When revolutions fail, the dreams behind them live on.
His fight for radical change may have died, but his dream of a better world never did.
This book is dedicated to my father, Willem De Roover,
For passing the dream on to us, so that we may do our bit to bring it closer to realization.
2
Acknowledgements
The past ten years have been a lively period. There were beautiful and difficult, peaceful and turbulent
times, but never a dull moment. During these years, new research groups in Europe and India came
into being, under the guidance of S.N. Balagangadhara (Balu). It has been a privilege and an honour to
be witness to—and, hopefully, sometimes part of—the growth of his research programme.
Learning from a real teacher is not easy; at least, it has not always been easy for me. But what
appears to be a struggle with the teacher is really a struggle of the student with his own ignorance. It
often seems difficult to let go of the delusions about ourselves that we embrace so happily, even though
they are the cause of our unhappiness. I feel a deep gratitude towards Balu for his guidance, generosity,
patience, and thoughtfulness as a teacher, and (perhaps most of all) for his command of the art of being
angry ‘with the right person and to the right degree and at the right time and for the right purpose, and
in the right way’.
It is impossible to describe all the ways in which the members of our core group in Ghent have
helped, guided, and supported me over the years. Without Sarika, Nele, Marianne, and Sarah, this
would not only have been a lonely journey but I would also be nowhere today. More than companions
alone, they are stars that brighten the darkest of nights.
It has been a joy to travel along the roads of our research programme with so many comrades
in India, Europe, and the US: Anil, Anne, Arun, Ashok, Ashwin, Ashwini, Chaitra, Divya, Dunkin,
Emanuel, GSR, Jolien, Kannan, Kavita, Martin, Polly, Prakash, Praveen, Rajaram, Ramananda,
Sadananda, Sandeep, Santhosh, Satya, Shankarappa, Shanmukha, Sufiya, Venkat, Vivek, vnr, Willem,
and many others. At different times and in different ways, the generosity of friends, family members,
and colleagues in giving me their time, thoughts, and support proved invaluable. I owe much to all of
you and look forward to the future that all of us will build together.
Finally, I would also like to thank the publishers of the journals and edited volumes where
earlier drafts of sections of this book appeared, for their permission to include this material here. Earlier
3
drafts of sections of chapters 1, 4, 5, and 6 appeared in the following journal articles and book chapters:
Sage Publications for ‘John Locke, Christian Liberty, and the Predicament of Liberal Toleration’, Political
Theory, 36(4); Imprint Academic for ‘Liberty, Tyranny, and the Will of God: The Principle of Toleration
in Early Modern Europe and Colonial India’, History of Political Thought, 30(1); Routledge for ‘The Dark
Hour of Secularism: Colonial Liberalism and Hindu Fundamentalism in India’, in Ranjan Ghosh (ed.),
Making Sense of the Secular: Critical Perspectives from Europe to Asia (New York: Routledge, 2013) (all three
essays co-authored with S.N. Balagangadhara); and Stanford University Press for ‘Secular Law and the
Realm of False Religion’, in Winnifred Fallers Sullivan, Robert A. Yelle and Mateo Taussig-Rubbo
(eds.), After Secular Law (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2011).
4
Introduction
The Crisis of Secularism
One need not be a prophet of doom to suggest that our coping with the cultural and religious diversity
of humanity has seen little progress during the last century. From Iraq to Israel, India to the Balkan,
Nigeria to Northern Ireland, Pakistan to Sudan, the list of plural societies disrupted by violent conflict
between their different religious and ethnic communities is long. Yet, in this same period, some parts
of the world were witness to the growing dominance and success of a particular way of solving the
problems of diversity: the liberal model of religious toleration and the secular state.
Even though this model took various forms in the nation-states that implemented it and among
the political thinkers who elaborated it, these share a number of formal properties. The liberal model
of secularism and toleration consists of a set of norms as to how a diverse society and its state ought to
be organized. On one hand, it claims that the state should be secular or religiously neutral. The state’s
policies and legal system cannot be based on any religious doctrine. Generally, religious authorities
should stay away from political authority and vice versa. Under this model, the state is prohibited from
endorsing the truth of any religion and from using its powers to enforce adherence to some religion.
On the other hand, the liberal model insists that the right to religious freedom should be granted to all
citizens. Each citizen ought to be free to believe and worship as he or she pleases, and all should respect
this freedom and tolerate each other’s forms of religious belief or unbelief. In this way, the model
divides plural societies into two spheres: a political or public sphere, where citizens are subject to the
laws and coercive power of the secular state, and another sphere, where they ought to be free to live
according to their religious values or conceptions of the good life.
The liberal model met with considerable success in the nation-states of Western Europe and
North America. After centuries of devastating wars of religion, these states enjoyed more than two
hundred years of relative peace among the religious groups in their societies. Systematic persecution
5
and discrimination of groups considered ‘heretic’ or ‘heathen’ gave way to toleration, religious freedom,
and the granting of equal rights to all citizens. We should never underestimate this achievement.
In early modern Europe, human beings were burned, pilloried, mutilated, and denied access to
all kinds of benefits for holding the wrong beliefs. As recently as 1826, a schoolmaster in Spain could
still be executed for heresy because of his deist views.1 Later in the same century, Protestant ‘nativists’
in the United States clashed with Catholics in violent riots and demanded exclusion of the latter from
political office.2 In 1886, a grand jury saw fit to have an American citizen sentenced on charges of
blasphemy.3 Liberal toleration may not have ended all forms of religious intolerance in the Western
world, but it certainly provided a powerful instrument to prevent these from shaping state policies and
laws.
A Model in Crisis
Today, the liberal model is under increasing pressure. Journalists and academics often blame this ‘crisis
of secularism’ on the re-emergence of ‘political religion’ across the world: Hindu nationalism in India;
political Islam in Turkey, the Middle East, and Northern Africa; Zionism in Israel; Protestant
evangelicals in the US. The separation of politics and religion, they suggest, is being challenged by
retrograde forces that once again seek their unity.4 This account attributes the growing pressures on
the liberal model to external factors that negate the norms of secularism. In doing so, it covers up major
flaws internal to this model, which have come to the surface in recent decades.
First, liberal secularism did not deliver the goods it had promised when it was implemented in
non-western societies. Take the case of India. From the declaration of Independence in 1947, the
1
Haliczer (1990), p. 357.
2
Jenkins (2003), pp. 27-8.
3
Sehat (2011), p. 1.
4
Bhargava (2010), pp. 81-2; Hibbard (2010); Juergensmeyer (2008); Lilla (2008); Needham and Sunder Rajan
(2007).
6
country’s first Prime Minister Jawaharlal Nehru made secularism part of the state credo; in 1976, the
declaration that India is a ‘secular’ republic was added to the Preamble to the Constitution. But here
the attempt to map the state onto the model of liberal secularism resulted in a rise rather than decline
in conflict between Hindus and Muslims. Systematic violence between different communities has
grown in frequency and intensity over the last six decades.5 Some argue that the elitist imposition of
secularism on Indian society lies at the root of the rising intolerance.6 Others suggest that the situation
should be blamed on the failure of Indian politicians to be truly secular and impartial.7 Wherever the
truth lies, the fact of the matter remains that the liberal model has failed to reproduce its European
successes in India.
In countries like India, some intellectuals now reject liberal secularism as a typically Western
invention that cannot be exported to other cultures. This does not mean they reject the model merely
because of its Western origins. Most of these intellectuals would not exclude basic physics, chemistry,
or biology from their countries’ educational curricula, even though these theories also hail from the
West. The problem, they suggest, is that liberal secularism is so intertwined with a Western cultural
context that it is bound to fail outside this context. For these thinkers, the liberal model lost much of
its shine because of its failure to offer a viable framework for peaceful co-existence in plural societies
outside the West.8
Second, in Europe also, the modus vivendi that crystallized within the outlines of the liberal
model is beginning to show cracks. In the second half of the twentieth century, new migrant
communities carried with them religious beliefs and practices that had earlier not been present in
modern Europe on any large scale, especially various forms of Islam. The attempt to accommodate
5
Brass (2003), pp. 6-9, 60-70; Chandra et al. (2000), pp. 434-5; Nandy et al. (1998).
6
Madan (1987), pp. 747-59; Nandy (1985), pp. 14-24.
7
Brass (1999), pp. 370-1, 375; Chandra et al. (2000), pp. 438-9; Chatterji (1995), p. ix; Tambiah (1998), p. 427.
8
See, for instance, Madan (1987); Nandy (1985), (1998b).
7
these groups within liberal secular states uncovered some limitations. In the name of secularism,
certain practices of Muslim groups, such as the wearing of headscarves, were banned from the public
sphere. Such policies had the effect of radicalizing some Muslims and creating antagonism towards the
government and the majority population of the European nation-states where they lived. They began
to advocate a strict religious identity that included such controversial practices.
Many European intellectuals blame this on the nature of Islam and the fact that it does not
allow for the separation of religion from politics. It is said that the Islamic world should go through its
own Enlightenment in order to learn the art of separation.9 Thus, the problem is again reduced to an
external threat to the liberal model: because of their illiberal religious convictions, certain Muslim
groups are not ready to accept the norms of secularism and toleration; therefore, they cannot currently
be integrated into this model. Hence, so the reasoning goes, we need a democratic Islam adapted to
liberal secular values.10
This explanation misses crucial dimensions of the growing diversity in European societies.
Other groups face similar problems: to protect the neutrality of the public sphere, governments have
disputed the right of Sikhs to wear turbans in schools, public office, and other settings. The liberal
model has also compelled such communities to take a particular form. In order to be recognized as
proper religious communities by Western democracies, groups need to identify their ‘religious beliefs’
and appoint ‘religious authorities’ that speak for the entire community, even where they lack such
structures. The traditions of these groups are not opposed to liberal secularism in any obvious sense.
Yet, the liberal model faces great difficulty in accommodating such communities new to the modus
vivendi that originally emerged in modern Europe.
9
See, for instance, Massie (2012).
10
See the discussion in Buruma (2010).
8
Third, recent analyses show that the liberal model is plagued by conceptual problems. Its norms
prescribe a particular relationship between the state and religion: the state ought to be neutral with
respect to religion; citizens ought to be free to practice their religion; religion should not intrude into the
public sphere. But what counts as religion? How do we distinguish the religious from the secular?
Secular states and courts of law across the world have had great difficulty in determining the scope of
religion. Still, they are compelled to take up this task in several types of cases: not only when groups
claim exemption from specific laws or some special status in the name of religion, but also when civil
authorities desire to ban certain symbols or modes of dress as religious intrusions into the neutral
public sphere. 11
Liberal states and courts are expected to be neutral towards all religions in their judgment as
to what counts as religion. Yet, when they ban certain practices from the public sphere because these
are ‘religious’, or determine that some practices are not ‘religious’ and do not fall under the scope of
religious freedom, the failure to be religiously neutral appears inevitable. No state or court possesses
an impartial scientific conception of religion; there are no shared secular criteria that enable one to
identify and delimit the sphere of religion in a manner neutral to all religions. Consequently, judges
and other secular authorities are bound to smuggle in some metaphysical or theological conception of
religion.12 That is, a specific religious language becomes the meta-language to discuss and decide on
matters of religion in courts of law and serves as the standard to reject certain practices as not ‘truly’
religious. This calls into question the very claim to religious neutrality and secularity at the heart of
the liberal model.
11
This matter will be discussed in detail in chapter 1. For illustrations of the problem, see Greenawalt (2006), pp.
124-56; Jensen (2011), pp. 341-64; Sullivan (2007).
12
On this practice of smuggling metaphysical positions into ‘neutral’ secular discourse, see Smith (2010), pp. 26-
38.
9
The coming chapters will closely examine these difficulties. At this point, just note that the
liberal model of secularism and religious toleration has lost much of the self-evident value it once had.
Yet, the problems it was designed to solve remain as acute as ever: states around the world continue
to confront tension and conflict between communities. How should we respond to the increasing
failure of the liberal model to produce peacefully diverse societies? The situation compels us to start
looking for alternatives elsewhere. Perhaps the flaws of the liberal model can be remedied. Even then,
the growing complexity of plural societies across the world calls for the exploration of potential
alternatives to this model.
The Asymmetry of Cultures
So far political theory has presented the models crafted in the modern West as the best options for all
other societies. There is a strong belief that all civilized countries ought to be liberal secular
democracies abiding by norms of neutrality, toleration, religious freedom, and the separation of politics
and religion. But it has become less credible today than before that the political models that happened
to emerge in early modern Europe are the norm for all human societies. This stance could survive in a
world of Western hegemony but is bound to crumble in our current ‘multipolar’ world.
In the early twenty-first century, our globe has seen fundamental shifts in its political and
economic power configurations. The fact that it has become trite to declare that the hegemony of
Western culture is coming to an end indicates the impact of these global shifts. The rise of Asian
countries like India and China to world power is significant here. For the first time in more than four
centuries, political leaders and thinkers from these cultures will play a central role in giving shape to
global debates. The rise of Asia is likely to affect our political thinking, particularly that about the
problems of diversity.13
13
For an eye-opening account of these developments from an Asian perspective, see Mahbubani (2008).
10
In the twenty-first century, different cultures will meet as genuine alternatives for the first
time—as forms of life that offer alternatives to each other.14 This does not entail some ‘clash of
civilizations’ where cultures will compete as rivals and one will emerge as victor. Rather, the current
situation can be viewed in simplified terms: each form of life with some stability over time has
approached and solved the problems of human existence in certain ways. Let us pitch our description
of these problems at a high level of abstraction. In order to survive and flourish, human groups had to
solve problems like political organization, creating an environment fit for human habitation, coping
with human diversity and human suffering … . Different cultures conceived of such problems
differently and also developed different solutions. When such cultural forms of life meet, their
approaches to the problems of human flourishing face each other as alternatives.
This opens up the possibility of choosing between such alternatives. Human groups will not
be able to adopt cultures as wholes. Cultures are not like shirts that can be changed at will. However,
we can imagine some society appropriating the solution that another has developed for certain
problems of human flourishing. In fact, the last three centuries provide instances of this process. Many
societies adopted the scientific theories, technological inventions, and political models originating in
the modern West. The fact that this process happened one-sidedly should not prevent us from
appreciating how it occurred: to some extent, through imposition by colonial states, but, where
successful, it happened largely through imitation and experimentation.
It is likely that the twenty-first century will see such practical imitation and experimentation
between cultures on a large scale. But the fact that we are still far away from this point calls for realism
and reflection on the obstacles before us. On one hand, this process needs to be guided by theoretical
reflection: intellectuals should reflect on the obstacles and differences between the forms of life that
14
Balagangadhara, (2012), p. 72.
11
face each other as alternatives. Importantly, they will have to devise reasonable criteria for finding out
which particular solutions to some specific problem of human flourishing are better than others.
On the other hand, the major obstacle is that the playing field is skewed. That is, cultural forms
of life are not meeting as alternatives in the contemporary world. In the words of S.N. Balagangadhara,
a peculiar asymmetry structures the encounter between cultures. At a macro-level, the Western form of
life is viewed as an alternative to all non-western forms of life, while the latter are rarely seen as
alternatives to the former. This is peculiar because the relationship of ‘being an alternative to’ always
presupposes symmetry: if coffee is an alternative to tea, then tea is an alternative to coffee. Under
today’s asymmetry, however, it is perfectly reasonable to suggest that India should follow modern
Western culture but it seems absurd to argue that Europe should emulate Indian culture.15 Considering
the currently dominant images of India, this would be like saying that Europe should implement the
caste system, untouchability, dowry, arranged marriages, and political corruption—perhaps with a
sprinkling of spirituality on the side.
Part of the problem is that the currently dominant descriptions of Asian cultures are those
developed in Europe over the last three or four centuries. Since Edward Said’s Orientalism (1978), we
have reason to suspect that this body of descriptions is problematic: Western conceptions of Asian
cultures tend to transform the latter into deficient variants of Western culture.16 Balagangadhara
characterizes this problem as follows: this body of descriptions reflects the Western cultural experience
of other cultures. That is, the descriptions describe how one particular form of life has experienced other forms
of life.
15
ibid., pp. 72-3.
16
Said (1978). For an overview of the debate concerning Orientalism, see Macfie (2000). For important criticism
of Said’s work, see Irwin (2007).
12
Now, the experience that one culture has of another does not correspond to an objective factual
description. Like any experience, it is structured by a background of prior attitudes and patterns of
action and thought. As a body of descriptions, Orientalism describes such a structured cultural experience
and not just the empirical realities of Asia. It is the product of a systematic attempt of European minds
to make sense of their experiences of Asian cultures. Significantly, this reflection takes the form of
apparent descriptions of other cultures. Yet these orientalist descriptions are shaped through and
through by cognitive constraints and a conceptual apparatus characteristic of the Western form of life.17
Consequently, a cultural asymmetry lies at the heart of this body of descriptions. These
conceptualize alternative forms of life from within a dominant cultural framework that reflects the
reference points of one particular form of life. How can we surmount this obstacle and restore
symmetry between cultures, when all we have to go by are the descriptions produced by one form of
life, namely, modern Western culture?
To appreciate the significance of this question, let us turn back to the theme of this study,
namely, the limits of liberal secularism and its solutions to religious diversity. In the twenty-first
century, a major task of political theorists will be to examine how Asian cultures offer potential
resources for alternative solutions to such problems. The problem of diversity is particularly promising
as a case in point. For centuries, Asian societies accommodated a diversity of religious, ethnic, and
cultural groups much greater than that of Europe at any point during its history.
In India, a variety of Hindu, Buddhist, Jain, and Sikh traditions have lived side by side with
Zoroastrian Parsis and different kinds of Jews, Christians, and Muslims for more than a millennium.
Over the years, there were occasional conflicts between groups, more systematic clashes at times, and
even decades of repression of certain traditions. Nevertheless, it is worth noting the following minimal
fact: Indian society never disintegrated in spite of this diversity. Therefore, it must have known successful
17
Balagangadhara (2012), pp. 34-60.
13
practices, heuristics, and mechanisms of co-existence between these groups. We need not romanticize
this as pristine harmony but there is certainly a need to investigate these forms of co-existence and
find out how they work. Once we gain insight into these forms of co-existence, these can then serve as
conceptual resources for developing a new political theory of pluralism, which explicitly presents itself
as an alternative to the liberal model.
Ideally, this is how a comparative political theory would go about its task, were it not for the
obstacle of cultural asymmetry.18 In this context, this obstacle takes a particular form. The liberal model
is part of a larger normative framework. It is intertwined with other values like equality, freedom, and
human dignity, and also with clusters of commonplace ideas about the nature of the human self and
society. This framework crystallized in early modern Europe from the sixteenth century onwards. In
this same period, European travellers and orientalists began to systematically describe the societies
and cultures of Asia. Through a process of selection and theorizing, a fairly coherent set of dominant
descriptions of Indian culture came into being in Western Europe. All of this happened within the
confines of a particular descriptive framework and its theoretical terms.
That is to say, European descriptions of India as the land of ‘Hindu religion’ and ‘the caste
system’ did not come into being independently of the development of the liberal secular framework.
The concepts of ‘religion’, ‘freedom’, ‘equality’, ‘tyranny’… informing modern Western conceptions of
Indian religion and the caste system were embedded in this emerging framework. Over the last two
centuries, the resulting descriptions have gained dominance and they continue to shape the study of
India.19
If this is the case, the difficulty must be obvious: when trying to study Indian culture and its
traditions of co-existence as potential alternatives to the liberal model, the descriptions one starts out
18
On the idea of a comparative political theory, see Parel (1992); Dallmayr (2004); March (2009); Thomas (2010).
19
See: Bloch et al. (2010); Dirks (2001); Inden (1990); King (1999).
14
with inevitably prevent one from succeeding. The inevitability is caused by the fact that the available
descriptions presuppose the liberal secular framework and frame Indian culture in terms of its concepts
and values. In other words, the outer cognitive limits of the dominant political theorizing concerning
toleration and secularism overlap with those of our ‘knowledge’ about India. Consequently, our current
knowledge of India cannot possibly offer the conceptual resources necessary to build an alternative to
the liberal model. The playing field where cultures meet as alternative forms of life is fundamentally
skewed.
A Different Route
Should we therefore simply ignore the liberal secular model while looking for alternatives? Such a
radical step would be unwise and its success improbable. On one hand, whatever may be its flaws, the
liberal model is a product of centuries of human experience and reasonable reflection. Rejecting it out
of hand would be folly, for this would mean losing access to a rich tradition of reasoning that shaped
many of our implicit and explicit ideas about the question of toleration. We would also lose the
potential benefits of this model such as its more successful policies of impartiality and intellectual
freedom.
On the other hand, discarding the liberal model is impossible, because its normative framework
has structured the available descriptions of Asian cultures. We would not be able to access alternative
forms of co-existence in these cultures without falling back into the very framework we intend to leave
behind. Moreover, if we ignore the liberal model, what would the alternatives be alternatives to? We
could not begin to demonstrate how such forms of co-existence have anything valuable to offer that is
not already present in liberal secularism.
The route explored in this book is different. It shall take the constraints of the liberal model of
religious toleration and the secular state as the focal point of its inquiry. The liberal secular framework
of the modern West is subject to culture-specific cognitive limits that have also structured Western
descriptions of Asian cultures. To be able to discover potential alternatives to the liberal model in Asia,
15
we simultaneously need to develop alternative descriptions of such cultural forms of co-existence. The
reason should be clear: we can only move beyond the cognitive limits of one by also going beyond those
of the other. But before we can do so, we need to have clarity on the nature and causes of these limits.
Therefore, this book shall examine how the normative model of liberal secularism crystallized
in modern Europe and how it determined the European understanding of another culture, namely,
India. Its focus will be on taking this first step: identifying the cultural constraints common to the
liberal secular model and the Western understanding of India.
The different chapters will not have much to say about what an alternative model of pluralism
and tolerance should look like. To take this next step, certain preconditions would have to be met: a
different kind of research concerning Indian culture, society, and politics is needed, which is still in its
infancy today. Currently, an international research group guided by Balagangadhara is in the process of
developing the required type of hypotheses and descriptions. Within the confines of this book, I can
only offer a promissory note by saying that these research results will be made available over the coming
years.
The reader will find an outline of the book at the end of the second chapter, after the theoretical
framework guiding this study has been explained. Therefore, I have chosen not to summarize its seven
chapters here. Before arriving at this outline, however, chapter one reveals a fundamental problem at
the heart of the liberal model of secularism and religious toleration and shows the practical implications
of this problem in contemporary Europe and India. This problem points to some of the cultural limits
of liberal secularism that will form the focus of this study. Next, chapter two reviews the different
theoretical frameworks available for writing the story of liberal secularism and its cultural limits before
it turns to sketching the research programme of which this book aims to be a part.
16
Chapter 1
Limits of Liberal Secularism
Mysticism, when transposed from the warm twilight of myth and fiction to the cold searchlight
of fact and reason, has usually little left to recommend itself. Its language, unless resounding
within its own magic and mystic circle, will often appear poor and even slightly foolish ...
Political mysticism in particular is exposed to the danger of losing its spell or becoming quite
meaningless when taken out of its native surroundings, its time and its space.20
With these words Ernst Kantorowicz opened his celebrated study of medieval political theology.
Written more than five centuries after the fact, they make one wonder how future generations will
look back on the political mysticisms of our time. Much like the theory that attributed two bodies to
the king, liberal secularism may face the danger of losing its spell or becoming quite meaningless when
taken out of its native surroundings, its time, and its space. Fortunately, in the twenty-first century,
we do not have to wait another half millennium to find out if this is the case. Today’s meeting of
cultures compels us to examine how this political model fares outside its own circle well before future
historians take up this task.
Is there any such thing as a liberal model of secularism? Modern nation-states are home to
different arrangements between the state and religion. France’s laïcité guarantees freedom of religious
belief and exercise, but it also involves militant banning of religion from the public sphere. In the
United States, the first constitutional amendment bars establishment of any state religion and protects
free exercise so as to prevent the state from interfering in religion. In contrast, the Church of England
remains officially established in the United Kingdom. The monarch is the head of the state and the
church, while some bishops hold reserved seats in Parliament as Lords Spiritual. In India, state
20
Kantorowicz (1997), p. 3.
17
secularism has involved far-reaching intervention in certain traditions, such as state management of
temples and the reform of Hindu law.
From a postmodern perspective, there are multiple ‘secularisms’ rather than one standard
form.21 Yet, from the variety alone, one cannot draw the conclusion that there is no such thing as
liberal secularism.22 These are variations on a model defined by a common set of norms and concepts
such as the distinction between politics and religion. This model prescribes a particular relationship
between the state and religion: the principle of separation says that the authority of each ought to
remain confined to its own realm; that of equality demands that followers of all religions be treated
equally; that of freedom states that citizens should be free to profess and practice their religion.
Critics may object that some ‘secularisms’ do not share these properties: in the UK, the state
lacks neutrality because of its ties to the church; French laïcité is so anti-religious that it violates the
principles of religious freedom; the Indian state regularly intervenes in religious affairs. Such criticism
plays on another crucial property of the liberal model: its normativity. Because it is normative, it relates
to factual instances in a peculiar way. For any nation-state that counts as an instance of liberal
secularism, one can always note that it is not really secular because it violates some of the relevant
norms.
Many differences among secular states in Europe and elsewhere have their roots in the
interplay between two distinct tendencies. The first emerges from the concern to ban all expressions
of religion from the public sphere, politics, and education. This goes together with a general suspicion
towards the different forms of ‘organized religion’: all of these are considered as potential threats to
21
See the introduction and several essays in Cady and Shakman Hurd (2010) and Jakobsen and Pellegrini (2008).
Also see Asad (2003), pp. 5-6; Burchardt et al. (2013); Khilnani (2007), p. 43; Tejani (2008), pp. 4-6.
22
In fact, as Rainer Forst argues with regard to the concept of toleration, speaking about different conceptions or
varieties of secularism presupposes a shared core meaning of the term ‘secularism’ and this core is the concept of
secularism. See Forst (2013), p. 17.
18
the public order. The second tendency is inspired by the conviction that the state should never interfere
in religion unless public order is at stake. The state should then allow all religious communities in
society to live by their own values and beliefs. In the Anglo-Saxon world the second tendency is
dominant, while the first tendency has shaped French laïcité.
Yet, fundamental to all such manifestations of the secular state are certain conceptual
problems. This chapter will uncover one such problem and trace its implications in various contexts.
The first section characterizes the puzzle of the two spheres: how can we distinguish between the
public political sphere and the private sphere of religion? This puzzle takes different forms in the
Western world, all of which jeopardize the clarity and coherence of the liberal model. The second
section travels to India and examines the forms taken by the puzzle in this part of the world. The
distinction between the religious and the secular turns out to be even more problematic here.
1.1. The Puzzle of the Two Spheres
Liberal political theory may not attribute two bodies to the head of state but it does postulate the
existence of two spheres in social life. It suggests that societies are divided into a public political
sphere, governed by the state, and another sphere, where we ought to be free to live according to our
own religious beliefs and values. The sphere of state coercion should be secular. And as long as the
rule of law is respected, the liberal state should refrain from interfering in the realm of religion and
tolerate all religions.23
Recently, state neutrality has replaced individual autonomy as the essential liberal value.24
This shift resulted from the late twentieth-century liberal-communitarian debate. Liberalism demands
that citizens confine their substantive conceptions of the good to their private lives, whereas the
political community is governed in terms of a formal conception of justice. This is problematic, said
23
Williams (1996), p. 22.
24
De Marneffe (1990), pp. 253-274; Dworkin (1985), pp. 191-204; Larmore (1990), pp. 339-60; Rawls (1996).
19
critics, because many do not experience their ideas about the good life in this manner. They do not
conceive of themselves as ‘unencumbered selves’ or ‘autonomous individuals’ but as members of a
community sharing basic goals and values. These cannot be confined to the private sphere but should
be taken into account in public political institutions. Besides, the liberal conception of the person does
impose a substantive value: it compels citizens to become autonomous individuals, disposing of their
commitment to community.25
In reply, liberal thinkers like John Rawls argued that individual autonomy was no longer
constitutive of their project. Political liberalism does not deny the value of community but merely
outlines its boundaries given the fact of reasonable pluralism in modern democracies. Citizens can
continue to cherish the substantive conceptions of the good they share with others. However, the
plurality of these conceptions compels them to reach consensus on a political conception of justice
that governs the state and its legal apparatus. This conception determines the basic structure of the
society where various communities live and should therefore be impartial towards all substantive
values, including individual autonomy.26
Political liberalism retains the twofold structure of earlier forms of liberalism: it still depends
on dividing human existence into a personal sphere, where our comprehensive doctrines shape our
lives and guide our actions, and a public sphere governed in terms of a freestanding political conception
of justice. As human beings, we live in these two spheres and suffer from a corresponding split of
identity: as ‘citizens’ we are subject to state coercion; as ‘private persons’ we are free. This generates
a basic problem: how should we identify the two spheres?
Generally, this question has been understood as that of determining where to draw the
boundary between the two spheres normatively: what should be the limit or scope of religious
25
See Buchanan (1989) and Sandel (1998).
26
Larmore (1990) and (1999), pp. 599-625; Rawls (1996), pp. 1-207.
20
toleration and freedom?27 Criminal behaviour such as murder, torture, or child abuse ought never to
be tolerated but there are ambiguous cases also, from pornography to public smoking. While the
question as to why one should obey the laws of the state is central to liberalism, the basic problem of
liberal toleration is the following: How far into our lives can these laws reach? What criterion
determines the scope of toleration? Where does the sphere of freedom end and that of coercion begin?
The Harm Principle
A major criterion used to delimit the sphere of state coercion from that of individual freedom is the
harm principle: only practices that do not cause harm to others ought to be tolerated. This principle
informs the widespread legal restrictions on religious freedom in the interest of public safety, health,
and order. Individual freedom ends where harm to others begins.
Famously, John Stuart Mill introduced the harm principle in his On Liberty (1859). There, he
intended to establish the limits of the power that could be legitimately exercised by society over the
individual. He came up with ‘one very simple principle’ that should govern the state in its compulsion
and control of individuals. The only end for which coercive authority can be exercised over the
individual is self-protection and the prevention of harm to others. ‘The only part of the conduct of
anyone for which he is amenable to society is that which concerns others. In the part which merely
concerns himself, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind,
the individual is sovereign’.28 This principle was to save democratic society from the tyranny of the
majority. Since the nineteenth century, liberal politics and jurisprudence have invoked it as the
standard to determine the scope of toleration.29
27
Forst (2013), p. 23; McClure (1990), pp. 361-91; Mendus (1989), pp. 9-11; Warnock (1987).
28
Mill (1987), p. 59, pp. 68-9.
29
Dworkin (1985), pp. 335-72; Dyzenhaus (1992), pp. 534-51; Harcourt (1999), pp. 109-95; Skipper (1993), pp.
726-30. For critical analysis, see Vernon (1996), pp. 621-32.
21
But there is a hitch to the harm principle: for its basic functioning, the question how we know
whether our actions harm others becomes vital. If the principle comprised of physical harm alone, it
would not help to fix the boundary between the spheres of freedom and coercion. Moreover, it is
difficult to prove that even flagrant violations of liberty such as slavery cause direct physical harm as
long as the slaves are ‘treated well’. However, once we go beyond physical harm, the ambiguity of the
harm principle surfaces. It is often impossible to tell whether an action of ours harms others. Severe
criticism that hurts a person’s ego may be seen as an attempt to ruin her psychological health or as an
effort to help her become happier. This problem of indeterminacy threatens the harm principle since
no viable criteria exist to determine when our conduct is harmful to others.30
The harm principle is useful as a heuristic for deciding where the state can legitimately
intervene. On a case-by-case basis, this has proven to be effective: say, when parents refuse inoculation
against diseases for their children on religious grounds, the state intervenes because this constitutes
a significant risk of harm to these children. However, the principle cannot function as a general
theoretical standard for distinguishing the sphere of personal freedom from that of state coercion,
since we possess no clear and cogent theory of what constitutes psychological harm and harmful
conduct. Consequently, the border between the two spheres becomes subjective. Depending upon our
metaphysical beliefs about harm, the human psyche, and the integrity of human existence, we
distinguish between the two spheres differently. At the normative level, it becomes impossible to
separate them in any consistent and consensual manner.
A Split of Identity
What, then, is the status of the twofold structure of the liberal model? How can we clarify the
distinction between the sphere of political coercion and that of religious freedom? If we want to explain
the liberal model of secularism to the non-modern, non-liberal, and non-western world, we cannot
30
Dworkin (1985), pp. 336-7; Gray (1983), p. 49; Smith (2010), pp. 70-106.
22
just assume that human lives have a ‘natural’ dual structure. We have to show how these two spheres
can be retrieved in actual experience. The challenge is to provide a criterion that allows us to identify
the two spheres at the empirical level. How to do so?
The political sphere is the domain of the state and its legal apparatus, whereas the private
sphere of religion consists of what is left over. However, this does not allow us to identify the spheres,
since any domain of our lives is subject to state laws at some point, while being free from them at
other points. Our bedrooms may seem the most private spaces we can imagine, but if a husband abuses
his wife in that space, the state is welcome to interfere.
Many theorists argue that ‘the distinction between the public and the private … is a slippery
one, incapable of being established in a way that accords either with an adequate empirical description
of the major institutions of modern society or with satisfactory normative justifications’ and conclude
that it concerns ‘a shifting and uncertain boundary’.31 Such remarks could be multiplied indefinitely.32
However, to say that the boundary is ‘constantly being renegotiated’ or that it is ‘an essentially
contested distinction’ evades the issue. The difficulty does not revolve around where the line is drawn
between the spheres.
Consider the case of a country and its borders. The renegotiation of the borders does not make
the country unidentifiable. Rather, the problem is to describe what lies within the borders. Even if its
borders change, France remains recognizable as a distinct nation-state. In the same way, the puzzle of
the two spheres is not about the precise location of the boundaries. To make sense of the distinction,
we should be able to recognize at least one of the two spheres. Either we possess a criterion to identify
the private sphere of religion and distinguish it from its public political counterpart, or vice versa. This
criterion should describe the characteristic properties of at least one of the spheres.
31
Wolfe (1997), p. 195.
32
Bailey (2002), p. 15; Casanova (1992), p. 17; Steinberger (1997), p. 293; Weintraub (1997), p. 2.
23
Even where we suggest that the spheres are fluid and overlapping, it does not make much
sense to speak of a public political and private religious sphere when we cannot distinguish between
them. Liberal theories presuppose the validity of this distinction without being able to explicate it.
This may be fine as long as such distinctions are confined to popular discourse but that ceases to be
the case when they buttress a political theory. Perhaps we could argue that this distinction belongs to
the basic intuitive ideas of Western societies and, consequently, there is no problem in implementing
the liberal model here. This manoeuvre fails: not only have Western societies become home to
communities that do not share the same cultural intuitions, but the model of liberal secularism has
also been exported to non-western societies.
This point is important in the context of claims about the freestanding position of liberalism.
Political liberalism claims to have disavowed all controversial metaphysical doctrines. As Rawls put it,
‘we apply the principle of toleration to philosophy itself: the public conception of justice is to be
political, not metaphysical’. This political conception ‘tries to draw solely upon basic intuitive ideas
that are embedded in the political institutions of a constitutional democratic regime and the public
traditions of their interpretation’.33
Or in Charles Larmore’s words, liberalism should today be seen as ‘strictly a political doctrine
and not a general “philosophy of man,” not a “comprehensive moral ideal”’. Yet, the liberal ideal ‘relies
on our being able to abandon “the cult of wholeness” and to embrace a certain differentiation between
our role as citizens, free of status and ascription, and our other roles where we may be engaged with
others in the pursuit of substantial ideals of the good life’. In that sense, Larmore continues, there is
some point to talking of a ‘liberal conception of the person’, since the distinction between these two
dimensions of human social life is largely confined to modern Western democracies.34
33
Rawls (1985), pp. 223-4.
34
Larmore (1990), p. 345, p. 351.
24
Larmore’s reference to the lack of a liberal conception of the person in non-western societies
allows me to restate the puzzle of the two spheres in a stronger form. Contemporary liberalism
conceives of itself as a normative political model: its conception of justice tells us how the basic
structure of society ought to be arranged. Perhaps we could confine its scope to the modern West.
Even then, this model should remain intelligible and accessible to different groups living there. If not,
they could never reach consensus on the political conception of justice. Even where the aim of
liberalism is not to present ‘a conception of justice that is true, but one that can serve as a basis for
informed and willing political agreement between citizens viewed as free and equal persons’, the
minimal precondition is that this conception is intelligible and accessible to all reasonably intelligent
citizens.35
Most non-western cultures are ignorant of the liberal conception of the ‘person’. To learn
about its virtues, they should be able to make sense of this conception and its public-private
distinction. That is, liberals need to explain how it is the case that each human lives in two spheres—
one where we are citizens subject to coercive state laws and another where we are private persons free
to live by our substantive conceptions of the good. The first step should demonstrate how to identify
these spheres in human society. But, as already discussed, there are no widely shared and generally
accessible criteria allowing us to recognize the spheres, let alone demonstrate their existence. So either
liberal secularism is a viable political model and it should solve this problem; or the liberal conception
of the ‘person’ is a piece of occult anthropology and then we can safely add liberal secularism to the
political mysticisms of our time.
Symbols of the Secular
The puzzle of the two spheres is not a piece of sophistry without practical implications. Wherever
liberal secular states grant religious freedom to their citizens and strive to keep religion out of politics,
35
Rawls (1985), p. 230.
25
they need to determine the scope of religion. That is, states and courts of law require criteria to
recognize practices or beliefs as religious. For instance, where secularism entails that religious symbols
should be removed from public institutions, states first need to decide which modes of dress, jewellery,
and objects count as religious symbols.
Take the recent debates about the headscarf or hijab in several European countries. In the name
of secularism, some argued that the headscarf is a religious symbol and that Muslim women should
not wear it in state schools or when they work as civil servants. What rational grounds are available
for deciding that the headscarf is a religious symbol?
A symbol is always a symbol to some individual or group of people. The symbolic function of
some object is never the same to all. To whom does the headscarf count as a religious symbol? Not to
Grace Kelly when she popularized the fashion accessory. Something is a religious symbol only to
followers of the religion that identifies it as such. It is a specific interpretation of Islamic doctrine that
transforms the headscarf from a piece of clothing into a religious symbol.
To those who are not members of this religion or do not accept this particular interpretation
of the Quran, the headscarf remains a piece of clothing. To some it symbolizes the submission of
women or Islamic attempts to take over public space in Europe; others respect it as a traditional
practice of some communities.36 But what is a symbol to one is not so to the other. Many view the
headscarf as a piece of clothing—no more and no less. If such symbolism depends on individual points
of view, how could a neutral secular state ever accept that the headscarf is a religious symbol, to be
banned from public institutions?
Advocates of secularism could argue that the headscarf counts as a religious symbol to Muslim
women who wear it. To them, the headscarf expresses certain religious beliefs; therefore, state
representatives should view it in this way. This is dubious: how does wearing a headscarf demonstrate
36
Freedman (2004), pp. 11-16.
26
that the woman in question holds specific beliefs? She may as well wear it because the headscarf has
become part of a struggle of Muslim minorities for equality and emancipation in European societies,
because she feels more comfortable, or because her husband or parents prefer this.37
Generally, the argument that a symbol becomes religious when so considered by followers of
a religion would work only if one is consistent: one should view all symbols of all religions as religious
symbols and ban these from public institutions. How could the secular state then determine what
objects count as religious symbols?
In 2004, the French National Assembly enacted a law prohibiting the wearing of overt insignia
and outfits whereby pupils express a religious affiliation in school.38 The author of the law, French
education minister and philosopher Luc Ferry, called for clear criteria to determine when headscarves,
bandannas, or beards become religious symbols.39 Indeed, when is a beard a religious symbol? When
Muslims sport it? Preventing only Muslim men from growing beards would amount to discrimination.
We could perhaps suggest that beards should be barred in cases where their wearers view them as
religious symbols. But how can the state determine a man’s motive for growing a beard? How can it
distinguish between beards that grow for aesthetic reasons and those that are religiously inspired?40
The state could prevent all employees and pupils from growing beards but this policy goes
against democratic freedoms. The only way out is to decide that beards of a particular shape and length
count as religious symbols. No bureaucrat or pupil may have such a beard. Then the state faces the
37
Killian (2003), pp. 567-90.
38
For explanations of this law and the French attitude towards headscarves, see Thomas (2006), pp. 237-59 and
Bowen (2007).
39
40
‘Laïcité: bandanas et barbes interdits’, Le Nouvel Observateur, 22-01-2004.
Similar problems concerning beards are now cropping up in British schools. See this URL:
<http://www.theguardian.com/world/2013/oct/03/muslim-boys-beards-breach-school-rules>; last consulted 4
October 2013.
27
embarrassing difficulty of demonstrating that a beard suddenly becomes a religious symbol on the day
the relevant collection of hairs reaches a particular length. This reveals the absurdity of the problem:
it is impossible for states to determine from a neutral perspective when some object is a religious
symbol. This is the case because there are no secular criteria to decide on the religiosity of symbols.
Only specific religious teachings can transform objects into religious symbols. In this regard, the
headscarf is similar to the beard.
The Secular Crucifix
So is the crucifix. This symbol stood at the heart of the landmark case of Lautsi v. Italy, which came
before the European Court of Human Rights in 2009 and 2011.41 Soile Lautsi, an Italian mother of
Finnish descent whose two sons attended a state school in Italy, contested the school’s refusal to
remove the crucifixes fixed to the walls of its classrooms. She filed a complaint before a regional
administrative court, arguing that the school crucifixes constituted an infringement of the principle of
secularism according to the relevant articles of the Italian Constitution. The Court, however, held that
the presence of crucifixes in classrooms violated neither the principle of the secular state nor the
religious freedom of the complainant’s children.42
The crucifix, the Court argued, was indeed a Christian religious symbol but it had also become
a historical cultural symbol in Italy. It represents the identity of the Italian people. According to the
Court, key elements of the Enlightenment like the secular state, freedom, and equal rights derive from
Christian teachings. There is a clear affinity between the ‘hard core’ of Christianity and the ‘hard core’
of the republican Constitution. Consequently, the crucifix is ‘a symbol of a value system: liberty,
41
42
Case of Lautsi and Others v. Italy, 18 March 2011, European Court of Human Rights, No. 30814/06.
For background information on the Lautsi case, see Andreescu and Andreescu (2010); Puppinck (2012);
Temperman (2012).
28
equality, human dignity and religious toleration, and accordingly also of the secular nature of the State
– principles which underpin our Constitution’.43
The Court admitted that various interpretations could be given to the sign of the cross,
including a strictly religious meaning. All such viewpoints were respectable but irrelevant in this case.
The meeting of cultures in Italian state schools made it indispensable to reaffirm Italian identity, ‘even
symbolically, especially as it is characterised precisely by the values of respect for the dignity of each
human being and of universal solidarity’. Christianity, the judge claimed, is the sole religion that does
not exclude the unbeliever, for it puts charity above all other values. As a Christian symbol, the crucifix
cannot exclude anyone without denying itself; ‘it even constitutes in a sense the universal sign of the
acceptance of and respect for every human being as such, irrespective of any belief, religious or other,
which he or she may hold’.44
When Lautsi appealed to the Consiglio di Stato, this supreme administrative court agreed that
in Italy the crucifix symbolized the religious origin of values like tolerance, mutual respect, and
freedom of conscience. In the Italian Constitution, the court said, ‘laicità’ or ‘secularism’ is not
proclaimed in express terms but derived from certain constitutional articles that deal with the
inviolable rights of the person (Art. 2), equality before the law (Art. 3), the mutual independence of
the state and the Catholic Church (Art. 7), and the religious freedom of denominations and individuals
(Art. 8, 19, and 20). To function within this legal framework, secularism had to take form under certain
operating conditions, such as the Italian nation’s cultural traditions and customs.
The meanings and purposes of the crucifix, the court pointed out, differ according to the place
where it is displayed – ‘one can even deny its symbolic value and make it a simple trinket having artistic
43
Lautsi v. Italy, paragraph 15.
44
ibid.
29
value at the most’. 45 In a nonreligious context like a school, this symbol does not discriminate if it is
capable of representing values of civil society. In Italy, the crucifix symbolically expresses the
transcendent origin of constitutional values. It does not take anything away from the particular
‘secular’ nature of the Constitution, for these values may be endorsed ‘secularly’ by all.
On 3 November 2009, the Lautsi case came before the Chamber of the European Court of
Human Rights. The Chamber rejected the Italian judges’ reasoning and concluded that the displaying
of crucifixes in state schools constitutes a violation of state neutrality. The religious meaning of the
crucifix is predominant, it said, and associated with the majority religion in Italy. The state should
refrain from imposing any beliefs, even indirectly, in places where persons depend on it. Any state has
a duty to retain confessional neutrality in public education. The visible presence of crucifixes in state
schools, the Chamber concluded, clashed with secular convictions and was ‘incompatible with the
State’s duty to respect neutrality in the exercise of public authority, particularly in the field of
education’.46 Hailed by some as a victory for state neutrality47, this judgement provoked uproar in
Italian and European public opinion.48
By insisting that the crucifix was the symbol of a particular faith, the Chamber had entered
the debate about its true meaning. The Italian Government, joined by third parties including twenty
European countries, objected to this interpretation and argued that the sign of the cross was a ‘passive
symbol’ lacking the impact of active conduct. It could be perceived not only as a religious symbol but
also as a cultural symbol standing for the founding principles of Western civilization and democracy.
45
Lautsi v. Italy, paragraph 16.
46
Lautsi v. Italy, paragraphs 31-2.
47
Andreescu and Andreescu (2010), p. 65.
48
Puppinck (2010).
30
The presence of crucifixes in classrooms was nothing more than ‘a legitimate contribution to enabling
children to understand the national community in which they were expected to integrate’.49
In response, the applicants argued that ‘the crucifix was without a shadow of a doubt a
religious symbol and trying to attribute a cultural value to it savoured of an attempt to maintain a
hopeless last-ditch defence’. The principle of secularism requires state neutrality and a neutral space
where everyone could live freely according to his own beliefs: ‘By imposing religious symbols, namely
crucifixes, in classrooms, the Italian State was doing the opposite’.50
In the end, the Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights argued that the Lautsi
case did not require it to rule on the compatibility between principles of secularism and the presence
of crucifixes in state-school classrooms. Its task was more limited: to assess whether the school
crucifixes conflicted with certain articles of the European Convention on Human Rights. The judges
called on the principle of the margin of appreciation, saying that latitude should be left to each EU
member state in determining whether crucifixes are permitted in public schools. Reversing the earlier
judgment, the Grand Chamber decided that the Convention had not been violated. Yet, to reach this
conclusion, the judges again assessed the status of the crucifix as a religious symbol and concluded
that it was essentially a passive symbol that did not actively indoctrinate or impose any particular
religious views.51
In the Lautsi case, we see the logic of liberal secularism at work: secular states need to establish
a neutral public space cleansed of religious symbols. But the scope of religion and the features that
distinguish it are anything but clear. From a neutral perspective, the state cannot even determine
49
Lautsi v. Italy, paragraphs 36-40.
50
Lautsi v. Italy, paragraphs 42-3.
51
Lautsi v. Italy, paragraphs 71-2. For comments on the Grand Chamber’s judgment, see de Been (2011), pp. 231-
5; Evans (2011), pp. 237-44; Fish (2011); Ronchi (2011), pp. 287-97.
31
which objects count as religious symbols. Consequently, in order to create such a space stripped of
religion, the need emerges to enter the religious realm and take the theological position that certain
objects are religious symbols conveying a particular message. This case brings to the surface the paradox
of a secular court of law deciding on the religiosity of a symbol.
Secularism is not an abstract model that appeared from nowhere, the Italian judges reasoned,
but it had emerged from centuries of development within European Christendom. Shaped by the
religious world where it crystallized, Italian secularism is a Christian secularism, which can be
represented symbolically by the crucifix. To reach this conclusion, the judges had to engage in some
heavy-duty theologizing. First, the regional Court offered a theology of religions that explained how
Christianity differs from other religions in that it cannot exclude unbelievers because it puts charity
above faith. The Consiglio di Stato did not go quite that far but it did give interpretations of Christian
teachings in order to argue that these correspond to the values constitutive of the secular state. In this
way, secular courts of law participated in theological debates about the true message of a religion.
The judges were right in saying that an object like the crucifix is a symbol only according to
the views of its beholder. It is a religious symbol only to those who know the theology of the cross.
Take a Hindu onlooker. Unaware of the importance of theology to Christianity and its doctrines about
the atoning death of Christ, he sees Jesus Christ as another swami or spiritual teacher, of which there
are thousands in India. To him, Jesus attained the deepest meditative trance on the cross and could
withstand pain and appear dead; his resurrection reflects the fact that Jesus returned from this state –
all events fairly common in India.52 When this Hindu looks at the cross, he sees it not as a religious
52
This Hindu view of Jesus Christ is not fictional; see the observations of the Russian thinker and indologist
Alexander Piatigorsky (1985), p. 211. Classical pagans like Celsus similarly viewed Jesus as a magician of some
skill; see Chadwick (1953), I: p. 6, p. 10 and I: pp. 28-9.
32
symbol conveying certain doctrines but simply as the sign of another swami. Hence, whether the
crucifix is ‘obviously’ a religious symbol depends on its viewer.
Lautsi v. Italy was not the first case where judges had to decide on similar issues but only the
latest in a string of cases in European countries.53 Wherever the secular state is called on to decide on
the religiosity of symbols, it embarks on a journey that ends up within the realm of religion.
Delimiting Religion in Law
Consider the following objection: admittedly, there are no neutral secular criteria to identify religion;
yet most citizens in the Western world share some understanding of what counts as religion. Even
without clear criteria, judges and administrators have been able to distinguish between the two spheres
in reasonable ways by relying on this consensus. Only philosophers are disturbed by the lack of
watertight principles to separate the political from the religious.
This objection points to an important truth. Courts often determine what counts as religion.
However, judges cannot be expected to develop some scientific theory that identifies and delimits the
realm of religion. Instead, they express a consensus prevalent in society as to the scope of religion. To
the best of their judgement, they should give reasonable answers to this question. These answers will
be context-sensitive: they may differ depending on the society in question or religious communities
involved in the case.
This is well illustrated by the Lautsi case. The Grand Chamber reversed the original decision
and called on the principle of the margin of appreciation to suggest that the Italian public opinion
should be taken into account. The absence of any European consensus on the question of religious
53
Andreescu and Andreescu (2010), pp. 55-7.
33
symbols in state schools speaks in favour of that approach.54 Thus we see how judges come to
judgements relying upon a local consensus about religion.
In this sense, one could argue, there is no need for any standard to delimit the realm of religion.
However, this route involves several difficulties. First, it may lead to a tyranny of the majority. Any
society’s views regarding religion are shaped by the majority religion that has historically dominated
that society. A practice not considered properly religious by the majority view will fall outside the
scope of religious freedom. Or, similarly, a symbol or practice considered cultural rather than religious
(because it belongs to the religion that shaped local culture) will be allowed entrance into state
institutions. In this way, beliefs and practices of minority religions shall be marginalized. Considering
that the principles of secularism mean to protect minorities, this would undermine the liberal model’s
very purpose.
Second, perhaps this modus operandi was effective as long as Western societies were relatively
homogeneous in terms of religion. Then, some consensus could emerge among religious majorities
like Protestants and Catholics and a few minorities like Jews and Muslims. In their reasoning
concerning religious freedom, jurists could then express this consensus. Contemporary Western
societies, however, have become more diverse than ever. In addition to the groups just mentioned,
they are home to Buddhists, Hindus, Jains, Sikhs, neo-pagans, atheists … . The chances of reaching a
consensus on the scope of religion among these groups are slim. Several of these traditions do not
even possess a conception of religion and its scope. Under these conditions, courts will end up
54
Lautsi v. Italy, paragraph 70. The Court also referred to other cases supporting this judgment: the Folgerø case
concerning the religion syllabus in Norwegian schools and cases about the place of Islam in ‘religious culture and
ethics’ classes in Turkish school.
34
privileging conceptions of religion shared by dominant groups and excluding alien views. Again, this
undercuts the very purpose of state neutrality and religious freedom.55
A third difficulty arises if one insists that the state should leave the question as to what counts
as religion to the religious communities. Judges can call on authorities or experts of the religions under
consideration in order to determine whether some practice, belief, or symbol is indeed religious.56 In
this way, secular courts of law avoid theologizing and express the consensus within this community.
Or do they? Again, there are several obstacles: in order to appoint experts and authorities, judges have
to decide that some form of life is indeed an instance of religion. Which criteria will allow them to do
so, if they cannot decide what counts as religion? In the relevant community, there will be
disagreement between different factions or experts. It will then be difficult for judges to find a
consensus. Moreover, the step of appointing authorities that speak for a religion presupposes the
structure of religions like Christianity, where such authorities exist. This approach compels any group
to agree on certain beliefs and practices essential to its identity and appoint persons with the authority
to represent these. Many communities and traditions do not share this structure.
In principle, none of these problems is unsolvable. It may be possible for a society and its legal
system to develop ways of reaching consensus among a variety of groups concerning the identity and
scope of religion. After all, courts are not asked to express an infallible consensus. In specific cases,
their judgments should propose solutions to this problem equitable towards the parties involved. This
shows that practical solutions might be worked out for the puzzle of the two spheres. However, such
solutions will inevitably be limited in reach: any consensus about the scope of religion is valid only for
a specific society during a specific period.
55
For an argument to this effect, see Smith (1995), p. 68.
56
For illustrations of this practice in American courts, see Sullivan (2007).
35
Take the case of the United State of America. No other nation possesses so rich and refined a
body of jurisprudence on religious freedom and state neutrality. The First Amendment of the U.S.
Constitution goes as follows: ‘Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or
prohibiting the free exercise thereof’. To assess whether some law or policy constitutes a violation of
the establishment clause or a burden on the free exercise of religion, judges require a minimal
understanding of what practices and beliefs are religious. For centuries, courts presupposed a Protestant
consensus view in their judgments concerning religious freedom and non-establishment.57
Considering the booming religious diversity of American society in the twentieth century, this
approach could not last.
American legal theorists recognize the lack of clear criteria to determine what counts as
religion as a major difficulty in interpreting the religion clauses.58 This has been especially troubling
for granting exemptions from generally applicable laws in the name of religious freedom. When some
individual invokes his religious beliefs to request exemption from some law, the state cannot accept
all such claims at face value. To do so, as the Supreme Court noted in one of its landmark judgments,
‘would be to make the professed doctrines of religious belief superior to the law of the land, and in
effect to permit every citizen to become a law unto himself’.59 In such cases, therefore, courts need to
circumscribe religion to find out whether a law implies a burden on free exercise.60
57
Beneke (2006); Sehat (2011).
58
From the vast body of literature on the religion clauses, see: Eisgruber and Sager (2007), pp. 22-50; Greenawalt
(1984), pp. 753-816 and (2006), pp. 124-56; Smith (1995) and (2011), pp. 107-50.
59
Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145 (1879), 5; cited in Employment Division, Department of Human Resources of
Oregon v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990), 879.
60
Gedicks (2006), p. 481.
36
Many thinkers argue that the criteria used by American courts to do so have been incoherent,
ad hoc, and biased in favour of majority religions.61 Others suggest that judges have developed a
number of balancing tests and doctrines to delimit the scope of religion in reasonable ways.62 Wherever
the truth lies, this debate yet again demonstrates that the puzzle of the two spheres poses fundamental
difficulties to the interpretation of liberal principles of secularism and religious freedom. If the liberal
model keeps running into such difficulties within the Western world, one can only begin to imagine
the troubles it encountered once it migrated to other cultures.
1.2. The Troubled Dream of Indian Secularism
Ever since the 1947 Independence Act and its partition of India and Pakistan, the question of
secularism has been at the centre of the subcontinent’s political struggles. The dream of India’s first
Prime Minister, Jawaharlal Nehru, was to transform the country into a secular nation-state. Communal
bloodshed during partition only increased the confidence that secularism was the single viable option
for India. With the rise of Hindu nationalism in recent decades, this issue has once again become as
urgent as it was then. Religious conflict appears to have intensified from the 1992 destruction of the
Babri Mosque in Ayodhya to the massacre of Muslims in Gujarat ten years later. Therefore, India needs
secularism.
At least, that is what the secularists tell us. Indian society is characterized by its religious
diversity, they claim, and therefore the state should be impartial towards all religions. In this view, the
problem with the Sangh Parivar is that it strives to transform India into a religious nation-state.63 If this
were to happen, the state would consistently take the side of the Hindu majority in conflicts and would
61
Eisgruber and Sager (2007), p. 29; for similar statements on the religion clauses in general, see Mansfield
(1984), pp. 847-907, 848; Smith (2007), pp. 109-10.
62
63
This is the position of Kent Greenawalt’s multi-valued approach; see his (2006), pp. 124-56.
The family of Hindu nationalist organizations including the Vishwa Hindu Parishad (VHP), the Rashtriya
Swayamsevak Sangh (RSS) and the Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP).
37
no longer be able to curb violence as an impartial arbiter. In short, the fear of India’s secularists is that
the country will disintegrate if politics is not separated from religion: ‘Secularism, for India, is not
simply a point of view, it is a question of survival’.64
When such importance is attached to the idea of secularism, one would expect its content to
be more or less clear. However, whenever Indian intellectuals attempt to pinpoint what secularism is,
they end up in obscurity and confusion. In the 1970s, one author made the following remark: ‘For the
last two decades Indians have been talking of secularism, yet the term remains vague and ambiguous.
One may, therefore, be justified in asking: what does secularism really mean – especially in the Indian
context?’65 Twenty years later, another author articulated a similar concern: ‘Such a commonplace
concept as secularism, with which the man in the street is so familiar and so used to, tends to acquire
the character of a riddle, a puzzle, an enigma amongst intelligentsia’.66
Some point out ‘the curious absence, the startling and significant vacuity of the notion
“secularism” itself’, and go so far as to claim that the notion has become ‘a sort of mantra, a quasireligious incantation’.67 Others put it mildly and say there is a tendency among Indian intellectuals to
interpret the concept in their own subjective manner,68 or they use more pointed terms: ‘Like liberal
Hindu gods who can take different forms and give a chance to the devotees to worship in any form
they like, in India the concept of secularism has acquired so many interpretations and it now means
different things to different groups of people’.69
64
Rushdie (1990), p. 19; see Chatterji (1995) for similar statements.
65
Mushir-Ul-Haq (1972), p. 6.
66
Sankhdher (1995), pp. 1-2.
67
Rai (1989), pp. 2770-73.
68
Khan (1994), pp. 370-83.
69
Srikanth (1994), p. 39.
38
The situation is no different in the courts. Confusion about the term ‘secularism’ surfaced in
the 1994 Supreme Court Bommai judgment, where seven judges explained their views on secularism,
each giving a different account. One judge concluded that ‘the term “Secular” has advisedly not been
defined presumably because it is a very elastic term not capable of precise definition and perhaps left
best undefined’.70 Whether Muslim or Hindu, rightist or leftist, these thinkers all agree that the term
‘secularism’ has acquired so many different meanings in India that it appears to have lost all meaning.
This section will argue that the semantic confusion surrounding the term ‘secularism’ masks
a more fundamental problem in the Indian debate. Instead of being embedded in a well-structured
theoretical framework, the notions of ‘secularism’ consist of a number of isolated normative
propositions proclaimed as though these are self-illuminating. But the principles of the liberal secular
state lack coherence and intelligibility in the Indian context. The puzzle of the two spheres takes an
acute form, because the conceptual background necessary for making sense of the liberal principles of
secularism and religious freedom is missing.
A Distinctive Secularism?
Over the last two decades, the Indian debate has focused on diagnosing the crisis of secularism.71 Some
authors conclude that factors internal to the secular state are to blame. Even though the Indian state
professes to be secular, they suggest, it has not been impartial towards religion. The state intervened
in the affairs of some religious communities while leaving others alone and used a tit-for-tat approach
70
71
S.R. Bommai vs Union of India, 1994 AIR 1918 at 29; cited in Sen (2010), pp. xxviii-xxix.
Madan (1997); Pantham (1997); Bhargava (1998a); Ganguly (2003); Needham and Rajan (2007);
Balagangadhara and De Roover (2007); Rao (2006).
39
in dealing with the different communities.72 Others argue that secularism has failed to take root in
India, because it was imposed on a deeply religious population by alienated Westernized elites.73
In response, it is argued that such critics presuppose one normative or ‘transhistorical’ model
of secularism—an idealized version of the Western separation of church and state. Instead, this
response continues, a specifically Indian form of secularism has come into being because of the
historical conditions under which it emerged.74 Secularism is a universal doctrine, Rajeev Bhargava
asserts, since its basic constituents are constant, namely, ‘a separation of organized religion from
organized political power inspired by a specific set of values’. But these elements can be interpreted in
several ways. Therefore, secularism has no fixed content, but ‘multiple interpretations which change
over time’.75 Indian secularism is distinct from Western secularism, such authors claim, for it was
transformed in the process of responding to problems like caste discrimination and extreme religious
diversity.76
India is supposed to be home to a different form and concept of secularism. So far we have
characterized the liberal model of secularism in terms of a number of central concepts and principles
and a basic problem that dogs this model. If secularism changed substantially in the Indian context,
then the problem at the heart of its conceptual structure may no longer be relevant. In that case, Indian
secularism should not face the difficulty of distinguishing between the public political sphere and the
72
Brass (1999), pp. 370-75; Chatterjee (1998), pp. 353-66; Rao (2006), pp. 48-9; Tambiah (1998), p. 427. This
assessment is shared by Hindu nationalists who accuse the Congress party and the Indian secularists of being
‘pseudo-secularists’ because of their failure to be impartial between Hindus and Muslims.
73
Madan (1998); Nandy (1985), (1998), and (2007).
74
Chandhoke (1999), p. 42; Pantham (1997); Tejani (2008), pp. 4-6.
75
Bhargava (2007), pp. 21-2. See Mahajan (2002).
76
Gary Jacobsohn (2003, pp. 49-50) calls the result ‘the ameliorative model’, which ‘embraces the social reform
impulse of Indian nationalism in the context of the nation’s deeply rooted religious diversity and stratification’.
40
sphere of religion. Yet it does. The distinction between the religious and the political plays as central
a role in the Indian debate as it does in the Western debates. The same set of problems returns in a
stronger form here.
For one, the relevant article of the Indian Constitution relies on the religious-secular
distinction. Article 25 grants ‘freedom of conscience and the right freely to profess, practice and
propagate religion’ but restricts this right by allowing the state to make laws ‘regulating or restricting
any economic, financial, political or other secular activity which may be associated with religious
practice’. Moreover, some Indian secularists provide definitions that leave no doubt as to the meaning
of the term. Secularism calls for ‘the demarcation of two realms of existence, the separation of church
from state, of the sacred from the secular’; it requires the separation of the state from religion in
general, from all faiths, or from any particular religious order; or it stands for the separation of religious
and non-religious institutions.77
These are typical formulae of liberal secularism that generate the puzzle of the two spheres. If
the separation of politics and religion is necessary, then one should be able to determine what
properties distinguish the religious domain from the secular political domain in India. If there is no
clarity on what makes some phenomena in society into religious phenomena or some institutions into
religious institutions, then there is no point in stating that the religious ought to be separated (or
equidistant) from the political.
The Constituent Assembly Debates
The foundations of the Indian secular state are located in the debates of the Constituent Assembly,
the body that drafted the Constitution of India between 1946 and 1949.78 Since most Assembly
77
The quote is from Chatterji (1995), p. x. The other formulations can be found in Gopal (1993), p. 13; Sen
(1996), p. 13; Bhargava (1998), p. 488.
78
Bhargava (2008), p. 12; Chiriyankandath (2000); Jha (2002), pp. 3175-80.
41
members agreed that India should become a secular democracy, they reproduced standard
formulations of religious freedom and the secular state.79 Yet, the trouble in interpreting these surfaced
whenever there was disagreement about their implications.
The most striking instance was the dispute about the question whether the secular state
requires a uniform civil code.80 This started when Mohamed Ismail, a Muslim representative, proposed
to add the following proviso to Article 35, which said that the state would secure for its citizens a
uniform civil code throughout the territory of India: ‘Provided that any group, section or community
of people shall not be obliged to give up its own personal law in case it has such a law’. Ismail defended
his proviso as follows:
Now the right to follow personal law is part of the way of life of those people who are following
such laws; it is part of their religion and part of their culture. If anything is done affecting the
personal laws, it will be tantamount to interference with the way of life of those people who
have been observing these laws for generations and ages. This secular State which we are trying
to create should not do anything to interfere with the way of life and religion of the people.81
Several Muslim representatives agreed that the secular state could not touch personal law because it
ought not to interfere in matters of religion.
When others rejected this proviso as a direct negation of Article 35, the dispute turned to the
correct interpretation of ‘the secular state’. Another representative insisted that Indians seemed to
have ‘very strange ideas’ about the secular state: ‘People seem to think that under a secular State, there
must be a common law observed by its citizens in all matters, including matters of their daily life, their
79
See Constituent Assembly Debates (CAD), Official Report, third reprint (New Delhi: Lok Sabha Secretariat, 1999),
vol. 3, p. 488 and vol. 7, pp. 815-6.
80
These debates continue today along the same lines, see Larson (ed.) (2001).
81
CAD, vol. 7, pp. 540-41.
42
language, their culture, their personal laws’. This is incorrect, he added, because, in a secular state,
‘citizens belonging to different communities must have the freedom to practice their own religion,
observe their own life and their personal laws should be applied to them’.82 At the time of this debate,
the idea that the same set of laws and rights should apply to all citizens, irrespective of religious
affiliation, was not a ‘very strange idea’ but a central principle of the liberal secular state. If the state
ought not to interfere with the ways of life of people, then legal uniformity would become impossible.83
Indeed, such reasoning led Muslim representatives to rejecting the attempt ‘to have uniformity
of law to be imposed upon the whole people’ concerning civil matters as ‘a tyrannous provision which
ought not to be tolerated’. In response, the lawyer K. M. Munshi remarked that democracies in the
West had uniformity of law and were hardly tyrannies. Munshi also denied that personal law was part
of religion. Expectedly, the dispute now took the form of disagreement about the scope of the term
‘religion’. Munshi argued that ‘religion’ should be restricted to spheres that legitimately appertain to
it, while the rest of life can be regulated by law.84 The state was welcome to interfere in the secular
affairs of any religion. But, as Ismail retorted, each community also disagrees on what was religious
and secular: ‘It is a question of difference of opinion as to what a religion should do or should not.
People differ and people holding different views on this matter must tolerate the other view’.85
In this debate, Muslim representatives treated the principle that ‘the state ought not to
interfere in religion’ as an isolated normative proposition and made use of a commonplace from Islamic
theology to interpret it—the belief that the Shar’iah has been ordained by Allah, and not by human
agency, and that humans should never modify it. Since religion covered all of God’s revelation, they
82
ibid., p. 544.
83
The rise of multiculturalism from the 1960s turned this into a contested idea, see Barry (2001).
84
CAD, vol. 7, p. 548.
85
ibid., pp. 721-2.
43
suggested, a secular state should not interfere in Muslim personal law.86 Confronted by this
interpretation, secularists in the Assembly could not draw upon any conception of religion that
clarified the properties determining the religiousness of a practice or belief. They had to take recourse
to other commonplaces to interpret this principle.
B.R. Ambedkar, the chief architect of the Constitution and advocate of social reform, borrowed
the cliché from European orientalists that religion in India covers all aspects of life from birth to death:
‘There is nothing which is not religion and if personal law is to be saved, I am sure about it that in
social matters we will come to a standstill’. He offered an alternative to seeing everything as religion:
‘There is nothing extraordinary in saying that we ought to strive hereafter to limit the definition of
religion in such a manner that we shall not extend beyond beliefs and such rituals as may be connected
with ceremonials which are essentially religious’.87 Ambedkar’s proposal, however, generated a vicious
circle, since his definition of ‘religion’ included the term to be defined. Without consensus on what
religion was, there would also be disagreement on what was essentially religious.
Judging Hinduism
The puzzle of the two spheres wreaks havoc in India, because it is even less clear here than elsewhere
how the religious and the secular are to be identified. The ‘majority religion’ of India is supposed to
be Hinduism, but there is no clarity as to what Hinduism is, whether it is a religion or not, or even
whether it exists or not.88 In 1946, Nehru noted the following: ‘Hinduism, as a faith, is vague,
amorphous, many-sided, all things to all men. It is hardly possible to define it, or indeed to say whether
it is a religion or not in the usual sense of the word’.89 It must be extremely difficult, if not impossible,
86
The same argument surfaced in the infamous Shah Bano case of the 1980s. See Bajpai (2002).
87
CAD, vol. 7, pp. 781-2.
88
There has been an extensive debate on these issues during the past three decades: see Balagangadhara (2005a);
Bloch et al. (2010); Dubuisson (2003); King (1999); Llewellyn (2005).
89
Nehru (1988a), p. 75.
44
to identify something that is indefinable, vague, amorphous, many-sided, and all things to all men.
But when one does not succeed in identifying Hindu religion, how can one even dream of separating
it from the state?
This constitutes a serious problem. Scholars agree there is no particular set of dogmas, beliefs,
or practices that defines the Hindu religion.90 Basically, the conclusion is that this religion does not
have any properties (common beliefs, institutions, or practices) allowing one to recognize it. If
Hinduism does not have such properties, how shall we determine when this religion intrudes into the
political domain? When does a state become Hindu as opposed to secular? When the government
publicly cites Rama as the prototype of the ethical king? Or when it consults an astrologer before
making a political decision? When a puja ritual is done in parliament or when a puranic story is told
by state officials? Any answer to such questions will derive from the properties that distinguish the
class of things Hindu from that of things secular. Since there is no consensus on this, one can fix this
standard as one chooses. Accordingly, one can give one’s own interpretation as to what it means for
India to be a secular state.
Perhaps the consequences are best illustrated when the Indian judiciary invokes a number of
definitions of ‘Hinduism’ and ‘religion’ to interpret laws related to religion. In 1952, the Bombay High
Court had to interpret the constitutional religious freedom articles in the case of Ratilal Panachand
Gandhi vs State of Bombay. Two petitioners had challenged the constitutionality of certain provisions of
the Bombay Public Trusts Act of 1950, which allowed the state to regulate the administration of public
religious and charitable trusts. They argued that Jain temples, which also fell under the scope of this
90
For some typical claims from the study of religion, see Dandekar (1971), p. 237; Flood (1996), p. 6; Michaels
(2004), pp. 3-5; Sharma (2003), pp. 1-19; Zaehner (1969), p. 2. For typical claims by Indian judges, see Sen
(2010), pp. 15-6.
45
trust, could only be used for specific purposes according to the tenets of Jain religion. Therefore, the
Bombay Act contravened the constitutional articles of religious freedom.
The judge pointed out that the religious freedom granted by Articles 25 and 26 was restricted:
‘It is not every aspect of religion that has been safeguarded, nor has the Constitution provided that
every religious activity cannot be interfered with’. Drawing on a specific etymology of the term
‘religion’ – originally proposed by the Christian church father Lactantius – the judge suggested that
this term should be understood in its strict etymological sense as ‘that which binds a man with his
Creator’. However, the petitioner’s lawyer argued, Jains do not believe in any Creator and, therefore,
the distinction could not apply to them. The judge responded as follows:
But even where you have a religion which does not believe in a Creator, every religion must
believe in a conscience and it must believe in ethical and moral precepts. Therefore, whatever
binds a man to his own conscience and whatever moral and ethical principles regulate the lives
of men, that alone can constitute religion as understood in the Constitution. A religion may
have many secular activities, it may have secular aspects, but these secular activities and
aspects do not constitute religion as understood by the Constitution.91
If religion is constituted by the conscience and its moral precepts, then one cannot consistently argue
that it does not encompass activities such as the administration of temples. Otherwise, one would
have to allow that managing the finances of a temple, including potential embezzlement of its wealth,
are actions outside the domain of morality and the conscience. But this does not make sense: according
to any follower of a religion or tradition, such actions do belong in that domain. Consequently, since
this judge argued that religion is constituted by ‘whatever binds a man to his own conscience and
whatever moral and ethical principles regulate the lives of men’, such ‘secular’ activities would have
to come under the realm of religion.
91
Ratilal Panachand Gandhi vs State of Bombay, 12 September, 1952, AIR 1953 Bom 242 at 4.
46
Still, interpreting religion in the ‘strict constitutional’ sense made the judge conclude that the
administration of property (including temples) was not religious but a secular activity regulated by the
state. Drawing on some definition of religion, the judge here determined for the followers of a tradition
which aspects of that tradition were essentially religious and secular. In another similar case, the same
Court had stated that even the authority of a religious body in relation to its members had nothing to
do with religion.92
When Ratilal and similar cases came before the Supreme Court of India, the bench rejected
this interpretation of Article 25. A religion, it argued, ‘is not merely an opinion, doctrine or belief’ but
‘has outward expression in acts as well’.93 In the important Shirur Mutt case, the Supreme Court
explicitly raised the issue: ‘The question is, where is the line to be drawn between what are matters of
religion and what are not?’94 Drawing on a definition borrowed from an Australian court, the judges
suggested that a religion may not only prescribe an ethical code, but also ‘rituals and observances,
ceremonies and modes of worship which are regarded as integral parts of religion, and these forms
and observance might extend even to matters of food and dress’. The Court then attempted to provide
a way out of the definitional quandary by arguing that ‘what constitutes the essential part of a religion
is primarily to be ascertained with reference to the doctrines of that religion itself’.95
This step shifts the problem to even more difficult questions: Which are the religions of India?
Is ‘Hinduism’ one of them? ‘Hinduism’ consists of a range of traditions, all of which prefer different
narratives, draw on different teachers, and emphasize different texts and customs. Which of these
contains the doctrine that determines the essential part of Hindu religion? Perhaps one could propose
92
Smith (1998), pp. 197-8.
93
Ratilal Panachand Gandhi vs State of Bombay and Ors., 18 March 1954, 1954 AIR 388 at 1064.
94
The Commissioner, Hindu Religious Endowments, Madras vs Sri Lakshmindra Thirtha Swamiar, 1954 AIR 282 at 1022.
95
1954 AIR 282 at 1025.
47
that there are many different Hindu religions.96 However, given the absence of fixed scriptures or
doctrinal systems distinguishing these from each other, where will we find the doctrines about the
essential parts of these religions? Given the nonexistence of established ecclesiastical authorities, who
will decide about this doctrine?
That these issues remain unresolved became clear in later cases, where the Court argued that
demonstrating that some practice was truly Hindu required that one produce its scriptural
foundations. The next step was inevitable: judges claimed that certain practices that appeared to
belong to some religion did not really constitute an essential and integral part. A community’s claim
could not always be accepted, for the ‘essentially religious’ might well be founded on superstition,
ignorance, and misunderstanding of the true teachings of Hindu religion. As Ronojoy Sen shows in
his work on religion in the Indian Supreme Court, Indian courts now took upon themselves the task
of reforming Hinduism back to scriptural purity and discarding all ‘superstitious accretions’ added to
its original core.97
To conclude, Indian judges have decided what religion is, what is secular and essentially
religious about certain practices, and what is truly religious as opposed to superstitious. At its most
disquieting, this modus operandi takes the form of the so-called ‘doctrine of essential practices’, which
allows the Supreme Court to reform religions and dispose of all ‘non-essential’ practices according to
a normative picture of rational religion.98 As many have noted, the criteria used to settle these issues
are deeply flawed, even though they bestow upon Indian judges a religious authority greater than that
of any high priest.99
96
Stietencron (2001).
97
See Sen (2010), pp. 49-67.
98
ibid., 40-72.
99
Mehta (2008), pp. 65-88; Chatterjee (1998), pp. 359-60; Derrett (1968), p. 447, p. 534; Dhavan and Nariman
(2000), p. 259; Galanter (1971), pp. 467-87; Smith (1998), pp. 196-201.
48
At this point, we can come back to the confusion surrounding the idea of secularism in India.
Fundamentally, this is caused by the lack of theoretical clarity in the religious-secular distinction.
Moreover, the term ‘secularism’ has grown to be a keyword in Indian political discourse to refer to any
kind of situation where different groups of people co-exist: if they get along well, this is because of
secularism; if they fight and kill each other, they are in need of the antidote of secularism. Anything
that allows different kinds of people to live together can be called ‘secularism’. The notion has become
as vague as it possibly could: it is defined as ‘a state of mind, almost an instinctive feeling, such as
existed, by and large, for many centuries in India, when Hindus, Muslims, Christians, Parsis and
followers of other faiths lived side by side in general harmony’100 or as ‘a respect for differences cutting
across class, caste, community, and gender, in which religion is a component in the shaping of identity
but not the determining criterion’.101
Instead of examining and theorizing the ways in which different communities have succeeded
or failed to live together peacefully in India, one takes recourse to the obscure language of secularism.
Consequently, the discourse of liberal secularism prevents one from understanding the problems of
pluralism in India, instead of helping to solve them. The urgency of these problems today makes it all
the more painful that some continue to believe that they can be resolved by endlessly repeating the
mantra that ‘the political’ should be separated from ‘the religious’.
1.3. Conclusion
This chapter has revealed a problem at the heart of the liberal model of secularism and religious
toleration, namely that of identifying the sphere of religion and distinguishing it from the public
political sphere. This split between two spheres—one of political coercion and the other of religious
freedom—is essential to the liberal model. Yet political theorists and jurists take it as a pre-theoretical
100
Gopal (1993), pp. 19-20.
101
Bharucha (1998), p. 6.
49
given requiring no explanation, even though the distinction between the two spheres is anything but
clear.
The idea of secularism, both its advocates and opponents acknowledge, emerged in the modern
West.102 This fact leads secularists and anti-secularists in India to very different conclusions. The latter
argue that secularism has become a sterile concept in India because of its alien origins.103 The former
disagree. Charles Taylor writes: ‘The Christian origins of the idea are undeniable, but this does not
have to mean that it has no application elsewhere’.104 Mushirul Hasan agrees: ‘The central issue is not
the Western provenance of an idea but its place and relevance in a plural society’.105 The sociologist
Andre Beteille has similar reservations: ‘Surely, the test of an idea or an institution should be its
capacity to meet our present needs and not its provenance’ and ‘geography can never be a decisive test
of the social value of an idea or institution’.106
It would indeed be problematic to argue that the Western origins of liberal secularism rule out
its relevance in India. Not only does this type of argument commit the genetic fallacy, we also know
from human history that ideas are rarely the exclusive property of one culture. The liberal model
emerged as a solution to certain problems that people faced in living together. Given its apparent
success in Europe, there was good reason for other plural societies to adopt it. Consequently, the fact
that an idea migrated from one culture to another cannot in itself constitute a problem.
102
Madan (1998), p. 754; Mahajan (2002), p. 35; Nijwahan (1995), pp. 183-8; Smith (1963), p. 22; Taylor (1998),
p. 37; Vanaik (1997), p. 29.
103
This point of view is taken by Gandhian anti-secularists like Madan and Nandy, and shared by some Hindu
nationalists: Madhok (1995), pp. 110-22; Nijwahan (1995), pp. 183-8.
104
Taylor (1998), p. 37.
105
Hasan (1996), p. 202.
106
Beteille (1994), p. 560.
50
However, the issue raised by the anti-secularists does not concern the origins of secularism
but its spectacular failure in India. To paraphrase Kantorowicz, they suggest that the language of liberal
secularism, unless resounding within its own magic and mystic circle, often appears poor and even
slightly foolish. That is, the liberal model seems to lose its spell and become quite meaningless when
taken out of its native surroundings, its time, and its space. These critics suggest that the reason for
this failure lies in the close ties between this model and the cultural and religious context where it
originated. This suggestion is certainly worth examining.
51