OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
chapter 23
con tem por a ry orthodox
cu r r en ts on the tr in it y
a ristotle papanikolaou
For contemporary Orthodox theology of the Trinity, the fourth century was clearly a
deinitive moment. It was then that Athanasius of Alexandria, more than any other theologian in the history of Christian thought up to that time, unequivocally declared the
full divinity of the Son. he explicit declaration of the divinity of the Holy Spirit soon
followed with the Cappadocian Fathers, especially Gregory of Nazianzus. Contemporary
Orthodox theology stands within this tradition of thinking on God as Trinity in one signiicant way: It continues to interpret the doctrine of the Trinity as the Christian airmation of a God whose being is love and freedom to be in communion with the not-God.
he link between the doctrine of the Trinity and the airmation of divine-human communion stands at the core of the three major trajectories in contemporary Orthodox
theology: the sophiology of Sergii Bulgakov, the apophaticism of Vladimir Lossky, and
the relational ontology of John Zizioulas.
Sophia! Orthoi!
he key to understanding Sergii Bulgakov’s (1871–1945) Trinitarian theology is to decipher (literally) what he means by ‘Sophia’, which has been the chief stumbling block to
appreciating Bulgakov’s work. he question that must be posed to Bulgakov is the following: Why is the concept of Sophia necessary for Trinitarian theology?
On the surface, Bulgakov’s Trinitarian theology seems quite ordinary. First, he accepts
the categories of hypostasis and ousia that were hammered out during the Trinitarian
controversies of the fourth century. Second, he gives an Augustine-inspired interpretation of the Trinity as the Father’s self-revelation in the Son, with the Holy Spirit being the
love that unites the Father and the Son, and, as such, completes the self-revelation of the
Father in the Son. he Cappadocians and Augustine made signiicant contributions
0001280893.INDD 328
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
contemporary orthodox currents
toward a theology of the Trinity, but they failed to elaborate further on the implications
of the homoousios, which was necessary in order to account for conceptualizing the
God-world relation in terms of communion. In both the Latin and the Greek forms of
Trinitarian theology, the homoousios was interpreted in terms of the attributes common
to the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit, and as that which constituted the unity of the
Godhead. While Bulgakov does not necessarily dispute these understandings of
the homoousios, they do not fully account for the God-world relation. It is, therefore, a
particular understanding of the God-world relation in terms of communion that leads
Bulgakov to claim that a further theological unpacking of the homoousios is needed
(Bulgakov 1993: 25).
he key to understanding the link between homoousios and Sophia in Bulgakov lies in
his notion of the self-revelation of God. he relation between the Father and the Son is
the self-revelation of the Father in the Son. his self-revelation, however, is only complete in the Holy Spirit, who unites the Father and the Son. Bulgakov identiies the Father
as ‘Divine Depth and Mystery, the Divine Subject of self-revelation’ (Bulgakov 2004:
359–93). If one were to bracket the self-revelation of God in the Son and in the Spirit, the
Father is, then, the Absolute, which cannot even be called God, since the latter is a relative term. his Absolute is an unknowable, impenetrable mystery. It is in the
self-revelation of the Father in the Son that the Father transcends this transcendence, or
reveals his transcendence as immanence, and is immanent as revealed.
he Son, therefore, is the Image of the Father, the Word of the Father in which is contained all words; the ‘objective self-revelation’ (Bulgakov 1993: 43) of the Father, the
Truth of the Father, and, as such, the divine content (Bulgakov 2008: 111). Bracketing
now the person of the Holy Spirit, the Father knows the Son as the Image of the Father,
and the Son knows the Father as that of which he is the perfect image. he relationship is
one of mutual mirroring, but this mirroring is not yet the accomplished self-revelation
of God.
Such a revelation is not a self-revelation unless it is actualized, and this actualization
is accomplished in the person of the Holy Spirit, who is the love that unites the Father
and the Son: he Father loves all that is revealed in the Son, and the Son returns this love
kenotically as the hypostatic image of the Father (Bulgakov 2004: 63). According to
Bulgakov, the self-revelation of the Father is not complete until the content that is
revealed in the Son is actualized as life by the Holy Spirit. In this sense, the Holy Spirit,
for Bulgakov, is the ‘spirit of truth’ and ‘represents the principle of reality. He transforms
the world of ideas into a living and real essence’ (Bulgakov 1993: 48–9). he Trinity is
thus the self-revelation of God to Godself, speciically, the self-revelation of the Father
mediated through Godself, the revealing hypostases of the Son and the Holy Spirit, the
Word and the Glory of God, respectively. In what is a striking ainity with the Karl Barth
of volume I, part I of the Church Dogmatics, Bulgakov identiies the Father as the revealing hypostasis, the Son as the revealed hypostasis, and the Holy Spirit as the revelation.
Where does Sophia it into all this? In the end, Sophia is identiied in Bulgakov’s system with the ousia of God hypostatized in the tri-hypostatic self-revelation of God; but,
as such, it is no longer simply ousia. Bracketing the self-revelation of the Father in the
0001280893.INDD 329
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
aristotle papanikolaou
Son and the Spirit, Bulgakov argues that the Father remains ‘in himself undisclosed’; as
undisclosed, he adds that ‘Sophia so far as the hypostasis of the Father is concerned,
connotes predominantly Ousia—prior to its own revelation as Sophia’ (Bulgakov 1993:
41). It is only in the self-revelation of God in the Son and the Holy Spirit that all that God
is is revealed, only in this self-revelation that all that God is is; there is an identiication
in Bulgakov between the self-revelation of God and the fullness of God’s existence. In
this fullness of God’s existence, ousia is no longer an apophatic concept indicative of
impenetrable mystery and transcendence of the Absolute; ousia is Sophia. Sophia, then,
for Bulgakov, is God’s being as the self-revelation of the Father in the Son and the Holy
Spirit. As Bulgakov states, ‘Sophia is Ousia as revealed’ (Bulgakov 1993: 54), or ‘Sophia is
the revelation of the Son and the Holy Spirit, without separation and without confusion’
(Bulgakov 2004: 189), or ‘Divine Sophia is God’s exhaustive self-revelation, the fullness
of divinity, and therefore has absolute content’ (Bulgakov 2002: 39).
As the very being of God it must necessarily, Bulgakov argues, refer to God’s relation
to the world, and not simply to the intra-Trinitarian relations, because, for Bulgakov, the
self-revelation of God in the Logos and the Holy Spirit is the revelation of all that God is,
and included in all that God is is God’s relation to creation and humanity. Bulgakov is
not arguing for the eternity of a creation that is restricted by time and space. If, however,
all theology is grounded in the premise that God has revealed Godself as Creator and
Redeemer, it is impossible for Bulgakov to conceive the thinking of God that does not
include God existing as eternally relating to creation in some way. Accordingly, God’s
self-revelation as the revelation of all that God is is also God’s being as love, and thus, as
freedom to create and redeem what is not God, and, thus, as eternally relating to creation. It is for this reason that Bulgakov identiies Sophia with ‘the divine world’ and links
Sophia with that famous Russian theological term sobornost; Sophia is the ‘cosmic sobornost of concrete all-unity in divine love’ (Bulgakov 2008: 103–4).
As the all-unity, Sophia is also identiied with another famous Russian theological
term, bogochelovechestvo, which is untranslatable, but has been rendered as Godmanhood, the humanity of God, or divine-humanity. he term originates with Vladimir
Sergeevich Solov’ev (1853–1900), considered the father of Russian sophiology, whose
inluence on Bulgakov is without dispute (Valliere 2000). Bogochelovechestvo signiies in
a more concrete way that God’s being as Trinitarian is always-already an eternal communion with humanity; and this always-already eternal communion with humanity
becomes the foundation for God’s creation of the anthropos as the image of God, and of
the incarnation of the Logos in Jesus. Creation in time and space is essentially a repetition
of the being of God, which includes the self-revelation of the Father in the Son through
the Holy Spirit. Bulgakov distinguishes between the divine Sophia and the creaturely
Sophia, with the divine Sophia being the foundation for the becoming of the world in
time and space. As the soul of the world in time and space, it is the creaturely Sophia, the
power of the world in its becoming toward union with the divine Sophia, which is divinization for Bulgakov—the unity of the divine and creaturely Sophia. Even though Sophia
is about God’s relation to the world, it is identiied with bogochelovechestvo for Bulgakov,
because it is in and through humanity that world is divinizable (Bulgakov 1993: 14).
0001280893.INDD 330
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
contemporary orthodox currents
he notion of self-revelation of God is integral to Bulgakov’s Trinitarian theology, and
it is here that one sees the inluence of German Idealism, although it should be made
clear that Bulgakov was critical of Fichte, Shelling, and Hegel, especially what he saw as
making creation constitutive of the being of God. he self-revelation of God gives an
account of why three in God. He faults both Latin and Greek Christian thinkers for not
engaging in a ‘theological deduction of the Trinitarian dogma’, which means that ‘[t]he
ontological necessity of precisely three, as a trinity, is not shown and not proved’
(Bulgakov 2004: 33). Bulgakov adds that ‘the trinity in Divinity in unity, as well as in the
distinction of the three concrete hypostases, must be shown not only as a divinely
revealed fact, valid by virtue of its facticity, but also as a principle owing to which Divinity
is not a dyad, tetrad, etc., in general not a pagan Olympus, but precisely a trinity, exhausting itself in its fullness and self-enclosedness’ (Bulgakov 2004: 7).
he proper way for thought to fathom this revealed fact is to begin with the assumption that God is Spirit; and it is here that one sees the more positive appropriation of
German Idealism by Bulgakov. According to Bulgakov, ‘[i]t is proper to spirit to have a
personal consciousness, a hypostasis, and a nature as its self-revelation, and the life of
spirit consists in the living out of this personal self-revelation in its nature. In spirit are
given: I, as personal self-consciousness; nature, as the source of its self-revelation; and
revelation itself as the life of the spirit in its nature’ (Bulgakov 2004: 61). If the logic of
this phenomenology of spirit as personal self-consciousness is self-evident in the created realm, then it must also apply to God, who is Absolute Spirit. Since there are no
limits or givens in God, there is no I in opposition to the not-I, as with created spirit;
God is for Godself ‘simultaneously I, thou, he, and therefore we and you’ (Bulgakov
2004: 54). God’s Trinitarian being as self-revelation is a perfect communion of persons
who, in their three distinct subjectivities, are one subject. In the notion of the dynamism
of the ‘I’ toward the other, Bulgakov was clearly inluenced by Pavel Florensky, whose
stamp is also evident in the Trinitarian theology of the well known Romanian theologian, Dumitru Staniloae (Florensky 1997; Staniloae 1998). he communion of persons of
the Trinity is thus the self-revelation of the Absolute, which is the Father, and this communion/self-revelation is a kenotic event in so far as it is constituted by the mutual kenosis of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit (Bulgakov 2004: 179–80, 384).
Although it is no doubt questionable whether German Idealist notions of the self can
be appropriated in Trinitarian theology, especially given postmodern criticism and
modiications of idealist notions of the self, the problems with Bulgakov’s so-called
‘Trinitarian deduction’ do not necessarily lead to the jettisoning of his sophiology.
What Bulgakov saw most clearly was that the Christian conceptualization of God as
Trinity was motivated not simply by a particular understanding of salvation, but was
ultimately an attempt to account for how God is in such a way so as to be in communion with what is not-God, which is the real point of the Trinity. Bulgakov also saw
clearly that, although much important work was done by Greek and Latin Christian
thinkers, the categories of ousia and hypostasis could not, by themselves, do the work of
conceptualizing God’s being as one of communion with the not-God. Bulgakov introduces a third term, ‘Sophia’, which he considers an ampliication of homoousios, to
0001280893.INDD 331
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
aristotle papanikolaou
account for God’s Trinitarian being as communion with the not-God, but he does so in
a way that avoids the pitfalls of social Trinitarianism. One could argue that Bulgakov’s
Sophia has ainities with the homistic notion of esse. Bulgakov might argue, however,
that esse, because arrived at philosophically, can only ground an analogy of being that
makes a certain kind of knowledge possible, but not knowledge as communion. In
terms of the analogy of being, Bulgakov is closer to Balthasar in attempting to conceptualize a Trinitarian understanding of being that would allow for communion. he real
relevance and challenge of Bulgakov’s notion of Sophia consists in how to think of the
immanent Trinity in such a way that accounts for God’s being as communion with the
world, but does so without falling into the inevitable problems of social Trinitarianism.
Bulgakov’s single, retrievable insight is that a third term is needed, and this third term
has something to do with Sophia.
An Apophatic Trinity
Vladimir Lossky (1903–1958) was also a Russian émigré to Paris, but his theology was
self-consciously developed in opposition to that of Bulgakov. heir diferences notwithstanding, both theologians saw the doctrine of the Trinity as rooted in the Orthodox
axiom of divine-human communion. While Bulgakov understood theology’s task as
developing the ontological implications of the Orthodox airmation of divine-human
union in Christ, Lossky would argue, beginning with his early work on Dionysius the
Areopagite, that the airmation of divine-human communion demanded an apophatic
approach to theology. In addition to Bulgakov, Lossky’s other sparring partner, which he
shared with the Catholic nouvelle théologie movement, was neo-scholasticism, which
was not reticent in criticizing Gregory Palamas’s understanding of the essence/energies
distinction.
For Lossky, the Christian belief in God as Trinity is a fact revealed in the Incarnation
of Christ, in whose person the divine and human natures are uniied. In so far as this
divine-human communion is a paradoxical union of two distinct ontological realities,
the uncreated and the created, the uniting of Godself to humanity in the person of Jesus
is a truth that reason is unable to prove or understand once given as a fact of revelation.
he Incarnation is an antinomic truth, by which Lossky means the simultaneous airmation of statements that are opposite or contradictory, the ‘non-opposition of opposites’, the opposition ‘of contrary but equally true propositions’. Given his emphasis on
antinomy, it is not quite accurate to accuse Lossky, as Michel René Barnes does, of appropriating uncritically heodore de Régnon’s interpretation that ‘Latin philosophy envisages irst the nature in itself and then proceeds to the expression; Greek philosophy
envisages irst the expression and then penetrates it to ind the nature’ (Lossky 1974: 26,
51; for a fuller response to Barnes, see Papanikolaou 2006: 181). In revealing the truth of
God and the God-world relation as antinomic, the Incarnation demands an apophatic
approach to theology. As Lossky puts it, ‘[t]he existence of an apophatic attitude . . . is
0001280893.INDD 332
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
contemporary orthodox currents
implied in the paradox of the Christian revelation’ (Lossky 1974: 15). Apophaticism, for
Lossky, is in one sense an understanding of the truth of God as lying beyond human reason. As we shall see more clearly below, it is not simply a necessary negation of positive
statements about God en route to a more analogical naming of God. Apophaticism is
equivalent to an ascetical exercise that is necessary if one wants to ascend to a true
knowledge of God—the mystical knowledge of unknowing.
Another antinomy revealed in the Incarnation is God’s being as Trinity. In approaching the Christian belief in God as Trinity, theology’s task is to ind the appropriate categories that would preserve the antinomy of God’s unity-in-distinction. here is a strict
divide, according to Lossky, between oikonomia and theologia, between the economic
and the immanent Trinity, and although we can assert that God is Trinity based on God’s
economy, we cannot engage in further speculation on God’s being in se. In fact, in order
to airm God’s Trinitarian being as unity-in-distinction, it is necessary for theology to
engage in an apophatic negation of the properties attributed to the persons of the Trinity
manifested in the economy. According to Lossky, ‘what will subsist beyond all negating
or positing, is the notion of the absolute hypostatic diference and of the equally absolute
essential identity of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit’ (Lossky 1974: 16). he antinomic categories used to express the doctrine of the Trinity were nature (ousia) and
person (hypostasis/prosopon). Once deconceptualized, ousia indicates what is common
in God, while hypostasis indicates the irreducibility of the three persons. he genius of
the Fathers lay in using synonymous words to express the Trinitarian antinomy, thus
allowing for the one side of the antinomy, God’s unity, always to refer to the irreducibility of the hypostases, and vice versa (Lossky 1976: 51).
Lossky, however, transgresses his own apophatic restrictions on the categories of
ousia and hypostasis in his development of a more positive theology of personhood that
is grounded in the theology of the Trinity. Personhood entails two constitutive aspects,
for Lossky: irreducibility (hypostasis) and freedom (ekstasis). A person is irreducible in
the sense of not being identiied with the common nature, by being irrevocably particular and irreplaceable. A person is free not in the sense of freedom of choice; ekstatic freedom, for Lossky, is freedom from the necessity of nature. Human personhood is an
ekstatic freedom from the limitations and initude inherent in created nature that can
only be given in mystical union with the uncreated. Lossky grounds this notion of ekstasis in the patristic notion of the monarchy of the Father. He argues that the monarchy of
the Father is necessary for the doctrine of the Trinity in order to maintain the antinomy
of the unity-in-distinction, since it ‘maintains the perfect equilibrium between the
nature and the persons, without coming down too heavily on either side. . . . he one
nature and the three hypostases are presented simultaneously to our understanding,
with neither prior to the other’ (Lossky 1974: 81). he monarchy of the Father also indicates, for Lossky, that the hypostasis of the Father cannot be reduced to God’s nature,
and this irreducibility is the Father’s freedom to ‘cause’ the Son and the Spirit, to give the
divine ousia to the Son and the Spirit (Lossky 1978: 46–7).
he monarchy of the Father also guards against the Filioque, the assertion that the
Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son. Lossky was (in)famous for his virulent
0001280893.INDD 333
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
aristotle papanikolaou
critique of the Filioque, claiming that ‘by the dogma of the Filioque, the God of the philosophers and savants is introduced into the heart of the Living God’ (Lossky 1974: 88).
Although this statement sounds excessive, Lossky viewed the Filioque as the result of a
neo-scholastic method that he viewed as itself excessively rationalistic. In its understanding of truth as propositional, from which the Filioque ultimately derives its justiication, Lossky saw neo-scholasticism as undermining the apophatic notion of
knowledge of God as mystical union, and thus the Christian airmation of divine-human
communion in Christ. here was, consequently, a practical concern driving Lossky’s
rejection of the Filioque, together with the theological method from which it resulted.
For Lossky, theology is necessarily apophatic, and hence, antinomic, so that the human
person could never rest complacent in her ascetic ascent toward God. One could say
that theology as antinomy exists as an ascetical exercise, allowing for the proper expression of dogma to guide the human ascent toward God, and not allowing anyone to think
that this movement toward knowledge of God is ever complete.
As the most widely read Orthodox theologian in the latter half of the twentieth century among Orthodox and non-Orthodox alike, Lossky was responsible for popularizing the essence/energies distinction, which became almost synonymous with Orthodox
theology. he essence/energies distinction is an antinomic expression for God’s transcendence and immanence. God’s essence is unknowable; creation is deiied through
participation in God’s energies. In response to neo-scholastic criticism of this distinction, Lossky asserted that the distinction is a necessary antinomy for airming participation in the uncreated life of God. he neo-scholastic, rationalistic notion of esse only
yields created grace, which contradicts the logic of divine-human communion. here
exists, however, a tension between Lossky’s airmation of participation in the uncreated
energies of God and his Trinitarian theology, as it leads to the inevitable question: If participation is in the divine energies, why is it necessary to airm God as Trinity? To say
that each of the persons of the Trinity conveys the divine energies in a distinctive manner is simply to beg the question. he contrast with Bulgakov here is telling: Whereas,
for Bulgakov, it is God’s being as Trinity, and hence, as Sophia, which is the ground for
the participation of the created in the life of God, in the Son and by the Holy Spirit, for
Lossky, the ground of creation’s participation in God is the essence/energies distinction,
which leaves one wondering how God’s being as Trinity matters for conceptualizing the
God-world relation in terms of communion. Lossky’s own theology of personhood indicates that it does matter, but it does not easily coexist with his non-negotiable airmation of the essence/energies antinomy for expressing divine-human communion.
The Ontological Revolution
In the recent revival of Trinitarian theology, the inluence of John Zizioulas (b. 1931) is
indisputable, especially his theology of personhood. Both Lossky and Zizioulas considered themselves part of a movement in contemporary Orthodox theology that was
0001280893.INDD 334
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
contemporary orthodox currents
engaging in a ‘neo-patristic synthesis’, a phrase coined by Georges Florovsky in opposition to Bulgakovian sophiology. hough self-identiied as part of the neo-patristic trajectory, Zizioulas distanced himself from two important elements that were common to
the neo-patristic theologians: apophaticism and the essence/energies distinction. he
Christian airmation of divine-human communion implied a Trinitarian ontology that
revolutionized Greek ontological monism, and which located the experience of God not
in God’s energies, but in the hypostasis of Christ.
he Christian doctrine of the Trinity is, according to Zizioulas, the inevitable result of
the Christian experience of God in the Eucharist. Christians from the beginning understood the Eucharist as an event of communion with the Body of Christ in the Holy Spirit.
It is this experience that grounds the Christian airmation of the full divinity of Christ
and the Holy Spirit, and hence, the doctrine of the Trinity (Zizioulas 1985: 80–3).
he Eucharistic experience of divine-human communion in Christ constitutes the
basis for what Zizioulas labels as the two ‘leavenings’ of Greek ontology by Christian
theology (Zizioulas 1985: 39). he irst is the airmation of creation ex nihilo, which
grounds the uncreated and created distinction, and which is demanded if the communion between the two is to be one of freedom and love, and not of necessity. his creation
out of nothing indicates positively that creation’s only hope for existence is a free and
loving communion with the uncreated; negatively, it indicates that creation itself is
inherently inite and, by itself, tends toward its own annihilation. Creation itself exhibits
a longing to be free from the necessity of initude inherent in its own nature. his longing is especially evident in the human creation of art (Zizioulas 2006: 206–49), in erotic
relations (Zizioulas 1985: 49–53), and in the phenomenological analysis of the question,
‘Who am I?’ (Zizioulas 2006: 99–112), all of which indicate a human drive for particularity and otherness that is ultimately thwarted by initude and death. his thwarted longing renders human existence ultimately tragic, since the conditions for its fulillment do
not exist within created nature, but only in communion with the uncreated.
he experience of communion in the Eucharist, and thus, of particularity and otherness, reveals that the being of God exists such as to be free to commune with what is notGod. he fact that this communion is realized in Christ by the Holy Spirit reveals that
God’s being is itself a communion between the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. It is
important, however, for Zizioulas that theology not conceptualize this communion in
the being of God in terms of necessity. His logic is as follows: Since creation itself longs
for a freedom from the annihilation that is necessarily inherent to created nature, for
God to git this freedom from necessity, God’s very being must exist as this freedom
from the necessity of nature (Zizioulas 1985: 43). Divine freedom, for Zizioulas, is already
revealed in the communion with God in Christ by the Holy Spirit. heology must ind
the proper categories to give expression to the Trinitarian being of God as communion.
In order to express faithfully God’s being as communion revealed in the Eucharistic
experience of God in Christ, the Cappadocian Fathers, according to Zizioulas, made
two crucial moves: First, they insisted on the monarchy of the Father, which consisted of
the second ‘leavening’ of Greek ontology. he monarchy of the Father airms that the
‘cause’ of God’s Trinitarian being is the person of the Father. In grounding the being of
0001280893.INDD 335
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
aristotle papanikolaou
God, and thus all being, in the person of the Father, the Cappadocian Fathers airm that
God’s Trinitarian being does not result from the necessity of God’s nature identiied as
love, or the difusive good, or the One, but is an event of freedom. As Zizioulas puts it,
[i]n a more analytical way this means that God, as Father and not as substance, perpetually conirms through “being” His free will to exist. And it is precisely His
Trinitarian existence that constitutes this conirmation: the Father out of love—that is,
freely—begets the Son and brings forth the Spirit. If God exists, He exists because the
Father exists, that is, He who out of love freely begets the Son and brings forth the
Spirit. hus God as person—as the hypostasis of the Father—makes the one divine
substance to be that which it is: the one God (Zizioulas 1985: 41).
Such an airmation is an ontological revolution, because for the irst time in the history
of philosophy, ontology is not associated with sameness and necessity, but with freedom,
particularity, otherness, and personhood.
he second crucial move orchestrated by the Cappadocian Fathers was to link the
philosophical categories of hypostasis and prosopon in order to give an adequate account
of the Trinitarian being of God (Zizioulas 1985: 27–49). Hypostasis by itself would lead to
tri-theism, while prosopon smacks of Sabellianism. Uniting the categories allows for the
airmation of the irreducibility of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit, while simultaneously asserting that this hypostatic existence is a relational event. In terms of the
monarchy of the Father, the person of the Father is Father as ‘cause’ of the Son and the
Spirit; thus, the person of the Father is constituted as such only in relation to the Son and
the Spirit. For Zizioulas, then, personhood, both human and divine, is an event of freedom (ekstasis) in a communion that constitutes one as irreducibly particular and irreplaceable (hypostatic).
One cannot fail to recognize the general lines of Lossky’s theology of personhood, even
if Zizioulas never explicitly credits him for these insights (Papanikolaou 2008). Zizioulas’
own emphasis on ontology, however, is a clear break with Losskian apophaticism, especially when Zizioulas airms that the experience of God in the Eucharist is one of the
immanent Trinity, which then forms the basis of a Christian Trinitarian ontology. In conceptualizing divine-human communion, Zizioulas also makes central the category of
hypostasis, speciically the hypostasis of Christ, rather than the divine energies.
Zizioulas’ interpretation of the Cappadocian Fathers’ reworking of the philosophical
categories of hypostasis and prosopon has recently come under attack, especially by
patristic scholars (Behr 2004; Ayres 2004). Although there may be some merit to the
claim that the Cappadocian Fathers did not explicitly set out to revolutionize ontology,
Zizioulas’ understanding of personhood as a relational event of freedom and uniqueness is logically implied in the Christian doctrine of the Trinity, especially if this doctrine is governed by the grammar of divine-human communion. If the reworking of
hypostasis and prosopon emerges against the background of a grammar of divine-human
communion, then hypostasis and prosopon are appropriated so as to allow for distinctions within God that would allow for communion with the ‘true’ God in the person
of Son; the language of ousia simply cannot do that work. Within the context of the
0001280893.INDD 336
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
contemporary orthodox currents
grammar of the doctrine itself, hypostasis and prosopon emerge in order to make sense
of the God who in love and freedom is incarnate in Jesus Christ. More problematic for
Zizioulas is his grounding the being of God in the freedom of the Father, which raises
the question of whether the Son and the Spirit possess the same freedom as the Father,
and thus, are persons in the same way as the Father.
Conclusion
In spite of their theological diferences, Bulgakov, Lossky, and Zizioulas agree that the
doctrine of the Trinity is grounded in the experience of divine-human communion in
Christ by the Holy Spirit. Each in his own way highlights a strand within the patristic
tradition: Lossky rightly emphasizes that knowledge of God is not propositional but an
experience of union, so that Trinitarian theology is inevitably apophatic and is itself an
ascetical exercise whose goal is to give expression to the Christian understanding of God
in such a way that guides the ascetical struggle to God; both Zizioulas and Bulgakov see
clearly the revolutionary ontology Christians were declaring in the doctrine of the
Trinity and attempt to advance the implications of early Christian thinking on the
Trinity—Zizioulas on hypostasis, and Bulgakov with his interpretation of the homoousios
as Sophia. he way forward for a contemporary Orthodox theology on the Trinity is not
to oppose these three trajectories, but to integrate their best insights into a theology of
the Trinity that is faithful to the impulse of early Christian thinkers on the Trinity, and
that delineates the wider cultural, economic, and political implications of the Christian
belief in a God whose being is communion.
Suggested Reading
he following are recommended: Bulgakov (2004); Lossky (1974); Papanikolaou (2006);
Zizioulas (1985). See also:
Demacopoulos, G., and Papanikolaou, A. (2008) (eds.) Orthodox Readings of Augustine
(Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press).
Gallaher, B. (2009), ‘he Christological Focus of Vladimir Solov’ev’s Sophiology’, Modern
heology, 25: 617–46.
‘he Filioque: A Church-Dividing Issue? An Agreed Statement of the North American
Orthodox-Catholic heological Consultation’, at: <http://www.scoba.us/resources/
orthodox-catholic/2003ilioque.html> (last accessed 25 September 2010).
Bibliography
Ayres, L. (2004), Nicaea and Its Legacy: An Approach to Fourth-Century Trinitarian heology
(Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Behr, J. (2004), he Nicene Faith (Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press).
0001280893.INDD 337
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 04/21/11, SPi
aristotle papanikolaou
Bulgakov, S. (2008), he Lamb of God, trans. Boris Jakim (Grand Rapids, Mich.:
Eerdmans).
——
— (2004), he Comforter, trans. Boris Jakim (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans).
——
— (2002), he Bride of the Lamb, Boris Jakim (trans.) (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans).
——
— (1993), Sophia—he Wisdom of God: An Outline of Sophiology, Revised edition, trans.
Patrick hompson, O. Fielding Clark, and Xenia Braikevitc (Hudson, N.Y.: Lindisfarne
Press).
Florensky, P. (1997), he Pillar and Ground of the Truth, trans. Boris Jakim (Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press).
Lossky, V. (1976), he Mystical heology of the Eastern Church (Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s
Seminary Press).
——
— (1974), In the Image and Likeness of God, ed. by J. H. Erickson and T. E. Bird (Crestwood,
N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press).
——
— (1978), Orthodox heology: An Introduction, trans. I. and I. Kesarcodi-Watson
(Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press).
Papanikolaou, A. (2006), Being with God: Trinity, Apophaticism and Divine-Human
Communion (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press).
——
— (2008), ‘Personhood and its exponents in twentieth-century Orthodox theology’, in
M. B. Cunningham and E. heokritof (eds.) he Cambridge Companion to Orthodox
Christian heology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 232–45.
Staniloae, D. (1998), Revelation and Knowledge of the Triune God, trans. and ed. I. Ionita and
R. Barringer (Brookline, Mass.: Holy Cross Orthodox Press).
Valliere, P. (2000), Modern Russian heology: Bukharev, Soloviev, Bulgakov: Orthodox
heology in a New Key (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans).
Zizioulas, J. (1985), Being as Communion (Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press).
——
— (2006), Communion and Otherness, ed. Paul McPartlan (New York: T. & T. Clark).
0001280893.INDD 338
4/21/2011 4:18:44 PM