On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
JOSEP CLUSA1
Abstract
This paper examines the debate about the referential meaning of Kant’s concept of
substance. In the Critique of Pure Reason and other works such as the Metaphysical
Foundations of Natural Science, the category or concept of substance appears quite
uncontroversially to have both a logical meaning (by which it means roughly ‘a
thing that is the ultimate subject of predication’) and an objective meaning (by which
it means roughly ‘a thing that is permanent’, or, equivalently, ‘a thing existing at all
times’). However, it is highly contested what kind of object, or objects, are supposed
to meet, in experience, the criteria imposed by the conjunction of these two distinct
meanings. I discuss two examples of the main interpretations to be found in the
literature: Peter Strawson (2000), who contends that the reference of substance is
only matter, and Claudia Jáuregui (2021), who also includes ordinary particular
objects as substances. I scrutinize their fit with some of the textual evidence,
primarily from the First Analogy of Experience, and finally reject Jáuregui’s
interpretation as implying a kind of mereological essentialism about particular
objects.
Keywords: substance, meaning, matter, ordinary objects, First Analogy of
Experience.
Sobre la semántica del concepto kantiano de sustancia
Resumen
Este artículo examina el debate sobre el significado referencial del concepto de
sustancia en Kant. En la Crítica de la razón pura y en otras obras como los
Principios metafísicos de la ciencia natural, hay consenso en que la categoría o
concepto de sustancia posee tanto un significado lógico (por el que significa
aproximadamente ‘algo que es el sujeto último de la predicación’) como un
significado objetivo (por el que significa aproximadamente ‘algo que es
permanente’ o, en términos equivalentes, ‘algo que existe en todo tiempo’). Sin
embargo, hay un debate acerca de qué clase de objeto, u objetos, se supone que
deben satisfacer, en la experiencia, las condiciones exigidas por la conjunción de
estos dos distintos significados. En el paper, discuto dos ejemplos de las principales
interpretaciones ofrecidas en la literatura: la de Peter Strawson, 2000, quien sostiene
1
Ph.D. from Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona. Academic Visitor at the Humboldt-Universität zu
Berlin. Contact: josepclusa@gmail.com. ORCID: https://orcid.org/0000-0003-1931-8716.
158
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
que únicamente la materia es la referencia de la sustancia, y la de Claudia Jáuregui,
2021, quien considera que los objetos ordinarios particulares son también
sustancias. Examino los argumentos de ambos autores a la luz de una parte de la
evidencia textual, sobre todo de la Primera Analogía de la Experiencia, y concluyo
rechazando la interpretación de Jáuregui por implicar una especie de esencialismo
mereológico sobre los objetos particulares.
Palabras clave: sustancia, significado, materia, objetos ordinarios, Primera
Analogía de la Experiencia.
1. Introduction
In the literature on Kant’s concept of substance, one sooner or later
encounters a distinction between two different meanings of substance
(Hahmann, 2010; Hall, 2011; van Cleve, 1999). According to the first,
substance is simply a thing that possesses qualities, more technically, a
subject of (different) predicates. Using Kant’s terminology, we may refer to
this as the logical meaning of substance. According to the second meaning,
however, substance is defined with the help of a purely temporal notion,
namely permanence. By this word (also, persistence; in German,
Beharrlichkeit), Kant denotes existence at all times (“ein Dasein zu aller
Zeit”, A242/B300; cf. also A185/B228–229), including hence time past, time
present, and time future. In this very robust sense, substance is something that
can be neither created nor destroyed. Again using Kant’s terminology, we
may call this second meaning the objective meaning of substance.2
Jonathan Bennet (2006), the first to distinguish between these two
meanings of substance, found the distinction not only in Kant’s work but in
the whole philosophical tradition from Aristotle downwards (see also the
references in van Cleve, 1999). To name but one example, Spinoza combined
the two meanings straightforwardly: he conceived God, or Nature, first, as a
subject of infinite attributes, and second, as an eternal and indestructible
being. However, even if philosophers may choose to fuse the logical and
objective meanings of substance, they should be under no illusion that the two
meanings are wholly distinct and must therefore be kept separate. Kant
2
See Oroño (2022) for a helpful discussion about the differences between the logical and objective
meanings of categories in general.
159
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
himself, as Bennet observes, was well aware of it, as is made clear by various
passages of the Critique of Pure Reason.
Let us take a look at a couple of them. The first comes from the
Schematism chapter: “if one leaves out the sensible determination of
permanence, substance would signify nothing more than a something [ein
Etwas] that can be thought as a subject (without being a predicate of
something else)” (KrV, A147/B186).3 The second comes from the chapter on
Phenomena and Noumena:
If I leave out permanence (which is existence at all times), then nothing is left in my
concept of substance except the logical representation of the subject, which I try to
realize by representing to myself something that can occur solely as subject (without
being a predicate of anything) (KrV, A242–243/B300–301).
Here, Kant can be understood as urging us to perform a kind of mental
experiment by which we succeed in disentangling the two meanings of
substance. From the complete concept of substance, as it were, we are first
told to remove permanence (referred to as a “sensible determination”, and
defined explicitly, at least in the second quotation, as “existence at all times”).
Next, after this removal or abstraction step, Kant invites us to contemplate all
that we are left with: the mere representation of ‘a something’ [ein Etwas]
which can only be a subject and never a predicate. Kant complains that this
representation, which he labels as logical, is by itself useless: “Now out of
this representation I can make nothing, as it shows me nothing at all about
what determinations the thing [das Ding] that is to count as such a first subject
is to have” (KrV, A147/B186–187).
But then it is not only the case that I do not even know of any conditions under
which this logical preeminence can be attributed to any sort of thing; it is also the
case that absolutely nothing further is to be made of it, and not even the least
consequence is to be drawn from it, because by its means no object whatever of the
3
I quote from Guyer’s and Wood’s translation (in Kant, 1998). Here and elsewhere, I have modified it
slightly for the sake of terminological consistency, using permanence instead of its synonym
persistence as a translation of Beharrlichkeit. References to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason use the A
(first edition) and/or B (second edition) pagination; references to other works, volume and page number
of the Academy Edition (Kant, 1990–).
160
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
use of this concept is determined, and one therefore does not even know whether
the latter means anything at all (KrV, A243/B301).
I think from these passages it quite clearly emerges that, for Kant, the
complete concept of substance necessarily includes both a logical and an
objective component. Although this is disputed in the literature by some
authors (such as Ameriks, 2000, or Langton, 1998, who argue that the
objective meaning is not compatible with the logical one), I take it to be the
general consensus (Guyer, 1987; Paton, 1936; Rosenberg, 2005; van Cleve,
1999) that the concept of substance can only attain its full semantic weight if
permanence is added to, or combined with, the pure logical notion of
something only being a subject, and never a predicate (for an overview of the
literature on that point, see Oberst, 2017).
Without this addition of the temporal notion (or ‘schema’), the
category or pure concept of substance would not lack meaning altogether—
since it would still possess logical meaning—but it would certainly lack what
Kant terms Sinn und Bedeutung (KrV, A156/B195), which we may translate
loosely as ‘sense and reference’.4
This brief summary of the different meanings of substance does not, I
believe, raise any deeply controversial issues. However, one question remains
highly disputed in the scholarly debate about substance. What is the exact
reference of substance? In other words, what kind of object, or objects in
experience, are supposed to meet in experience the conditions demanded by
(the combination of) the logical and objective meanings of substance?
Framing this question further in semantical terms, I will call this question one
about the referential meaning of substance.
Now, the Kantian texts seem to make room for different kinds of
objects satisfying the concept of substance, and hence allow—to put it slightly
frivolously—for substantially different interpretations. In the remainder of
my paper, I will therefore first present (section 2) two examples of the main
interpretations available in the literature. One associates the reference of
substance exclusively with matter (see Hahmann, 2009, 2010; Strawson,
4
Kant seems to use Sinn and Bedeutung more or less interchangeably, but when both terms are used in
conjunction in the expression Sinn und Bedeutung, they seem to come down to what I have called the
complete concept of substance, or what Kant describes as ‘the objective reality of concepts’. For a
comparison between Kants’ terminological uses of Sinn and Bedeutung and Frege’s see Nolan (1979).
161
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
2000); the other also identifies substance with empirical or ‘ordinary
particular objects’ (Jáuregui, 2021).
In the next section (section 3), I will then examine some passages from
the First Analogy of Experience to see which interpretation fits better with
this text (the locus classicus of Kant’s discussion of substance), and in
particular, with the new ‘Proof’ of the ‘Principle of Permanence’ in the BEdition. I will argue that, although there is good textual evidence on both
sides, the Strawsonian interpretation is to be preferred on systematic grounds.
Finally (section 4) I will briefly discuss an intriguing problem raised by
Jáuregui’s interpretation: the question of whether ordinary particular objects
are identical to their constituent material parts. Jáuregui argues that they are,
suggesting that ordinary particular objects, despite appearances, hold the
status of absolutely permanent substances. I will challenge Jáuregui’s view,
objecting that it leads to an implausible conception of ordinary particular
objects, one that commits her to mereological essentialism.
2. The Referential Meaning of Substance: Matter or Ordinary Particular
Objects?
Let us begin with the first interpretation, championed by authors like Andree
Hahmann (2009, 2010) or Peter Strawson (2000). According to them, the
referential meaning or reference of substance is, and can only be, matter
[Materie]. In other words: strictly speaking, only matter, defined by Kant as
“the movable in space […] insofar as it itself possesses a moving force” (OP,
AA 21: 491) or as “the movable in space, insofar as it fills a space” (MAN,
AA 04: 496), is substance; ordinary particular objects are thus excluded from
this status.
This interpretation comes in two versions. In strong, monist versions,
the only object referred to by ‘substance’ is the whole of matter, or “all
matter” (Hahmann, 2009, p. 192; Sans, 2005, p. 59; Strawson, 2000, p. 270).
According to this, there would only be “One Big Substance” (as Hannah puts
it [2006, p. 392ff.]). In a weaker, pluralist reading, however, any of the parts
into which matter can be divided counts as substance as well (this I take to be
the view of Buroker [2006] and Melnick [1973]). For such a view, there
162
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
would be, as it were, Infinitely Many Substances, as for Kant, no part of
matter is ultimately indivisible.5
One passage that supports the reading of substance as matter, in both
monist and pluralist versions, stems from the Metaphysical Foundations of
Natural Science. There Kant writes:
The concept of substance means the ultimate subject of existence, that is, that which
does not itself belong in turn to the existence of another merely as a predicate. Now
matter is the subject of everything that may be counted as belonging to the existence
of things. […] Thus matter, as the movable in space, is the substance therein. But
all parts of matter must likewise be called substances, and thus themselves matter in
turn, insofar as one can say of them that they are themselves subjects, and not merely
predicates of other matters (MAN, AA 04: 503; Kant, 2012).
Notice that the first sentence (“substance means the ultimate subject
of existence”) is merely a restatement of what Kant, following the Aristotelian
tradition, takes to be the logical meaning of substance. After this, we might
have expected Kant to go on mentioning the next necessary (and objective)
component of this concept: permanence. Instead, Kant proceeds to identify
straightaway what we have called the referential meaning of substance,
namely matter. About this matter, this passage says only that it is “the
movable in space”, and likewise, that it is “[the] substance therein [sc. in
space]”, but again without any mention of or hint at permanence. However,
as we shall see later,6 Kant thinks indeed that matter is sempiternal, claiming
at one point that “we do not have […] anything permanent on which we could
base the concept of a substance, as intuition, except merely matter” (see KrV,
B278).
According to the second interpretation, defended recently by Claudia
Jáuregui (2021), the referential meaning of substance should not be restricted
to matter. It should include ordinary particular objects of our experience as
well, that is, individual physical objects like tables, chairs, stones, or pieces
of paper. One should be mindful, however, that Jáuregui is not suggesting that
substance has two different referential meanings, compatible at the same
time—say, on the one hand matter, and on the other hand ordinary particular
5
6
See for instance the rejection of the thesis of the Second Antinomy.
As we shall see in section 3 discussing the ‘combustion of wood’ example.
163
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
objects. Her point is rather the opposite: parts of matter and ordinary objects
are, in her view, identical; in other words, ordinary objects are nothing but
parts of matter. I quote one passage of her paper: “The objects of our everyday
experience are parts of matter, and those parts are as substantial as matter
itself, and must be absolutely permanent” [“[L]os objetos de nuestra
experiencia cotidiana son partes de la materia, y esas partes son tan
sustanciales como la materia misma y han de permanecer de un modo
absoluto”] (Jáuregui, 2021, p. 24, a. trans.).
Thus, if I understand it correctly, Jáuregui’s argument runs something
like this:
i) All ordinary particular objects7 are parts of matter.
ii) All parts of matter are substances.
iii) Therefore, all ordinary particular objects are substances.
Let us pause for a moment to look at each of these propositions. The
second premise is hardly contentious. I have quoted the text of the
Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, in which Kant himself states
that “all parts of matter must likewise be called substances” (MAN, 04: 503).
Even interpreters with monist leanings, like Strawson, allow for parts of
matter—divisible out of the totality of matter—to be called by the name
‘substances’ (although, as a matter of fact, only in a rather condescending,
secondary and ‘courtesy’ sense, cf. Strawson, 2000).
The conclusion of Jáuregui’s argument—that ordinary objects are
substances—can also claim some strong independent textual evidence in its
favour. For instance, in the Proof of the Third Analogy, Kant appears to treat
ordinary particular objects (although of a peculiarly large size, as we shall see
in a moment) as if they were downright paradigms of substance. Thus, to
illustrate the principle that substances coexisting in time stand in causal
interaction with each other, he chooses the Moon and the Earth as examples:
7
Besides “objects of our everyday experience” [“objetos de nuestra experiencia cotidiana”], Jáuregui
also uses the locution “particular objects” [“objetos particulares”] (2021, p. 24–25), so no harm will
follow, I think, from using ‘ordinary particular objects’ to mean roughly the same.
164
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
Things are simultaneous if in empirical intuition the perception of one can follow
the perception of the other reciprocally, and vice versa (which in the temporal
sequence of appearances, as has been shown in the case of the second principle,
cannot happen). Thus I can direct my perception first to the Moon and subsequently
to the Earth, or, conversely, first to the Earth and then subsequently to the Moon,
and on this account, since the perception of these objects can follow reciprocally
each other, I say that they exist simultaneously (KrV, B256–257).
The first premise, however—that ordinary objects are parts of
matter—is highly contested. Many authors deny it (Sans, 2000; Tetens, 2006;
Thöle, 2011) on the grounds that ordinary objects are only made of, or
composed of, matter. We can find a clear example of this view in Strawson’s
article “Kant on Substance”. There he writes: “Kant’s doctrine regarding
ordinary composite material objects is not that they are, strictly speaking,
substances, but rather that they are (adjectivally) substantial, i.e. composed of
substance or matter” (Strawson, 2000, p. 269). Ordinary objects, as it turns
out, do not fulfill the criteria imposed by the two meanings of substance,
which, when conjoined, yield what we identified earlier as the complete
concept of substance. First, ordinary particular objects, such as an individual
man, or an individual horse (the typical examples of substance given by
Aristotle in his writing Categories),8 do not seem to satisfy the logical
criterion of always being a subject, and never a predicate. This is presumably
because we could say something like ‘this portion of matter is Socrates’, thus
turning this individual man into a predicate (see van Cleve, 1999). Next,
ordinary objects do not seem either to satisfy the objective criterion of being
permanent, that is, of existing at all times. (As is well known, all men are
mortal, and Socrates is, well, a man).
I quote Strawson again:
Kant, though he would of course admit that such ordinary individuals as Alexander
and Bucephalus can be, and are, represented as subjects of predication, must hold
that they are not irreducibly such, but can rather be thought of as mere
determinations of something else; he must hold that if he is to be faithful both to his
formal criterion of substance and to the view that, in the field of phenomena, i.e. in
8
“Substance […] in the primary sense of the term […] is that which can be neither predicated of a
subject nor found in a subject, for example a particular man (ὁ τὶς ἄνθρωπος) or a particular horse (ὁ
τὶς ἵππος)” (Aristoteles, Cat. 2a. 11–13; 1938, a. minor modifications on translation).
165
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
the field of the only significant application of the concept (category) only what is
permanent is to count as substance. For it is clear that such ordinary individuals as
Alexander and Bucephalus and lumps of rock are not permanent, but do come into
and go out of existence (2000, p. 271).
One might want to raise two objections to Strawson’s denial that
ordinary objects can be substances. The first is on textual grounds. If
Alexander and his horse are not proper Kantian substances, it seems to follow
that neither the Earth nor the Moon can be, which contradicts the passage
from the Third Analogy just quoted above. The second objection is more
systematic, and is made by Jáuregui (2021) in his interesting reply to this line
of argument. The thrust of it is to reaffirm that ordinary objects are parts of
matter (identical to parts of matter), not merely composed of matter. Insofar
as they are parcels of matter, as it were, they are genuine substances.
Jáuregui’s view, which, as far as I can see, resembles mereological
essentialism about ordinary objects in contemporary metaphysics—the view
that “whatever parts a thing has, it has essentially or necessarily” (Loux and
Crisp, 2017, pp. 243–245), deserves a separate discussion. But before
examining it more closely, I propose to have a fresh look at what is arguably
Kant’s most important text about substance, the First Analogy of Experience.
Perhaps this will put us in a better position to understand what the reference
of substance ultimately is.
3. The First Analogy of Experience: Change, Alteration, and the Sempiternity
of Substance
The formula of the First Analogy of Experience, in the A-version, reads as
follows: “All appearances contain that which is permanent (substance) as the
object itself [der Gegenstand selbst], and that which can change as its mere
determination, i.e., a way in which the object exists” (KrV, A182). In this first
formula, as many commentators since Bennet (2006) have noted, the two
meanings of substance—logical and objective—are present at the same time.
Kant describes substance, on the one hand, as an object [Gegenstand]
possessing a determination [Bestimmung]. This determination (which we
could also describe as an accident, property, or attribute) is, in turn, defined
as a mode, or way [eine Art], in which the object exists. These
characterizations correspond closely to the logical meaning of substance. Yet
166
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
Kant also describes substance, on the other hand, as the permanent or
persistent [das Beharrliche], in contrast to the transitory or changeable [das
Wandelbare]. This latter characterization corresponds closely enough to the
objective meaning of substance. Both meanings, however, are presented in
combination: as it turns out, the permanent is the object, and the transitory or
changeable, its determination.9
Now there are two approaches for fleshing out, as it were, the
reference of substance in this formula. One is to illustrate it with commonsensical examples. A leaf of a tree turns from green to yellow; what changes
are the colours, but the leaf itself doesn’t change, it persists (cf. van Cleve,
1999). A car gets a new wheel; the wheel is changed, but the car remains the
same. Water freezes; the state of the water changes, but water itself does not
thereby disappear.10 From these examples, we might conclude that ordinary
objects are substances. However, these examples seem, on closer inspection,
to conflict squarely with the strict definition of permanence given by Kant.
Permanence is, for Kant, not relative (existence for some particular stretch of
time, however long that stretch may be) but absolute. It is existence at all
times, in one word, sempiternitas.11 Measured against this standard, the
9
It is true that in the formula of the B-Edition (“In all changes of appearances substance is permanent
[beharrt], and its quantum is neither increased nor diminished in nature”) this combination of meanings
has disappeared, and only the second sense of substance (‘substance as the permanent’) is mentioned.
However, this does not need to imply a contradiction with the A-Edition formula, as suggested by Hall
(2011) and others. For a sustained argument against a contradiction between the formulas see Hahmann
(2010).
10
For a version of this example, used however to illustrate the category of causality, see KrV, B162–
163.
11
In the First Analogy at least, the closest Kant comes to employing the word ‘sempiternity’ (the word
used in the anglophone Kant scholarship following the lead of Bennet) occurs within the paraphrase of
the principle of substance as “[the principle of] sempiternal existence [immerwährendes Dasein] of the
proper subject in the appearances” (KrV, A185/B228) (Guyer and Wood translate immerwährend as
‘everlasting’). In the Opus Postumum, however, the word appears explicitly: “Sempiternitas ist
necessitas phaenomenon” (OP, AA 21: 584). The German word used by Kant himself for the Latin
sempiternitas is ‘alldauernd’ (OP, AA 21: 584). Another useful passage that sheds light on the meaning
of sempiternity stems from §29 of the Inaugural Dissertation: “Nam mundus hic, quanquam
contingenter exsistens, est sempiternus, h. e. omni tempori simultaneus, ut ideo tempus aliquod fuisse,
quo non exstiterit, perperam asseratur” [“For, although this world exists contingently, it is sempiternal,
that is to say, it is simultaneous with every time, so that it would, therefore, be wrong to assert that there
had been a time at which it did not exist”] (MSI, AA 2: 417; Kant, 1992, p. 413; I have substituted the
more etymological ‘sempiternal’ for Walford’s more idiomatic ‘everlasting’). Although the context is
different—sempiternity is applied here to mundus and not to substantia—it can be seen that already at
this stage of Kant’s thinking, ‘sempiternity’ (permanence) is defined as existence “simultaneous with
every time” (omni tempori simultaneus), another way to say: existence at all times. Finally, a note might
be in order about the difference between the meanings of ‘eternity’ and ‘sempiternity’. Sometimes
sempiternity is defined so as to apply to entities that will go on existing for all time future, but which,
however, were created by God in the past (this applies for example in Catholic Theology to angels). In
contrast, eternity would be the wider concept, applying to an entity that existed always in the past, exists
167
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
temporal careers of leaves, cars, and water molecules are by far too shortlived.
We find a clear-cut statement of the sempiternity of substance in one
of the many glosses that follow the Proof of the First Analogy:
[W]e can grant an appearance the name of substance only if we presuppose its
existence at all time [ihr Dasein zu aller Zeit], which is not even perfectly expressed
through the word ‘permanence’ since this pertains more to future time. Nevertheless
the inner necessity of being permanent [zu beharren] is inseparably connected with
the necessity of always having existed, and the expression may therefore stand (KrV,
A185–186/B228–229).
The second approach that can be taken to illustrate the formula of the
First Analogy in the A-Edition (recall: “All appearances contain that which is
permanent (substance) as the object, and that which can change as its mere
determination, i.e., a way in which the object exists” [KrV, A182]) avoids
using common-sensical examples. Instead, it uses examples that presuppose
a certain scientific view of ordinary particular objects—namely, the view that
they are made up of matter. One such example is provided by Kant himself
in the First Analogy:
A philosopher was asked: How much does the smoke weigh? He replied: If you take
away from the weight of the wood that was burnt the weight of the ashes that are
left over, you will have the weight of the smoke. He thus assumed as
incontrovertible that even in fire the matter (substance) never disappears but rather
only suffers an alteration in its form (KrV, A185/B228).
In this example, probably inspired by Lavoisier’s principle of
conservation of mass (Allison, 2010), substance is equated to matter. In
contrast, the ordinary objects involved—the piece of wood before combustion
and, subsequently, the ashes and the smoke—are presented not as substances,
now, and will exist in the future, that is, a being that exists at all times (again for Catholic Theology, in
this case, God). Kant’s use of sempiternity differs from this. He seems to be aware of it, since he points
out that he will be using the word ‘permanence’ although “the word ‘permanence’ pertains more to
future time” [“das Wort Beharrlichkeit geht mehr auf künftige Zeit”] (see KrV, A185–186/B228/229),
and hence does not express perfectly his own thought that substance exists at all times, including also
the whole past (KrV, A185–186/B228/229).
168
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
but quite on the contrary, as mere manifestations or accidents of substance.
In other words, they are instances of the different forms that matter can take
(cf. the expression “suffers an alteration in its form”, for German “die Form
derselben [sc. der Materie] [erleidet] eine Abänderung”). Thus, the example
of the burning wood provides good prima facie textual evidence for the need
to exclude ordinary objects from being genuine substances.12
This impression is strengthened if we take into consideration how
Kant defines two key terms used in the First Analogy: change and alteration.
According to Kant’s definition, change [Wechsel] implies a change in
existence itself. If something changes, then it either comes into existence or
goes out of existence; it arises or perishes. On the other hand, according to
Kant’s definition, alteration [Veränderung] it’s not a change in existence but
only a modification in the way, or mode, in which an object exists. The
passage where this distinction occurs is the following:
Alteration is a way of existing that succeeds another way of existing of the very
same object. Hence everything that is altered is lasting [bleibend], and only its state
changes. Thus since this change concerns only the determinations that can cease or
begin, we can say, in an expression that seems somewhat paradoxical, that only what
is permanent (the substance) is altered, while that which is changeable does not
suffer any alteration but rather a change, since some determinations cease and others
begin (KrV, A187/B230–231)
We may sum up this view by saying that change [Wechsel] is
existence-change (cf. Bennet, 2006), whereas alteration [Veränderung] is a
replacement of properties in the course of time, that is, a replacement of old
properties by new ones in one and the same object.
Now, given these definitions, it seems fair to say that ordinary
particular things, at some point or another in time, experience a Wechsel, an
existence-change. Because, for all we can observe or know, they come into
existence and also pass away. This includes not only leaves of trees but also
the Earth, the Sun or even, according to the current cosmological theories, all
12
I say prima facie because as noted earlier, there are passages (the Third Analogy for instance) where
Kant clearly seems to identify ordinary particular objects with substances. In other words, the textual
evidence on this point seems to be conflicting.
169
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
atomic elements. Hence, it would be simply a mistake to assume that these
objects are substantial.
Claudia Jáuregui would likely disagree with this argument. In her
paper, she argues that the coming into being and going out of existence of
ordinary objects are only apparent. I quote again from her paper: “Everyday
experience confirms the thesis of the absolute permanence of particular
objects. They therefore have a proper substantial character. Its relative
permanence is only apparent” [“La experiencia cotidiana confirma la tesis de
la absoluta permanencia de los objetos particulares. Ellos poseen pues un
carácter propiamente sustancial. Su permanencia relativa es solo aparente”]
(2021, p. 26).
Jáuregui provides an independent argument to explain why it only
appears that particular objects are relatively permanent, whereas, in fact, they
are absolutely permanent. But before delving into it, we might want to know
why, for Kant, substances must be absolutely permanent in the first place. For
that, let us take a look at the Proof of the First Analogy in the B-Version.
All appearances are in time, in which, as substratum (as permanent form of inner
intuition), both simultaneity as well as succession can alone be represented. The
time, therefore, in which all change of appearances is to be thought, lasts and does
not change; since it is that in which succession or simultaneity can be represented
only as determinations of it. Now time cannot be perceived by itself. Consequently,
it is in the objects of perception, i.e., the appearances, that the substratum must be
encountered that represents time in general and in which all change or simultaneity
can be perceived in apprehension through the relation of the appearances to it (KrV,
B224/225).
This passage is notoriously difficult (prompting some interpreters to
confess their bafflement at it, for instance van Cleve, 1999 [cf. Bennet,
2006]). However, I take Kant to be making an analogy between time and
substance. Just as time is the substratum of all change of appearances that we
perceive in inner sense, so must substance act as the object underlying all
changes that we perceive in outer sense. By the same token, just as time itself
can’t change (if it is to be the underlying object of all change in inner sense),
neither can substance change (if it is to be the substratum of all changes of
170
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
appearances in outer sense).13 The conclusion of the argument is that, in order
to make possible the perception of change in outer sense, substance must be
supposed to always remain the same [bleibt immer [die]selbe]:
Consequently, that which is permanent, in relation to which alone all temporal
relations of appearances can be determined, is substance in the appearance, i.e., the
real in the appearance, which as the substratum of all change always remains the
same. Since this, therefore, cannot change in existence [im Dasein nicht wechseln
kann], its quantum in nature can also be neither increased nor diminished (KrV,
B225).
One step in the argument leading to this conclusion is especially
relevant to our leading question (What is the reference of substance?). This is
the premise that “time itself cannot be perceived”. This premise is offered by
Kant as a reason to look, in the next step, “in the objects of perception” [in
den Gegenständen der Wahrnehmung] for something that, being perceptible,
can serve as a representative or proxy of time in experience. In one word,
from the impossibility of perceiving time as substratum of change in outer
sense, Kant infers the need to look for substance instead, locating this very
substance in the phaenomenon [Substanz in der Erscheinung].14
However, as noted in the literature, this step confronts us with a
dilemma (Hall, 2011). If substance must be something perceptible, and at the
same time the reference of substance is said to be matter, then it follows that
matter should be an object of our perception. However, as many critics point
out, matter itself cannot be perceived directly either. We perceive only its
manifestations (Oberst, 2015; Thöle, 2011). We can see, for example, the
13
The argument depends thus on the premise that what constitutes the basis of change cannot itself
change. This anti-regress assumption has been called into question, on the grounds that this basis might
also be forever changing (so Caird quoted in Kemp Smith, 1923; for a defence see Allison, 2010). Van
Cleve (1999) helpfully points out to a similar anti-regress argument in the Second Analogy:
“[A]ccording to the principle of causation actions are always the primary ground of all change of
appearances, and therefore cannot lie in a subject that itself changes, since otherwise further actions
and another subject, which determines this change, would be required” (KrV, A205/B250).
14
For an account of how empirical objects might best be used as proxies of time in experience, and
thus used to measure time, see Buroker (2006; cf. also Melnick, 1973). However, that these objects and
their actions (the movement of the Earth around the Sun to calculate a year, or the oscillations of an
atom Caesium to calculate a second for instance) are only approximations of substance, and not genuine
substances, follows again if we consider that none of these objects is known to exist “at all times” i.e.,
known to be sempiternal.
171
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
piece of wood, and then the ashes and the smoke, but we cannot see matter.15
If, on the other hand, we understand ordinary objects to be the referential
meaning of substance (this would be a possible reading of “the objects of
perception” in the text above) we face the problem of explaining how it comes
about that we ever do perceive the coming into (and going out of) existence
of them, say, perceive the birth and death of individual men and horses. On
that point, Kant seems uncompromising. For him it is conceptually impossible
to have a perception of a substance arising or perishing:
[A]rising or perishing per se cannot be a possible perception unless it concerns
merely a determination of that which is permanent, for it is this very thing that is
permanent that makes possible the representation of the transition from one state
into another, and from non-being into being, which can therefore be empirically
cognized only as changing determinations of that which lasts (KrV, A188/B231).
Kant can be taken here to be saying that, at least in the world of
phenomena, substance is permanently being perceived—as it were, without
interruption—since otherwise the very perception of change would be
impossible. Notice that this is not the same, however, as claiming that our
perception of substance must be permanent. Rather, it is claiming that our
perception or representation is of something permanent (for this contrast,
though in terms of representation and not of perception, see Kant’s footnote
in KrV, Bxli).
4. Mereological Essentialism? Jáuregui on the Absolute Permanence of
Ordinary Particular Objects
I finally come to Jáuregui’s strategy to avoid the puzzle posed by the Proof
of the First Analogy. Recall that she has to explain why it seems that we
perceive that ordinary objects are only relatively permanent, while in fact they
last forever. As she puts it: “Therefore, we can ask ourselves why, if the
objects of our everyday experience are parts of matter, and the parts of matter
15
This objection would be reminiscent of Hume’s observation that we can only perceive different
qualities, but not their underlying ‘substance’. Cf. the following quotes from A Treatise of Human
Nature: “[T]here is [no thing], but what is coloure’d or tangible” (Hume, 2000, p. 154), “a substance is
entirely different from a perception” (Hume, 2000, p. 153). For a comparison between Hume and Kant
on substance, see Rosenberg (2000).
172
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
possess absolute permanence, we tend to consider them as possessing only
relative permanence” [“Así pues podemos preguntarnos por qué si los objetos
de nuestra experiencia cotidiana son partes de la materia y las partes de la
materia poseen una permanencia absoluta, tendemos a considerar que ellos
poseen una permanencia meramente relativa”] (Jáuregui, 2021, p. 25). I am
not sure that I can do justice to Jáuregui’s argument in the brief space that
follows. However, here is what I take it to be in a nutshell: ordinary objects
possess both necessary material properties (since they are essentially identical
to parts of matter, after all) and contingent empirical properties (since they
are now big, now small; now warm, now cold; now red, now blue etc.).
Sometimes, it so happens that when the empirical properties of an object
change, we continue nonetheless to perceive the one and same object. At other
times, however, when the empirical properties change, we get the (false)
impression that the ordinary object itself arises or perishes. Jáuregui
illustrates this latter kind of illusory impression with the following Kantinspired example. Suppose we throw a stone and a piece of paper into the fire:
If we throw a piece of paper and a stone into the fire, after a minute the paper will
have ceased to exist and will have turned to ashes. The stone, on the other hand, will
remain a stone in which some change of temperature will certainly have taken place
[…]. It is entirely contingent that in the case of paper, we possess an empirical
concept with which we think of this new state as if it were a different kind of object,
and that the appearance is then generated that the paper ceased to exist and the ashes
began to exist (Jáuregui, 2021, p. 25).16
I don’t think that Jáuregui’s example supports well her conclusion,
which, at any rate, would be overly revisionary about the concept of ‘ordinary
particular object’ that we do have. Above all, I think it is fair to say that we
do really perceive pieces of paper going out of existence as they get burnt.
Supposing otherwise would be to suggest that a piece of paper still exists after
being burnt—which is plainly absurd, at least if we still hold to the Kantian
premise that the existence of a substance must be connected to perception.
16
“Si arrojamos al fuego un trozo de papel y una piedra, al cabo de un minuto el papel habrá dejado de
existir y se habrá transformado en cenizas. La piedra, en cambio, seguirá siendo una piedra en la que
se habrá operado seguramente algún cambio de temperatura. […]. Es totalmente contingente que en el
caso del papel, poseamos un concepto empírico con el cual pensamos ese nuevo estado como si tratara
de un tipo de objeto diferente, y que se genere entonces la apariencia de que el papel dejó de existir y
comenzaron a existir las cenizas”.
173
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
Another way to express disagreement with Jáuregui’s argument
would be to say that it does not seem consistent with the distinction Kant
makes between change and alteration. If we follow Kant’s terminology to the
last consequence (which is admittedly neither a very easy, nor a very helpful
thing to do in all cases, given the variety of locutions for ‘change’ in either
Spanish or English, or for that matter in German),17 then I think we should
say that fire changes the piece of paper, in the sense that it destroys it
(existence-change in Bennet’s [2006] terminology). It may be true that, in that
sense, fire cannot change a stone, or not easily at once (stones are noncombustible). But surely this does not mean that nothing can change stones
(an explosion will surely change them).18
To further discuss Jáuregui’s view, surely, it would be necessary to
consider in more detail what we really mean by the concept of an ‘ordinary
particular object’. In a systematic spirit, let us contemplate, however briefly,
the possibility raised by her interpretation that an ordinary object is identical
to parts of matter. This view, as far as I can see, closely resembles what is
called mereological essentialism in contemporary metaphysics (cf. Loux and
Crisp, 2017). According to this view, an object or thing is a whole essentially
identical to its constituent parts, meaning that the loss of any of these parts
will make this thing be another—and hence destroy it (for a defence of this
view, see Chisholm, 1973).
For Jáuregui, as we have just seen and at least as I have interpreted
her, ordinary objects have both necessary material properties (namely, being
essentially identical to a certain portion or quantity of matter) and contingent
empirical properties (namely, being such and such, say having black fur and
a white-tipped tail). From the first group of necessary or essential properties,
17
Cf. for instance the typical compound German word Radwechsel. Whether or not wheels are
considered substances, the expression does not (ordinarily) imply that wheels get destroyed when they
are changed!
18
Thus the “stone’s change of temperature” noted by Jáuregui would be in Kant’s manner of speaking
a change of temperature and an alteration of the stone. In saying that the stone alters, we do not imply
however that the stone is a substance in a genuine sense. Using also terminology offered by Kant, we
can say the stone is a substance ‘comparative’, that is, in a merely “comparative sense”. Kant uses
namely the Latin adverb comparative to qualify such a substance, as well as the expression substantiae
comparativae (AA 18: 145) precisely for qualities or accidents which, in regard to another qualities or
accidents, act as subjects, but which themselves are not ultimate subjects (see Oberst, 2017, for a
definition, a discussion and references; cf. also Langton, 1998, on the related concept of phaenomenon
substantiatum).
174
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
it follows that for any particular ordinary object x, say a cat, it is necessary
for x to be some definite portion of matter.
Now consider the so-called Problem of the Many in the guise of a cat
called Tibbles (cf. Burke, 1996). If Tibbles the Cat is necessarily identical to
a specific, well-defined, and circumscribed parcel of matter then what
happens if Tibbles loses her white tipped tail? Is she now another cat? It might
seem so, since she is now a lesser portion of matter than before—hence
another portion of matter altogether. It seems, therefore, that every minimal
change taking place in Tibbles—even at the microparticle level—would make
her another cat. There would be, as a consequence, far too many cats around.
Jáuregui’s view is also confronted with such a paradox. For if one holds
ordinary objects to be necessarily identical to certain wholes of matter (not
merely contingently made up of this set, or that set, of particles of matter),
then one ends up committing oneself to a ‘revisionary’ metaphysics about
ordinary particular objects—a metaphysics that may be philosophically
attractive, but which goes against some of our most deep-seated commonsense assumptions about individual objects, such as that there is just one cat
Tibbles, and not many.19
To summarize the discussion so far. We may agree that substance is
‘the ultimate subject of predication’ (logical meaning of substance) and even
concur with Kant that it must be permanent or sempiternal (objective meaning
of substance) to be fully meaningful (to have what Kant terms Sinn und
Bedeutung, cf. KrV, A156/B195). However, when it comes to pinpointing the
referential meaning of substance—the perceptual object to which this concept
is to be applied—we are confronted with a dilemma. If we identify the
reference of substance with matter, we face the objection that matter itself
cannot be an object of perception. This is the main difficulty confronting
interpretations such as that of Peter Strawson. Conversely, if we identify the
reference of substance with ordinary particular objects, we are confronted
with the problem that no such object is truly absolutely permanent. This is the
challenge facing the interpretation of Claudia Jáuregui. Despite good textual
19
It has been helpfully pointed out to me by an anonymous referee that my example of Tibbles is not
really an objection to Jáuregui’s argument, since Tibbles is a proper noun, and cat is an empirical
concept, that we merely use contingently to think about ordinary particular objects. As parts of matter,
ordinary particular objects would be absolutely permanent, even though cats might not be. Although I
see the point, it still seems to me that the expression ‘ordinary object’ [objeto cotidiano] is misleading
if it is used to refer to everlasting parts of matter, as opposed to empirical objects such as black-furred
cats with white-tipped tails.
175
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
evidence supporting both views, I find Strawson’s interpretation less
problematic overall, as the choice of matters at least ensures the absolute
permanence of substance. To further defend an interpretation along these
lines, however, more work is needed to explore the connection between
matter and perception.
References
Allison, H. E. (2010). Kant’s Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and
Defense. Yale University Press.
Ameriks, K. (2000). Kant and the Fate of Autonomy: Problems in the
Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
Aristotle (1938). Categories. On Interpretation. Prior Analytics. Harvard
University Press.
Bennett, J. (2006). Kant’s Analytic. Cambridge University Press.
Burke, M. B. (1996). Tibbles the Cat: A Modern “Sophisma”. Philosophical
Studies, 67–74.
Buroker, J. V. (2006). Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: An Introduction.
Cambridge University Press
Chisholm, R. M. (1973). Parts as Essential to Their Wholes. Review of
Metaphysics, 581–603.
Guyer, P. (1987). Kant and the Claims of Knowledge. Cambridge University
Press.
Hahmann, A. (2009). Kritische Metaphysik der Substanz: Kant im
Widerspruch zu Leibniz. Walter de Gruyter.
Hahmann, A. (2010). Wozu braucht Kant die Kategorie der Substanz?
Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 579–594.
Hall, B. (2011). A Dilemma for Kant’s Theory of Substance. British Journal
for the History of Philosophy, 79–109.
Hanna, R. (2006). Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Oxford University
Press.
Hume, D. (2000). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford University Press.
176
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
Jáuregui, C. (2021). Sobre la posibilidad de una interpretación monista de la
Primera analogía de la experiencia. Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofía, 1–
10.
Kant, I. (1990–). Gesammelte Schriften. Akademie-Ausgabe.
Kant, I. (1992). Inaugural Dissertation. In Theoretical Philosophy 1755-1770
(pp. 373–376). Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (2012). Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science. Cambridge
University Press.
Kemp Smith, N. (1923). A commentary to Kant’s ‘Critique of pure reason’.
Macmillan.
Langton, R. (1998). Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in
Themselves. Oxford University Press.
Loux, M. J., and Crisp, T. M. (2017). Metaphysics: A Contemporary
Introduction. Routledge.
Melnick, A. (1973). Kant’s Analogies of Experience. University of Chicago
Press.
Nolan, J. P. (1979). Kant on Meaning: Two Studies. Kant Studien, 70(1–4),
113–130.
Oberst, M. (2015). Substanz. In M. Willaschek, J. Stozenberg, G. Mohr, and
S. Bacin (Eds.), Kant-Lexikon (pp. 2208–2212). Walter de Gruyter.
Oberst, M. (2017). Kant über Substanzen in der Erscheinung. Kant Studien,
108(1), 1–18.
Oroño, M. (2022). Kant and the Objective, Logical and Transcendental
Meaning of the Categories. Estudos Kantianos, 10(1), 185–197.
Paton, H. J. (1936). Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience. Allen & Unwin.
Rosenberg, J. F. (2000). Identity and Substance in Hume and Kant. Topoi,
19(2), 137–145.
Rosenberg, J. F. (2005). Accessing Kant: A Relaxed Introduction to the
Critique of Pure Reason. Oxford University Press.
177
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240
Josep Clusa
On the Semantics of Kant’s Concept of Substance
Sans, G. (2005). Wie viel Substanz braucht Kant? Revista Portuguesa de
Filosofía, 61(3/4), 707–730.
Strawson, P. F. (2000). Entity and Identity: And Other Essays. Oxford
University Press.
Tetens, H. (2006). Kants ‘Kritik der reinen Vernunft’: ein systematischer
Kommentar. Reclam.
Thöle, B. (2011). Die Analogien der Erfahrung. In G. Mohr, and M.
Willaschek (Eds.), Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft (pp. 267–296).
Akademie Verlag.
van Cleve, J. (1999). Problems from Kant. Oxford University Press.
Received: 06/02/2024
Accepted: 31/05/2024
178
Revista de Estudios Kantianos
Vol. 9, Núm. 1 (2024): 158-178
ISSN-e: 2445-0669
https://www.doi.org/10.7203/REK.9.1.28240