EVENT REALIZATION AND DEFAULT ASPECT
LING482-02 Final Revisions July 20 2003
Jürgen Bohnemeyer
University at Buffalo – SUNY
Department of Linguistics
627 Baldy Hall
Buffalo, NY 14260-1030
Phone: +1 716 645 2177 ext 727
e-mail: jb77@buffalo.edu
and
Mary Swift
University of Rochester
Department of Computer Science
Rochester, NY 14627 USA
Phone: +1 585 273 2366
e-mail: swift@cs.rochester.edu
2
ABSTRACT – There are languages – e.g., German, Inuktitut, and Russian –
in which the aspectual reference of clauses depends on the telicity of their
event predicates. We argue that in such languages, clauses or verb phrases
not overtly marked for viewpoint aspect implicate or entail ‘event
realization’, a property akin to Parsons’s (1990) ‘culmination’. The
aspectual reference associated with the use of clauses not overtly marked for
aspect is computed in accordance with the dependence of realization
conditions on telicity and in line with principles of Gricean pragmatics. We
formalize event realization and capture the telicity-dependent patterns of
aspectual reference on which it is based by combining Krifka’s (1989, 1992,
1998) event lattices with a model-theoretic interpretation of Klein’s (1994)
theory of tense and aspect. The latter permits us to treat the ‘topic times’ of
aspectual operators as temporal constraints on event realization.
3
1. INTRODUCTION
The relationship between telicity,1 ‘viewpoint aspect’ (in particular, the
perfective-imperfective distinction; cf. Smith 1991),2 and what we call
‘event realization’ in this article has been known to semanticists implicitly
at least since Garey (1957), Kenny (1963), and Vendler (1957), in the sense
that it lies at the heart of the inference patterns known as the ‘Imperfective
Paradox’, as shown in Dowty’s (1979, p. 133) expository examples, based
on Vendler (1957):
(1)
a. John was drawing a circle.
b. John drew a circle.
1
Telicity is often characterized in terms of a ‘set terminal point’ (Vendler 1957), some final part of
events that must be realized for a telic predicate to apply to them. Events that instantiate atelic
predicates lack such a set terminal point. This is actually a semantic reconstruction of the
energeia-kinesis distinction of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Θ 6. The term ‘telicity’ was apparently
introduced by Garey (1957). In §3, we assume a definition of telicity in terms of quantizedness.
2
An alternative term is ‘grammatical aspect’, in contrast to ‘lexical aspect’ or ‘aktionsart’, which
covers telicity, but also other properties, like dynamicity and durativity (see Smith 1991).
Viewpoint aspect is often characterized in terms of the metaphor of internal (imperfective) vs.
external (perfective) perspective on an event (e.g., Comrie 1976). In discourse, these perspectives
can be understood as ‘reference points’ (after Reichenbach 1947), i.e., events or time intervals
that overlap with the event (internal view) or are ordered sequentially with respect to it (external
view). This explains the impact of viewpoint aspect on ‘temporal anaphora’ phenomena in
discourse, which has attracted much attention, especially in Discourse Representation Theory
(e.g., Hinrichs 1986, Kamp and Rohrer 1983, Partee 1984). Alternative approaches to aspectuality
characterize lexical aspect in terms of ontological classifications of eventualities and grammatical
aspect in terms of operators over the ontological properties (e.g., Bach 1986; Dowty 1986; Moens
1987).
4
(2)
a. John was pushing a cart.
b. John pushed a cart.
(1a) does not entail that a complete event that could be described by draw a
circle did in fact occur – in our terms, the telic predicate encoded by draw a
circle does not have event realization under imperfective aspect .
Consequently, (1a) does not entail the perfective (1b); in fact, the
propositions encoded by these two sentences are incompatible – they cannot
both be true of the same individuals (in particular the same circle.) within
the same time frame. In contrast, the atelic push a cart is compatible with
realization in the imperfective and licenses the inference to (2b).3 The
behavior of a predicate regarding the Imperfective Paradox patterns is
actually the most reliable criterion crosslinguistically for distinguishing telic
and atelic predicates; additional criteria include compatibility with duration
(for-type) vs. time frame (in-type) adverbials, as in John drew a circle in
/*for 5 seconds vs. John pushed a cart for /*in 5 seconds (cf. Dowty (1979
p. 60) for an overview of this and other tests).
This article picks up from the observation that there are languages – e.g.,
German, Inuktitut (an Inuit language of arctic Quebec), and Russian – in
which the aspectual reference of clauses or verb phrases (henceforth for
short: clauses) depends on the telicity of the event predicates they encode. In
5
such languages, clauses not overtly marked for viewpoint aspect implicate
or entail ‘event realization’, informally, the factual occurrence of an event as
described by a certain predicate at a certain time. The aspectual reference
associated with the use of a clause is computed in accordance with this and
with principles of Gricean pragmatics. Telic predicates only entail
realization under perfective aspect, and clauses encoding them are thus
interpreted perfectively in the default case. Atelic predicates are compatible
with realization under both imperfective and perfective aspect, but since
imperfective and perfective form an entailment scale with respect to
realization, clauses that encode atelic predicates and are not marked for
perfective aspect are interpreted imperfectively. Effectively, the correlation
in (3) emerges:
(3)
Preferred correlation between telicity and viewpoint selection
Event predicate
Viewpoint
Telic
~
Perfective
Atelic
~
Imperfective
We propose an analysis of the Imperfective Paradox in an event-based
semantics, namely Krifka’s (1989, 1992, 1998) ‘mereological’ (latticetheoretic) semantics of event predicates, which has the advantage over
3
We argue in §3.3 that expressions like push a cart may be exceptional in entailing realization in
the imperfective; most atelic predicates seem merely indeterminate in this regard.
6
interval-semantic treatments (such as Bennett and Partee 1978; Dowty 1979;
Taylor 1977) of accounting in a plausible fashion for a larger set of details.
The core of our analysis is the property of event realization, which we
model as an advancement of Parsons’s (1990) ‘culmination’. We argue that
event realization is the basis on which aspectual reference is assigned to
clauses not overtly marked for aspect in languages with telicity-dependent
aspectual reference.
We formalize event realization and capture the telicity-dependent
patterns of aspectual reference on which it is based by combining Krifka’s
event lattices with a model-theoretic interpretation of Klein’s (1994) theory
of tense and aspect. The attractiveness of Klein’s theory for our purposes
lies in particular in its definition of viewpoint aspect vis-à-vis so-called
‘topic times’. The topic time of an utterance that asserts or questions a
proposition about some event is the time with respect to which the
proposition is evaluated. This permits us to treat topic time as a temporal
constraint on event realization: only those parts of an event the ‘run times’
of which are entailed by the viewpoint-aspectual properties of the
proposition to be included in the topic time are realized. To show that event
predicates are associated with telicity-dependent aspectual reference on the
basis of event realization combined with Gricean maxims, we introduce a
model-theoretic ‘default aspect’ operator that has the same type-theoretic
7
properties as the operators we use to interpret (im)perfective aspects under
Klein’s theory, but is defined only in terms of event realization.
In §2, we introduce the phenomenon of telicity-dependent aspectual
reference, with data from Inuktitut, German, and Russian. We also briefly
compare this phenomenon to different forms of zero-marked aspectual
reference in other languages. We then propose model-theoretic analyses of
the property of event realization and the default aspect operator based on
Klein and Krifka in §3. We show that the operator indeed has a perfective
interpretation with telic predicates and an imperfective one with atelic
predicates, and we discuss how the operator accounts for the phenomena at
hand. In §4, we briefly review evidence from child language indicating that
aspectual interpretation on the basis of event realization is the preferred
form of aspectual reference in the early stages of child language
development crosslinguistically. This suggests that event realization has a
powerful impact on language use from an early age.
2. TELICITY-DEPENDENT ASPECTUAL REFERENCE
By telicity-dependent aspectual reference, we mean the phenomenon that
clauses or verbal projections not overtly marked for viewpoint aspect are
assigned semantic viewpoint-aspectual operators on the basis of the telicity
8
of their event predicates.4 An ideal system of telicity-dependent viewpoint
aspect has the structure depicted in Table 1:
Predicate atelic
Viewpoint
imperfective
perfective
Æ
overtly expressed
telic
overtly expressed
Æ
Table 1. An ideal telicity-dependent aspect system
Here, Æ stands for a viewpoint aspect operator that has no overt expression.
Our goal in this article is to show that in telicity-dependent systems, clauses
that lack overt viewpoint operators are assigned aspectual reference on the
basis of an implicature or entailment of ‘event realization’. In this section,
we discuss three languages that exhibit some form of telicity-dependent
aspectual reference – Inuktitut, German, and Russian. We then compare
these systems to one in which aspect marking depends on the classification
of event predicates in terms of processes vs. state changes, found in Yukatek
4
We assume that verbs, verbal projections, and clauses encode the natural-language counterparts of
model-theoretic event predicates – predicates denoting properties of events – in the sense of e.g.,
Davidson (1967), Krifka (1989, 1992, 1998), Parsons (1990). The event predicates encoded by
verbal projections and clauses are composed out of the event predicates lexicalized by verbs and
certain adjuncts and the predicates over individuals encoded by arguments and other adjuncts
through operations that are modelled by lambda abstraction and function application. Lexicalaspectual properties such as telicity and dynamicity are properties of event predicates. Viewpoint
aspects are operators that denote ordering relations between the ‘run times’ of events and certain
other time intervals – in the treatment developed in §3, ‘topic times’ – which serve as
‘viewpoints’, or ‘reference points’, in the sense of Reichenbach (1947). For the sake of simplicity,
we assume that every clause contains exactly one viewpoint operator. Whether viewpoint
operators are crosslinguistically encoded by a particular syntactic projection – some kind of
‘aspect phrase’ – is a matter we remain uncommitted on.
9
Maya. We also briefly contrast telicity-dependent viewpoint aspect with
dynamicity-governed systems, as found in English.
Inuktitut, a language spoken by the Inuit of arctic Quebec,5 has a single
temporally zero-marked verb form that occurs with both telic and atelic
predicates, but its interpretation differs depending on the telicity of the
predicate. Temporally zero-marked constructions encoding telic event
predicates have a perfective interpretation, as in (4), and those encoding
atelic predicates have an imperfective interpretation, as in (5) (Swift
forthcoming). 6
(4)
Anijuq.
(5)
Pisuttuq.
INU
ani-juq
pisuk-juq
go.out-PAR.3.SG
walk-PAR.3.SG
‘He/she went out.’
‘He/she is walking.’
This zero-marked form is contrasted with marked forms that encode
perfective viewpoints in clauses with atelic predicates and imperfective
viewpoints in clauses with telic predicates. Overt markers must be used to
5
The examples here are from the Tarramiut (Hudson Strait) dialect of Inuktitut.
6
The following abbreviations are used in the interlinear glosses: 1 – First person; 3 – Third person;
A – ‘Set-A’ (ergative/possessor) cross-reference marker; AUX – Auxiliary; B – ‘Set-B’
(absolutive) cross-reference markers; CMP – Completive; IMPF – Imperfective; INC –
Incompletive; ING – Ingressive; NPRES – Non-present tense; PAR – Participial (the standard
indicative mood in Tarramiut ); PAST – Past tense; PRS – Present tense; PRV – Perfective; SG –
Singular; TEL – Telic (prefix); TERM – Terminative; TP – Terminal particle.
10
express aspectual viewpoints other than those available with the zeromarked forms in (4) and (5), such as imperfective viewpoints with telic
predicates as in (6) and perfective viewpoints with atelic predicates as in (7).
(6)
Anilirtuq.
(7)
Pinasugiirtuq.
INU
ani-liq-juq
pinasuk-jariiq-juq
go.out-ING-PAR.3.SG
work-TERM-PAR.3.SG
‘He/she is (in the process of)
‘He/she finished
going out.’
working.’
We now turn to a language that lacks overt aspect marking altogether,
namely (Standard) German.7 German atelic descriptions in the present or
past tense are preferentially interpreted imperfectively, while telic
descriptions in the same tenses are preferentially interpreted perfectively (cf.
Bohnemeyer 1998).
(8)
GER
a. Als wir
when we
in Nijmegen eintrafen,
regnete es.
in Nijmegen arrived(PAST) it rained(PAST)
‘When we arrived in Nijmegen, it was raining.’
b. Als wir
when we
in Nijmegen eintrafen,
in Nijmegen arrived(PAST)
11
regnete es
eine Stunde lang.
it rained(PAST) for an hour
‘When we arrived in Nijmegen, it rained for an hour.’
(9)
GER
a. Als ich
when I
schrieb
Marys Büro
betrat,
Mary’s office entered(PAST)
sie
wrote(PAST) she
an einem Brief.
at a letter
‘When I entered Mary’s office, she was writing a letter.’
b. Als ich
when I
schrieb
Marys Büro
betrat,
Mary’s office entered(PAST)
sie
wrote(PAST) she
einen Brief.
a letter
‘When I entered Mary’s office, she wrote a letter.’
Example (8b) differs from (8a) in the added duration adverbial eine Stunde
lang ‘for an hour’, which renders the event description telic.8 The only
7
Colloquial dialects show a variety of weakly grammaticalized progressive periphrases; cf. e.g.,
Ballweg (1981); Delisle (1986).
8
The adverbial eine Stunde lang ‘for an hour’ renders the event predicate ‘bounded’ in the sense of
Depraetere (1995). Since bounded predicates are quantized, they satisfy the definition of telicity
we give in §3. We use this explicit form (a) for the sake of the minimal contrast to the atelic
predicate encoded without the adverbial and (b) to have unambiguous telicity.
12
natural interpretation of (8a) is that the rain is unbounded vis-à-vis the
arrival in Nijmegen, i.e., the description of the rain event is semantically
imperfective. In contrast, while such an interpretation is still possible in
(8b), by far the most natural reading of this sentence is that the rain started
at the arrival in Nijmegen, i.e., the rain is referred to perfectively. Similarly,
(9a) differs from (9b) in the partitive construction an einem Brief which
entails that only an unspecified part of the letter was written, rendering the
description atelic (cf. Krifka 1992). Example (9a) cannot be understood any
other way than that the writing event was ongoing during the entering event,
so in semantic terms, it is presented imperfectively. In contrast, (9b)
suggests that the writing event’s onset coincided with the entering (at least
this reading is more plausible than the overlap reading); i.e., the description
of the writing event is interpreted perfectively.
However, while a certain tradition of German studies may be construed
as arguing that clauses with atelic predicates actually encode imperfectivity,
and those with telic predicates encode perfectivity (see e.g., Eisenberg 1986,
Engel 1988; Ehrich 1992; Leiss 1992), the correlation can in fact be shown
to be no more than an implicature.9 For example, perfectivity in (9b) can
easily be blocked or cancelled in an appropriate context:
9
See Bohnemeyer (1998) for an analysis of a small German corpus elicited under controlled
conditions, showing a significant tendency of clauses with telic predicates to occur more often
13
(9)
b’. Als ich
when I
Marys Büro
Mary’s office entered(PAST)
schrieb
sie
wrote(PAST) she
einen Brief.
a letter
Überrascht blickte
surprised
betrat,
sie
looked(PAST)she
auf,
up
legte
den Stift
zur Seite,
laid(PAST)
the pen
aside
und lächelte
mich an.
and smiled(PAST) me
at
‘When I entered Mary’s office, she wrote / was writing / a letter.
Surprised, she looked up, put the pen away, and smiled at me.’
In (9b’), reference to the letter writing is understood to be imperfective – the
speaker’s entering overlaps with the letter writing, and completion of the
letter is not entailed. The analysis of telicity-dependent aspectual reference
we propose in §3 in fact predicts no more than an implicated alignment
between (a)telicity and (im)perfectivity. However, these implicatures may
turn into entailments due to ‘pragmatic strengthening’ (Hopper and Traugott
1993); this appears to have happened in Inuktitut, and possibly also in the
Russian case discussed below.
with perfective interpretations and of clauses with atelic predicates to occur more frequently with
14
The differential aspectual interpretation of clauses with telic and atelic
predicates in German has some interesting “side effects” that deserve further
attention. Firstly, as pointed out independently by Ehrich (1992) and Leiss
(1992), the so-called present tense of German tends to have present time
reference with atelic predicates, as in (10), but future time reference with
telic predicates, as in (11) (in contexts where it is understood as reference to
individual events rather than habitual or generic reference).
(10)
Es schneit.
GER
it snows(PRS)
‘It is snowing.’
(11)
Der Zug
fährt ab.
GER
the train
leaves(PRS)
‘The train is leaving / going to leave / will leave.’
Example (11) has not only pre-state readings (e.g., an announcement at the
station, warning passengers and bystanders that the train is about to leave),
but also purely predictive readings (e.g., ‘The train will leave (at such-andsuch time known to us)’). In contrast, the most likely interpretation for
example (10) is that snow is falling at the time of utterance. This is easily
imperfective interpretations.
15
explained by the preferences of (10) for imperfective and (11) for perfective
interpretations, in combination with a constraint excluding perfective
viewpoints from present time reference in most contexts (see e.g., Smith
1991, pp. 110-112).
The second “side effect” of the telicity-dependent aspectual interpretation
of clauses in German is the indirect impact telicity gains, via determining
viewpoint-aspectual reference, on temporal anaphora phenomena in
discourse. In narratives, clauses encoding telic predicates come to be
associated with ‘referential shift’ (i.e., sequential event order), as in (8b) and
(9b) above, while clauses encoding atelic predicates are associated with the
maintenance of reference points, and thereby with overlap, as in (8a) and
(9a). This is highly reminiscent of the treatment of temporal anaphora in
English in Dowty (1986), Hinrichs (1986), and ter Meulen (1995) – all of
these describe temporal anaphora as governed by the distinction between
Vendlerian states and activities on the one side and accomplishments and
achievements on the other, i.e., effectively, by telicity. In our view, this
analysis is better suited to the facts of Dutch and German than to those of
English.10 We think that temporal anaphora phenomena are universally
governed by viewpoint aspect, as suggested by Kamp and Rohrer (1983) for
10
The Dutch phenomena are somewhat similar to the German ones., though not completely Unlike
Standard German, Dutch has a grammaticalized progressive construction. However, unlike in
English, the use of the progressive is not obligatory with imperfective viewpoints in Dutch (cf.
Boogaart 1999). On the impact of the availability of a progressive construction on the
interpretation of aspectually unmarked clauses, see below.
16
French, Bohnemeyer (1998) for German and Yukatek Maya, and Boogaart
(1999) for Dutch. The impact of telicity on temporal anaphora in Dutch and
German is an artifact of the telicity-dependence of aspectual reference in
these languages. Since English has a dynamicity-governed aspect system
(see below), the telicity-biased analysis of temporal anaphora makes the
wrong predictions for activity verbs. These are dynamic and atelic, and thus
should trigger reference point maintenance according to Hinrichs, Dowty,
and ter Meulen. Thus, Dowty (1986) predicts that the second clause in (12)
should maintain the reference point introduced by the first clause, due to the
atelic predicate encoded by tick:
(12)
John entered the president’s office. The clock on the wall ticked
loudly. (Dowty 1986: 38)
Our consultants consider (12) marked. The interpretation that the clock has
been ticking before John entered seems indeed natural; but to indicate
overlap, the second clause should appear in the progressive. Since it does
not, it is interpreted perfectively, leaving consultants groping to coerce an
interpretation in line with referential shift (e.g., a semelfactive reading of
tick).11
11
The position that activity verbs pattern with achievements and accomplishments with respect to
temporal anaphora in English is implicitly shared by Kamp and Reyle (1993) and Smith (1991).
17
The case of Russian, Czech, and other Slavic languages is slightly more
complex than that of Inuktitut and German. In Russian, unprefixed verbs
such as kolót’ ‘prick’, kryt’ ‘cover’, igrát’ ‘play’, or pisát’ ‘write’ are mostly
atelic. Telic predicates, on the other hand, are mostly encoded by prefixed
verbs (or verbs suffixed with the ‘semelfactive’ suffix –nu).12 This includes
prefixed counterparts of the atelic unprefixed forms, such as vý-kolot’
‘thrust out’, ‘tattoo’; ot-krýt’ ‘open’; pro-igrát’ ‘lose’; and pere-pisát’
‘copy’. The relationship between telicity and prefixation is quite systematic;
even unprefixed verbs that one would expect to be telic on the basis of their
English glosses are in fact atelic. Consider the example of stávit’ ‘put’ (and
see Filip (1999) and Krifka (1992) for the following):
12
There are some 50 unprefixed telic verbs, such as brósit’ ‘throw’, dat’ ‘give’, kónčit’ ‘end’, and
past’ ‘fall’. These are all inherently perfective, and thus in fact correspond to our hypothesis.
However, they have suppletive imperfective ‘partners’, and these inherently imperfective verbs
are naturally difficult to test for telicity. Moreover, arguably not all prefixed verbs are telic. As
Filip (1999,PP. 200-207) shows for Czech – the Russian data are parallel – there are prefix verbs
which combine with duration adverbials, rather than with time span adverbials, and to this extent
pattern with atelic verbs. These are in particular members of the ‘cumulative’ (e.g., na-nosít’ drov
‘bring a sufficient amount of wood’), ‘delimitative’ (e.g., po-čitát’ ‘read for a while’), and
‘attenuative’ (e.g., pri-leč’ ‘lie down for a bit’) ‘aktionsarten’ (quoting Russian examples from
Isačenko 1975: 381-397). Filip submits that these quantify over the event variable or an
individual variable carrying an ‘incremental theme’ role or both. If an incremental theme is
involved, quantizedness of the event predicate may depend on quantizedness of the incremental
theme. Since the verbs in question are perfective, and we characterize telicity in terms of
quantizedness in §3.1, this is the only case that poses a potential problem for our account.
However, note that the verbs in question do seem to entail event realization; at least they lack
imperfective counterparts. In any case, these predicates need further study. Finally, as for the
18
(13)
Včera
ja stavila
knigi
na polku
RUS
yesterday I put(PAST) books(PL) on shelf
dva časa.
two hours
‘Yesterday I put books on the shelf for two hours.’
(14)
Včera
ja po-stavila
vse knigi
na polku
RUS
yesterday I TEL-put(PAST) all books(PL) on shelf
za dva chasa.
in two hours
‘Yesterday I put all the books on the shelf in two hours.’
The telicity contrast in (13)-(14) is due to (13) referring to an indefinite set
of books, but (14) to a definite one. Russian does not have a definite article
(definiteness interpretations on noun phrases are in fact often triggered on
the basis of telic verb prefixes); the delimitation of the set of books in (14) is
forced by the universal quantifier vse. This renders the event predicate
encoded by (14) quantized and thereby telic (cf. §3). The selection of time
adverbials reflects the telicity contrast – dva chasa ‘for two hours’ is a
duration adverbial, while za dva chasa ‘in two hours’ in (14) is a time span
adverbial. Crucially, the atelic stávit’ is acceptable in (13), but not in (14),
while the telic po-stávit’ is acceptable in (14), but not in (13).13
semelfactives in –nu (e.g., glot-nut’ ‘swallow’), these are telic and inherently perfective and thus
fit our analysis.
13
We thank Tania Kochetkova and Mikhail Masharov for Russian examples and judgements.
19
Now, even though in the tradition of Russian grammaticography,
unprefixed verbs such as those quoted above are called ‘imperfective’,
semantically they allow for both imperfective and perfective interpretations,
as Klein (1995) has shown.14 (13) in fact shows a perfective use of stávit’.
However, the prefixed verbs are strictly perfective. Thus, while the simplex
stávit’ in (15) is most likely interpreted imperfectively (in terms of the
viewpoint metaphor, the putting event is viewed internally in (15); in terms
of the effect on temporal ordering, the putting event is interpreted to overlap
with the when-clause event), the prefixed po-stávit’ in (16) does not permit
this reading (the two events can only be understood to be ordered
sequentially).
(15)
Ja stavila
knigi
na polku
RUS
I put(PAST)
books(PL) on shelf
kogda
uslyšala
novosti.
when
heard(PAST) news
‘I was putting books on the shelf when I heard the news.’
14
Our analysis of the Russian data closely follows Klein (1995). Note that Klein’s use of the terms
‘perfective’ and ‘imperfective’ as designating semantic aspect operators (cf. §3) does not always
align with how these terms are traditionally used in Slavic linguistics to denote verb form classes.
Our treatment parts company with Klein’s mainly in that we consider the essential contribution of
the prefixes to the aspectual “mix” to be telicity, not state change.
20
(16)
*Ja
po-stavila
vse knigi
na polku
RUS
I
TEL-put(PAST)
books(PL)
on shelf
kogda
uslyšala
novosti.
when
heard(PAST) news
‘I was putting all the books on the shelf when I heard the news.’
The perfectivity of po-stávit’ renders (17) pragmatically anomalous: Igor
cannot have interrupted the shelving of the books (both because of the
entailment of realization and because of sequential ordering); hence, it is
unclear what he did interrupt.
(17)
RUS
? Ja po-stavila
I TEL-put(PAST)
vse knigi
na polku
books(PL)
on shelf
kogda
Igor’ prerval
menja.
when
Igor’ interrupted(PAST) me
‘I had put all books on the shelf when Igor interrupted me.’
/*‘I was putting all the books on the shelf when Igor interrupted
me’
Many prefixed telic verbs form so-called ‘secondary imperfectives’ by
suffixation of -iv/-yv. (18) shows the atelic pisát’ ‘write’; (19) the telic perepisát’ ‘copy’. (20) features the secondary imperfective pere-písyvat’ ‘be
21
copying’; in this context, the inherently perfective pere-pisát’ is again
anomalous.
(18)
RUS
Včera
ja pisala
pis’ma
dva časa.
yesterday I wrote(PAST) letters(PL) two hours
‘Yesterday I wrote letters for two hours.’
pis’mo za dva časa.
(19)
Ja pere-pisala
RUS
I TEL-wrote(PAST) letter
in two hours
‘I copied the letter in two hours.’
(20)
Ja pere-pis-yvala
pis’mo
RUS
I TEL-write-IMPF-PAST letter
kogda
Igor’ prerval
menja.
when
Igor’ interrupted(PAST) me
‘I was copying the letter when Igor interrupted me.’
The picture that emerges here can be summarized as follows: verbs
encoding telic predicates are zero-marked for perfective aspect; if they
produce imperfective forms at all, they require the suffix –iv/–yv for this
purpose. In contrast, atelic predicates without overt aspect marking are
compatible with both imperfective and perfective interpretations. This is in
22
line with the analysis in §3, to the extent that atelic predicates may have
event realization under both aspects. However, our account further predicts
that imperfectivity should be a preferred interpretation with atelic
predicates. Whether this indeed holds for Russian remains to be
investigated.
To properly delimit the scope of our analysis, let us briefly compare
telicity-dependent aspectual reference to other cases in which the viewpoint
of clauses not overtly marked for aspect depends on lexical-aspectual
properties. A system that at first sight looks strikingly similar to that of
Inuktitut is found in Yukatek, the Mayan language of the Yucatan peninsula
in Mexico and Belize. Intransitive process verbs take a zero suffix when
combining with the imperfective aspect auxiliary, as in (21), but the suffix
-nah when combining with the perfective aspect auxiliary, as in (22).
(21) K-u=meyah-ø.
YUK IMPF-A.3=work(INC)
‘He works/is working.’
(22) H=meyah-nah-ih.
PRV=work-CMP-B.3.SG
‘He worked.’
Conversely, intransitive state change verbs take the suffix -Vl15 when
combining with the imperfective aspect auxiliary, as in (23), and a zero
suffix when combining with the perfective auxiliary, as in (24) (cf.
23
Bohnemeyer (2002, in press)).16
(23)
YUK
K-u=kim-il.
(24) H=kim-ø-ih.
IMPF-A.3=die-INC
PRV=die(CMP)-B.3.SG
‘He dies / is dying.’
‘He died.’
The aspect marking patterns in (21)-(24) do not directly reflect the
telicity of the predicate encoded by the clause, but only the lexical
classification of the verb stem in terms of the distinction between processes
and state changes in the sense of von Wright (1963) and Dowty (1979) and
similar proposals by Bach (1986), Klein (1994), Moens (1987) and others.
The form of the aspectual suffixes a verb occurs with are determined in the
lexicon and do not vary with the referential and quantificational properties
of the argument noun phrases it combines with in syntactic projections. One
might think of the Yukatek system as a “lexicalized” version of the telicitygoverned split exhibited by languages like Inuktitut and Russian. For
instance, kim ‘die’ is telic when combined with a quantized theme argument,
as in (23); but when combined with a nonquantized noun phrase like máak
‘people’, it becomes atelic (see e.g., Verkuyl (1972, 1992); Krifka (1989,
1992, 1998)). Yet, either way, it is zero-marked for perfective aspect and
15
/V/ represents a vocalic morphophoneme the quality of which is determined by a root vowel
(‘vowel harmony’).
24
requires an overt suffix to express imperfective aspect (see Bohnemeyer
2002 for details). Table 2 summarizes the analysis of the pattern in (21)(24):
Verb class process
Viewpoint
imperfective
perfective
Æ
overtly expressed
state change
overtly expressed
Æ
Table 2. Aspect marking sensitive to verb classes
A type of differential aspect marking that appears to occur quite frequently
in the languages of the world is that exhibited by English. We illustrate this
type of system with examples from the Kwa language Ewe, spoken in
Ghana and Togo. Like English, Ewe contrasts a marked progressive
(expressing imperfective viewpoint) with a zero-marked perfective form. In
both languages, the aspectual reference of the marked form – the
progressive – as well as that of the zero-marked form is independent of
telicity, as shown in (25) and (26).17
(25) a. Kofi dze
EWE
16
d]
Kofi contact illness
In addition, there are two other classes of intransitive state change verbs which overtly mark both
aspects, and the same holds for all transitive verbs.
25
tsódzo `agbe
vase`e ku`agbe.
from
until
Monday
Wednesday
‘Kofi was ill from Monday till Wednesday.’
b. Ési
me-yi
é-gb]
lá,
when 1.SG-go 3.SG-place TP
é-dze
d].
3.SG-contact illness
‘When I went to him, he was ill.’
(26) a. Kofí kp] TV
ets].
EWE
yesterday
Kofi see
TV
‘Kofi watched TV yesterday.’
b. Esi
when
é-n]
me-yi
k]fí gb] ets]
1.SG-go Kofi place yesterday
TV
3.SG-AUX:NPRES TV
lá
TP
kp]-m3.
see-PROG
‘When I went to see Kofi yesterday he was watching TV.’
The examples in (25) show the stative phrase dze d] ‘be ill’ (literally ‘be in
contact with illness’) with perfective viewpoint in (a) and imperfective
17
The Ewe examples have been kindly provided by James Essegbey.
26
viewpoint in (b). In both cases, there is no overt aspect marking. In contrast,
the dynamic kp] TV ‘watch TV’ in (26) is interpreted perfectively when not
aspectually marked, as in (a), and requires progressive marking to achieve
an imperfective interpretation, as in (b). The translations of (25) and (26)
illustrate the same point for English. Since progressive marking does not
depend on telicity (rather on dynamicity), neither does the aspectual
interpretation of the simple tense forms. Such systems are likely found in
languages that have fully grammaticalized progressives, but not
imperfective aspect markers. In first approximation, progressives express
imperfective viewpoints, but are restricted to dynamic clauses (cf. Dowty
1979; Taylor 1977). Dynamic clauses unmarked for viewpoint aspect then
come to be associated with perfective aspect through Gricean Quantity
implicatures (Grice 1975; cf. also Levinson 2000). Table 3 summarizes
dynamicity-dependent aspect marking:
Predicate stative
Viewpoint
imperfective
perfective
Æ
Æ
dynamic
overtly expressed
Æ
Table 3. Aspect-marking sensitive to verb classes
In contrast to the systems depicted in Table 2-3, telicity-dependent
aspectual reference in clauses without overt viewpoint aspect markers
presumably only arises if overt viewpoint aspect marking either depends on
27
telicity – as in Inuktitut and Russian – or is lacking altogether, as in
German. Quite possibly the aspectual interpretation of the zero-marked
clauses always starts out as an implicature, as in German; but this
implicature may turn into an entailment (as appears to have happened in
Inuktitut and Russian) through the process of semantic change known as
‘pragmatic strengthening’ (cf. Hopper and Traugott 1993). The analysis we
develop in §3 predicts implicated alignments of aspectually unmarked
clauses encoding telic predicates with perfective viewpoints and of
unmarked clauses encoding atelic predicates with imperfective viewpoints.
We submit that aspectually unmarked clauses in languages with telicitydependent viewpoint aspect implicate event realization and are aspectually
interpreted accordingly.
3. TOWARDS A SEMANTIC EXPLANATION
We propose that in languages with telicity-dependent aspectual reference,
such as those discussed in §2, verbal projections and clauses which are not
overtly marked for viewpoint aspect implicate event realization, on the basis
of Grice’s (1975) second maxim of Quantity. Their aspectual reference is
then computed in accordance with the conditions under which the event
predicates they encode have event realization. This is perfective aspect for
telic predicates, while atelic predicates are compatible with realization under
both perfective and imperfective viewpoints – Grice’s first Quantity maxim
28
here triggers a scalar implicature to imperfective.
We develop our account as follows. In §3.1, we lay out the framework of
our analysis, based on Krifka’s (1989, 1992, 1998) mereological approach
to event semantics and telicity and Klein’s (1994) account of tense and
viewpoint aspect. In §3.2, we introduce the concept of event realization. We
start from Parsons’s (1990) related notion of ‘culmination’, take into
account recent criticisms of Parsons’s proposal , and eventually arrive at a
definition which, in line with Klein’s theory of aspect, constrains realization
to those parts of an event the ‘run times’ of which fall into the ‘topic times’
for which a proposition about the event is evaluated.
In §3.3, we argue that event predicates are associated with telicitydependent aspectual reference on the basis of event realization combined
with Gricean maxims. We introduce a model-theoretic ‘default aspect’
operator that has the type-theoretic properties of viewpoint aspects under
our interpretation of Klein’s theory, but is defined in terms of event
realization, and examine under what conditions this operator has the telicitydependent aspectual interpretations observed in §2-§3. We do not consider
default aspect a (notional) aspectual operator on a par with perfective and
imperfective aspect. For one, we are unaware of any language that overtly
marks default aspect. Default aspect is merely the preferred or exclusive
aspectual interpretation of predicates not overtly marked for aspect in
languages in which aspect marking and aspectual reference depend on event
29
realization. In §3.4, we review the data of §2 and discuss how default aspect
accounts for them. In §4, we briefly consider the possible role of event
realization in constraining aspectual reference in child language.
3.1 PREREQUISITES
With Davidson (1967), Parsons (1990), and many others, we assume that
natural language predicates denote properties of events. In the spirit of
Krifka (1998, p. 206), we adopt the definition of an ‘event structure’ E that
includes a domain of events UE and a ‘time structure’ TE. E defines a
mereological ‘part structure’ on UE, which includes a part relation ≤E and a
proper part relation <E among events. TE defines analogous relations ≤T and
<T over a domain of time intervals UT. ≤E and ≤T are partial order relations
defined via primitive mereological ‘sum’ operations, and E and TE are join
semilattices with respect to these sum operations. E moreover includes a
‘temporal trace’ function tE from UE to UT which assigns ‘run(ning) times’
to events. We understand these as situated time intervals the lower bounds
of which are marked by the beginnings of the events and the upper bounds
of which mark the ends of the events.
We follow Klein (1994) in considering viewpoint aspect operators as
relating the run time tE(e) of an event e (corresponding to Klein’s ‘time of
the situation’) to the ‘topic time’ tTOP of some proposition “about” e. Tense
operators then relate topic times to coding times. Topic times are the times
30
for which propositions are, depending on the illocution of the utterance,
asserted to be true, questioned for their truth, “requested” to be made true,
and so on – in short, the times with respect to which propositions are
evaluated. Consider (27):
(27)
On Monday, Floyd was ill.
There are at least two ways in which the interval denoted by on Monday
may constrain the topic time for which the proposition encoded by Floyd
was ill is asserted – the proposition may hold for the entire interval, or there
may be an implicit existential quantification over some subinterval for
which the proposition is asserted (say 3 pm to 4 pm). Either way, the topic
time does not bind the run time of the state of Floyd being ill – Floyd may
well continue to be ill through Wednesday. But whatever happened prior to
Monday or after Monday has no impact on the truth of (27), which is only
evaluated for this particular topic time.
Because topic times delimit the evaluation of propositions, we argue
below that they constrain event realization. Of particular interest for the
present purposes are perfective aspects, which encode inclusion of t(e) in
tTOP and thus entail realization of the entire event (as in our formalization in
(28), where P is an event predicate), and imperfective aspects, which encode
proper inclusion of tTOP in t(e) and thus entail realization of proper
31
subevents at most ((29); see Figure 1 in §3.2):18
(28) PRV := lPltTOP$e[P(e) Ù t(e) ≤T tTOP]
(29) IMPF := lPltTOP$e[P(e) Ù tTOP <T t(e)]
The binding of tTOP by a lambda operator in (28)-(29) reflects Klein’s (1994
p. 108) view that aspectual operators constrain ‘projection ranges’ of
possible topic times rather than operating on definite topic times; it is really
these projection ranges that are assigned to tTOP in (29). From these
projection ranges, some definite topic time may then be selected in context.
In this regard, topic times play a similar role in Klein’s theory to that of
Reichenbachian ‘reference points’ (Reichenbach 1947) in treatments of
tense and aspect in Discourse Representation Theory, such as Hinrichs
(1986), Kamp and Rohrer (1983), and Partee (1984). That is, every
proposition in discourse is evaluated with respect to its own unique (set of)
topic time(s), but contextual inferences may determine the topic time of one
proposition to be identical to or ‘shifted’ with respect to that of some
18
Precedence relations between t(e) and tTOP yield prospective (as in English be going to +
infinitive constructions, where tTOP precedes t(e)) and perfect aspects (as in the English perfect
tenses, where tTOP follows t(e)). For the relation between event realization implicatures and such
aspectual interpretations see §3.3. Partial overlap of t(e) and tTOP is discussed but not properly
accounted for in Klein (1994), and is disregarded here as well.
32
proposition in surrounding discourse.19
Now consider some examples:20
(30) Am Nachmittag schrieb
Hans
in the afternoon wrote(PAST) Hans
einen Brief.
a letter
‘In the afternoon, Hans wrote a letter.’
(31) Am Nachmittag schrieb
Hans
in the afternoon wrote(PAST) Hans
an einem Brief.
at a letter
‘In the afternoon, Hans was writing a letter (lit.: wrote part of a
letter).’
The topic times for the evaluation of (30)-(31) are delimited by the
adverbial am Nachmittag ‘in the afternoon’. The semantically perfective
(30) entails that the time of letter writing is included in this time, and thus
that the letter was completed in the afternoon. In (31), the partitive an einem
Brief ‘at a letter’ restricts realization within the afternoon frame to part of a
letter. Since the writing of some part of a letter equals a partial writing of
the letter, this has the effect of locating the topic time frame within the run
time of the hypothetical writing of the complete letter, which explains why
19
In “tensed” languages, the ranges of possible topic times are further constrained by tense
operators, which on Klein’s view relate topic times to coding time, or the ‘time of utterance’.
20
We thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting (30)-(31).
33
the truth conditions of (31) are rather like those of the imperfective In the
afternoon, Hans was writing a letter.
As for (a)telicity, in line with Krifka’s approach, we view these not as
properties of events, but as properties of event predicates. The closest
mereological second-order properties that may be used to capture the
properties of telic and atelic predicates are quantizedness and cumulativity,
respectively. In (32), we define all telic event predicates as quantized and
vice versa, based on Krifka’s (1992 p. 32; 1998 p. 200) characterization of
quantized predicates.
(32) "PÍUE [TELE(P) « "e,e’ÎUE[P(e) Ù P(e’) ® Øe’<Ee]]
According to (32), an event predicate P is telic if an event e’ that instantiates
P cannot be a proper part of another event e that also falls under P.21
21
Krifka (1992, 1998) cautions that while clearly all quantized event predicates are telic, there may
be non-quantized telic predicates as well. Krifka (1992, p. 36) mentions the predicate encoded by
walk to the station – would this not be instantiated by any number of “subwalks” that all
terminate at the station? However, on closer examination, this is not so obvious. Consider Loretta
walked to the station. There are various ways in which this sentence may be used in natural
interactions. For example, with the main stress on walk, it may simply answer a question about
how Loretta got to the station. But it seems that in any context in which one might try to test the
sentence for telicity – be it via the Imperfective Paradox, compatibility with duration vs. time
span adverbials, etc. – one has to compute the truth conditions of walk to the station’ with respect
to some implicit starting point that is to be retrieved from context. In this case, the truth
conditions of Loretta walked to the station are equivalent to those of something like Loretta
walked from where she was before to the station, which of course encodes a quantized predicate.
In short, we feel justified in considering quantizedness at least a reasonable enough
approximation of telicity to restrict our discussion to it.
34
The case for cumulativity – the property of event predicates to apply to
the mereological sum of any two subevents it applies to – as a necessary and
sufficient condition for atelicity is a different story. Cumulativity is for
various reasons rather impracticable for our goals. For one, in order to
calculate the conditions atelicity imposes on event realization, we need to
talk about the subevents of events in the denotation of atelic predicates –
and not about their sums. So in a first approximation, we define atelicity in
(33) as divisiveness, i.e., by requiring that events falling under atelic
predicates have at least one proper part that falls under the same predicate:
(33) "PÍUE[ATELE(P) « "eÎUE [P(e) ® $e’ÎUE[P(e’) Ù e’<Ee]]]
But divisiveness is still too broad: it sweeps under the rug important
differences distinct types of atelic predicates show regarding event
realization.22 In order to get at these differences, we consider a continuum of
cases ranging from completely divisive and homogenous predicates to those
that only have atomic events in their extension. This latter case is telic,
while all other predicates on the continuum are atelic.
Predicates that are ‘homogeneously divisive’ are those that have the
‘subinterval property’ in the sense of Taylor (1977) and Dowty (1979), i.e.,
22
It should not come as a surprise to find the class of atelic predicates rather heterogeneous. After
all, atelicity is essentially a negative property. This is the very reason why we are struggling here
to find some positive characterization.
35
all subevents of events in the extension of the predicate also fall under the
predicate:
(34) "PÍUE[HOMDE(P) « "eÎUE[P(e) ® "e’ÎUE[e’≤Ee ® P(e’)]]]
Perhaps Vendler (1957) chose his paradigm activity example push a cart
with something like homogenous divisiveness in mind.23 In the case of push
a cart, there are at least no obvious candidates for atomic pushing events;
but with probably the great majority of natural language event predicates,
this is certainly different. The notion of ‘atoms’, the smallest parts that
instantiate the predicate, and that of ‘atomic predicates’ may be defined as
in (35)-(36), respectively, following Krifka (1992, p. 32):
(35) "PÍUE,"eÎUE[ATOME(e,P) « P(e) Ù Ø$e’ÎUE[P(e’) Ù e’<Ee]]
(36) "PÍUE[ATME(P) ®
"eÍUE[P(e) ® $e’ÎUE[e’£Ee Ù ATOME(e’,P)]]]
That is, an event e is a P-atom iff it falls under P and does not contain any
subevent that also falls under P. And a predicate P is atomic iff every event
e that falls under P has a P-atom as a part. A clear enough example of an
23
Except as a characterization of activities such as denoted by push a cart, Vendler would restrict
(34) to non-instantaneous subevents.
36
atomic predicate is encoded by eat peanuts – only subevents in which more
than one peanut is eaten instantiate this predicate. It follows from (33) that if
all events in the extension of P are P-atoms, then P must be quantized and
thus telic, and given (32), the inverse holds as well. Thus:
(37) "PÍUE [TELE(P) « "eÎUE[P(e) ® ATOME(e,P)]]
Therefore, if P is atelic (in the sense of divisive), it must have at least one
non-atomic event that falls under it:
(38) "PÍUE[ATELE(P) « $eÎUE[P(e) Ù ØATOME(e,P)]]
We show in §3.3 that homogeneously divisive predicates entail realization
with respect to any topic time that overlaps with the run time of an event in
their denotation. With regard to atomic predicates, we argue that realization
is indeterminate, since it is impossible to know whether the run times of any
P-atoms overlap with topic time. It is not clear to us whether there are any
predicates in natural languages that apply to events composed out of
combinations of homogeneously divisive and atomic parts; but if there are,
the indeterminacy argumentation carries over to them, since there is no way
of knowing whether topic time falls in a homogeneously divisive part or
not. The same goes for cases such as walk, where we have a relatively clear
37
intuition that the predicate must be somehow atomic, but we do not find it
easy to delimit the atomic subevents.
3.2 EVENT REALIZATION AND TOPIC TIME
‘Realization’ of an event amounts to what is meant in ordinary English by
saying that an event occurs or happens.24 We take realization to be the
“eventish” equivalent of the existence of individuals. However, we cannot
hope to model realization simply by existential quantification over an event
variable. ‘Event arguments’ are often existentially bound by default in
Davidsonian frameworks (cf. e.g., (41) below). More importantly, beyond
the technicalities of Davidsonian event semantics, existential quantification
in predicate calculus seems on the whole ill-suited to the representation of
the “contingent” (in particular: time-bound) existence/realization of
individuals/events in imagined or experienced reality; and this naturally
extends to the encoding of existence/realization in language (see von
Stechow (2001) for the argumentation regarding existence).
The account of realization we give here has two components: an “intrapropositional” one, which captures the dependence of realization on the
event predicate and the time for which a proposition is evaluated, i.e., the
Kleinian ‘topic time’ of the utterance, and a propositional-level component,
which captures the relativity of realization vis-à-vis possible worlds. We
24
We borrow the term ‘event realization’ from Pederson (forthcoming) and Talmy (1991).
38
only provide a formal treatment of the former notion. It is not difficult to see
that the notion of event realization, as we envision it here, has a denotation
that does not carry over across possible worlds. Thus, future time reference
(39a), epistemic modals (39b), belief contexts (39c), and counterfactuals
(39d) all constitute opaque contexts for realization, in the sense that they do
not license the inferences that the (interlocutor’s model of the) actual world
in which the utterances are made contains an event of John drawing a circle.
(39) a. John will draw a circle.
b. John may draw a circle.
c. Floyd thought that John drew a circle.
d. If Floyd had shown up, John would have drawn a circle.
Yet, the inference patterns of the Imperfective Paradox go through in these
contexts as long as the worlds with respect to which the propositions are
evaluated are kept constant:
(40) a. John will be pushing a cart.
John will be drawing a circle.
b. John may be pushing a cart.
John may be drawing a circle.
\ John will push a cart.
not\ John will draw a circle.
\ John may push a cart.
not\John may draw a circle.
39
And so on. So to the extent that we appeal to event realization in our
account of these patterns, event realization should be equipped to have the
desired effect independently of possible-world semantics. A good starting
point is Parsons’s (1990) notion of ‘culmination’. In Parsons’s framework,
the semantics of (41a) and (b) may be spelled out as in (41a’) and (b’),
respectively (cf. Parsons 1990, pp. 170-172):
(41) a. John was drawing a circle.
a’. $t[t<now Ù$e[drawing_a_circle(e) Ù agent(John,e) Ù Hold(e,t)]]
b. John drew a circle.
b’. $t[t<now Ù$e[drawing_a_circle(e) Ù agent(John,e) Ù Cul(e,t)]]
This accounts for the Imperfective Paradox by treating the circle drawing
event in (41a) as ‘unculminated’; instead, the predicate Hold, which
represents the equivalent of Cul for states, encodes the semantic
contribution of the progressive. Since Parsons does not state the truth
conditions for either Cul or Hold, it remains unclear what it means for an
event to hold instead of culminating (cf. also Landman 1992; Zucchi 1999).
Aside from this, a major drawback of Parsons’s proposal is the application
of Cul directly to events and times, leaving aside the contribution of the
event predicate. Accordingly, while the analysis in (41a’) captures the
40
drawing of the circle remaining unculminated, it fails to license the
inference that at least part of the event is realized, which might well
instantiate the predicate draw’, even if it does not instantiate draw a circle’.
25
In line with Krifka’s mereological approach to event semantics, and in
agreement in this respect with Zucchi (1999), we attempt to avoid these
problems by relativizing realization not merely to events and times, but also
to event predicates; it is thus not events as such that are (un)realized at
particular times, but events under a predicate.
A final issue concerns the identity of the time variable in (41). Should
this be equated with the ‘run time’ of the event, i.e., the situated time
interval defined by beginning and end of the event? In the spirit of Klein
(1994), we think not. Klein’s analysis of the progressive in (41a) (cf. (29)
above) would situate the topic time tTOP with respect to which (41a) is
asserted within the run time of the circle drawing event. It is only the part of
the event carved out by overlap with tTOP that is asserted to be realized (cf.
Figure 1).
25
To deal with telicity, Parsons is forced into an ontological distinction between events and
41
processes, the latter being treated as indefinite sequences of culminated event atoms.
42
Figure 1. Realization and topic time under Klein's (1994) analysis of
imperfectives
If
the
predicate the event instantiates is telic, the proper subevent overlapping with
topic time cannot itself fall under the predicate; hence, realization under
imperfective aspect is excluded with telic predicates. In contrast, if the
predicate is atelic, it is at least not excluded that the proper subevent
selected by the imperfective for overlap with topic time instantiates the
predicate .26 Topic time has this power of constraining event realization
because by definition it constrains the time for which propositions about
some event are asserted, questioned, etc. The part of such propositions we
are concerned with here is the application of an event predicate to the event
at the topic time in certain worlds. Imperfective aspect restricts this part of
the proposition’s “claim” to a topic time within the run time of the event,
and thereby excludes realization of the event as a whole from what the
propositions make claims about. Whether the proper subevent that falls
within topic time, and thus within what the proposition is about, instantiates
the predicate, and thus ensures realization, is then largely a matter of the
26
We argue in §3.3 that event realization with atelic predicates under imperfective aspect is actually
strictly speaking indeterminate, except in the – perhaps somewhat unrealistic – case of
homogeneously divisive predicates.
43
telicity of the predicate.27
We are now in a position to define event realization “within” a possible
world:
(42) "P,tTOP,eÍE[REALE(P,tTOP,e) « $e’[P(e’)Ùe’£EeÙt(e’)≤TtTOP]]
That is, a predicate P is realized by event e at topic time tTOP, or
equivalently, e is realized under P at tTOP, if and only if at least the run time
of a subevent e’ of e that also falls in the denotation of P is included in tTOP.
3.3 FROM EVENT REALIZATION TO DEFAULT ASPECT
We argue that if a language has predicates that are formally zero-marked for
aspect, but have telicity-dependent aspectual reference, then these predicates
come to be aspectually interpreted under an implicature of event realization.
We can thus model this implicated aspectual operator as in (43), and ask
what its interpretation will be depending on the telicity of the predicate.
(43) DASP := lPltTOP$e[REALE(P,tTOP,e)]
(43) has the format of the aspectual operators in (28)-(29). When applied to
27
One might ask whether it is sensible to assign run times to unrealized events, as our analysis does,
in view of the severe restrictions on combining imperfectives with, e.g., duration specifications
(Mittwoch 1988; cf. also Zucchi 1999). In our view, there is no contradiction here. It seems
44
an event predicate P and an event variable e bound by existential closure,
DASP will assign to tTOP a suitable topic time ‘projection range’ such that e
is realized under P. Two questions arise now: (a) why should aspectually
unmarked predicates come to implicate something like (43)? And (b),
assuming that predicates are aspectually interpreted under (43), what values
will DASP assign to tTOP, and what relations between tTOP and the run time
t(e) will this determine?
Regarding (a), we submit that Grice’s (1975) second maxim of Quantity
(Q2) provides the answer: “Do not make your contribution more
informative than is required”; cf. also Levinson’s (2000) equivalent ‘IHeuristic’, “What is expressed simply is stereotypically exemplified”. It
certainly seems reasonable to consider aspectual reference under event
realization more stereotypical than aspectual reference under lack of
realization, and thus leave the latter to overtly marked forms. This
assumption is supported by our interpretation of the child language data
cited in §4. If reference to realized events is developmentally prior to
reference to unrealized events, this can be taken as evidence to the greater
stereotypicality of aspect under realization compared to aspect under lack of
realization.
Now for (b), the interpretation of DASP depending on the telicity of the
predicate. Note first that given (42), (43) requires tTOP and t(e) to overlap
impossible to understand the semantics of imperfectives without reference to proper subevents,
45
(since at least the run time of a subevent of e must be included in tTOP),
ruling out prospective and perfect aspect interpretations. Furthermore, if P is
telic, then it must be the case that t(e)≤TtTOP (run time included in topic
time), i.e., DASP produces a perfective viewpoint according to (28). This is
because according to (32), if P is telic, no proper subevent of e falls under
P. Thus, the only way for tTOP and t(e) to overlap is t(e)≤TtTOP. In other
words, telic predicates only have realization under perfective aspect. This
explains part of the Imperfective Paradox, namely why John was drawing a
circle does not entail realization of a circle drawing event at any topic time,
and thus does not license John drew a circle.
But what if P is atelic? First, suppose P is homogeneously divisive. Then
according to (34), any subevent of e will instantiate P. This includes an
infinite number of proper subevents e’ such that t(e’)<TtTOP (inclusion of the
proper subevent in topic time) and yet P(e’). Hence, realization of e under P
at tTOP is compatible with tTOP<Tt(e) (topic time is a part of the run time
interval of e), i.e., imperfective viewpoint according to (29). Assuming that
push a cart encodes a homogeneously divisive event predicate, this explains
why John was pushing a cart being true at some definite tTOP entails that
John pushed a cart is true at the same tTOP, i.e., the second half of the
Imperfective Paradox. This is because whatever subevent of John’s cart
pushing is carved out by its run time coinciding with topic time falls under
which by their very definition imply at least intensionally “larger” events and their run times.
46
push a cart’.
However, a perfective interpretation of DASP is of course possible with
atelic predicates as well – perfectivity always gives realization (t(e)≤TtTOP as
in (28) makes t(e’)≤TtTOP in (42) trivially true for e’=e.) So truthconditionally, the interpretation of DASP with homogeneously divisive
predicates is vague regarding perfectivity. But in this case, all else being
equal, a scalar implicature licensed by Grice’s (1975) first maxim of
Quantity (Q1, “Make your contribution as informative as is required”, or
Levinson’s (2000) equivalent ‘Q-heuristic’ (“What isn’t said, isn’t”)) will
assign an imperfective reading to DASP due to the absence of perfective
marking.28 Imperfective and perfective aspects form an entailment scale (or
‘Horn scale’, after Horn (1972)) regarding event realization. Consider (44):
(44) "P,tTOP,e,e’ÍE[e’£Ee ® [[IMPF(P,tTOP,e) Ù REALE(P,tTOP,e’)]
® [PRV(P,tTOP,e) ® REALE(P,tTOP,e’)]]]
That is, any subevent of e that realizes P under imperfective aspect will also
realize P under perfective aspect. The inverse, however, does not hold.
Consider again Figure 1. In the imperfective, because of t(e)≤TtTOP, there
may be marginal subevents of e the run times of which do not overlap with
tTOP (the hatched parts of e in Figure 1). Suppose such a marginal subevent
28
We are indebted to Manfred Krifka for this obsservation .
47
e’ happens to fall under P – as it must if P is homogeneously divisive. e’
would be realized under perfective aspect in this case (its run time falling
inside topic time), but not under imperfective aspect (its run time falling
outside topic time).
There is a more general way of looking at this problem, which we
introduce here since we will need it below when talking about atomic
predicates. Even if the marginal subevent e’ does not itself fall under P, it
would still be realized as part of the larger e under perfective aspect. This
idea is not too hard to formalize, since being realized as part of a larger
event is simply being a part of a larger event that is realized:
(45) "P,tTOP,e’ÍE[PREALE(P,tTOP,e’)
« $eÎUE[e’£Ee Ù REALE(P,tTOP,e)]]
(46) "P,tTOP,e,e’ÍE[e’£Ee ® [[IMPF(P,tTOP,e) Ù PREALE(P,tTOP,e’)]
® [PRV(P,tTOP,e) ® PREALE(P,tTOP,e’)]]]
(46) says that any subevent that is p-realized (i.e., ‘realized as a part’) under
imperfective aspect is also p-realized under perfective aspect. It is easy to
show that the inverse of (46) does not hold, regardless of the telicity of the
predicate. Any subevents included in the hatched parts of e in Figure 1 will
be p-realized under perfective, but not under imperfective aspect.
48
So in terms of subevent realization, perfective aspect is stronger and
more informative than imperfective aspect. In line with this, absence of
perfective marking in a context where perfective might have been marked
Q1-implicates an imperfective interpretation. More specifically, subevents
that would be entailed to be (p-)realized under perfective aspect, but not
under imperfective aspect, will be assumed to be unrealized under lack of
perfective marking, which amounts to imperfective reference to e under P
(see Levinson 2000 for further discussion of scalar implicatures).
Now let us turn to atomic atelic predicates, such as those encoded by
sneeze or eat peanuts. Consider Figure 2.
Figure 2. Realization under imperfective aspect with atomic predicates
In order for a subevent e’ of e to realize an atomic atelic P under
imperfective aspect, e’ has to be (part of) a P-atom the run time of which
falls into topic time. How do we know when this is the case? We think that
the best answer to this question might be that strictly speaking, we never do.
Because to come up with anything more than a conjecture, we would need
to know the values of both tTOP and the run times t(e’) (or at least the
49
duration) of all candidate P-atoms. But as Klein (1992) argues, it is
pragmatically strange to have definitely specified both a topic time and the
run time of an event related to the topic time by some aspect operator. And
as Mittwoch (1988) and Zucchi (1999) argue, to specify the duration of an
event is strange, at best, under imperfective aspect anyway. For these and
other reasons, it seems impossible to know whether, e.g., (47) licenses (48):
(47) Friederike was eating peanuts when a monkey snatched the bag.
(48) Friederike ate peanuts.
This, one might object, cannot be right – (47) does seem to entail (48). We
agree; but we think that the entailment goes through for a different reason.
Other than under a ‘futurate’ (or ‘prospective’) reading (which seems
impossible in (47)), the truth conditions of the progressive in (47) require
Friederike at topic time to already have started eating peanuts (although this
admittedly does not follow from the Kleinian definition of the imperfective
viewpoint in (29)). Thus, a world in which (47) is true must have recorded a
history that includes an earlier time at which an initial peanut eating
subevent was realized. But this is in more than one respect outside the scope
of our present concerns. All that matters here is that there is no way of
making sure that there is one and the same topic time with respect to which
both (47) and (48) can be truthfully asserted. In this sense, we argue, event
50
realization is indeterminate with atelic atomic predicates under imperfective
aspect.
This, however, does not affect the validity of (46) and the event
realization Horn scale. If a given subevent e’ is p-realized in the
imperfective, it is also p-realized in the perfective, while the opposite does
not necessarily hold. And since indeterminacy of realization does not mean
that DASP with atelic atomic predicates is incompatible with an
imperfective interpretation, absence of perfective marking will still trigger a
Q1-implicature to imperfective aspect, as long as an imperfective
interpretation is not blocked, as it is in the case of telic predicates
(perfective and imperfective are the only possible interpretations of DASP).
As we have argued in §3.2, all atelic predicates are either homogeneously
divisive, or atomic, or their behavior regarding realization can be viewed as
falling between that of atomic and homogeneously divisive predicates. To
summarize, if an aspectually unmarked predicate Q2-implicates event
realization, and is assigned aspectual reference accordingly, then if that
predicate is telic, it must have perfective aspectual reference. If the predicate
is homogeneously divisive, it will have event realization under both
perfective and imperfective aspect. In this case, since imperfective and
perfective aspect form a Horn scale in terms of subevent realization,
absence of perfective marking will trigger a Q1-implicature to imperfective
interpretation. And if the predicate is atelic, but has atomic subevents, then
51
realization at topic time is indeterminate, and since the predicate is still
compatible with both perfective and imperfective readings, Q1 will again
select the latter.
In the next section, we revisit the phenomena introduced in §2, to see
how aspectual reference under event realization can account for them.
3.4 EVENT REALIZATION AND THE CROSSLINGUISTIC PHENOMENA
In this section, we address the role of default-aspectual interpretations on
the basis of event realization in telicity-dependent aspectual reference as
described in §2.
Probably the simplest case of telicity-dependent aspect is that of Standard
German, a language that lacks overt aspect marking altogether. Wherever
contextually admissible, event descriptions in such a language will Q2implicate event realization. Given the dependence of realization conditions
on telicity, telic predicates come to be associated with perfective
viewpoints, while clauses encoding atelic predicates Q1-implicate
imperfective viewpoints.
The case of Inuktitut differs from that of German merely in that overtly
expressed aspect operators pick up the combinations that fall outside default
alignment, i.e., imperfective with telic predicates and perfective with atelic
predicates. The same holds for the marked imperfective aspect in –iv/-yv of
Russian prefixed telic verbs. In both Inuktitut and Russian, the existence of
52
marked contrasting forms appears to have had the effect of triggering
‘pragmatic strengthening’ of the implicated meanings associated with the
zero-marked constructions, apparently to the point of turning them into
entailments. Clauses encoding atelic predicates may have both imperfective
and perfective interpretations in Russian. This is in fact predicted by our
account – atelic predicates are compatible with realization under both
imperfective and perfective aspect! Whether and under what conditions
zero-marked clauses with atelic predicates Q1-implicate imperfectivity, as
they do in German, remains to be ascertained.
4. FURTHER IMPLICATIONS: CHILD LANGUAGE
In this section we examine evidence from first language acquisition
suggesting that event realization also plays a crucial role in the development
of temporal reference in early child language crosslinguistically.
Across a number of typologically diverse languages, children’s early
utterances show an initial bias in time-locational and aspectual reference
based on verb semantics. Specifically, children use telic predicates
predominantly or only with perfective aspect and past time reference, and
atelic predicates predominantly or only with imperfective aspect and present
time reference. An early influential study by Bronckart and Sinclair (1973)
found that young French children typically referred to events with clear
results with the passé composé, but they used the présent for events with no
53
clear result. Antinucci and Miller (1976) reported comparable findings for
Italian: children used the passato prossimo for telic event descriptions with
clear results, but they never used past marking with atelic event
descriptions. Several studies on English acquisition have shown that young
children first use -ed and irregular past forms in reference to completed
events, typically with clearly discernible result states, as in The milk spilled
and It broke, while they use progressive -ing primarily in reference to
ongoing activities, such as She is swimming (e.g., Bloom, Lifter and Hafitz
1980; Shirai and Anderson 1995; Clark 1996). Similar patterns of restricted
temporal reference in early child language have also been reported for a
number of non-Indo-European, including Inuktitut (Swift forthcoming).
In the interpretation of these findings, several researchers have invoked
Piaget’s (1969) influential view, which maintains that cognitive concepts
are prerequisites for linguistic development, and children in their early
stages of development are ‘egocentric’, live in the ‘here-and-now’, and do
not refer to events outside of their immediate experiential environment until
they have the ability to ‘decenter’, i.e., abstract away from their own
experience. For example, Antinucci and Miller explain children’s restricted
distribution of verb forms with the idea that observable results provide a
“concrete link” between a past event and a current state from which a young
child could construct a representation of the past event, and the lack of such
results explains the absence of past forms with atelic event descriptions.
54
Alternatively, Slobin (1985) has argued that children have semantic
predispositions for two basic temporal categories: process (ongoing,
dynamic) and result (punctual, completed).
We propose a different yet compatible explanation for young children’s
restricted distributions of verb forms, based on the dependence of realization
conditions on telicity in combination with Piaget’s early developmental
restriction to the “here-and-now”. On our analysis, children’s initial
utterances show a preference for aspectual reference under event realization.
Atelic event predicates are compatible with realization under both
imperfective and perfective aspect, imperfective aspect and present time
reference is preferred since it requires no shift away from the “here-andnow” of coding time, as perfective aspect normally does. Since perfective
aspect is required for the realization of telic predicates, however, past time
reference may be licensed by result states that link past events to coding
time, as suggested by Antinucci and Miller (1976).29
Children use whatever forms are appropriate in the language they are
acquiring to talk about realized events. In English, these are the simple past
form for perfective aspect and the -ing form for imperfective aspect. In
29
On our account, future time reference is excluded both by the constraint to event realization and
the one against disalignment between topic time and coding time. This is, however, not to say that
children do not express needs, fears, and desires – but these are conceptualized and encoded as
55
Inuktitut, however, event realization plays a special role. As shown in §2, a
single zero-marked verb form is used to express both imperfective aspect
with atelic predicates and perfective aspect with telic predicates. So while it
may be argued that children acquiring English actually interpret the -ing
form as an imperfective marker and the -ed form as a perfective marker, the
structure of Inuktitut offers no basis for such an analysis. However, the
Inuktitut acquisition data show that children come to terms with this
temporal variation within a single construction at an early age. Our analysis
gives a uniform meaning to the Inuktitut zero-marked form, namely
reference to realized events, and on our account, that is exactly what
children acquiring Inuktitut take it to be. More generally, if young children
in early stages of development only talk about their experienced reality, then
they only talk about realized events. On this analysis, children’s early time
reference is not governed by a dichotomy between processes and results, but
by the single category of event realization.
5. CONCLUSION
We have argued that the property of event realization – the “eventish”
equivalent of the existence of individuals – plays a powerful role in natural
language semantics. Event realization mediates the interactions between
experiential states that hold at coding time.
56
aspectual viewpoints and telicity known as the Imperfective Paradox. On the
basis of these interactions, Gricean generalized conversational implicatures
assign telicity-dependent viewpoints to clauses and verbal projections not
overtly marked for aspect in languages with aspect systems as diverse as
those of German, Inuktitut, and Russian. Moreover, we suggest that event
realization constrains aspectual reference in early child language such that
reference to realized events developmentally precedes reference to
unrealized events, indicating a strong cognitive basis for event realization as
manifest in language use from an early age.30
REFERENCES
Antinucci, F. and R. Miller: 1976, ‘How Children Talk about What
Happened’, Journal of Child Language 3, 167-189.
Bach, E.: 1986, ‘The Algebra of Events’, Linguistics and Philosophy 9, 516.
Ballweg, J.: 1981, ‘Simple Present Tense and Progressive Periphrases in
German’, in H.-J. Eikmeyer and H. Rieser (eds.), Words, Worlds and
Contexts: New Approaches in Word Semantics, pp. 222-233, de Gruyter,
Berlin.
30
We thank Wolfgang Klein, Manfred Krifka, and two anonymous reviewers for insightful
comments that have improved the paper. We also benefited from discussions at the conference
Perspectives on Aspect at the Utrecht Institute of Linguistics in December 2001, where we
presented an early version of the paper.
57
Bennett, M. and B. Partee: 1978, Toward the Logic of Tense and Aspect in
English, Indiana University Linguistics Club, Bloomington, IN.
Bloom, L., K. Lifter and J. Hafitz: 1980, ‘Semantics of Verbs and the
Development of Verb Inflection in Child Language’, Language 56, 386412.
Bohnemeyer, J.: 1998, Time Relations in Discourse, PhD dissertation,
University of Tilburg, The Netherlands.
Bohnemeyer, J.: 2002, The Grammar of Time Reference in Yukatek Maya,
Lincom, Munich.
Bohnemeyer, J.: in press, ‘Split Intransitivity, Linking, and Lexical
Representation: The Case of Yukatek Maya’, Linguistics 42.
Boogaart, R. J. U.: 1999, Aspect and Temporal Ordering, Holland
Academic Graphics, The Hague.
Bronckart, J. P. and H. Sinclair: 1973, ‘Time, Tense, and Aspect’, Cognition
2, 107-130.
Clark, E. V.: 1996, ‘Early verbs, event types, and inflections’, in J. H. V.
Gilbert and C. E. Johnson (eds.), Children’s language Vol. 9, pp. 61-73,
Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Comrie, B.: 1976, Aspect, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Davidson, D.: 1967, ‘The Logical Form of Action Sentences’, in N. Rescher
(ed.), The Logic of Decision and Action, pp. 81-95, Pittsburgh University
Press, Pittsburgh.
58
Delisle, H. H.: 1986, ‘Am / Beim Progressive Constructions in German’, in
M. C. Marino and L. A. Perez (eds.), The Twelfth LACUS Forum 1985,
Lacus, Lake Bluff, IL, pp. 215-224.
Depraetere, I.: 1995, ‘On The Necessity of Distinguishing between
(Un)Boundedness and (A)Telicity’, Linguistics and Philosophy 18, 1-19.
Dowty, D. R.: 1979, Word Meaning and Montague Grammar, Reidel,
Dordrecht.
Dowty, D. R.: 1986, ‘Aspectual Class and Discourse’, Linguistics and
Philosophy 9, 37-61.
Ehrich, V.: 1992, Hier und Jetzt. Studien zur Lokalen und Temporalen
Deixis im Deutschen, Niemeyer, Tübingen.
Eisenberg, P.: 1986, Grundriss der Deutschen Grammatik, Metzler,
Stuttgart.
Engel, U.: 1988, Deutsche Grammatik, Julius Groos, Heidelberg.
Filip, H.: 1999, Aspect, Eventuality Types, and Noun Phrase Semantics,
Garland, NY.
Garey, H. B.: 1957, ‘Verbal Aspect in French’, Language 33, 91-110.
Grice, H. P.: 1975, ‘Logic and Conversation’ , in P. Cole and J. L. Morgan
(eds.), Speech Acts, pp. 41-58, Academic Press, NY.
Hinrichs, E.: 1986, ‘Temporal Anaphora in Discourses of English’,
Linguistics and Philosophy 9, 63-82.
59
Hopper, P. J. and E. C. Traugott: 1993, Grammaticalization, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Horn, L. R.: 1977, On the Semantic Properties of Logical Operators in
English, PhD dissertation, UCLA, Los Angeles, CA.
Isačenko, A. V.: 1975, Die Russische Sprache der Gegenwart. Teil I:
Formenlehre [The Contemporary Russian Language. Part I:
Morphology], Hueber, Munich.
Kamp, H. and U. Reyle: 1993, From Discourse to Logic, Kluwer,
Dordrecht.
Kamp, H. and C. Rohrer: 1983, ‘Tense in Texts’, in R. Bäuerle, C.
Schwartze and A. von Stechow (eds.), Meaning, Use, and Interpretation
of Language, pp. 250-269, de Gruyter, Berlin.
Kenny, A.: 1963, Action, Emotion, and Will, Routledge, London.
Klein, W.: 1992, ‘The Present Perfect Puzzle’, Language 68, 525-552.
Klein, W.: 1994, Time in Language, Routledge, London.
Klein, W.: 1995, ‘A Time-Relational Analysis of Russian Aspect’,
Language 71, 669-695.
Krifka, M.: 1989, ‘Nominal Reference, Temporal Constitution and
Quantification in Event Semantics’, in R. Bartsch, J. van Benthem and P.
van Emde Boas (eds.), Semantics and Contextual Expressions, pp. 75115, Foris, Dordrecht.
60
Krifka, M.: 1992, ‘Thematic Relations as Links between Nominal Reference
and Temporal Constitution’, in I. A. Sag and A. Szabolcsi (eds.), Lexical
Matters, pp. 29-54, CSLI/SRI International, Menlo Park, CA.
Krifka, M.: 1998, ‘The Origins of Telicity’, in S. Rothstein (ed.), Events and
Grammar, pp.197-235, Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Landman, F.: 1992, ‘The Progressive’, Natural Language Semantics 1, 132.
Leiss, E.: 1992, Die Verbalkategorien des Deutschen, Berlin: de Gruyter.
Levinson, S. C.: 2000, Presumptive Meanings, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Mittwoch, A.: 1988, ‘Aspects of English Aspect: On the Interaction of
Perfect, Progressive and Durational Phrases’, Linguistics and Philosophy
11, 203-254.
Moens, M.: 1987, Tense, Aspect and Temporal Reference, PhD dissertation,
University of Edinburgh.
Parsons, T.: 1990, Events in the Semantics of English, The MIT Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Pederson, E.: forthcoming, ‘Event Realization in Tamil’, in M. Bowerman
and P. Brown (eds.), Crosslinguistic Perspectives on Argument
Structure: Implications for Learnability, Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah,
NJ.
Piaget, J.: 1969, The Child’s Conception of Time, Routledge, London.
Reichenbach, H.: 1947, Elements of Symbolic Logic, Macmillan, London.
61
Shirai, Y. and R. W. Andersen: 1995, ‘The Acquisition of Tense-Aspect
Morphology: A Prototype Account’, Language 71, 743-762.
Slobin, D. I.: 1985, ‘Crosslinguistic Evidence for the Language-making
Capacity’, in D. I. Slobin (ed.), The Crosslinguistic Study of Language
Acquisition Vol. 2, pp. 111-220, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Smith, C. S.: 1991, The Parameter of Aspect, Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Swift, M. D.: forthcoming, Time in Child Inuktitut: A Developmental Study
of an Eskimo-Aleut Language, Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin.
Talmy, L.: 1991, ‘Path to Realization – via Aspect and Result’, Proceedings
of the Seventeenth Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society,
Berkeley Linguistics Society, Berkeley, pp. 480-519.
Taylor, B.: 1977, ‘Tense and Continuity’, Linguistics and Philosophy 1,
199-220.
ter Meulen, A. G. B.: 1995, Representing Time in Natural Language, MIT
Press, Cambridge, MA.
Vendler, Z.: 1957, ‘Verbs and Times’, The Philosophical Review
LXVI,143-160.
Verkuyl, H. J.: 1972, On the Compositional Nature of the Aspects, Reidel,
Dordrecht.
Verkuyl, H. J.: 1993, A Theory of Aspectuality: The Interaction between
Temporal and Atemporal Structure, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
62
von Stechow, A.: 2001, ‘Temporally Opaque Arguments in Verbs of
Creation’, in B. Cecchetto, G. Chierchia, and M. T. Guasti (eds.),
Semantic Interfaces, pp. 278-319, CSLI, Stanford.
von Wright, G. H.: 1963, Norm and Action, reprint 1971, Routledge,
London.
Zucchi, S.: 1999, ‘Incomplete Events, Intensionality and Imperfective
Aspect’, Natural Language Semantics 7,179-215.