the foreground. Heidegger’s (1996) thinking is a clear point of
departure for Gadamer, noting that: “interpretation is never a presuppositionless
grasping of something previously given…what is initially “there” is nothing else than
the self-evident, undisputed prejudice of the interpreter, which is necessarily there in
each point of departure” (p. 141). Thus, we are always relying on pre-judgment in order
to make sense of our experience because we need a working stance from which to make
sense of what we encounter. According to Gadamer, if we really had to suspend belief
for anything that we had not explicitly judged, then it would be impossible to get along
in the world. In this light, Bernstein (2002) portrays Gadamer’s project as an attempt to
correct the Enlightenment’s view of understanding, in which authority and tradition
were seen as dogma that required the emancipatory power of critical reason. From
Gadamer’s perspective, grounding our understanding on critical rationality that aims to
be free from assumptions fails to grasp that “all understanding requires prejudices or
prejudgments—prejudgments that are inherited from tradition” (p. 272).
However conditioned and prejudiced, understanding in Gadamer’s sense does
not have to become provincial. First of all, prejudices are rooted in cultures that are
composed by various heterogeneous voices. While some may remain dominant, it is
always possible to retrieve less prominent ones in light of changing circumstances.
More importantly, although we begin to understand from our prejudices, we do not need
134
to remain stuck in them but are capable of revising them in light of new situations and
experiences. For example, the civic dialogue that unfolded profoundly challenged the
prejudices present before the civil rights movement. In the hermeneutic view, such
transformation does not come about by escaping prejudice, but by critically engaging it
on the basis of a better understanding. This better understanding itself does not arise
from some enlightened rationality that transcends the limits of cultural prejudice. It is
itself an understanding developed by reworking already existing possibilities within the
tradition. The ideal of equality was already available as part of the civic discourse in the
1950’s. However, this idea had to be appropriated and reinterpreted in light of current
needs and concerns for it to open up the political possibilities that it did. This
engagement with a possibility inherent in the tradition, in the form of critical
appropriation, allowed members of society to change their social standing. Such
possibilities would only be marginally available in other periods, or perhaps not be
available for appropriation at all.
However, Gadamer (1975) recognizes that critical appropriation, and in fact all
dialogue, requires an openness that grants us the freedom to think critically and confront
perspectives. Gadamer characterizes this freedom as a distinctively human
phenomenon: “other creatures do not have a relationship to the world, but are, as it
were, embedded in their environment...man’s relationship to the world is characterized
by freedom from environment” (p. 444). Echoing Heidegger, he reminds us that Dasein
holds an open relationship to a world rather than being instinctually determined by an
135
environment. According to Gadamer (1975), this openness is realized in language,
which grants us a “free, distanced orientation” (p. 445) in the process of “coming to an
understanding” (p. 446) with others. In other words, having a shared language opens up
a space of meanings and concerns that allows us to consider different perspectives. By
enacting language in dialogue, we try to reach an understanding about a common matter
giving ourselves over to the conversation itself. As Guignon (2004) explains: “in his
description of authentic conversation, Gadamer shows how the participants in the
conversation can leave behind their self-preoccupation”, letting the “ongoing play of
ideas...carry the matter forward” (p. 165). Clearly this open engagement is not a
distance from meaning, as in objective detachment, but rather a meaningful distance in
which we are able to let what we encounter address us in its otherness. In this sense, it
represents an example of what Heidegger calls Gelassenheit, or releasement, which
Dreyfus (1992) describes as “a serene openness to a possible change in our
understanding of being” (p. 339). This releasement, requires “letting beings be” as an
active process of receptive and engaged understanding (Heidegger, 1993, p. 125).
However, understanding in this sense is not just an intellectual exchange of ideas, but a
“ life process in which a community of life is lived out” (Gadamer 1975, p. 446).
From a hermeneutic perspective, coming to an understanding in treatment does
not mean avoiding oppression and maintaining equality, but actively engaging with the
patient by quieting our expectations and giving ourselves over to the matter at hand.
This kind of active listening, which should be familiar to a practicing therapist, has a
136
binding force that has nothing to do with being free in the modern sense. Nor can this
listening be free from assumption or prejudice, given the situated nature of
understanding. To be sure, there is a risk of becoming too one-sided in our prejudices,
but Gadamer believes there is always a corrective in dialogue, in letting the other’s
claim show us our limits. Of course, this presupposes that we enter into dialogue
authentically, meaning that we are always seriously open to the truth value of what our
partner says. Seen from this light, the self is this ongoing authentic conversation that
reminds us of our limits and effectively shapes the meaning of our life. If for Heidegger
the self is an unfolding story, for Gadamer it is better understood as an unfolding
conversation.
Personhood and Embeddedness
Martin and Sugarman (1999) are right in attempting to transcend the either/or of
modern and postmodern approaches to selfhood. Both fail to address important aspects
of our existence: our capacity for agency and our belonging to a social structure. After
all, we are all people whose identity depends on social frameworks of meaning, but who
are also capable of innovation and agency. However, recognizing these two realities
does not necessitate that we posit a theoretical or psychological distancing from our
traditions. Doing so entails at least partly assuming a Cartesian view of personhood, one
that fails to see that originality and agency arise mainly from engaged interpretations of
137
our historical possibilities rather than mainly from neutralizing and objectifying our
world in order to obtain the distance needed to exercise our distinctive human agency.
In relational approaches, Mitchell’s (2000) appeal to an enduring core ends up
betraying a retreat into the individualism that it tries to escape. Whatever core remains
through and behind social construction must be unaffected by it, and thus at least
partially solipsistic. But beyond this, Mitchell wants to retain the concept of an
intrapsychic life, and from Heidegger’s perspective this proves problematic in many
ways. The most important of these problems is that doing so places meaning inside a
subject rather than in the unfolding of a storied or conversational self.
On the other hand, postmodern critiques of this notion of interiority involve a
total dissolution of the self, which brings about problems of its own. Even if we
acknowledge that there are multiple selves, it is hard for postmodernists to explain how
we maintain a sense of enduring identity. Clearly, thinking of the self as singular and
enduring can be limiting, rigid, and oppressive. But living in constant fragmentation and
ambiguity does not seem like an appealing alternative. Postmodernists readily accept
that there is no longer an absolutely secure foundation for our identity, and in the face
of this they often retreat into a pragmatic relativism. But their position betrays an
underlying belief that absolute knowledge is the only type of knowledge, and in the
absence of this we are left with nothing but individual subjectivity. Their resulting
ironic detachment is not too different from scientific indifference. A socially constituted
self is never in the position to arbitrarily pick and choose his or her beliefs. As Gadamer
138
notes, our prejudices set the playing field for the possibility for understanding. Even
though we can challenge them, improve them, or embrace them upon further
examination, what we can never do is to think that we can detach from them in such a
way that we are in the position to merely reject them.
The psychoanalytic intersubjectivists (Stolorow, Orange, and Atwood, 2001)
present a more nuanced approach. They recognize that appealing to intrapsychic
experience is problematic in many fronts. In fact, they often criticize their relational
colleagues for remaining enthralled by modernism. But their discussion of individual
worlds is inconsistent with Heidegger’s and Gadamer’s philosophy. For them, the world
is never something that is individually constituted. It certainly depends on the
participation of individuals, but it is not contained within them or carried along with
them as personal structures of meanings. Even though we can have many different
experiences in the world, we are still part of the same social reality. Of course, this does
not mean that everyone’s experience is the same. Differences and conflict in our
experience of the world based on gender and race are real, but they always presuppose a
common arena of social engagement within which we have our disagreements and
conflict. After all, if we were all truly inhabiting our own worlds, we would not have so
much to disagree on because we would not be relating to each other to begin with.
Many of these conflicting views do a good job of exposing the shortcomings and
problems with the other side of the argument, and in doing so they may intimate a fresh
approach of a third way beyond these extremes in the mind of a sensitive reader.
139
However, they say very little about what that third way or genuine path would be. I
believe the hermeneutic view I have discussed here sketches such a view in a broad but
credible way. Although there are many details to be filled in and many questions to be
answered, it seems to me hermeneutics offers a fresh point beyond these clashing
perspectives. In the end, it seems best to understand hermeneutics not as offering a
theoretical replacement to relational approaches, but rather as providing a wider context
within which their best insights can be incorporated and some of their limitations
transcended. Construed as an authentic conversation that is always open to revision
through partnering dialogue, the self can be understood as both essentially relational yet
also capable of agency and responsibility.
140
Chapter 5: Clinical implications
Introduction
As previously stated, an inquiry into our understanding of selfhood is limited if
it does not inform the realities of clinical practice. Unfortunately, according to several
prominent psychoanalytic theorists, the relationship between theoretical innovation and
clinical practice in psychoanalysis is far from being understood with clarity. Loewald
(1970) warns us that “an investigation of the relationship of psychoanalytic theory to
the psychoanalytic process and method is fraught with difficulties and pitfalls” (p. 45),
and Greenberg (1986) notes that “few issues in psychoanalysis are quite so muddled, or
tend to generate quite so much confusion in the mind of the clinician, as the relationship
between theory and technique” (p. 87), while Ornstein and Ornstein (2003) note “there
is a high degree of ambiguity in the psychoanalytic literature about the precise role and
function of theory in the psychoanalytic treatment process” (p. 157).
Nevertheless, many psychoanalytic thinkers also argue that even if we can’t
properly grasp their relationship, theory and practice are inextricably tied. For example,
Smith (2003) makes the case that “theory ‘thinks’ in the analyst” (p. 1) by providing a
framework for the selection of relevant information in what would otherwise be an
overwhelming amount of possible interpretations. Conversely, while theory frames the
clinical encounter, Loewald (1970) reminds us that it needs to “keep faith with our work
as analysts”, such that its abstractions are valuable only insofar as they respond to the
141
particulars of the session (p. 45). In other words, theories must helpfully address the
here-and-now reality of the session. This need to make the theory relevant to the
particulars of the encounter requires the analyst to apply it in specific ways. According
to Greenberg (1986):
Theory applied is, inevitably, theory interpreted. Personal predilection gives the
application an idiosyncratic, and decisive, cast. By the time it is run through the
analyst's particular vision of human life, not to mention his personality, the
impact of theory is difficult to trace. (p. 87)
The interconnectedness of personal and theoretical positions does not amount,
according to Greenberg (1986), to a subordination of “theory to intuition, empathy, and
pragmatism” (p. 87). Even if the application of theory requires adopting a first-person
perspective, the substance of those theoretical principles still compels the analyst to
pursue certain directions in treatment, even if it cannot prescribe action directly and
unequivocally. For example, the classical dictum to avoid gratifying the patient stands
in stark contrast to the relational emphasis on participative disclosure.
On the other hand, Fonagy (2003) is right in qualifying the influence of theory
on practice by noting that “it has been impossible to achieve any kind of one-to-one
mapping between therapeutic technique and theoretical frameworks” (p. 25).
Additionally, Fonagy (2003) argues, psychoanalytic theory has often been driven by
clinical discoveries, which casts doubt on the traditional image of technique organically
flowing from a refined theoretical position. Fonagy’s (2003) observation certainly gains
142
support from Kohut’s (1979) and Guntrip’s(1996) clinical grounding for their
theoretical shift. It seems then that there is an interplay of theoretical and practical
dimensions in the clinical encounter and in the development of theory. Ornstein and
Ornstein’s (2003) reflections on the influence of theory on practice are particularly
relevant here:
Each clinical presentation we listen to quickly reveals the existence of two
artificially separable, but in reality thoroughly intertwined, layers of experience
in the analytic situation. The first layer of experience consists of the clinical
atmosphere created by the analytic dyad: for example, how patient and analyst
greet each other; how the issues regarding the fee are negotiated; how silences
are tolerated by each; and so on. The experiences in the first layer are affected
by the experiences in the second layer. The impact of the analyst's particular
public theory can be more readily discerned in the second layer, based on what
the analyst selects to comment on— what areas he or she chooses to investigate
and to interpret” (p. 159)
Ornstein and Ornstein (2003) present theory and practice as interrelated
layers of psychoanalytic experience that mutually inform each other, arguing that
personal, interpersonal, and theoretical positions all influence the therapeutic encounter.
In spite of their acute observations, we are left wondering just how this interrelatedness
unfolds in the consulting room. How is it that theory affects practice and vice versa?
143
Greenberg’s (1986) observation that “theory applied is, inevitably, theory
interpreted” suggests that utilizing theory is like following the assembling instructions
for a new piece of furniture. Clinical judgment enables a therapist to respond at the right
time and for the right purpose rather than follow rule-based behavior. In fact, we read
manuals when we lack the expertise to do something. Dreyfus (2000) notes that the
mark of a novice is precisely this need for rules, while expertise is characterized by
knowing “how to perform the appropriate action without calculating and comparing
alternatives” (p. 159). At the point of expertise “theory ‘thinks’ in the analyst” (Smith,
2003, p. 1) organically informing the ongoing dialogue. However, as a context bound
interpretive process, the voice of theory in practice must respond to the realities of the
analyst-patient relationship rather than dictating the direction of treatment. For that
reason, effective practice involves listening to the voice of theory as much as
developing useful clinical theory involves listening to the unfolding relationship
between analyst and patient. Yet, once more, it is far from entirely clear how this
process unfolds, or should unfold, in treatment.
Theory and practice reconsidered
Part of what obscures the concrete relationship between theory and practice is a
working definition of theory that is based on the natural scientific model of
understanding. As mentioned before, theory in this sense as the dispassionate
144
contemplation of objects independent of human meanings and practices, serves an
essential purpose when pursuing natural science. Desirable advancements in medicine,
agricultural production, and communication, to name only a few areas, have been
achieved as a result. But Guignon (1993) notes that in psychology :“many therapists and
mental health professionals continue to feel that the mainstream ‘scientific’ theories
designed to explain and guide psychotherapy fail to capture much of what actually goes
on in the practice of therapy”, adding that “standard theories fail to make sense of the
rich and complex forms of moral discourse that characterize therapeutic dialogue” (p.
216) . Psychoanalysis itself is already deeply involved in the process of debating its
identity as a natural science or a culture-bound interpretive discipline (Gedo, 1999). The
work of Strenge (1991), Schafer (1992), and Stern (2003) stand as examples of theorists
who reject the framework of the natural sciences as inadequate for capturing the
psychoanalytic process. The reason for this, according to Taylor (2002), is that the very
object of psychology is essentially different from that of the natural sciences:
in Truth and Method, Gadamer shows how understanding a text or event, which
comes to us out of our history, has to be construed, not on the model of the
“scientific” grasp of an object, but rather on that of speech-partners who come to
an understanding (Verständigung). If we follow Gadamer's argument here, we
come to see that this is probably true of human science as such. That is, it is not
simply knowledge of our own past that needs to be understood on the
“conversation” model, but knowledge of the other as such. (pp. 126-127)
145
Taylor (2002) goes on to argue that the inadequacies of a natural scientific
model emerge when contrasting human beings to physical objects or processes. First,
and particularly relevant for psychology, unlike objects, human beings talk back thus
making any kind of theory development a bilateral endeavor. Second, the goal of
enquiry in the human sciences is different because it does not seek “attaining some
finally adequate explanatory language, which can...exclude all future surprises” (Taylor,
2002, p. 127). Third, and most important, because we are asking questions about human
beings:
The end of the operation is not control, or else I am engaging in a sham,
designed to manipulate my partner while pretending to negotiate. The end is
being able in some way to function together with the partner, and this means
listening as well as talking, and hence may require that I redefine what I am
aiming at. (Taylor, 2002, p. 127).
As a result of having a radically different object of study, a theory in the social
sciences, particularly one as practically concerned as psychology, needs to reflect and
respond to the realities of human relationships. Doing so would lead to a permeable
integration of theoretical and practical dimensions of social scientific practice.
The theory-practice relationship articulated in this sense can be captured, and
potentially enriched, by Gadamer’s (1975) account of dialogical understanding. From
this perspective, theory speaks in practice as much as it listens to it; both inform but
cannot dictate the other. The domination of theory risks dogmatism, while its
146
abolishment risks foreclosing the possibility of reflecting on our practices. Theory has
the potential to let crucial material stand as relevant and thus become part of the
discussion. Conversely, it cannot exhaust the issues that become relevant in treatment.
Furthermore, from a hermeneutic perspective, treatment is embedded in a larger cultural
horizon suffused by rich meanings and possibilities that make the theory-praxis
relationship possible in the first place. In Gadamer’s (1974) language, theory and
practice are part of this wider cultural horizon within which analyst and patient strive to
understand each other.
Hermeneutic dialogue as a model for the theory-practice relationship
As previously noted, Gadamer (1975) holds that all understanding is historically
situated and conditioned by the prejudices that we bring along to the situation: “we
started by saying that a hermeneutical situation is determined by the prejudices that we
bring with us. They constitute, then, the horizon of a particular present, for they
represent that beyond which it is impossible to see” (p. 306). Such a statement could
lead the reader to believe that all understanding blinds us to anything that stands outside
our prejudice, but Warnke (1987) explains that Gadamer strongly rejects the idea that
“because we are prejudiced, or, otherwise put, because we speak a certain language and
use certain categories we are cut off from their languages, other cultures, and even our
own past” (p. 81). As Taylor (2002) points out, for Gadamer “the road to understanding
147
others passes through the patient identification and undoing of those facets of our
implicit understanding that distort the reality of the other” (p. 132).
What is more, our situated understanding is never fixed or complete but always
in the process of becoming revised in light of something new. Gadamer (1975) notes
that it is an “error in thinking to claim that the horizon of the present consists of a fixed
set of opinions and valuations” (p. 306), but we should notice that “the horizon of the
present is continually in the process of being formed because we are continually having
to test all our prejudices” (p. 306). This ongoing reworking of our own meanings in
light of the truth of the matter under discussion is not a prescription, but rather a
common feature of human existence. Even in the most desperate of situations, Gadamer
tells us, people often strive to reach a common understanding that is based on shared
discussion about a common matter. Although Gadamer has been taken to task by
Derrida (1989) for what he considered to be an overly optimistic view of humanity’s
good will to engage in dialogue, Gadamer has a strong argument in his observation that
any communicative act presupposes the desire to be recognized and the belief that it is
possible. Surely there are better and worse versions of this, but the act of trying to reach
an understanding on a common matter is a universal feature of human existence,
according to Gadamer.
There are always risks and limitations when we try to understand. But Gadamer
utilizes the concept of a horizon to emphasize that in understanding “one learns to look
beyond what is close at hand—not in order to look away from it but in order to see it
148
better, within a larger whole and in truer proportion” (p. 305). Simply stated, in
maintaining awareness of our finite take on things, we are able to transcend it by
appealing to a broader context and enriched horizon. This does not mean that we
somehow reach a point where we can understand free of prejudice, instead, our
prejudices become transformed by richer and wider horizons. The goal is not to
transcend prejudice because, as a positive phenomenon, prejudice always makes
understanding possible in the first place by providing a ground from which to make
sense of a situation.
According to Gadamer (1975), hermeneutic dialogue of this kind involves two
constitutive movements: the anticipation of completeness and application. The first
movement involves granting provisional authority to the claims of the person, text, or
experience that we encounter and engage in dialogue. This is a difficult task, because it
requires a person to take what Gadamer (1975) calls an attitude of “being negative
towards itself” (p. 461), in order to let the meaning of what is confronted truly assert
itself. This demands a special kind of rigor in listening that requires the granting of at
least temporary authority to the claim of the other. But it does not mean that we have to
surrender our views to passively accept what is presented to us. That would not be
understanding but indoctrination, and the corrective to this possibility is what Gadamer
calls application, which entails considering the other’s claim in light of our own situated
horizon. Scharff (1997) effectively illustrates how application and the anticipation of
completeness functions in open dialogue:
149
When I am disposed to listen, I no longer state, or speak out of, "my position."
Nor do I try to keep myself out of the affair and merely paraphrase or say back
the other's words. Rather, I draw upon my own determinate materials--my own,
current, yet always only partially explicit understanding--to form a listening
statement. And I let the other correct it. (p. 1)
Scharff’s comment draws attention to several feature of hermeneutic dialogue.
First, he notes that it requires a disposition to listen, a type of openness to the claim of
the other that compels us to curtail our tendency to speak from a set of already formed
ideas about what should be said, what he calls a position. Nevertheless, he points out
that listening always occurs from a particular vantage point, albeit not a fully
determinate one, from which to respond to what is said. Lastly, this act requires an
involvement in the situation, and thus responding by merely paraphrasing what was said
illustrates a detachment and lack of understanding. This kind of involved openness from
one’s incomplete perspective also reveals that anticipation of completeness and
application are not sequential steps in a method, but rather a concrete disposition in
dialogue with others. These movements occur simultaneously, meaning that I can only
listen if I can both grant some authority to the other’s claim, however minimal, while
making sense of it from the concrete realities of my situation. What is more, personal
prejudices are not arbitrarily created; they are embedded in shared traditions handed
down through history, such that understanding becomes “situated within an event of
tradition, a process of handing down” (p. 309). In other words, Gadamer does not think
150
that dialogue occurs between two separate subjectivities, it is a shared unfolding event
that is historically situated in the larger conversation of the tradition. This is why
Gadamer (1975, p. 278) claims that we belong to history before it belongs to us.
Gadamer’s notion of authentic dialogue can inform treatment while explaining
how this process shapes the self. As previously noted, Gadamer contextualizes
Heidegger’s critique of a substantive view of the self by bringing to light how we
define our identity by means of an ongoing conversation with culture and others. To the
extent that this conversation is authentic, it allows a person to confront their limits and
gain a renewed sense of identity and purpose. Under the model of selfhood as an
ongoing authentic dialogue, the self is a conversation stretched from birth to death, and
therapy is an opportunity to reexamine our unfolding history, to rework our history in
light of present concerns as it is oriented towards a future. Rather than focusing on the
self in isolation from context, therapeutic dialogue is a working through of our being-inthe-world as it opens up in one’s history and future possibilities. In the end, the insights
of a hermeneutic approach, of authentic dialogue with one another, are not terribly new.
When therapy is done well, it already incorporates many of its features. In essence, it
points to the importance of the telling of stories that help make sense of our identity and
our life.
In this sense, a relational approach is a concrete theoretical advancement that
captures the best insights that motivated Freud himself. Spezzano (1995) reminds us
that: “Ironically, toward the end of her life, Anna Freud told the American
151
psychoanalyst Robert Coles that…she lamented that Freud the confessional storyteller
had been replaced in the minds of analysts by Freud the theorist” (p. 21). As Mitchell
(2000) states, Freud was always concerned with making sense of human relationships
(p. ix). Retrieving this hermeneutic dimension in Freud, who at one point recognized
that establishing a theoretical psychology based on a natural science model is perhaps
unachievable (Flyvbjerg, 2001), is necessary in light of our need to enter in authentic
dialogue with the tradition of psychoanalysis, and psychotherapy at large. Gadamer’s
notion of authentic dialogue provides the opportunity to retrieve relational and classical
insights while providing a corrective to their partial allegiance to modern ideals of
context free individuality.
Hermeneutics and treatment
It is difficult to concretely spell out how a case, the analysis of Mr. Z for
example, would exactly play out from this hermeneutic perspective. Certainly, appeals
to internal and determining psychic structures would draw attention away from an
engagement in history and crafting future possibilities. Instead, there is a real need to
help the patient articulate the nature of their dissatisfaction in light of their best
understanding of their situation and how they project themselves in the future. Mr. Z is
isolated, anxious, and arrested in history, still dominated by an experience that he seems
152
to be repeating, stuck in an eternally recurring present. This repetitive attunement to his
history is not something to overcome through rational insight, as an objectively
detached observer. Neither can it be just catharted out, like a purely emotive experience
also detached from the binding meanings of the past. Mr. Z is forced to truly face
himself and confront the experience that continues to be repeated in an ongoing event of
interpretation. This involves a carefully monitoring of his actions, thoughts, and feelings
in light of his history and how he already knows it falls short of where he would like to
be. To be sure, this occurs in the context of partnering dialogue, where Mr. Z can be
given the opportunity to thematically rework the meaning of that experience as a matter
of shared concern. Mr. Z needs to articulate with earnestness, what is it like to continue
to be that injured child in light of his need to be an adult in the world. Not because he
needs to be cradled or because he needs the compassion to heal a narcissistic injury.
Certainly compassion is an integral part of this confrontation and rewriting of one’s
history and thus self-understanding. But the direction of that questioning is provided by
what Mr. Z already knows: he is not living well, and there is more to life than what he is
experiencing. Of course, the classic alternative of helping Mr. Z renounce childish
wishes for wholeness is also inappropriate here. Mitchell and Aron (1999) are right in
pointing out that there is value in opening an alternative between merely validating the
patient’s feelings and asking them to achieve a stoic rational insight into their situation.
The careful process of helping patients see their relationship to others, so that modifying
it is an option, is neither colluding nor criticizing the client. It involves engaging in
153
dialogue to help them confront the ongoing event that they are, in light of their present
dissatisfaction with how their life is unfolding. Clients are aware, however remotely,
that they fall short of who they need to be. Articulating that pre-reflective understanding
in open dialogue with another brings it into the open so it can be thematically reworked.
For the client, engaging in this process requires both trusting the claims of the therapist
who helps understand their limits, but also applying the therapists voice in light of their
experience. What emerges in that process, when it is conducted authentically, is
perspicuously described by Guignon (2004) in the following manner:
the locus of this activity as we experience it is not my mind and yours, but rather
the “between” made concrete in the issue of the truth of the matter we are
discussing. In vital, intense discussion, egos fall away and are replaced by
something much more important: the matter that matters. (p. 165).
From a hermeneutic perspective, what matters in the unfolding of people’s life is
always shaped by shared cultural values and meanings. Taylor (1985) notes that these
constitute “inescapable frameworks” (p. 1) that provide the basis for meaningful action
and identity. In this sense, the therapeutic endeavor involves examining and reworking
the values and commitment that already shape our identity. But because dialogue is
always done through a partnering effort, it follows that the therapist cannot
meaningfully partake of that conversation unless they also engage and comment on the
meanings and values that are shaping the client’s life. Certainly relational approaches
are quick to acknowledge the role of the analyst in shaping the direction of the therapy
154
(Mitchell & Aron, 1999; Fairfield, Layton, & Stack, 2002), but it is not clear that they
let the implications of this observation sink deeply enough. Zeddies and Richardson
(1999) note that after criticizing traditional notions of the therapist as wise expert,
Mitchell (1998):
suggests that ‘the analyst's expertise lies, most fundamentally, in his or her
understanding of a process — what happens when one person begins to express
and reflect on his or her experience in the presence of a trained listener, in the
highly structured context provided by the analytic situation” (p. 21). In this sense,
Mitchell's approach offers “a view of the analyst's knowledge and authority that
portrays the analyst as an expert in collaborative, self-authorizing self-reflection”
(p. 26).
However well intentioned, and likely based on a deep respect for the autonomy
of the other, Mitchell’s observations miss that it would be impossible to truly listen
without already participating in some shared meanings. What is more important, if
listening is not to become a mere parroting but a way to help the patient reframe their
experience in richer and more constructive ways, Mitchell must rely on frameworks of
meaning that will inevitably transforms the personal search for meaning of the client. In
other words, therapy cannot exercise what Mitchell (1992) calls the facilitation of
“personal meaning” (p. 285) without somehow bringing to the table a viewpoint that
informs what enriches meaning in everyday life.
155
The modern fear of indoctrinating the client clearly presents itself here
(Guignon, 2004, p. 232), and it is not without reason given the degree of trust the client
places in the therapy and the potential for abuse. But it becomes essential to see that this
respect for the autonomy of the other, perhaps reminiscent of the Hippocratic dictum to
“first do no harm”, is itself a meaningful framework that shapes the direction of
treatment. As part of a larger modern project of promoting personal emancipation from
oppressive structures, explicitly embodied in the feminist approach of Fairfield, Layton,
and Stack (2002), we respect the client’s individuality and tentatively offer our theory.
But this underlying respect for autonomy tends to obscure other values that make a
treatment outcome successful. Buechler (2004), in her recent book Clinical Values:
Emotions that Guide Psychoanalytic Treatment poignantly articulates some of the
resources upon which treatment draws to achieve its aims:
Treatment is, I believe, inherently a life-and-death struggle. It takes enormous
energy and commitment from both participants. I don’t think we can muster,
sustain, and inspire this over a career if all we believe we have to offer is one
among many possible perspectives. Theories making such modest claims appeal
to the mind more than the heart or soul. They don’t engender enough hope, or
joy, too sustain a real fight for life. (p. 2)
Mitchell (1993) views hope as an essential aspect of successful treatment, and his
description of this phenomenon in clinical practice is rich and nuanced. Yet, as
Buechler accuses, relationality as a theory of self can be found thin and wanting in light
156
of the wealth of meanings Mitchell describes in his therapeutic vignettes. Relational
psychoanalysis clearly attempts to thicken psychoanalytic descriptions of selfhood with
its emphasis on the interconnectedness of human experience, which echoes Aristotelian
values of politically embedded personhood. Yet Hillman (1994), in an article exploring
psychology’s view of the patient in light of Aristotelian notions of selfhood, explains
that:
the patient cannot, definitely not, by definition, become a citizen, so long as the
model of the psyche which therapeutic analysis serves remains fixed where it is.
this model locates psyche either as intrapersonal (within human subjects) or
interpersonal (between subjects in relationships, transference, group dynamics,
and family systems). Soul is not in the world of systems like trees, rocks, cars
and ashtrays, nor is it in the world of systems like education, finance, party
politics, language and technology (p. 30).
Mitchell’s (1993) rich description of hope and dread in the psychoanalytic
situation evidences a masterful grasp of the subtle dynamics of human interrelatedness
that have binding and healing force. To the extent that this phenomena is subsumed
under the facilitation of personal fulfillment, it misses its structuring power and reduces
it to an instrumental means to an end. In the case of Mr. Z, it is likely that his feelings
of isolation and anxiety would become reinforced if the treatment is modeled on the
ideals of individuality and self-determination rather than engagement, commitment, and
openness to others. Hirsch (2003) describes the analytic situation in relational
157
approaches as working under “ the assumption of a universal conflict revolving around
the wish to remain enmeshed within internalized familial configurations, on one hand,
and the striving for the freedom and the loneliness of separation and individuation on
the other” (p. 217). It is clear to see how the alternatives repeat the seemingly
inescapable dilemma of the self either collapsing into a determining history, or stoically
detaching from it to face a lonely fate. Mr. Z cannot bear either alternative, he cannot
continue being who he is, and he would not do well in becoming more individuated.
We can find an alternative in authentic dialogue, one that rests on carefully
interpreted cultural meanings, as a helpful possibility for Mr. Z. Treatment in this sense
cannot use the cultivation of “a capacity for a certain responsiveness to oneself”(p.
184), as Mitchell (2001) suggests, as a yardstick for its success. In authentic dialogue
there is a cultivation of a responsiveness to the ongoing conversation, always reliant on
the participation of its members but also transcending their individual outlooks and
carrying them forward. The mark of success in treatment, from a Gadamerian
perspective, is suggested by the development of phronimos (Vessey, 2002), a lived
practical wisdom, which allows patients to respond appropriately to situations. In other
words, the patient is able to masterfully respond to the challenges presented by life.
Zeddies (2001), and Flyvbjerg (2001) identify phronesis as the sine qua non for
successful psychoanalysis and social science respectively. They explain, however, that
it is different from a technical orientation to life, wherein our behavior is seen as means
to obtaining some end rather than being intrinsic to the end itself. In this sense,
158
phronetic dialogue involves careful deliberation about one’s ends in life, in light of
one’s best understanding of our values and commitments. Of course, as Zeddies (2001)
remarks: “Thinking about analytic work as a moral enterprise stands in sharp contrast to
what has heretofore been the conventional “wisdom” within analytic circles of what
psychoanalytic therapy is and how it should work” (p. 228). Yet psychoanalysis, and
psychology at large, is already involved in this process whether or not it becomes
explicitly aware of it. Ultimately, heeding Heidegger and Gadamer’s thought requires
contextualizing relational and classical approaches in a wider philosophical horizon that
allows us to retain the best of their insights, while suggesting directions for
improvement. As such, the effort of this work constitutes merely a point of departure,
and requires further deliberation about how an authentic dialogical effort could be
practiced in treatment. However, if we take Heidegger and Gadamer’s thought to heart,
we can never reach any final take in matters of self-understanding.
159
References
Beattie, H. J. (2003). 'The repression and the return of bad objects': WRD Fairbairn and
the historical roots of theory. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 84(5),
1171-1187.
Beck, A. T. (1979). Cognitive therapy of depression. New York: Guilford Press.
Beebe, B., & Lachmann, F. (2003). The Relational Turn in Psychoanalysis: A Dyadic
Systems View from Infant Research. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 39(3), 379409.
Berman, E. (1997). Relational psychoanalysis: a historical background. American
Journal of Psychotherapy, 51(2), 185-203.
Bernstein, R. J. (1983). Beyond objectivism and relativism science, hermeneutics, and
praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Bernstein, R. J. (2002). The Constellation of Hermeneutics, Critical Theory, and
Deconstruction. In R. J. Dostal (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Gadamer
(pp. 267-282). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Blackburn, S. (1994). The Oxford dictionary of philosophy. Oxford; New York: Oxford
University Press.
Bodin, G. (1994). A comparison of concepts in self-psychology and Winnicott's theory
of the development of the self. Scandinavian Psychoanalytic Review, 17(1), 4058.
160
Bromberg, P. M. (1980). Sullivan's Concept of Consensual Validation—Sullivan's
Concept of Consensual Validation and the Therapeutic Action of
Psychoanalysis. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 16, 237-248.
Bruch, H. (1977). Sullivan's Concept of Participant-Observation (A Symposium)—
Participant Observation. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 13, 347-350.
Carveth, D. L. (1996). [ Review of the book Fairbairn and the Origins of Object
Relations]. Canadian Journal of Psychoanalysis, 4(2), 343-353.
Chodorow, N. J., & Chodorow, N. (1991). Feminism and Psychoanalytic Theory. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Cottingham, J. (1998). Descartes. New York: Oxford University Press.
Crastnopol, M. (2001). Convergence and Divergence in the Characters of Analyst and
Patient: Fairbairn Treating Guntrip. Psychoanalytic Psychology, 18(1), 120-136.
Cushman, P. (1990). Why the self is empty. American Psychologist, 45(5), 599-611.
Cushman, P. (1994). Confronting Sullivan's Spider—Hermeneutics and the Politics of
Therapy. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 30, 800-844.
Derrida, J. (1980). Writing and difference. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Derrida, J. (1989). Three questions to Hans-Georg Gadamer. In D. Michelfelder & R.
Palmer (Eds.), Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer-Derrida Encounter
(pp. 52-54). Albany, New York: SUNY Press.
Derrida, J. (1997). Of Grammatology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Descartes, R. (1988). Selected Philosophical Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge
161
University Press.
Dimen, M., & Goldner, V. (2002). Gender in Psychoanalytic Space: between clinic and
culture. New York: The Other Press.
Dostal, R. J. (2002). The Cambridge companion to Gadamer. New York, NY:
Cambridge University Press.
Dreyfus, H. (2000). Could Anything Be More Intelligible than Everyday Intelligibility?
Reinterpreting Division I of Being and Time in the Light of Division II. In M. A.
Wrathall & J. E. Faulconer (Eds.), Appropriating Heidegger (pp. 155-174). New
York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-In-The-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and
Time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dreyfus, H. L., & Wrathall, M. A. (Eds.). (2002). Heidegger reexamined. New York:
Routledge New York.
Eagle, M. N. (2003). The Postmodern Turn in Psychoanalysis: A Critique.
Psychoanalytic Psychology, 20(3), 411-424.
Ellenberger, H. F. (1970). The Discovery of the Unconscious: The History and
Evolution of Dynamic Psychiatry. New York: Basic Books.
Fairfield, S. (2001). Analyzing Multiplicity: A Postmodern Perspective on Some
Current Psychoanalytic Theories of Subjectivity. Psychoanalytic Dialogues,
11(2), 221-251.
Fairfield, S., Layton, L., & Stack, C. (Eds.). (2002). Bringing the Plague: Toward
162
Postmodern Psychoanalysis. New York: The Other Press.
Flax, J. (1990). Thinking Fragments: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, and Postmodernism in
the Contemporary West. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Flyvbjerg, B. (2001). Making Social Science Matter: Why Social Inquiry Fails and How
it Can Succeed Again. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fonagy, P. (2003). Some Complexities in the Relationship of Psychoanalytic Theory to
Technique. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 72(1), 13-47.
Fosshage, J. L. (2003). Contextualizing Self Psychology and Relational Psychoanalysis:
Bi-Directional Influence and Proposed Syntheses. Contemporary
Psychoanalysis, 39(3), 411-448.
Foucault, M. (1978). Politics and the study of discourse. Ideology and Consciousness, 3,
7-26.
Foucault, M. (1982). The Subject and Power. Critical Inquiry, 8(4), 777-795.
Foucault, M. (2002). Archaeology of Knowledge. London: Routledge.
Frank, G. (1998). On the Relational School of Psychoanalysis: Some Additional
Thoughts. Psychoanalytic Psychology, 15(1), 141-153.
Freedheim, D. K. (1992). History of psychotherapy: a century of change. Washington,
DC: American Psychological Association.
Gadamer, H. G. (1977). Philosophical Hermeneutics. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Gadamer, H. G. (1994). Truth and method. New York: Continuum New York.
163
Gadamer, H. G. (2000). Subjectivity and intersubjectivity, subject and person.
Continental Philosophy Review, 33(3), 275-287.
Gadamer, H. G., Misgeld, D., & Nicholson, G. (1992). Hans-Georg Gadamer on
Education, Poetry, and History: Applied Hermeneutics: State University of New
York Press.
Gergen, K. J. (2001). Psychological science in a postmodern context. American
Psychologist, 56(10), 803-813.
Gerson, M. J. (1993). Sullivan's Self-In-Development—Family Context and Patterning.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 29, 197-218.
Giorgi, A. (1970). Psychology as a Human Science: A Phenomenologically Based
Approach. New York: Harper & Row.
Glassman, M. (1988). Kernberg and Kohut: A Test of Competing Psychoanalytic
Models of Narcissism. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 36,
597-625.
Green, A. (2000). The Intrapsychic and Intersubjective in Psychoanalysis.
Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 69(1), 1-39.
Green, M. R. (1977). Sullivan's Participant Observation. Contemporary Psychoanalysis,
13, 258-359.
Greenberg, J. R. (1986). Theoretical Models and the Analyst's Neutrality.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 22, 87-106.
Greenberg, J. R., & Mitchell, S. A. (1983). Object relations in psychoanalytic theory.
164
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Grey, A. (1988). Sullivan's Contribution to Psychoanalysis—An Overview.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 24, 548-576.
Grotstein, J. S. (1999). Melanie Klein and Heinz Kohut: An Odd Couple or Secretly
Connected? Progress in Self Psychology, 15, 123-146.
Guignon, C. (Ed.). (1993). The Cambridge companion to Heidegger. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Guignon, C. (2002). Philosophy and authenticity: Heidegger’s search for a ground for
philosophizing. In M. Wrathal & J. Malpas (Eds.), Heidegger, Authenticity and
Modernity, Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus (Vol. 1, pp. 79–101).
Guignon, C. (2004). The existentialists critical essays on Kierkegaard, Nietzsche,
Heidegger, and Sartre. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Guntrip, H. (1965). [Review of the book Introduction to the Work of Melanie Klein].
International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 46, 258-261.
Guntrip, H. (1996). My Experience Of Analysis With Fairbairn And Winnicott: How
Complete A Result Does Psychoanalytic Therapy Achieve? International
Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 77, 739-754.
Hazell, J. (1991). Reflections on my Experience of Psychoanalysis with Guntrip.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 27, 148-166.
Heidegger, M. (1968). What is Called Thinking? (G. G. J, Trans.). New York: Harper &
Row.
165
Heidegger, M. (1971). Poetry, language, thought. New York: Harper & Row
Heidegger, M., & Krell, D. F. (1993). Basic writings from "Being and time" (1927) to
"The Task of thinking" (1964). London: Routledge.
Heil, J. (2003). Philosophy of mind a contemporary introduction. London: Routledge.
Hillman, J. (1994). Man is by nature a political animal or: patient as citizen. In S.
Shamdasani & M. Münchow (Eds.), Speculations After Freud: Psychoanalysis,
Philosophy, and Culture (pp. 27-40).
Hirsch, I. (2003). Analysts’ Observing-Participation with Theory. Psychoanalytic
Quarterly, 72(1), 217-240.
Holm, S. (1998). Hans-Georg Gadamer on mental illness—A critical review. Medicine,
Health Care and Philosophy, 1(3), 275-277.
Inwood, M. J. (2000). Heidegger: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Kernberg, O. F. (1997). The Nature of Interpretation: Intersubjectivity and the Third
Position. The American Journal of Psychoanalysis, 57(4), 297-312.
Klein, M. (1932). The psycho-analysis of children. New York: Delacorte Press.
Klenbort, I. (1978). Another Look at Sullivan's Concept of Individuality. Contemporary
Psychoanalysis, 14, 125-135.
Kohut, H. (1959). Introspection, Empathy, and Psychoanalysis—An Examination of the
Relationship Between Mode of Observation and Theory. Journal of the
American Psychoanalytic Association, 7, 459-483.
166
Kohut, H. (1972). Thoughts on Narcissism and Narcissistic Rage. Psychoanalytic Study
of the Child, 27, 360-400.
Kohut, H. (1977). The restoration of the self. New York: International Universities
Press.
Kohut, H. (1979). The Two Analyses of Mr. Z. International Journal of PsychoAnalysis, 60, 3-27.
Kohut, H. (1982). Introspection, Empathy, and the Semi-Circle of Mental Health.
International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 63, 395-407.
Kuriloff, E. (1998). Winnicott and Sullivan: Playing with the Interpersonal Model in a
Transitional Space. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 34(3), 379-388.
Kuriloff, E. A. (2002). Where the Fiercest Attention Becomes Routine: A Discussion of
Harry Stack Sullivan and Feminist Psychoanalysis. Contemporary
Psychoanalysis, 38(2), 301-314.
Kwawer, J. S. (1998). On Using Winnicott. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 34(3), 389395.
Layton, L. (1998). Who's that girl? Who's that boy? clinical practice meets postmodern
gender theory. Northvale, NJ: J. Aronson.
Layton, L. (2002). Gendered subjects, gendered agents: Toward an integration of
postmodern theory and relational analytic practice. In M. Dimen & V. Goldner
(Eds.), Gender in Psychoanalytic Space: Between Clinic and Culture (pp. 285–
311). New York: Other Press.
167
Leffert, M. (2007). A contemporary integration of modern and postmodern trends in
psychoanalysis. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 55(1),
177-197.
Leffert, M. (2007). Postmodernism and its impact on psychoanalysis. Bulletin of the
Menninger Clinic, 71(1), 22-41.
Levenson, E. A. (1992). Harry Stack Sullivan: From Interpersonal Psychiatry to
Interpersonal Psychoanalysis. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 28, 450-466.
Lionells, M. (2000). Sullivan's Anticipation of the Postmodern Turn in Psychoanalysis.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 36(3), 393-410.
Lipovetsky, G., Charles, S. b., & Brown, A. (2005). Hypermodern times. Malden, MA:
Polity.
Locke, J. (1849). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding: W. Tegg.
Loewald, H. W. (1970). Psychoanalytic Theory and the Psychoanalytic Process.
Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, 25, 45-68.
Malpas, J. E., Wrathall, M. A., & Dreyfus, H. L. (2000). Heidegger, Authenticity, and
Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Martin, J., & Sugarman, J. (1999). The Psychology of Human Possibility and
Constraint. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Martin, J., & Sugarman, J. (2000). Between the modern and the postmodern. The
possibility of self and progressive understanding in psychology. American
Psychologist, 55(4), 397-406.
168
Matthews, M. R. (1989). The scientific background to modern philosophy. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company.
Michels, R. (2003). Discussion: The Several Relationships of Theory and Practice.
Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 72(1), 275-285.
Mitchell, S. A. (1981). The Psychoanalytic Treatment of Homosexuality: Some
Technical Considerations. International Review of Psycho-Analysis, 8, 63-80.
Mitchell, S. A. (1986). The Wings of Icarus:—Illusion and the Problem of Narcissism.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 22, 107-132.
Mitchell, S. A. (1988). Relational Concepts in Psychoanalysis Cambridge: MA:
Harvard University Press.
Mitchell, S. A. (1992). Introduction: What does the analyst know? Psychoanalytic
Dialogues, 2, 279-285.
Mitchell, S. A. (1993). Hope and Dread in Psychoanalysis. New York: Basic Books.
Mitchell, S. A. (1998). The Analyst's Knowledge and Authority. Psychoanalytic
Quarterly, 67(1), 1-31.
Mitchell, S. A. (2000). Relationality: From Attachment to Intersubjectivity. New York:
Analytic Press.
Mitchell, S. A. (2001). No Search or Getting Down to Business? Psychoanalytic
Quarterly, 70(1), 183-199.
Mitchell, S. A., & Aron, L. (1999). Relational psychoanalysis: the emergence of a
tradition. New York: Analytic Press.
169
Mitchell, S. A., & Black, M. J. (1995). Freud and Beyond: a history of modern
psychoanalytic thought. New York: Basic Books.
Modell, A. H. (1985). The Works Of Winnicott And The Evolution Of His Thought.
Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 33(Suppl.), 113-137.
Mulhall, S. (1996). Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Heidegger and Being and
Time: Routledge.
Ogden, T. H. (1985). The Mother, the Infant and the Matrix: Interpretations of Aspects
of the Work of Donald Winnicott. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 21, 346-371.
Ogden, T. H. (2001). Reading Winnicott. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 70(2), 299-323.
Ogden, T. H. (2002). A new reading of the origins of object-relations theory.
International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 83(4), 767-782.
Orange, D. M., & Stolorow, R. D. (1998). Self-Disclosure from the Perspective Of
Intersubjectivity Theory. Psychoanalytic Inquiry, 18(4), 530-537.
Ornstein, P. H., & Ornstein, A. (2003). The Function of Theory in Psychoanalysis: A
Self Psychological Perspective. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 72(1), 157-182.
Ovesey, L. (1969). Homosexuality and Pseudohomosexuality: Science House.
Pattison, G. (2000). Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to the Later Heidegger:
Routledge.
Reis, B. (2005). The self is alive and well and living in relational psychoanalysis.
Psychoanalytic Psychology, 22, 86-95.
Richardson, F. C., Fowers, B. J., & Guignon, C. B. (1999). Re-envisioning Psychology:
170
Moral Dimensions of Theory and Practice. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Rubens, R. L. (1984). The Meaning of Structure in Fairbairn. International Review of
Psycho-Analysis, 11, 429-440.
Sartre, J. P. (2001). Being and Nothingness. New York: Citadel Press.
Schacht, L. (1988). Winnicott's Position in Regard to the Self with Special Reference to
Childhood. International Review of Psycho-Analysis, 15, 515-529.
Schafer, R. (1992). Retelling a Life: Narration and Dialogue in Psychoanalysis. New
York: Basic Books.
Scharff, D. E., & Birtles, E. F. (1997). From Instinct To Self: The Evolution And
Implications Of WRD Fairbairn's Theory Of Object Relations. International
Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 78, 1085-1103.
Scharff, R. C. (1971). On "Existentialist" Readings of Heidegger. Southwestern Journal
of Philosophy, 71(2), 7-20.
Scharff, R. C. (1997, November). What Postmodernists Don't Get. Paper presented at
the Conference on After Postmodernism at the University of Chicago, Chicago,
IL.
Shipley, J. T. (1945). Dictionary of word origins. New York: The Philosophical Library
New York.
Siegel, L. I. (1987). Sullivan's Conceptual Contributions to Child Psychiatry.
171
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 23, 278-298.
Silverman, D. K. (1996). Arithmetic of a One-and Two-Person Psychology: Merton M.
Gill, an Essay. Psychoanalytic Psychology, 13(2), 267-274.
Silverman, D. K. (2000). An Interrogation of the Relational Turn A Discussion With
Stephen Mitchell. Psychoanalytic Psychology, 17(1), 146-152.
Skolnick, N. J., & Warshaw, S. C. (Eds.). (1992). Relational perspectives in
psychoanalysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.
Slife, B. D. (1997). Toward a Theoretical Psychology:: Should a Subdiscipline Be
Formally Recognized? American Psychologist, 52(2), 117-129.
Smith, H. F. (2003). Editor's Introduction: Theory and Practice: Intimate Partnership or
False Connection? Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 72(1), 1-12.
Spezzano, C. (1995). " classical" Versus" contemporary" Theory—the Differences That
Matter Clinically. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 31, 20-20.
Stack, C. (1999). Psychoanalysis Meets Queer Theory: An Encounter with the
Terrifying Other. Gender and Psychoanalysis, 4(1), 71-87.
Stern, D. B. (2000). The Limits of Social Construction: Commentary on Paper by
Cynthia Dyess and Tim Dean. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 10(5), 757-769.
Stern, D. B. (2003). Unformulated Experience: From Dissociation to Imagination in
Psychoanalysis. New York: Analytic Press.
Stockwell, R. P., Minkova, D., & NetLibrary, I. (2001). English Words History and
Structure. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
172
Stolorow, R. D. (1995). An Intersubjective View of Self Psychology. Psychoanalytic
Dialogues, 5(3), 393-399.
Stolorow, R. D., Atwood, G. E., & Orange, D. M. (1999). Kohut and Contextualism:
Toward a Post-Cartesian Psychoanalytic Theory. Psychoanalytic Psychology,
16(3), 380-388.
Stolorow, R. D., Atwood, G. E., & Orange, D. M. (2002). Worlds of Experience:
Interweaving Philosophical and Clinical Dimensions in Psychoanalysis. New
York: Basic Books.
Stolorow, R. D., Orange, D. M., & Atwood, G. E. (2001). Cartesian and Post-Cartesian
Trends in Relational Psychoanalysis. Psychoanalytic Psychology, 18(3), 468484.
Strenger, C. (1991). Between hermeneutics and science. An essay on the epistemology
of psychoanalysis. Psychology Issues, 59, 1-234.
Sullivan, H. S. (1940). The Collected Works of Harry Stack Sullivan. New York:
Norton.
Sullivan, H. S. (1970). The Psychiatric Interview. New York: WW Norton & Company.
Sullivan, H. S., & Mullahy, P. (1953). Conceptions of modern psychiatry. New York:
Norton
Sutherland, J. D. (1980). The British Object Relations Theorists: Bálint, Winnicott,
Fairbairn, Guntrip. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 28,
829-860.
173
Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Taylor, C. (1995). Overcoming epistemology. Philosophical Arguments, 1–19.
Taylor, C. (2002). Gadamer on the Human Sciences. In R. J. Dostal (Ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Gadamer (pp. 126-142). New York, NY: Cambridge
University Press.
Taylor, C. (2003). Rorty and Philosophy. Richard Rorty, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 158–180.
Thompson, C. (1978). Sullivan and Psychoanalysis. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 14,
488-501.
Thompson, C. (1979). Sullivan and Fromm. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 15, 195200.
Tubert-Oklander, J. (2007). The Whole and the Parts: Working in the Analytic Field.
Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 17(1), 115-132.
Vessey, D. (2002). Gadamer's Critique of Heidegger's Account of Authentic Relations
to Others. Retrieved September 12, 2007, from
http://www.geocities.com/davevessey/Vessey_Gadamer_Heidegger.htm
Vessey, D. (2005). Gadamer's account of friendship as an alternative to an account of
intersubjectivity. Philosophy today, 49(5), 61-67.
Viney, W., & King, D. B. (1993). A History of Psychology: Ideas and Context. Boston:
Allyn and Bacon.
Warnke, G. (1987). Gadamer: Hermeneutics, Tradition and Reason. Stanford: Stanford
174
University Press.
Winnicott, D. W. (1975). Through Paediatrics to Psycho-Analysis. New York: Basic
Books.
Wrathall, M. A., & Faulconer, J. E. (2000). Appropriating Heidegger. New York:
Cambridge University Press
Zeddies, T. J., & Richardson, F. C. (1999). Analytic Authority in Historical and Critical
Perspective: Beyond Objectivism and Relativism. Contemporary
Psychoanalysis, 35(4), 581-601.
Zimmerman, M. (2000). The End of Authentic Selfhood in the Postmodern Age? In J.
E. Malpas, Wrathall, M. A., & Dreyfus, H. L. (Ed.), Heidegger, Authenticity,
and Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus (pp. 123–148).
175
Vita
Guido Mascialino attended Jefferson High School, Guayaquil, Ecuador. In 1994 he
entered The University of New Hampshire in Durham, New Hampshire. He received
the degree of Bachelor of Arts from The University of New Hampshire in May, 1997.
During the following years he was employed as a residential treatment counselor at The
Chase Home, in Portsmouth, New Hampshire. In September, 1998, he entered the
Graduate School at The University of Texas at Austin.
Permanent Address: 78 Congress St., Apt. 5, Brooklyn, New York 11201
This dissertation was typed by the author.
176