Moral Reason
Julia Markovits
(Under contract with Oxford University Press. Draft of June 2013.
Please do not cite or circulate without permission.)
For Inga and Dick
2
Contents
Acknowledgments ............................................................................................................................ ii
Chapter 1 Reasons and Moral Relativism ............................................................................. 1
1.1 Two sorts of questions ...................................................................................................................... 1
1.2 The analytic question ......................................................................................................................... 6
1.3 The threat of relativism ................................................................................................................. 14
1.4 ‘Ought’ and reasons.......................................................................................................................... 20
Chapter 2 Internalism and the Motivating Intuition ..................................................... 33
2.1 Two arguments for internalism.................................................................................................. 33
2.2 Motivating intuitions ....................................................................................................................... 42
2.3 Counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition ...................................................................... 48
2.4 What These Counterexamples Can Teach Us ....................................................................... 61
Chapter 3 Why Be An Internalist About Reasons?.......................................................... 64
3.1 Internalism without the Motivating Intuition ...................................................................... 64
3.2 Remotivating internalism: epistemic humility ................................................................... 67
3.3 Remotivating internalism: the analogy to theoretical reasons.................................... 73
3.4 Remotivating internalism: the motivating force of moral judgments ...................... 82
3.5 Categorical internal reasons? ...................................................................................................... 83
Chapter 4 Kant’s Argument .................................................................................................... 89
4.1 The problem of obligations .......................................................................................................... 89
4.2 Kant’s “formula of universal law” .............................................................................................. 94
4.3 Three imperatives ......................................................................................................................... 101
4.4 Humanity as an end ...................................................................................................................... 113
4.5 The “unconditioned condition” of value .............................................................................. 117
4.6 Worries about Kant’s argument .............................................................................................. 130
Chapter 5 Kantian Internalism ...........................................................................................135
5.1 Skepticism about procedural practical rationality .......................................................... 135
5.2 The instrumental imperative .................................................................................................... 144
5.3 The prudential imperative ......................................................................................................... 149
5.4 The moral imperative .................................................................................................................. 161
Chapter 6 Is the Moral Imperative Categorical?............................................................182
6.1 A first response: the problem of Maria revisited ............................................................ 182
6.2 A second response: the categorical ‘use’ of ‘ought’ ........................................................ 187
6.3 A third response: categorical imperatives and practice rules................................... 191
Chapter 7 What Do We Have Moral Reason To Do? .....................................................203
7.1 Persons and things ........................................................................................................................ 203
7.2 Consent ............................................................................................................................................... 222
7.3 Infants and animals ....................................................................................................................... 240
7.4 Immorality as irrationality? ...................................................................................................... 242
Bibliography ..................................................................................................................................245
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the following for permission to reproduce previously
published material:
•
Palgrave MacMillan for permission to reprint “Internal Reasons and
the Motivating Intuition,” first published in New Waves in Metaethics
(edited by Michael Brady) in 2011, which appears here as §2.1‐3.1,
in slightly amended form;
•
Oxford University Press for permission to reprint significant
portions of “Why Be An Internalist About Reasons?,” first published
in Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 6 (edited by Russ Shafer‐Landau)
in 2011, which appear here as §3.2‐3.5 in slightly amended form.
This book has been many years in the making. It began as a masters’ thesis,
written during my time as a B.Phil student at Oxford, which then formed the core of
my doctoral dissertation, also completed at Oxford. During that time I benefitted
from the generous financial support of a number of institutions. The Philosophy
Faculty and Somerville College, Oxford provided me with a graduate scholarship,
which, in conjunction with grants from the Overseas Research Studentship Award
Scheme and the Oxford University Clarendon Fund Bursaries, supported my first
three years of study. Christ Church, Oxford, funded my last two years of research by
providing me with a Senior Scholarship. I look back on my time as a graduate
student at Oxford with great fondness, and I owe all of these institutions heart‐felt
thanks.
After completing my doctorate, I was lucky enough to receive a Junior
Fellowship at the Harvard Society of Fellows. The fellowship provided me with a
ii
rare luxury for a post‐doctoral philosopher: three years of uninterrupted research
time. This meant I had time to begin reworking my dissertation project into a book;
but also, and just as crucially, it meant I had time, for a while, to ignore it completely
and think about new topics. By the time I returned to the manuscript in the second
half of my fellowship, I was able to see it with the clearer sight afforded by distance.
In that time and in the years since, with the benefit of the supportive philosophical
community at MIT, I have re‐written much of it entirely. But the basic outlines of
the project and the motivating thoughts behind it remain the same.
Two people in particular helped me to write this book. The first is my
doctoral thesis advisor Derek Parfit. I would not have thought it possible for
someone to be so generous in his encouragement of a project built on premises so at
odds with his own philosophical convictions. The defense of a philosophical
position can only benefit from repeated collisions with the most forceful and
persuasive arguments for the opposite view. I hope some such benefit will be
evident in this book, and that I have managed at least to address, if not allay, some of
Parfit’s worries about internalism. That I share many of those doubts will be readily
evident to the reader. So too, I hope, will be the pervasive influence of Parfit’s
thought throughout the book, despite the distance between the conclusions for
which I argue and his own. Our philosophical instincts are, I think, not so far apart
as those conclusions make them seem.
Just as indispensable to my completion of this book has been the help I have
received, in a less formal capacity, from Stephen Kearns. He has read and talked
through with me every argument in it. Many of the ideas developed in the book
iii
began as conversations with him, during our time as graduate students together at
Oxford. I was quite concerned, when I left Oxford, about how I would learn to do
philosophy without him. I needn’t have worried. Skype does wonders for
expanding the reach of philosophical conversations, and Stephen’s advice has been
as crucial to the final formulation of the ideas in this book as it was to their
origination. I consider myself extremely lucky to have him as a long‐distance
sounding board.
In addition to these two, a number of people gave me very generous and
helpful comments, either in writing or in person, on large parts of the manuscript at
various stages of development. For such help I owe thanks to Ruth Chang, Roger
Crisp, Kate Manne, Rebecca Markovits, Adrian Moore, Phillip Stratton‐Lake, and
Kurt Sylvan. I have also benefitted greatly from numerous conversations about this
work, in settings both formal and informal, over the years. Unfortunately, I won’t be
able now to recall all the people who have helped me in this way, but the list
includes at least Robert Adams, Brian Ball, Terence Cuneo, Jamie Dreier, David
Enoch, Caspar Hare, Niko Kolodny, Rae Langton, Ofra Magidor, Graham Oddie,
Michael Smith, Daniel Star, Nicholas Sturgeon, Mark van Roojen, and R. Jay Wallace.
I’ve had opportunities to present some of the work represented in the book
to audiences at Berkeley, Brown, Carnegie Mellon, Cornell, MIT, NYU‐Abu Dhabi,
Oxford, Rice, Rutgers, UC‐Santa Barbara, the University of British Columbia, the
University of Melbourne, the University of Nebraska‐Lincoln, the University of Oslo’s
Center for the Study of Mind in Nature, the University of Texas‐Austin, and the
Wisconsin Metaethics Workshop. I know that many of the suggestions and concerns
iv
raised by audience members in those talks have made their way directly into the
book. The same is true of comments made by the excellent graduate students at MIT,
from whom I have been fortunate to learn. Though many of these people no doubt
deserve to be acknowledged by name, my porous memory forces me to settle
instead for this general thanks.
For thoughtful help in preparing the index, much better than I could have
done myself, and for other sound suggestions, I thank Brendan Dill. Thanks also go
to Peter Momtchiloff, my editor, and the staff at OUP, for their advice, patience, and
support, as well as to an anonymous reader for OUP, whose very helpful comments
on the initial draft of the book revealed an eye that is at once generous and critical—
in other words, just what any author would hope to find in a referee.
And I am more grateful than I can say to Sally Haslanger, whose advice and
reassurance have helped me to finish this book, and helped me in so many other
ways as well.
I have said that this book has been many years in the making. In fact, the
earliest seed of the project was a term paper I wrote when I was a Yale
undergraduate for a class on Kant’s ethics taught by Allen Wood. He introduced me
to a very likeable Immanuel Kant, in whose thinking the value of rational nature as
an end in itself plays the central role. I am grateful for the introduction.
A final word of thanks goes to my family: Rebecca, Benjamin, Stefanie, and
Daniel (and their families), and especially to my parents, Inga and Dick, and my
partner, Jeff Moses: without their good will, steadfast support, skills in crisis
v
management, and stubborn faith in my abilities, any undertaking would be a great
deal more difficult than it is.
Julia Markovits
May 2013
vi
Chapter 1
Reasons and Moral Relativism
1.1 Two sorts of questions
What are reasons for action? The question is multiply ambiguous.
First, the term “reason” is itself infamously ambiguous. A reason for an
action might be a fact that explains why an agent acted, or a fact that motivates the
agent to act, or a fact that helps justify an agent’s action. An example may help: the
fact that I haven’t gotten enough sleep lately may (partly) explain why I snap at you.
But it doesn’t motivate me to snap at you – it’s not the consideration on the basis of
which I choose to do so. Perhaps I choose to snap at you because your voice is
rather shrill for this time of the morning, and it’s getting on my nerves, and my
snapping at you will get you to stop talking. These facts are what motivate me to act
as I do.1 But these facts don’t justify what I do – after all, it’s not your fault that I
haven’t been sleeping, and you can’t (and shouldn’t) change the register of your
voice just to suit me. I ought not to snap at you as I do. So my motivating reasons
are not, in this case, justifying reasons. Things would be different, perhaps, if you
were to blame for my lack of sleep – if I’m underslept because you keep waking me
up, at 5 a.m., by practicing arias under my bedroom window in your unsteady
1
Motivating reasons are also a species of explanatory reasons: they feature in explanations of what
agents do that operate at the level of the agents’ intentions.
1
soprano. In that case, the early hour and the shrillness of your voice may well justify
my telling you to put a lid on it.2
My focus in this book will be on this last kind of reason – the justifying, or
“normative”, kind, though its relation to the other kinds of reasons will sometimes
be of interest, too. My question is: what are normative reasons for action?
There is a second source of ambiguity in my question, even after we restrict
our topic to normative reasons: it can be read as an analytic or a substantive
inquiry: as asking what reasons are or what reasons there are.
So, for example, someone might offer as an answer to the substantive
question – the question of what we have reason to do – the thesis that only facts
about the (agent‐neutral) value of the consequences of an action are reasons to
perform it. Or that what we have reason to do depends on what others can consent
to our doing. Or that only facts about how the action would satisfy the desires of the
agent provide the agent with reasons to perform it.
There is in fact a lot of disagreement about how to answer the substantive
question. But even if we disagree about this, we should be able to agree on an
answer to the analytic question – the question about what reasons are. Indeed, we
will have to agree about this on some level, more or less, at least implicitly, if our
differing answers to the substantive question are to count as disagreements at all: as
rival answers to the same question.
2
Sometimes, when I’m motivated to act by the consideration that justifies my acting, the same fact is
an explanatory, motivating, and justifying reason.
2
Fortunately, we do, most of us, agree on an answer of sorts to the analytic
question: it’s commonly accepted that a normative reason for action is a
consideration that counts in favor of the action. Some philosophers argue that
nothing else useful can be said about what a reason is. (“‘Counts in favor of how?’”
Scanlon famously asked; and replied, “‘By providing a reason for it’ seems to be the
only answer.”3) But other philosophers – sometimes called reasons‐internalists –
think there is more we can say. They have offered a kind of desire‐based view as an
account, not of what reasons there are but of what reasons are: they’ve suggested
that what it is for a consideration to count in favor of an action is for it to show that
performing the action stands in the right relation to the agent’s desires, broadly
understood: archetypically, by showing that the action will help satisfy one of those
desires.
So: What is it to have a reason to do something? is one sort of question; what
is it we have reason to do? is another. The two questions can be, and often are,
explored separately. This seems quite natural. After all, on the face of it, it seems
like quite different sorts of considerations would be relevant each of them. The first
question falls into the domain of meta‐ethics; the second, into ‘normative’, or first‐
order, ethics. Arguments about the nature of normativity – about what we’re talking
about when we talk about normative reasons – seem to operate at a different level
from arguments about whether, say, we have reason to override the will of a
resistant patient to perform surgery that’s necessary for her future health.
3
See Scanlon, What We Owe To Each Other, p. 17.
3
But our answers to these two different questions may turn out not to be
independent. What reasons are may have implications for what reasons there are.
(In fact, this wouldn’t be surprising.) So the door is opened to a troubling kind of
tension: it could be that the account of what reasons are that is most plausible in its
own right entails a view of what we have reason to do that is independently
implausible. In fact, as I will argue, it looks very much like this is the case. That
would leave us with some unpalatable choices; we’d have to bite some bullets in one
theory or the other.
The first half of this book addresses the analytic question: I will be exploring
and then defending a version of a (loosely‐speaking) desire‐based, internalist,
account of what normative reasons are. But I’m quite unsympathetic to the (more
narrowly‐speaking) desire‐based view about what reasons there are. I firmly
believe we have reasons, especially moral reasons, to do many things we have no
desire to do, and even when we do desire to do these things, our reason to do them
isn’t that doing them will satisfy our desires. There are moral reasons that apply to
all of us, regardless of what we happen to desire.
Does the internalist account of what reasons are entail that there are no such
reasons – and that we have no reason to do what we don’t want to do? It may look
obvious that it does, and that a bullet must be bitten somewhere, either in our
metaethical or in our first‐order moral theory. If having a reason depends on having
a relevant desire, and if desires differ from person to person, there seems to be no
basis for assuming that everyone has reason to be moral. But looks can be
deceiving, and the bullet may yet be avoided. It may be that the independently
4
plausible answers to the analytic and substantive questions are more compatible
than they at first appear. That, in any case, is what I hope to suggest. So after
defending the loosely‐speaking desire‐based account of what reasons are, I will
argue, in the second half of this book, that it doesn’t commit us to a problematically
desire‐based account of what reasons there are. In other words, I will try to provide
an internalist defense of universal, or categorical, moral reasons.
If such a defense is available, then, I will suggest, what appeared to be a
weakness of the internalist account of reasons may turn out to be its greatest
strength. One of the appealing features of the internalist analysis of reasons is, as I
will argue in Chapter 3, that it offers us something non‐question‐begging to say in
defense of our reasons ascriptions – a kind of “Archimedean point” (to borrow a
phrase from Bernard Williams) against which we can brace ourselves in disputes
about reasons. The internalist defends her claims about what someone has reason
to do by appealing to that person’s own commitments.
Moral philosophers have long been concerned about how to respond to the
amoralist – the person who recognizes what morality requires of him, but wonders
why he should do what morality requires. The moral ought, this amoralist might
concede, is certainly about him – it refers to him. But it doesn’t follow merely from
this that it has a proper, normative hold on him (whatever that comes to), any more
than the fact that the dictates of some old‐fashioned religion refer to me – a religion
that in no way reflects what I care about – entails that I have any real reason to
comply with them. Because internalist accounts of reasons ground reasons in facts
5
about our desires, broadly understood, an internalist defense of moral reasons may
allow us to provide a more satisfying answer to the amoralist. Or so I will argue.
1.2 The analytic question
I’ve been characterizing internalism about reasons as a “loosely‐speaking
desire‐based account” of what reasons for action are, according to which our having
a reason to perform some action depends on our having some desire that
performing the action will help us satisfy. But I should begin to speak less loosely.
The essential feature of an internalist account of reasons is that it ties the truth of a
reasons claim to the presence of a suitable element in what Bernard Williams called
the agent’s motivational set: “the set of his desires, evaluations, attitudes, projects,
and so on.”4
The loose formulation I have been working with is too loose in at least two
ways. Firstly, not all and not only our desires give us reasons. Not all of our desires
give us reasons because unjustified false beliefs or bad reasoning can give us desires
we have no reason to fulfill. And not only our desires give us reasons, because we
value and act for the sake of many things we can’t properly be said to desire,
because they aren’t the kinds of ends we could achieve or come to possess; for
example, we often act for the sake of other people. Our “motivational set” contains
everything for the sake of which we act, everything we pursue, promote, protect,
and respect.
4
Williams, Bernard, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame”, p. 35.
6
Secondly, and relatedly, linking what we have reason to do with what
satisfies our desires suggests that reason plays a purely instrumental role. I’ll follow
Williams, however, in allowing for the possibility that we have reason to act in ways
that serve our ends non‐instrumentally—perhaps the action in question is
constitutive of some end or commitment, or expresses that commitment.5
Internalism about reasons might be generally formulated as the view that
what we have reason to do depends fundamentally on what ends, understood in this
broad way, we already have. It follows from the internalist picture that if we are
rational relative to our ends (broadly understood), then we are rational, all things
considered. On the externalist view, defended, for example, by Derek Parfit, what
reasons we have need be in no way connected to the ends that we in fact hold.
It may be helpful to take a particular spelling‐out of the internalist thesis as a
starting‐point (it will not be our ending‐point). Williams’ formulation of the view
has been influential. According to Williams’ version of internalism, for some agent A
to have a reason to perform some action φ, that action must be related to A’s
“motivational set” in a particular way. Specifically, Williams says, it must be the case
that “A could reach the conclusion that he should φ...by a sound deliberative route
from the motivations that he has in his actual motivational set—that is, the set of his
desires, evaluations, attitudes, projects, and so on.”6 Put in an over‐simplified way,
an internal interpretation of reasons is one that takes an agent A to have a reason to
φ only if A would after procedurally rational deliberation have some end the
5
Williams, “Internal and External Reasons,” p. 104.
6
Williams, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame”, p. 35.
7
attainment of which will be served by his φ‐ing.7 (Remember that Williams
understands both the notion of an end and that of serving an end quite broadly.)
One element of following a “sound deliberative route” is, according to
Williams, possessing the relevant information. In this way he allows that an agent
who is otherwise deliberating rationally may have a reason of which she is unaware,
or may think she has a reason that she in fact does not have. Williams is here
describing what might be called “objective reasons.” Roughly speaking, his view is
that we have objective reason to do whatever we would be motivated to do if we
were deliberating procedurally rationally and were fully informed. The reason I
have to jump out the window of the building I’m in to escape a fire of which I have
no evidence provides one example.
There is, however, a second class of internal reasons that we can call
“subjective reasons.” Consider the reason I have to jump out the window when I
have a justified false belief that the building is on fire. Because I would not be
motivated to jump out the window if I were fully informed, we need to supplement
the conception of a reason just discussed with one that does not build the full
information requirement into the notion of a sound deliberative route. Roughly
speaking, we have subjective reason to do whatever we would be motivated to do if
7
Williams, “Internal and External Reasons”, p. 101. In “Internal and External Reasons,” Williams
states the internalist thesis as a biconditional: “A has a reason to φ iff A has some desire the
satisfaction of which will be served by his φ‐ing.” (Williams later qualifies this simple statement of
the thesis to allow that desires based on false beliefs or bad reasoning aren’t reason‐giving (pp. 102‐
103).) In “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame,” Williams explicitly defends only the “only if”
half of this biconditional – the claim that connection to the agent’s motivations is a necessary
condition for her having a reason – though he notes that he thinks the sufficiency half of the claim is
also true (pp. 35‐36).
8
we were deliberating soundly from our current epistemic position. The two classes
of reasons intersect—for example, the reason I have to escape through the window
when I know or ought to know the building is on fire is both an objective and a
subjective reason. But each class also contains some reasons not found in the other.
Both objective and subjective reasons are, on this account, internal reasons: they
link facts about what reasons we have to facts about our existing motivations.
It’s plausible that we are morally obligated to do only what we have sufficient
evidence to believe it would be best to do, not what it would (in fact) be best to do.
For example, a doctor is morally obligated to prescribe the course of treatment her
evidence tells her is most likely to cure her patient, not the treatment that (against
all evidence) happens to be best; if all the evidence suggests that I need penicillin,
and my doctor has no evidence that I’m allergic, she fails to fulfill her obligations if
she refuses me penicillin, even if it turns out I am allergic. So the reasons grounding
moral obligations are subjective reasons. (Unless I specify otherwise, I will, in what
follows, use “reason” to refer to subjective reasons.)
So according to Williams’ version of internalism: a consideration can be a
reason for me to φ only if it would motivate me to φ if I were deliberating in a
procedurally rational way from my antecedent ends.
I should dispatch an initial worry by making a clarification. Derek Parfit has
distinguished (as I did above) between analytic and substantive versions of the
internalist thesis. He finds the substantive version of the internalist thesis no more
appealing than I find it. But, Parfit worries, if the internalist thesis is intended to
state an analytic truth, then it merely stipulates a definition of the internalists’ term
9
“reason,” and so states a “concealed tautology.” In that case, he argues, internalists
and externalists may simply be talking past one another when they argue about
what reasons are and what reasons people have, as their use of the word “reason”
may be merely homonymous. Here the real dispute, as Parfit later suggests, is about
which sense of “reason” is the important one: the one that interests us, for example,
when we are discussing what ought to be done (Parfit goes on to call analytic
internal reason claims “true but trivial”).8
My own view is that the internalist thesis should be read neither as
stipulating a definition nor as making a substantive normative claim about what we
have reason to do. Instead, it makes a claim about what it is for some fact to be a
reason in a sense of “reason” that is shared by both internalists and externalists,
according to which a reason is simply a consideration that counts in favor of doing
something.
I don’t deny that some internalists explicitly defend internalism as true in
virtue of meaning. Williams sometimes seems to argue for this view in “Internal and
External Reasons.” Even these internalists aren’t stipulating a definition of “reason”,
as Parfit suggests. Rather, they’re defending a view about how a particular English
word, one used synonymously by internalists and externalists, is defined.9
8
Parfit, On What Matters, Volume Two, pp. 275‐277. See also Volume One, p. 72.
9
9 An exception here is Kate Manne, whose “Internalism About Reasons: Sad But True” argues that
there may be multiple common and useful senses of the term “reason,” at least one of which is
distinctively subjectivist. Manne allows that the general idea of a consideration counting in favor of
an action may be broader than the distinctively subjectivist concept of a reason, but thinks that
general idea elides some important distinctions.
10
Parfit might concede this is what such internalists think of themselves as
doing, but he finds the internalist account of what our shared word means deeply
implausible: how could his own meaning be so hidden from him? That is why he
has begun to suspect internalists and externalists of talking past each other – fooled
into thinking they’re discussing the same topic by a homonym. But I’m not
interested in defending internalism as a thesis about how “reason” is defined or what
our reasons‐claims mean. Instead, I’m interested in defending internalism as a thesis
about what reasons are.
Understood in this way, the internalist thesis represents an analysis not in
the linguistic sense that philosophers often have in mind, but rather in the sense
that is more familiar from chemistry – the sense, for example, in which water has
been analyzed as bonded hydrogen and oxygen. Similarly, internalism aims to
provide an informative account of what property the property of being a reason –
the property of being a consideration that counts in favor of something – is identical
to. It need not aim to provide a rival theory of what we mean by the term “reason,”
any more than the theory that water is bonded hydrogen and oxygen represented an
attempt to explain what we meant by the term “water.” Parfit may be right that the
meaning of his terms could not be so hidden from him; but history has taught us that
the fundamental nature of the things our terms pick out often is hidden from us.10
Parfit might resist this analogy. He might reply that the pre‐theoretical concept water had “an
explicit gap that [was] waiting to be filled”, and so was, in a sense, crying out for further analysis: that
even our pre‐theoretical concept of water was of some substance – whatever it is – that runs in our
streams and fills our lakes and oceans and falls from the sky and is odorless, colorless, and potable,
etc. Reason, he might say, is not ‘gappy’ in this way. Parfit makes precisely this move in rejecting
reductive naturalist utilitarian accounts of rightness; rightness, he says, is not gappy in the way that
our pre‐theoretical concept of heat left a gap – that property, whatever it is, that causes water to boil,
(continued on next page)
10
11
So analyses in this sense can, like the analysis of water as H2O, be surprising;
and they needn’t strike us as obviously true once we hear them. (This can be true
even of non‐empirical analyses, as the venerable philosophical debate about the
correct analysis of knowledge brings out.) But analyses that are too surprising
threaten to eliminate their object. Consider an “analysis” of mermaids that shows
them to be manatees, or an investigation of the monster under the bed that shows it
to be my big brother.11 Parfit, naturally, might worry that if the internalist analysis
of reasons proves to be the right one, that’ll amount to showing that reasons as he
took them to be don’t exist after all. Indeed, some versions of reasons‐internalism
strike me as eliminativist in just this way. Some reductive naturalist versions of
internalism, for example, take normative reasons to be facts that would motivate us
if we attended to them.12 According to these theories, there are no irreducibly
normative reasons: normative‐reasons‐ascriptions report purely psychological
facts.
This view may have the virtue of side‐stepping some of metaphysical
mysteriousness that seems to cling to the idea of a normative reason. But I share
Parfit’s suspicion that the reasons‐theorist who “analyzes” normative reasons in this
and certain sensations in us, etc. – before scientists discovered it to be molecular kinetic energy. (On
What Matters, Volume Two, pp. 301‐302.) But I am much less confident than Parfit seems to be in
our ability to recognize which of our concepts are or aren’t gappy – candidates for further reduction
or analysis. It’s not at all clear to me, for example, that heat would have struck me, pre‐theoretically,
as gappy. (I am, however, much more sympathetic with Parfit’s view that some proposed reductive
analyses, such as naturalistic reductions of normative concepts, threaten to eliminate their objects, as
I go on to discuss above.)
11 Parfit offers the example of an analysis of God that determines that God is simply the love some
people feel for others. (Ibid., pp. 304‐305.)
12
W.D. Falk, for example, defends a version of this claim in “’Ought’ and Motivation.” See p. 116.
12
way has changed the subject. When I ascribe a normative reason to someone, I am
not merely saying that certain considerations would cause her to act in some way, if
she were to attend to them. I am saying those considerations count in favor of her
acting in that way. I am not merely making a prediction about how she will act, or
would act under other circumstances. I am holding her to a normative standard she
can fail to live up to. I am saying that if she is not motivated accordingly, she has
gone wrong – acted irrationally.
But non‐reductive versions of internalism, like Williams’, do not seem to me
to raise the same eliminativist worries that reductive versions raise. Williams’ thesis
does not equate reasons with merely psychological properties, and it appeals to a
genuinely normative standard – the standard of procedural rationality. This
normative standard and psychological facts about the agent’s antecedent ends
jointly determine her reasons.13 On Williams’ view, the person who fails to be
motivated by her reasons has gone wrong: she has failed to deliberate soundly.
Some externalists have found the account of reasons we’re considering
unsatisfactory in a different way. Although the non‐reductive internalist account of
reasons recognizes reasons to be irreducibly normative, and does not equate
reasons with merely psychological facts, Parfit has suggested that even the non‐
reductive internalist concept of a reason is not relevantly normative. Employing that
concept may, according to Parfit, allow us to make genuinely normative claims
“about which ways of deliberating are procedurally rational, and in other ways
13
Similarly, if I believe that at least some of my reasons for belief are jointly determined by facts
about what I already believe and by the (genuinely normative) rules of inference, my account of the
nature of these reasons won’t reduce them to merely psychological facts.
13
ideal.” But it would not allow us to make any genuinely normative claims “about
reasons, or about what we should or ought to choose, or to do.”14
And indeed, it may seem unsatisfying to suggest that someone who has failed
to act as she has a moral reason to act is merely guilty of a procedural irrationality –
like an error in logic, say. Someone who acts wrongly seems to be doing something
more – something worse – the behaving irrationally. So the even the non‐reductive
internalist account of reasons we’re considering here might seem too reductive. But
it seems to me that whether the internalist account of normative reasons is too
reductive, or not relevantly normative, will depend very much on the details of the
view, and on what failing to live up to the normative standard it establishes can look
like. This worry should, therefore, be postponed until the real work of developing
the internalist analysis of reasons is behind us.
1.3 The threat of relativism
There are, I have said, ways of going wrong with respect to our reasons, on
the internalist view. Most obviously, if I’m deliberating soundly from my existing
ends and motivations, I will take the means necessary to achieving them (or, if I’m
not willing to, abandon the end in question). I’m procedurally irrational if I intend
to catch the 6 o’clock train home, know that it takes me 10 minutes to reach the
station, and still haven’t left my office by 5:50. I have an (internal) reason to leave
my office to which I am failing to respond. If internalism is right, we can have
14
Parfit, On What Matters, Volume Two, pp. 285‐288.
14
reason to do certain things given that we have certain ends, whether or not we do
them.
But what if we’re missing the relevant ends? Internalists have traditionally
turned to Hume to underwrite their view that the scope of the normativity of
practical reason does not extend to the adoption of our most fundamental ends.
“Reason alone can never be a motive to any action of the will,” Hume insists. He
goes on to explain:
Where . . . objects themselves do not effect us, their connexion [of
effect to cause, which reason makes evident to us] can never give
them any influence; and ’tis plain, that as reason is nothing but the
discovery of this connexion, it cannot be by its means that the objects
are able to affect us.15
Hume is talking here about the scope of the motivating force of reason. But
his skepticism about the possibility that reason could motivate us to adopt new ends
is due to his views about the limits of the scope of the normative force of reason.16
Reason doesn’t motivate us to adopt new ends because recommending new ends –
ends that aren’t derived from our old ones – is not part of its job description: Hume
identified practical reason as nothing but the discovery of the connection of effect to
cause, and thereby confined it to playing an instrumental role.17 This is why he says,
15 Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, pp. 413‐414 (II, 3, iii).
16 As Christine Korsgaard has argued: she points out in “Skepticism about Practical Reason”
(reprinted in Creating the Kingdom of Ends) that Hume’s “motivational skepticism” – doubts about
the scope of reason as a motive – derives from his “content skepticism” – doubts about whether
principles of reason have any content that could give substantive guidance to choice and action. See
especially Creating the Kingdom of Ends, pp. 311‐314.
17 Some scholars (notably David Millgram) have argued that Hume rejected even instrumentalism
about practical reason, in favor of a more thoroughgoing skepticism, but I will set this (and other)
questions of textual interpretation of Hume aside. (See Millgram, “Was Hume a Humean?,” especially
§1.)
15
elsewhere, that “the ultimate ends of human actions can never, in any case, be
accounted for by reason, but recommend themselves entirely to the sentiments and
affections of mankind,”18 and famously concludes: “Reason is, and ought only to be,
the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and
obey them.”19
The task of reason is to recognize the appropriate means to take to achieve
our ends, and to transfer motivational force from our ends to those means. That is, if
we are motivated to pursue the ends, we should be motivated to pursue the means.
If our reasoning faculty is performing this task then we are behaving rationally. And
if, furthermore, our deliberative process does not stumble over any false beliefs or
informational gaps, we will not fail to act on the reasons that apply to us, regardless
of the ends we start out with.
Williams more or less agrees:
The internalist proposal sticks with its Humean origins to the extent
of making correction of fact and reasoning part of the notion of ‘a
sound deliberative route to this act’ but not, from the outside,
prudential and moral considerations.20
So on both Williams’ and Hume’s accounts, the scope of the normativity of
internal reasons extends to corrections of instrumental reasoning, but does not
necessarily extend to prudential and moral concerns, since whether we have reason
18 Hume, Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals,
(hereafter, “Enquiry”), p. 293 (Second Enquiry, Appendix I), emphasis in the original.
19
Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, p. 415 (II, 3, iii).
20
Williams, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame,” pp. 36‐38. Williams adds, “To the extent
that the agent already has prudential and moral considerations in his S, of course, they will be
involved in what he has a reason to do. They will contribute to an internal reason.”
16
to pursue our own good or the interests of others will depend on what we care
about going in. Thus Hume has infamously written of prudence,
’Tis [not] contrary to reason to prefer even my own acknowledg’d
lesser good to my greater,21
and of morality,
’Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole
world to the scratching of my finger.22
Although Williams points out (as Hume certainly allowed) that the motivational sets
of most agents do in fact contain prudential ends and moral commitments, and even
more have ends to the achievement of which prudential and moral behavior is
instrumental – he essentially agrees with Hume. He writes of the prudential case,
If an agent really is uninterested in pursuing what he needs; and this
is not the product of false belief; and he could not reach any such
motive from motives he has by the kind of deliberative processes we
have discussed; then I think we do have to say that in the internal
sense he indeed has no reason to pursue these things.23
And he reaches a similar conclusion in the moral case, as his discussion of the
following example brings out:
Suppose, for instance, I think someone (I use ‘ought’ in an unspecific
way here) ought to be nicer to his wife. I say, ‘You have a reason to be
nicer to her’. He says, ‘What reason?’ I say, ‘Because she is your wife.’
He says—and he is a very hard case—‘I don’t care. Don’t you
understand? I really do not care.’ I try various things on him, and try
to involve him in this business; and I find that he really is a hard case:
there is nothing in his motivational set that gives him a reason to be
nicer to his wife as things are.
There are many things I can say about or to this man: that he is
ungrateful, inconsiderate, hard, sexist, nasty, selfish, brutal, and many
21
Hume, p. 415 (II, 3, iii).
22
Ibid.
23
Williams, “Internal and External Reasons”, p. 105.
17
other disadvantageous things. … There is one specific thing the
external reasons theorist wants me to say, that the man has a reason
to be nicer.24
And this, Williams concedes, the internalist about reasons cannot claim. To put the
point more finely, the internalist cannot even say of the cruel husband that he ought
to be nicer to his wife without abandoning the plausible tie between what a person
ought to do and what he has reason to do.
Williams is not the only internalist willing to bite one of these bullets.
Philippa Foot’s internalism led her to reject the claim that everyone need have
reason to do as morality requires, and as a result, to reject the connection between
what we ought to do and what we have reason to do.25 (I’ll return to that possibility
in the next section.) And Gilbert Harman has famously taken the truth of
internalism to imply a kind of moral relativism. In “Moral Relativism Defended,”
Harman argues (first) that moral ought judgments (at least judgments of the form “A
ought to f” or “It’s wrong of A to f”) imply the existence of moral reasons; (second)
that such reasons must be rooted in the goals, desires, or intentions of the subject of
such judgments, so that a rational and fully informed agent would be motivated to
accept the moral principle to which the judgment appeals; and (third) that a rational
agent may fail to have the relevant desires and ends underlying any particular moral
24
Williams, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame”, p. 39.
See Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” in Virtues and Vices. Foot’s views on
the relationship between reasons and ends changed over the course of her career.
25
18
principle, and so fail to have the reasons the corresponding judgment ascribes to
him.26
Harman concludes that it would be false to say of cannibals that they ought
not to eat a stranded ship‐wreck survivor, false to say of a contented assassin
employee of Murder, Inc. that he ought not to kill his next victim, and even false to
say of Hitler (assuming that his value system differed in sufficiently dramatic ways
from ours) that he ought not to have ordered the extermination of the Jews.
Derivatively, Harman thinks we can’t say of any of these agents that they were wrong
to act as they did.27
Harman’s chosen bullet is moral relativism. His conclusions strike me as
unacceptable. If we are to avoid them, we seem to be left facing the following
dilemma: either we must, like Foot, give up on the tie between ‘ought’‐claims and
reasons, or we must abandon internalism about reasons.
26
Harman, Gilbert, “Moral Relativism Defended,” particularly pp. 3‐11. Also see Harman’s “What is
Moral Relativism?” (especially pp. 152‐159), and “Is There a Single True Morality?” Harman’s
version of moral relativism is actually quite complex. Because he introduces it as a kind of relativism
of social agreement, it might easily be mistaken for a version of normative cultural relativism,
according to which what we ought to do depends on the norms accepted by our social group. The
internalist version of relativism that I describe above, by contrast, looks much more individualistic.
As Harman’s argument makes clear, however, he is moved to adopt relativism on internalist grounds.
The element of the group’s normative commitments is introduced, I believe, by the way Harman
distinguishes moral reasons from non‐moral reasons: Harman says we have moral reason to do
something if we intend to do it on the understanding that others have the same intention. (See “Moral
Relativism Defended,” pp. 11‐12.)
27
Harman, “Moral Relativism Defended,” pp. 5‐8.
19
1.4 ‘Ought’ and reasons
In “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives”28, Philippa Foot
distinguishes between two different “uses” of “ought” in judgments about what
others ought to do: the hypothetical use, which presupposes that the subject of the
judgment has a desire or interest, broadly understood, that would be served by his
doing as we judge he ought; and the categorical use, which makes no such
presupposition. For example, when we say someone “ought to leave now, to catch
the 6 o’clock train”, we presume that she wants to be on that train. If we learn she is
really headed somewhere else, we withdraw the judgment. But moral judgments
aren’t like that: we don’t, for example, withdraw our judgment that Hitler ought not
have issued his terrible orders when we learn that they fit perfectly into his plans.
Should we conclude that, since “ought” entails “has (conclusive) reason to”,
everyone has reason to be moral, regardless of their contingent ends and desires?
Foot argues no. After all, she argues, we find the categorical use of “ought” in cases
where we should clearly not conclude that categorical – universal – reasons follow.
Her example is the “ought” of etiquette: we would not withdraw the judgment that
invitations issued in the third person ought to be answered in the third person if we
learn that someone has no interest in this sort of propriety. But we would never
conclude, on this basis, that everyone has reason to be proper in this way. Despite
the categorical form of the “ought” of etiquette, Foot says, someone might
28
Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” pp. 157‐173.
20
reasonably wonder whether he has reason to do as he oughtE, and that question, she
suggests, must be answered in the usual way, by looking at the agent’s ends.
Foot sees no grounds for thinking the moral case is any different:
The fact is that the man who rejects morality because he sees no
reason to obey its rules can be convicted of villainy but not of
inconsistency. Nor will his action necessarily be irrational. Irrational
actions are those in which a man in some way defeats his own
purposes, doing what is calculated to be disadvantageous or to
frustrate his ends. Immorality does not necessarily involve any such
thing. It is obvious that the normative character of moral judgment
does not guarantee its reason‐giving force.29
Could this be the solution to our dilemma? Can we avoid troubling relativist
conclusions like those Harman draws by insisting that the moral “ought” applies to
an agent independently of his reasons?
Williams, at times, seems to be suggesting something like this. In “Ought and
moral obligation” he argues for a distinction between the moral and the “practical or
deliberative” sense of ought: the latter, but not the former, necessarily entails that
the agent has reason, in the internal sense, to do as we say he ought. If we discover
that he does not aim to do so, and furthermore, that there is no sound deliberative
route to that aim from any end he does have, we must withdraw our statement.
Williams concludes that “an agent can consistently recognize that he is under a
moral obligation to do a certain thing, yet conclude in his deliberation that he ought
not to do that thing”, where the final “ought” is the ought of practical reason.30
29
Ibid., pp. 161‐162.
30
Williams, “Ought and moral obligation”, in Moral Luck, p. 120.
21
Williams, like Foot, thinks that not much is lost by this concession. “What
weight or content is there in the thought that some [moral] obligation applies to [an
agent who refuses to respond to it]?”, he asks:
The statement of obligation certainly refers to him, but that obvious
truth does not capture the thought. Moreover, if he does not care
about these considerations, then the commentators will feel that he
ought to care about them. That distinguishes the obligations from
some other oughts … but it does not ultimately provide any more
‘hold’ over the agent, since whatever question arises for the first ought
must also arise about this second one. Beyond those facts, however,
there are no more – except the rage, frustration, sorrow, and fear of
someone who sees someone else blandly doing what the first person
morally thinks they ought not to be doing. In some sense, this critic
deeply wants this ought to stick to the agent; but the only glue there is
for this purpose is social and psychological.31
This glue, Williams suggests, is all we should be looking for. The issue is not
whether our wrong‐doer has normative reasons to act better, but whether we can,
by any means, trigger his reformation.
The externalist, he acknowledges, wants more. She wants to express, with
the judgment that an agent, regardless of his ends, morally ought to do something,
the thought that there is an ‘external reason’ for him to do so: “[t]his would seek to
‘stick’ the ought to the agent by presenting him as irrational if he ignored it, in a
sense in which he is certainly concerned to be rational.” But, Williams says,
I doubt very much, in fact, whether this proposal does capture what
the ordinary moral consciousness wants from the ought of moral
obligation, as opposed to something read into it by a rationalistic
theoretical construct.32
31
Ibid., p. 122.
32
Ibid, pp. 122‐123.
22
What’s more, Williams thinks that even if we abandon this ambition, we still
have plenty of arrows of moral criticism in our quiver. After imagining the cruel
husband who, he has conceded, may have no reason to be nicer to his wife, Williams
writes:
There are many things I can say about or to this man: that he is
ungrateful, inconsiderate, hard, sexist, nasty, selfish, brutal, and many
other disadvantageous things. … There is one specific thing the
external reasons theorist wants me to say, that the man has a reason
to be nicer. … But if [this form of words] is thought to be appropriate,
what is supposed to make it appropriate, as opposed to (or in addition
to) all those other things that may be said? The question is: what is
the difference supposed to be between saying that the agent has a
reason to act more considerately, and saying one of the many other
things we can say to people whose behaviour does not accord with
what you think it should be? As, for instance, that it would be better if
they acted otherwise.33
According to Williams, the claim that the man in his example has reason to be
nicer is either simply false (if we accept the internalist picture) or hopelessly
obscure (if we try to adopt the externalist one). Moreover, the restriction of our
responses in the case of the cruel husband to the other expressions of moral
condemnation that Williams lists does not result, Williams seems to be suggesting,
in an important loss of meaning. These expressions are perfectly sufficient to
express the view that the man ought morally to be nicer to his wife.
And Harman, too, makes a very similar move, as a way of softening his
relativist conclusions. There may be some moral‐ought judgments we can make of
Hitler and his fellow villains, he suggests, if they are moral‐ought‐judgments that
don’t entail reasons‐claims. He says, for example, that perhaps we can say that
33
Williams, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame”, pp. 39‐40.
23
Hitler ought not to have issued his order if we mean no more by this than that it was
a terrible thing that he did so – just as we might say that cancer ought not to kill so
many people, meaning it’s terrible that so many people die of the disease; in making
this judgment we are, of course, imputing no reasons to cancer. 34
But we clearly mean more than this when we judge that Hitler acted wrongly.
And, as Harman himself acknowledges, even this use of ‘ought’ does not seem quite
natural unless there is someone who ought – in the reasons‐implying sense – have
done something to stop the harm in question. He approvingly cites Thomas Nagel’s
observation that the claim that a certain hurricane ought not have killed so many
people usually implies the absences of safety or evacuation procedures the
authorities ought to have provided.35 Ought, that is, in the reason‐implying sense.
(This is certainly what we meant when we made this judgment about Hurricane
Katrina.) In the cancer case, the ‘ought’‐formulation seems most natural if we think,
for example, that our government should be putting more funding into cancer
research or screening. In Hitler’s case, too, our readiness to make ought‐judgments
reveals our recognition of the presence of reasons. But Hitler is not like cancer or a
hurricane. When we say that Hitler ought not to have ordered the extermination of
the Jews, we don’t, of course, just mean that someone (else) ought to have prevented
him from doing so. We would make this judgment about Hitler’s actions even if no
34
Harman, “Moral Relativism Defended,” p. 6. Harman suggests that some other kinds of moral
judgments might also not entail anything about an agent’s reasons – he seems to allow, for example,
that Hitler’s actions were evil. (See p. 5) But it’s unclear why Harman allows himself this judgment –
after all, the judgment that Hitler’s actions were evil surely entails that it was wrong of him to
perform them, and that he (morally) ought not to have done so. I raise a related worry about
Williams’ similar response below.
35
See ibid., especially note 2.
24
one (else) had been in a position to prevent them. The reasons we are imputing we
are imputing to Hitler himself.
Nagel’s observation helps bring out the extent to which our ordinary use of
“ought” (or “should”) – including the moral one – is bound up with reasons‐claims:
reasons seem to be lurking in the background even in uses of “ought” that appear to
describe non‐rational subjects. And (as Foot would acknowledge) in many non‐
moral cases, “ought” seems to mean something very close to “has most reason to.”
Consider the instrumental “ought”: “she ought to use a Phillips screwdriver;”36 or
the “ought” of expectation: “he ought to have arrived by now”, which might be
parsed as “we have sufficient reason to expect him to have arrived by now.” Why
think the moral ought behaves differently?37
We should, I think, be very reluctant to cut the tie between moral‐ought
claims or other forms of moral assessment and reasons‐ascriptions. It is worth
remembering that the sense of “reason” at issue here is not some narrow, technical
one, but rather the perfectly ordinary sense that, I’ve said, internalists and
externalists share, according to which a reason is simply a consideration that counts
in favor of an action. It’s actually less easy than Foot’s discussion suggests to hear
even the “ought” of etiquette as having no implication for an agent’s reasons – most
36
Another example of Williams’ (from “‘Ought’, ‘Must’, and the Needs of Morality” (unpublished,
2002)).
37
As Harman notes elsewhere, understanding the moral “ought”‐claims as claims about agents’
reasons also helps makes sense of the fact, emphasized by W.D. Ross, that we use “ought” in two ways
– to express what Ross calls prima facie “oughts” (as we do, e.g., when we say “One ought to keep
one’s promises”), and to express all‐things‐considered “oughts.” The prima facie “ought” signifies the
presence of a reason to act in a certain way (a reason pointed toward, for example, by the true moral
principle about promise‐keeping), whereas the all‐things‐considered use of “ought” indicates the
direction the balance of all reasons tips. (Harman, “Reasons,” pp. 8‐10.)
25
speakers who would say something like “you ought to begin eating with the
outermost fork” assume that conforming with the rules of etiquette is something
you have reason to do. It may be possible for a speaker, by means of the right set‐up
and intonation, to cancel the implication: “you’re supposed to use the outside fork
first, but you should really to use whichever fork you like.” But such uses of “ought”
and “are supposed to” seem more descriptive than normative – they merely report
the requirements spelled out by certain rules, without taking those requirements to
be considerations actually counting in favor of anything. Indeed, the switch from
“you ought to” or “you should” to the (to me) much more comfortable‐sounding
“you’re supposed to” in cases like this is a tell‐tale sign that we’ve moved away from
normative talk here. “You’re supposed to” is a passive formulation: it feels more
comfortable, when the speaker is communicating the verdict of norms she doesn’t
embrace, because it allows her to report the verdict of those norms descriptively, as
endorsed by others, without endorsing them herself.
Clearly, moral judgments aren’t like this: when we say, of Williams’ cruel
husband, that he ought to be kinder to his wife, we aren’t just reporting that some
widely accepted standard of behavior requires it; we are condemning him. In any
case, reducing the force of moral‐ought claims to the kind of descriptive force
evinced by etiquette‐judgments seems a terribly unsatisfactory way for anyone with
anti‐relativist moral intuitions to avoid Harman’s relativist conclusions.
This brings us back to Williams’ question, asked rhetorically, perhaps, but
deserving of an answer nonetheless:
[W]hat is the difference supposed to be between saying that the [cruel
husband] has a reason to act more considerately, and saying one of
26
the many other things we can say to people whose behaviour does not
accord with what you think it should be?
What gets lost if we concede that our moral language does not imply anything about
the reasons of the agents we judge?
The first answer to this question is one that Williams himself provides.
Williams is certainly right that it would be better if the cruel husband acted
otherwise, just as it would be better if cancer killed fewer people, and better, too, if
Hitler had killed fewer people. But as I’ve said, we react very differently to the
cancer epidemic than to the Holocaust. We deeply regret deaths caused by cancer;
we wish the disease were less deadly, more susceptible to a cure. But we don’t just
regret the deaths Hitler caused; we blame Hitler for them.38
Williams offers an account of blame that is in keeping with his internalist
commitments. He concedes that blaming someone for an action is appropriate only
in cases where that person can be said to have some reason to act differently. But
this doesn’t mean, he says, that we can only blame people who already share our
moral commitments. There are two kinds of circumstances, he argues, in which it is
appropriate for us to blame people who act in ways that violate our moral
commitments. First, they may have acted in ways that violate some commitment in
their own motivational set – a commitment they share with us. These are the easy
cases. But just as importantly, he argues, we often blame people who may lack the
38
Blame is the impersonal counterpart to the “personal reactive attitude” of resentment discussed by
Peter Strawson. Here I am agreement with Strawson about the kinds of circumstances that would
make such resentment (or blame) inappropriate: ignorance, cumpulsion, accident. Williams’ “hard
cases” do not act in ignorance, or under compulsion, or accidentally. See Strawson, “Freedom and
Resentment.”
27
relevant commitment, provided they have, instead, a desire to avoid our
disapproval. Our very act of blaming, then, gives them a reason not to act in this way
which they would not have had had their act not registered our disapproval.
Williams continues:
Focused blame, then, involves treating the person who is blamed like
someone who had a reason to do the right thing but did not do it. It
does not typically register simply a deliberative failure at the time, but
rather, in varying strengths, the kinds of proleptic mechanism I have
sketched. Of course, there are some hard cases, people who lie
beyond any such mechanism; and it is a support for an account on
these lines, that it is precisely people who are regarded as lacking any
general disposition to respect the reactions of others that we cease to
blame, and regard as hopeless or dangerous characters rather than
thinking that blame is appropriate to them. This represents the
absence from their [motivational set] of anything that can be reached
by these mechanisms, anything it might even be hoped could yield
recognition.39
But this pragmatic account seems to me to not to capture our practice of blaming.
Unless we consider these “unreachable” people—the “hard cases”—to be
fundamentally irrational (in essence, not guilty by reason of insanity)—and it is
precisely this characterization of such people that Williams wants to reject—we
think them just as deserving of blame, if not more so, as people who are more
responsive to the opinions of others.40 If Williams is right, and such people really
have no reason to act differently, then blaming them becomes inappropriate. So
here, then, is one thing we seem to lose by giving up on the link between moral
39
Williams, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame”, pp. 42‐43.
40
Note that on Williams’ view, blame becomes inappropriate as soon as the proleptic mechanism
fails – that is, as soon as our bad judgment would fail to motivate the agent in question. We needn’t
imagine this recalcitrant agent as someone who is totally immune to the judgments of all others ‐
just as someone immune to our negative judgment. It seems to me that we blame a lot of people who
don’t care what we think of them.
28
judgments and reasons‐ascriptions: the tie between wrong‐doing and
blameworthiness seems severed, too.
The discussion of etiquette‐judgments, above, suggests an additional answer
to Williams’ question: what gets lost when we cut the tie between moral judgments
and reasons‐ascriptions is the objective normativity we intend our moral judgments
to have.
Williams claims that even the internalist can say of the cruel husband that he
is “ungrateful, inconsiderate, hard, sexist, nasty, selfish, brutal.” But these words, as
Williams of course recognized, have normative as well as descriptive components.
In calling the man cruel, I mean more that he is willing to cause his wife to suffer to
no purpose. I mean that his doing so is unjustified. On Williams’ view, as on Foot’s,
this further, supposedly normative element of my judgment simply reports the fact
that the man’s actions conflict with my own commitments – that, for example, I
would have reason to be nicer to his wife, were I in his shoes (given the elements in
my motivational set), and that I do have reason to wish he’d be nicer. The Williams‐
internalist makes no claim, of course, to the universal authority of those
commitments. Williams’ account seems to avoid the threat of a Harman‐style agent‐
relativism only by falling into a kind of appraiser‐relativism instead: the judgment
that the cruel husband acts wrongly is true, on this reading, when his actions conflict
with the (contingent) moral commitments of the person making the judgment.
Williams’ internalist account of reasons is, of course, inspired by Hume. But
Hume is more open‐eyed than Williams about the extent to which limiting reason to
a procedural role threatens to constrain our ability to make moral judgments. Moral
29
judgments, Hume says, unlike, for example, judgments about what had better, from
my perspective, occur, purport to have objective, or at least intersubjective, validity.
He draws the contrast this way:
When a man denominates another as his enemy, his rival, his
antagonist, his adversary, he is understood to speak the language of
self‐love, and to express sentiments, peculiar to himself, and arising
from his particular circumstances and situation. But when he bestows
on any man the epithets of vicious or odious or depraved, he then
speaks another language, and expresses sentiments, in which he
expects all his audience are to concur with him. He must here,
therefore, depart from his private and particular situation, and must
choose a point of view, common to him with others; he must move
some universal principle of the human frame, and touch a string to
which all mankind have an accord and sympathy.41
Making a moral judgment in the absence of a true internal‐reason ascription is not
an option, according to Hume. Indeed, moral judgments, on Hume’s view, implicitly
appeal to universally shared internal reasons.
Hume, of course, does not succumb, as a result, to total skepticism about
morality. He argues instead that there is (at least, as he puts it, “while the human
heart is compounded of the same elements as at present”) an item that is common
to the motivational sets of all people, which can therefore form the foundation of an
intersubjectively valid moral code. All people, Hume says, in fact care about social
stability and the public good, at least to some extent; since this, he says, is the only
thing all people care about, any moral judgment, or expression of moral approval or
disapproval, must be built on this foundation – must attach to actions which
promote or undermine the public good: “this affection of humanity, … being
41
Hume, Equiry, p. 272 (Second Enquiry, IX, i), emphasis in the original.
30
common to all men, … can alone be the foundation of morals, or of any general
system of blame or praise.”42 This is why Hume leans towards utilitarianism.
While Hume is optimistic that there is something – the public good – we all in
fact value, which can underwrite some universally prescriptive moral judgment, he
seems to take this to be largely a contingent matter. He certainly doesn’t think, as
we’ve seen, that we’re rationally required to value the public good. (Recall his
earlier admonition: “’Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the
whole world to the scratching of my finger.”) If someone does not value the public
good (and not because of a failure of information or means‐end reasoning), then, it
seems to follow from Hume’s view, we cannot claim that promoting the public good
is something we ought, morally, to do. Hume takes moral relativism to be an
untenable position – morality is, on his view, conceptually universalistic. If he is
right, then internalism seems to threaten to lead not to moral relativism but to moral
nihilism.
Unfortunately, Hume’s optimism seems unwarranted: it appears that there
are people who do not value the public good, and not because of any obvious
ignorance or instrumental irrationality. But Hume is, I think, on the right track. The
compatibility of internalism about reasons with universal moral truths hinges not
on the rejection of the link between moral requirements and reasons but on the
discovery of some end that all procedurally rational agents share, which can form
the foundation of morality. Whether there is any such end will be the subject of the
42
Ibid.
31
second half of this book. But first, a simpler solution must be assessed: we can
avoid the threat of moral relativism and hold on to the link between what we ought
to do and what we have reason to do by rejecting the internalist account of reasons.
Perhaps what we have reason to do does not, after all, depend on our desires,
broadly understood. Why should we accept internalism about reasons?
32
Chapter 2
Internalism and the Motivating Intuition
2.1 Two arguments for internalism
Internalist theses, of which Bernard Williams’ is a leading example, describe
a necessary relation between an agent’s having a reason and some other, broadly‐
speaking motivational, fact about the agent. So, for example, internalists might
claim that an agent can have a reason to perform some act only if he has a relevant
desire, or only if he would be motivated to perform it in suitably idealized
circumstances, such as the conditions of procedural rationality. Why should we
accept internalism about reasons?
I’ll begin by exploring the thought, appealed to by Williams and often cited in
support of internalism, that reasons must be capable of explaining action: it must be
possible for a fact that is a reason for an agent to act to be the reason he acts – the
reason that motivates him. I’ll call this the Motivating Intuition. As I will argue, it
represents a key step in Williams’ argument for internalism. And indeed (as I will
try to show), the Motivating Intuition has much to be said for it. The problem is that
versions of internalism that reflect the Motivating Intuition are vulnerable to
numerous counterexamples, and that attempts to revise the internalist thesis to
avoid these counterexamples introduce a divide between normative reasons and
possible explanations of action. The result is that workable versions of internalist
theses lose the support of the Motivating Intuition, and so begin to appear
unmotivated. But the same counterexamples that forced the modification of
internalist theses, and others, should also lead us to reconsider the Motivating
33
Intuition itself. Indeed, I will argue in this chapter that we should reject the
Motivating Intuition, and that examples of reasons we have to act which cannot, or
should not, be the reasons why we act are in fact quite common.
Where does this leave internalism? If the Motivating Intuition is misguided,
should we reject the internalist thesis? Are there any other grounds for thinking
there is a necessary connection between facts about our reasons and facts about our
current motivational profile? In the next chapter, I will argue that there are.
The first argument. Williams’ argument for internalism about reasons in his
seminal article “Internal and External Reasons” seems to begin from the assumption
that the concept of a reason is the concept of a consideration that could explain the
actions of a rational agent. Williams thinks that when we say someone has a reason
to φ, what we mean is that he would be motivated to φ if he were rational. Though
this claim is sometimes presented as the internalists’ conclusion, it is in fact is the
starting point of Williams’ argument. (For example, Williams claims that an external
reasons statement (not just an internal reasons statement) “implies that a rational
agent would be motivated to act appropriately.”43) He then points out that it’s easy
enough to see what it would take for an internal reasons statement to be true of an
agent. If A has an internal reason to φ, this means that A would be motivated to φ if
he deliberated in a procedurally rational way from his existing ends and motivations
(that’s the internalist part), and it’s easy enough to see why such procedurally
rational deliberation might give rise to a new motivation, derived from one of the
43
Williams, “Internal and External Reasons,” p. 109.
34
old ones. It’s no mystery, Williams suggests, to see how an internal reason might
serve to explain the actions of an agent who deliberates rationally.
It’s much harder, Williams argues, to understand what it would take for an
external reasons statement to be true of an agent. Because if claiming that an agent
has a reason to φ amounts to claiming that he would be motivated to φ if he were
rational, and if claiming the reason is external amounts to claiming that it does not
apply to the agent in virtue of any of his existing motivations, then the external
reasons theorist must explain how it could be true of the agent that a process of
rational deliberation would motivate him to φ, despite the fact that, by hypothesis,
he need have no existing motivations from which the new motivation to φ could be
derived. And Williams finds it hard to imagine a process of rational deliberation
that could give rise to a motivation to act, but not by taking any existing motivations
as a starting‐point.
Williams considers the possibility that an external reason could explain the
action of the agent whose reason it is, provided the agent is rational, by means of the
agent’s coming to believe he has the reason act. Rational agents, after all, will form
true beliefs about their reasons, and will be motivated to do as they believe they
have reason to do, so if an agent comes to believe an external reason to φ applies to
him, then if he is rational he will be motivated to φ, regardless of his former
motivations. And this, the thought is, is enough to establish the truth of the external
reasons claim.
An example might make this possibility clearer. The external reasons
theorist will want to claim that Jim has a reason to give to charity, say, regardless of
35
whether he has any desire, broadly understood, which might give rise, after
procedurally rational deliberation, to a motivation to give to charity. That is to say,
Jim has an external reason to give to charity. But if Williams is right about what all
reasons claims (including external reasons claims) must mean, then this statement
amounts to the claim that Jim would be motivated to give to charity if he were
rational, regardless of his actual motivations. How could that be true? The
suggestion under consideration is that the external reasons claim is true because, if
Jim were rational, he would recognize that he has reason to give to charity, and
(because he is rational) this recognition would motivate him to do so (regardless of
his prior motivations).
But, Williams asks, what would Jim’s “recognition” amount to? If, again,
Williams is right about our concept of a reason, it would have to amount to the
recognition, on Jim’s part, that he would be motivated to give to charity if he were
rational (regardless of his existing motivations). It is a true belief in this proposition
that is supposed to trigger in the rational Jim a motivation to give to charity. But
now we do seem to have put the cart before the horse. After all, we were trying to
determine how that proposition could be true. It doesn’t seem to help to say that it
can be true, because if it were true, and rational Jim therefore believed it and was
motivated accordingly, then it would be true. So, Williams concludes, we can make
sense of the idea of a normative reason, which Williams says, just is the idea of a
consideration that would motivate a rational agent, only if we accept his version of
the internalist thesis: that an agent can have a reason to perform some action only if
36
he could be motivated to perform it by following a sound deliberative route from his
existing ends and motivations.
The second argument. Some of the central claims of Williams’ defense of
internalism sow the seeds of another argument Williams himself does not make, but
that is often attributed to internalists.44 This argument begins from something like
Williams’ conceptual claim about reasons: “It must be a mistake,” Williams writes,
“to simply separate explanatory and normative reasons. If it is true that A has a
reason to f, then it must be possible that he should f for that reason; and if he does
act for that reason, then that reason will be the explanation of his acting.” Similarly,
the first premise of this second argument claims:
(1)
It must be possible for me to be motivated by the reasons that
apply to me. So a consideration can be a reason for me to φ
only if it can motivate me to φ.
A second premise also looks familiar:
(2)
A consideration can motivate me to φ only if it is relevantly
connected to my “motivational set”—that is, only if it would
motivate me to φ if I were deliberating in a procedurally
rational way from my existing ends and motivations.
The internalist conclusion follows from these premises:
(3)
Therefore, a consideration can be a reason for me to φ only if it
would motivate me to φ if I were deliberating in a procedurally
rational way from my existing ends and motivations.
What should we make of this argument? One question it raises immediately
is whether the notion of possibility at work in premise (1) is plausibly the same as
Thomas Nagel offers it on behalf of internalism in The Possibility of Altruism (p. 27), although he
rejects one of the premises.
44
37
the notion of possibility at work in premise (2), as it must be if the argument is to go
through. The ‘can’ in premise (2) suggests psychological possibility: it identifies the
conditions under which an agent who begins with a particular psychological profile
might be motivated to perform some action. Is this also a plausible interpretation of
the ‘can’ at work in premise (1)? Is it plausibly a conceptual constraint on when a
consideration can count as a reason for an agent that there are circumstances in
which that agent, burdened, at least at the outset, with his actual psychological
profile, might be motivated by that consideration to act? If we take seriously
Williams’ claim that our concept of a reason is the concept of a conditional
explanation of the actions of the agent for whom it is a reason, then this does strike
me as a reasonable way of interpreting the argument’s first premise. And the
premise seems to gain some support from the ought‐implies‐can principle: it’s very
plausible that we ought to be motivated by the reasons that apply to us, so it’s also
plausible that it must be psychologically possible for us to be motivated by those
reasons.
The second premise raises some additional worries. It looks like a version of
what is sometimes called the Humean Theory of Motivation. Recall Hume’s
contention:
Where…objects themselves do not effect us, their connexion [of effect
to cause, which reason makes evident to us] can never give them any
influence; and ‘tis plain, that as reason is nothing but the discovery of
this connexion, it cannot be by its means that the objects are able to
affect us.
He continues:
…[R]eason alone can never produce any action, or give rise to
volition.... … Nothing can oppose or retard the influence of passion,
38
but a contrary impulse. … Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of
the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve
and obey them. 45
In its crudest form, the Humean Theory of Motivation claims that all motivation
depends on a relevant antecedent desire. The argument I’ve outlined refines this
thesis in one important respect: it expands the set of attitudes that can ground
motivation to include more that just desires (narrowly understood). Williams,
recall, makes clear that he agents’ “motivational sets” to include, in addition to
straightforward desires, “such things as dispositions of evaluation, patterns of
emotional reaction, personal loyalties, and various projects, as they may be
abstractly called, embodying commitments of the agent.”46
Even so, the second premise of the argument is controversial at best. It looks
to be making an empirical assertion about psychology—an assertion about what
kinds of mental events can trigger the formation of new motivations—without
backing it up with empirical research (never a promising strategy in philosophical
argument). Why should we believe that the formation of a belief never triggers the
formation of a new motivation? 47 After all, even a knock on the head could do that.
But we might again revise the premise to make it more plausible. Alfred
Mele, for example, defends a view he calls the “antecedent motivation theory” and
attributes to Hume. He writes:
in actual human beings, all motivation nonaccidentally produced by
practical reasoning issuing in a belief favoring a course of action
45
Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, pp. 414‐15 (II, 3, iii).
46
Williams, “Internal and External Reasons,” p. 105.
47
I.e., one not derived from our existing motivations.
39
derives at least partly from motivation‐encompassing attitudes
already present in the agent before he acquires the belief.48
Mele allows that beliefs might sometimes motivate, but claims that reasoning can
motivate us non‐accidentally only on the back of an antecedent motivation.49
It is not obvious how we are to understand the notion of non‐accidental
motivation, but it is possible that if we spell that notion out, and adjust our first
premise accordingly, a version of the above argument for internalism may still go
through. We might interpret the idea of practical reasoning non‐accidentally
producing motivation in terms of rational motivation – motivation that drives us
when and because we are rational. If we amend the premises of the internalist
argument accordingly, it reads:
(1*)
It must be possible for me to be rationally motivated by the
reasons that apply to me. So a consideration can be a reason
for me to φ only if it can rationally motivate me to φ: that is,
motivate me to φ when and because I am rational.
(2*)
A consideration can rationally motivate me to φ only if it is
relevantly connected to my “motivational set”—that is, only if
it would motivate me to φ if I were deliberating in a
procedurally rational way from my existing ends and
motivations.
(3*)
Therefore, a consideration can be a reason for me to φ only if it
would motivate me to φ if I were deliberating in a procedurally
rational way from my existing ends and motivations.
48
Alfred Mele, Motivation and Agency, p. 89.
49
Mele contrasts this view with the “cognitive engine theory,” which asserts:
in actual human beings, some instances of practical evaluative reasoning, in or by
issuing in a belief favoring a course of action, nonaccidentally produce motivation
that does not derive at all from antecedent motivation. (p. 89)
40
Our new premise (1*) stays true to the intuition from which we began – that
a reasons‐statement – even a normative reasons statement – must still be able to
serve as an explanation. After all, it was never the internalist’s claim that any
normative reason will serve as the actual explanation of the actions of the agent to
whom it applies, since agents frequently fail to act as they have reason to act,
whether because of ignorance or poor judgment or weakness of will. Rather,
internalists appeal to the intuition that reasons should explain our actions when
things go well – when we’re not subject to such irrationalities. Reasons must be able
to explain how we act when and because we are rational.
And consider the support the premise got from the ought‐implies‐can
principle. I suggested earlier that premise (1) was plausible because it is entailed by
ought‐implies‐can and another plausible claim: that we ought to be motivated by the
reasons that apply to us. But it seems that we can plausibly claim more than this:
it’s better to be rationally responsive to our reasons than to be merely accidentally
motivated by them. In other words, we ought to be not just motivated by our
reasons, but rationally motivated by them.
Our new premise (2*) also improves upon the old premise (2). It no longer
makes overreaching empirical claims about the conditions under which motivation
of any kind is possible. And it sticks closer to its Humean origins in its focus on the
role Reason can play in generating motivation. (3*) is identical to (3): our two new
premises issue in the internalist conclusion as surely as the original ones did.
41
2.2 Motivating intuitions
Fleshing out the second argument for internalism along these lines brings out
a striking similarity between this argument and the argument for internalism that
Bernard Williams actually makes in “Internal and External Reasons.” For it is now
clear that the central premises driving both arguments are the same: both rely, first,
on the claim that a consideration could be a reason for me to act only if it would
motivate me to act if I was rational, and second on the claim that no process of
rational deliberation could produce in me a new motivation to act except by taking
my existing motivations as a starting‐point. Nonetheless, the arguments – at least
their first central premises – are powered by different intuitions. Williams takes his
first premise to be supported by intuitions about what our reasons statements
mean. The second argument’s first premise is supported by appeal to a conceptual
connection between reasons (even normative reasons) and action‐explanations, and
also, I have suggested, by a plausible assumption about how we ought to be
motivated, taken together with the ought‐implies‐can principle.
The arguments’ second central premise – the Humean one – has been the
chief focus of the philosophical disagreement about the nature of reasons for action.
Defenders of internalism about reasons have touted their theory’s ability to reflect
the myriad intuitions captured by the arguments’ first premise: that practical
reasons must be capable of motivating rational agents. Externalists have defended
their view by attempting to block the implication from that first premise to the
internalists’ conclusion, largely by attacking the Humean Theory of Motivation in its
42
various forms. But the first premise itself, and the intuitions underlying it, have
received less scrutiny.
In this chapter, I will describe in detail some of the varied intuitions that
might be taken to support the claim that it must be possible for us to be motivated
by the reasons that apply to us, at least if we are rational. Then I will describe a
series of counterexamples intended to undermine our confidence in that premise:
reasons to act that cannot, or should not, motivate us to act are, I will argue, quite
common. But, I will argue in the next chapter, this should not lead us to abandon
internalism. Some of the intuitions that were taken to support the internalists’ first
premise might nonetheless provide some direct support for a version of internalism
that does not rely on that premise. And this version of internalism has more to be
said for it. Because this version of internalism does not rely on the Humean Theory
of Motivation, it may also be better‐placed to withstand the externalist attack.
So: why might one think that some consideration cannot be a reason for us
to act unless it could motivate us to act, and would do so if we were rational? I
touched on some of the reasons for thinking this in setting out the two arguments
for internalism above. I’ll begin with the intuition about the meaning of our reasons
statements that, I have suggested, is the driving force behind the first argument for
internalism – the one Williams actually makes explicitly. Why does Williams think
that the conception of reasons as facts that would motivate us if we were rational is
one that internalists and externalists share? Williams writes:
There are of course many things that a speaker may say to one who is
not disposed to φ when the speaker thinks that he should be, as that
he is inconsiderate, or cruel, or selfish, or imprudent; or that things,
and he, would be a lot nicer if he were so motivated. Any of these can
43
be sensible things to say. But one who makes a great deal out of
putting the criticism in the form of an external reason statement
seems concerned to say that what is particularly wrong with the agent
is that he is irrational. It is this theorist who particularly needs to
make this charge precise: in particular, because he wants any rational
agent, as such, to acknowledge the requirement to do the thing in
question.50
The whole point of ascribing a reason to someone, either internal or external,
Williams thinks, is to make clear to them that if they fail to act accordingly, they are
failing by their own lights – they are failing to live up to a standard whose
bindingness on them they must themselves, as rational agents, acknowledge: the
standard of rationality. This is what makes such a charge different from saying
merely that it would be better if they acted this way, or that we would wish them to
do so, or would do so in their place. The shared etymology of reason and rationality
is no accident. (Williams’ claim is that on this understanding of what reasons
statements mean, only internal reasons statements can be true.) As I argued in the
last chapter, reasons statements aim at objectivity, or at least inter‐subjectivity, and
they add something to our arsenal only if we can use them, in this way, to appeal to
the requirements of this shared standard.51
Williams’ claim about what our reasons statements mean is backed up by an
additional claim about the conceptual link between reasons and explanation. It is no
accident of etymology that we use the same word, “reason”, to describe both the
50
Williams, “Internal and External Reasons,” p. 110.
As I argue in Chapter 1 (§1.4), my own view is that thick moral concepts like cruel or selfish also
aim at objectivity – and so can be appropriately applied only when a reason‐ascription is also
appropriate. The charge of selfishness, for example, does not merely imply that the selfish person is
more protective of her own interests that we would like her to be, say, or than is normal, but rather
that she is more protective of her own interests than she has reason to be.
51
44
grounds on which we act (sometimes called motivating reasons), and the reasons
for us to act (sometimes call normative reasons). In both cases, Williams suggests,
reasons statements explain action: motivating reasons explain why we actually act
the way we do, and normative reasons statements explain how we would act if all
went well – if we did not succumb to weakness of will, or confusion, or ignorance, or
poor judgment: if, in other words, we were rational.
So, Williams takes it to be a conceptual truth about reasons that they are the
considerations that would move good practical reasoners. This certainly seems
plausible, and it is reinforced by a claim that is often made about practical reasons:
that they must be action‐guiding. Reasons, the thought is, are not purposeless: they
guide us in how to behave. But a reason that could not motivate us, even if we were
perfect practical reasoners, could not play this action‐guiding role. So all reasons
must be capable of motivating us insofar as we are reasoning well.
Michael Smith has called the claim that “what we have normative reason to
do is what we would desire to do if we were fully rational” a “platitude” about
practical reasons. He argues that it follows naturally from considering what is
involved in identifying our reasons: from how we should go about deciding what to
do. When we deliberate about how to act, he says, we ask for advice. But we don’t
ask just anyone for advice; we look for advice from people who are better situated
than we are to know what we should do – who are better informed, and more
rational, and less subject to our weaknesses of will – but who know us, and what
drives us, well. In other words, Smith suggests, suitably idealized, we are ourselves
best placed to give ourselves advice. When we look for our reasons, what we want
45
to know is how we would act if we were better placed than we actually are: if we
were fully rational.52
Then there is the claim that I appealed to in support of the second argument
for internalism, above. Surely, we ought to be motivated by any reason that applies
to us – indeed, we ought to be so motivated when and because we are rational.
Since ought implies can, it must follow that we can be motivated by any reason that
applies to us, when we are rational. This thought becomes all the more forceful if
we accept the very plausible claim that virtue is a matter of motivational
responsiveness to practical reasons.53 For if we accept that thought, but deny that
we ought always to be responsive to our reasons, then we are denying that we ought
always to be virtuous.
The power of reasons to motivate rational agents might also help explain
another fact that is often comes up in the literature on internalism about reasons:
that rational agents are reliably motivated to act as they judge they have reason to
act. If considerations that provide reasons themselves have the power to motivate
rational agents, this fact is neatly explained: rational agents are motivated to act by
their judgment that they have reason to act because rational agents’ judgments
about their reasons are true, and are the discovery of facts that themselves have the
power to motivate those agents when they are rational.
52
Michael Smith, The Moral Problem, pp. 150‐151.
53
For defenses of this claim, see, e.g., my “Acting for the Right Reasons,” and Nomy Arpaly’s
Unprincipled Virtue.
46
Finally, some philosophers have appealed to a somewhat more nebulous idea
in support of the claim that our normative reasons must be capable of motivating us,
at least when we are rational. They have suggested that a conception of reasons that
allows that we might have reasons that could get no motivational grip on us, even
when we’re reasoning as we should, would unacceptably alienate us from our
reasons. Peter Railton has made a point like this as part of a defense of an
internalist account of an agent’s good: “it would be an intolerably alienated
conception of someone’s good,” he writes, “to imagine that it may fail in any way to
engage him.”54 It’s appealing to think something similar may be true of our reasons
more generally. As Williams and others have argued, it may be a limiting condition
on our moral obligations that they somehow reflect what drives us.55 And there
must be something about the reasons for me to act that makes them mine. Shouldn’t
it be a requirement on some consideration’s providing me with a reason to φ that I
can appeal to it to justify myself when I do φ? But I can appeal to such a
consideration honestly only if it was one of the (motivating) reasons I did φ. If a
consideration can’t motivate me to φ, than how can I point to it to justify myself for
having done so?
Taken together, these considerations provide compelling support for the
claim that reasons must be capable of motivating the agents to whose reasons they
54
Peter Railton, “Facts and Values,” p. 9.
55
As Williams puts it, “[t]here can come a point at which it is quite unreasonable for a man to give up,
in the name of the impartial good ordering of the world of moral agents, something which is a
condition of his having any interest in being around in the world at all.” (Williams, “Persons,
Character, and Morality,” in Moral Luck, p. 14.)
47
are, and will motivate them if they are rational. I will call this claim the Motivating
Intuition. As I have argued, the Motivating Intuition plays an essential role in at least
two important arguments for internalism about reasons. Unfortunately, as
examples will show, the Motivating Intuition is false.
2.3 Counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition
The counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition that I will describe fall into
several classes. The first, and most commonly discussed, class of counterexamples
encompasses reasons we have because we are not perfectly rational. Some of these
examples put pressure on the idea, which is reflected in part of the Motivating
Intuition, that how we should act is determined by how we would act if we were
more ideally rational than we are. Here are two such examples, both of which are, in
some version, familiar from the literature on internalism:
The student of reasoning. We surely have reason to take measures
to improve our ability to reason: we have reason, for example, to take
lessons in chess, or logic, and it is becoming increasingly common for
universities to require students to take courses in “reasoning and
critical thinking.” But if we were fully rational, we would not be
motivated to take any such measures.
Even if our reasoning ability itself is unexceptionable, lack of self‐control or
weakness of will can also present us with obstacles that we ought to take into
account:
The sore loser. A squash player, who, after suffering an
embarrassing defeat, rightly believes he will hit his opponent out of
anger if he does not leave the court immediately, surely has reason to
48
leave, although if he were fully rational, and so not weak‐willed, he
would be motivated instead to shake his opponent’s hand.56
As these examples bring out, facts about how we would act if we were ideally
rational can seem irrelevant to our actual, non‐ideal circumstances, in which we face
impediments that our perfectly rational counterparts do not. And we might wonder,
more generally, why we should care about the motivations of people who are, after
all, quite fundamentally different from us: what makes sense for Spock may make
no sense for Captain Kirk.
What can we learn from these examples? They suggest that the Motivating
Intuition, as I’ve stated it, is false; that (contra Smith) it is not, after all, a “platitude”
about practical reasons that what we have reason to do is what we would be
motivated to do if fully practically rational; and certainly that Williams’ claim about
what our reasons‐statements mean is mistaken: if we think someone has reason to
improve his reasoning skills, despite acknowledging that he would not be motivated
to do so if he were fully rational, we cannot plausibly mean by our reasons claim
that he would be motivated to improve his reasoning skills if he were fully rational.
Where does this leave internalism? Examples such as these show that a simple
version of the internalist formula, like the one that emerges as the conclusion of the
two influential internalist arguments I set out above, is guilty of the “conditional
fallacy.” Our reasons can’t be restricted to what we would be motivated to do if we
were perfectly procedurally rational – rational relative our existing ends and
motivations. If we were fully rational relative to our existing ends and motivations,
56
The example is due to Michael Smith (“Internal Reasons,” p. 111), who is elaborating on a character
introduced by Gary Watson.
49
we would not be motivated to do things like take chess or reasoning lessons, or
abruptly walk off the squash court to avoid instigating a fight. So many internalists,
Smith included, have replaced the simple internalist thesis with a more complicated
thesis that avoids the conditional fallacy: they have suggested, for example, that we
have reason to do what our fully procedurally rational counterparts would desire or
advise us to do in our actual situation.57
Responses of this kind have some virtues. They allow internalism to retain
the appeal to the shared standard of rationality that Williams considered so central
to understanding reasons claims. And they also retain the tie between reasons and
advice from a well‐placed advisor that Smith appealed to in support of the supposed
“platitude” about practical reasons. But Robert Johnson has argued that revisions
like this sacrifice the most appealing feature of internalism about reasons – its
accommodation of the intuition that a reason for an agent to act must be capable of
serving also as an explanation of how the agent acts, in the right circumstances:
Once one moves away from [simple internalism about reasons] in
such ways in order to avoid the conditional fallacy, an explanatory gap
opens up – in this case, between your better self desiring that you
should do something and you yourself being motivated to do it. The
gap opens because it may be impossible for the desire had by your
rationally ideal self to play any role in the explanation of your
actions.58
Johnson suggests that if internalists are to retain their advantage over
externalists, they must find a way of avoiding the conditional fallacy while
57
See, for example, Michael Smith, The Moral Problem, p. 151.
58
Robert N. Johnson, “Internal Reasons: Reply to Brady, Van Roojen and Gert,” p. 574. See also
Johnson, “Internal Reasons and the Conditional Fallacy”.
50
continuing to satisfy the “explanatory requirement” – the requirement that an
agent’s normative reasons be capable of explaining his actions, by serving as his
motivating reasons for acting. The two examples I’ve discussed so far do nothing to
undermine the force of that requirement: we can be motivated by the reasons we
have not to harm people to walk away instead of instigating a fight, and we can be
motivated by the reasons we have to improve our reasoning skills to take chess
lessons or courses in critical thinking, even if our ideally rational counterparts
would not be so motivated, and even though the desires they might have on our
behalf seem explanatorily irrelevant to how we act.
But as other counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition, including the
example on which Johnson himself focuses, show, the case for internalism about
reasons would not be strengthened by its satisfying the explanatory requirement,
because reasons need not be capable of motivating us, after all.
Let’s start with Johnson’s own example59:
“James Bond”. Let’s say I become convinced I am James Bond. The
fact that I am suffering from such a delusion may give me an excellent
reason to see a psychiatrist for treatment. But it cannot motivate me
to see the psychiatrist. For if this fact could motivate me to seek help,
I would no longer be convinced I was James Bond. Someone who
firmly believes he is James Bond cannot be motivated to seek a
psychiatrist by the fact that his belief is a delusion.
Johnson is right that the versions of internalism about reasons that are
revised to avoid the conditional fallacy must allow that “James Bond” has such a
reason, since it seems hard to deny that “James’s” perfectly rational counterpart
59
Johnson, “Internal Reasons: Reply to Brady, Van Roojen, and Gert,” p. 575.
51
would advise him to seek psychiatric help, or would wish that he’d (fortuitously)
seek help, were he to suddenly find himself in “James’s” less‐than‐ideal position.
And he is right that this shows that such revised versions of internalism do not
satisfy the explanatory requirement. But the “James Bond” example is as much a
counterexample to the explanatory requirement itself as it is to simple, unrevised
internalism. It suggests that internalists should perhaps not be trying to
accommodate the explanatory requirement in the first place.
The story of “James Bond” has the characteristic neatness and outlandishness
of a philosopher’s example. But I hope to demonstrate that cases of normative
reasons that cannot motivate the agents whose reasons they are are in fact quite
common and familiar. I’ll begin with an example from theoretical reasoning:
My Fallibility. I currently have some unjustified beliefs. Let’s call this
plausible proposition my fallibility. My current unjustified beliefs are
reasons for me to believe that I have some unjustified beliefs. But
they can’t be the reasons why I believe in my fallibility. Because if I
were convinced of my fallibility by the fact that I have those beliefs,
then I would no longer count as having them. For example, imagine
that I believe that Elvis is still alive, despite overwhelming good
evidence to the contrary. Call the fact that I believe Elvis lives BEL.
I’m aware of BEL, and BEL provides good evidence of my fallibility.
But I can’t be convinced of my fallibility by BEL. If I were, I wouldn’t
really count as believing that Elvis lives, and so BEL would not obtain
(and, of course, could no longer provide support for my fallibility).
Similarly (given that I believe Elvis lives), the fact that Elvis is dead
and this has been well‐documented (call this fact ED) provides me
with a good reason to believe in my fallibility. And I undoubtedly
ought to believe in my fallibility. But I can’t be justified in believing in
it by ED, because if I believed ED, I couldn’t really believe Elvis lives.
In which case ED would no longer provide support for my fallibility.
We might respond to this case by questioning whether the fact that I believe
that Elvis lives really gives me a reason to believe in my fallibility. But it clearly gives
52
you a reason to believe in my fallibility, if you have access to exactly the same
information as I have, both about Elvis and about my beliefs. And it would be
strange if a fact that provided you with a reason didn’t also provide me with a
reason, when you and I have access to the same evidence. Similarly, I’m not tempted
to conclude that, since I believe Elvis lives, ED isn’t really evidence I have for my
fallibility, and so isn’t a reason for me to believe in my fallibility. It seems
indisputable that I have reason to believe ED, and ED clearly establishes my
fallibility.
The examples I’ve discussed so far all involve reasons we have because we
are not perfectly rational. These reasons could not motivate us if we were fully
rational, because they would not apply to us if we were fully rational. But there are
other circumstances in which our reasons might not be capable of motivating us.
One interesting class of counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition concerns things
we have reason to do (and can do), but which we cannot do for those reasons. In a
paper investigating some apparent paradoxes of deterrence, Gregory Kavka
describes circumstances, which he calls “Special Deterrent Situations” (or SDSs), in
which agents would find themselves faced with reasons of this sort. An SDS arises
when we have reason to intend to apply a very harmful sanction, affecting many
innocent people, in retaliation for what would be a similarly extremely harmful and
unjust offense, because intending to apply such a sanction is the likeliest means of
deterring the offense. But, because the sanction is so harmful and its victims
innocent, we have no reason to actually apply the sanction should the offense
53
occur.60 Such circumstances are likely not just the stuff of philosophy papers: a
plausible real‐life SDS (which Kavka discusses) is provided by:
Nuclear Deterrence. Perhaps the most likely way to deter a nuclear
attack is to intend to retaliate against any attacking nation by
responding in kind.61 But if an attack should occur, no good could
come of actually retaliating. So if I am responsible for the defense
strategy of a nation threatened by nuclear attack, I have reason to
intend to retaliate against any such attack with a nuclear attack
targeting the aggressor. But I have no reason to actually retaliate.
Because of this I cannot be motivated to form the intention to retaliate
if I am fully rational: rational agents do not form intentions to act
against their own (correct) assessment of the balance of reasons. And
what’s more, they cannot intend to perform actions they know they
will not perform when the time for performance comes: if the nuclear
attack occurs, and I know I have conclusive reason not to retaliate, I
won’t retaliate. And since I know, now, that I won’t retaliate were an
attack to occur, I cannot intend to retaliate.
Kavka’s familiar Toxin Puzzle provides a similar, if more fanciful, example:
Toxin Puzzle. If I am offered a million dollars today to simply form
the intention tonight to drink a (non‐lethal, but ill‐making) toxin
tomorrow, I cannot (certainly not if I am rational) be motivated to
form the intention to drink the toxin by the reason (the million‐dollar
prize) I have to form it, since I know now that I will not need to drink
the toxin to win the prize, and so have no reason to drink the toxin,
and conclusive reason not to. When tomorrow rolls around, drinking
the toxin can make me no richer, and will make me considerably
sicker. So I would have to be very irrational to drink it. If I’m
resourceful, I may succeed in finding another way to motivate myself
to intend to drink the toxin (and to drink it) – for example, by betting
a friend a substantial sum of money that I will drink it; but in this case
I will not be motivated to form the intention by the original reason I
had to form it – that is, by the million‐dollar prize (though the prize
will have motivated me to make the bet).62
60
See Gregory Kavfa, “Some Paradoxes of Deterrence.”
61 Kavfa notes (citing Herman Kahn, On Thermonuclear Warfare, p. 185, and Anthony Kenny,
“Counterforce and Countervalue,” pp. 162‐164), that “writers on strategic policy frequently assert
that nuclear deterrence will be effective only if the defending nation really intend to retaliate.”
(Kavka, p. 278)
62
See Gregory Kavka, “The Toxin Puzzle,” pp. 33‐34.
54
The Toxin Puzzle and the problem of Nuclear Deterrence differ from the cases
I’ve already discussed: they do not turn on reasons that I have because I am not fully
rational. (If anything, the problems of motivation they bring to light afflict us
because we are, in a sense, prisoners of our own rationality.) The reasons I have to
intend to drink the toxin, or to intend to initiate a retaliatory attack, might not be
capable of motivating me even when I’m not fully rational. This is simply not how
the process of intention‐formation works. The forming of intentions to act is driven
by our motivations to perform the intended act. I cannot, through sheer force of
will, form an intention to do something I believe I have no reason to do, and
conclusive reason not to do, even if I believe I have reason to form the intention.
In being non‐voluntary in this way, intention‐formation resembles belief‐formation.
We cannot believe at will, simply because doing so would benefit us in some way,
when our perception of the balance of epistemic reasons tips the other way. So here
is another counterexample to the Motivating Intuition from the realm of reasons for
belief:
Pragmatic Belief. I may have overwhelming pragmatic reasons to
believe some proposition – perhaps that my disease is curable, if
optimism would make me more likely to recover. But I cannot believe
my disease is curable for that reason – I cannot be motivated to
believe this by the fact that believing it will increase my chances of
survival. Again, I may be able to bring myself to believe it by some
other means; but I cannot believe it for the only genuine reason I have
to believe it: my pragmatic reason.
Should we perhaps conclude that reasons such as these – reasons for
believing that are not generated by the believed proposition’s truth, or reasons for
intending that are not generated by the intended action’s value – are not genuine
55
reasons after all? I don’t think so. After all, it may be possible for me to get myself
to form the relevant intention or belief by other means: I might, in Toxin Puzzle (as I
suggested), make a bet with a friend that gives me reason to actually drink the toxin,
and so motivates me to form the intention to drink it; or I might, in Nuclear
Deterrence, encourage in myself the kind of jingoistic fervor that I know will reduce
my level of concern for the potential victims of a retaliatory attack to the point
where I could intend to retaliate; or I might, in Pragmatic Belief, purposefully seek
out medical opinions only from doctors with a reputation for optimism. If any of
these methods of manipulating my own beliefs and intentions have a chance of
success, I may have reason to undertake them. The very facts that could not
motivate me to form the relevant beliefs and intentions give me reasons to try to
bring it about that I form them in some other way. But it would be very strange if I
had a reason to bring it about that I believe or intend something I have no reason to
believe or intend. If I have no reason to believe or intend something, why trick
myself into doing so? In order to explain why we might sometimes have reasons to
manipulate ourselves in this way, we need to acknowledge that we can have reasons
to believe or intend something that cannot motivate us to believe or intend it. 63
63
Might I be misdescribing these cases? Are they really cases where our reasons to believe or intend
something can motivate us to believe or intend it, just indirectly? Maybe, for example, I count as
being motivated to intend to drink the toxin by the promise of the million‐dollar prize in virtue of the
promise of the prize’s serving as a second‐order motivation for me to be (first‐order) motivated by
something else – my bet with my friend, say – to intend to drink the toxin. If that’s right, this might
not be a counterexample to the Motivating Intuition after all.
But higher‐order motives don’t co‐motivate the acts motivated by the first‐order motives
that they target – at least not simply in virtue of functioning as higher‐order motives. Other cases
help bring this out. Consider, for example, a religious believer, who, from self‐interested motives
(she fears divine retribution) manages to turn herself (perhaps through particularly effective
counseling – let’s not worry too much about the details) into someone who is genuinely (and
noninstrumentally) motivated by the needs of others. Or consider a violent heavy drinker whose
(continued on next page)
56
As Kavka notes, SDSs also bring out the somewhat surprising conclusion
that we might sometimes have reason to corrupt ourselves – to bring about in
ourselves dispositions to act against the balance of moral reasons, or to fail to be
properly motivationally sensitive to some moral reasons. An agent faced with a
genuine SDS, like Nuclear Deterrence, ought (if she can) to bring it about that she
forms the deterrent intention – in this case, to retaliate – even though this means
she’ll have reduced her sensitivity to genuine moral reasons. This has important
implications for our consideration of the Motivating Intuition. In particular, it seems
to run counter to a thought which played an important role in our defense of the
Motivating Intuition: that we ought always to be as virtuous as we can be, and
therefore, since it’s plausible that being virtuous is a matter of being appropriately
motivationally sensitive to our moral reasons, that we ought always be motivated by
the reasons that apply to us. This thought, I argued, underlies the crucial first
premise of the second argument for internalism I set out in §2.1. But as Kavka’s
SDSs show, we sometimes have reasons to lessen our own sensitivity to reasons.
In Nuclear Deterrence and Pragmatic Belief we may have reason to corrupt
ourselves because unless we do, we will not be able to form intentions or beliefs we
have good reason to form. In Nuclear Deterrence, the problem arises because of the
wife threatens to leave him unless he starts acting out of (noninstrumental) concern for her
wellbeing, and who is motivated to stop drinking, not out of concern for his wife, but simply, and
selfishly, because he fears loneliness – knowing that getting sober will result in his becoming more
concerned for his wife for her own sake. It seems right to say, of both these people, that they are
morally better after their reformations than before, despite the self‐interested motives driving those
reformations. Though they may be motivated to develop good motives by selfish reasons, their
actions after their reformation do not seem to be motivated by self‐interest. And just as their higher‐
order selfish motivating reasons should not be seen as co‐motivating the actions motivated by the
first‐order motives the selfish ones targeted, so my higher‐order motivating reasons to acquire a
motivation to intend to drink the toxin should not be seen as co‐motivating that intention.
57
partly involuntary nature of intention‐formation: we cannot, at will, form the
intention to do something we believe we have no reason to do. And cases where we
have reason to intend to do something we have no reason to do may be quite rare.
But the problem for the Motivating Intuition in fact much broader than the example
of SDSs suggests. It is in fact surprisingly often true that we ought not to be
motivated by reasons that apply to us.
Usually, when it is true that we ought not be motivated by our reasons, this is
because we are more likely to succeed at doing what we have reason to do if we
aren’t motivated by those reasons.64 A particularly grim version of this problem is
faced by soldiers fighting in a justifiable war. The military historian Richard
Holmes, who interviewed veterans of many wars, describes the problem faced by
the soldier this way:
[a] soldier who constantly reflected upon the knee‐smashing, widow‐
making characteristics of his weapon, or who always thought of the
enemy as a man exactly like himself, doing much the same task and
subjected to exactly the same stresses and strains, would find it
difficult to operate effectively in battle. … Without the creation of
abstract images of the enemy, and without the depersonalization of
the enemy during training, battle would become impossible to sustain.
64
We can design science‐fictiony cases to show that it might be possible for an agent to find herself in
a situations where she cannot successfully do what she has reason to do if she is motivated by that
reason. Phillip Stratton‐Lake describes the following example:
Consider a world in which there is an omnipotent, evil demon whose aim is to stop
good people from doing what they should in the light of the normative reasons why
they should so act.... He achieves this by making it the case that if a good person
ever acts from the normative reasons why she should so act, he will make it such
that this action is wrong, and he tells them this. Every good person knows,
therefore, that she cannot do the right thing from the normative reasons why this is
right. For they know that if they are motivated to act in this way, then their actions
will be morally wrong. (Kant, Duty, and Moral Worth, p. 18.)
In Stratton‐Lake’s evil‐demon world, we cannot do what we have reason to do for that reason,
because the demon will ensure that the actions of well‐motivated people bring about horrific
consequences. But it doesn’t follow that we can’t do what we have reason to do.
58
… If … men reflect too deeply upon their enemy’s common humanity,
then they risk being unable to proceed with a task whose aims may be
eminently just and legitimate.65
This might be so even if the “enemy’s common humanity” underlies the
justification for the war itself, and so provides a fundamental reason for fighting.
That is:
Soldier in a Just War. In a war fought on humanitarian grounds,
soldiers may have reason to desensitize themselves to the common
humanity of the inhabitants of an enemy state so that they can more
effectively fight a war whose very justification is provided by that
common humanity. If they have reason to fight in the war, and fight
effectively, then they ought not be motivated to fight by that reason.66
Pragmatic grounds not to be motivated by the reasons that apply to us are often
generated when we are forced to act in emergency situations and against great
odds, a fact that was strikingly demonstrated by post‐crash interviews of Captain
Chelsey Sullenberger, the US Airways pilot who miraculously succeeded in landing a
commercial jetliner with no working engines on New York’s Hudson River,
improbably saving the lives of all 155 passengers and crew on board:
65 Richard Holmes, Acts of War: The Behaviour of Men in Battle, p. 361. Soldiers in war also use the
expression “tango down” to indicate that a hostile human “target” has been eliminated (“tango”
represents the “t” in “target”), whereas they use the expression “man down” when one of their own
fellow soldiers has been hit. See the online dictionary Wiktionary, (“Appendix: Glossary of military
slang”, under “T”, URL: http://en.wiktionary.org/wiki/Appendix:Military_slang#T, accessed August
18, 2010).
66
I don’t want to suggest that such desensitization is easy to justify or usually justified. Indeed, the
fact, described by Holmes, that soldiers often must be desensitized in this way to be effective soldiers
is, I believe, one of the reasons why wars are hard to justify. Not only do wars require participants to
“corrupt” themselves to be effective soldiers (a cost with immediate and long‐term effects,for the
soldier as well as for others, that should not be underestimated), but the need for such self‐
corruption also creates a significant risk that soldiers will prosecute a potentially justifiable war in a
manner that makes it unjustified; as Holmes says, “if the abstract image [of the enemy, internalized
by soldiers in training] is overdrawn or depersonalization is stretched into hatred, the restraints on
human behavior in war are easily swept aside.” (p. 361)
59
Emergency Landing. On January 15th, 2009, Captain Sullenberger
successfully emergency‐landed an Airbus A320, which had lost all
thrust in both engines due to a double bird strike, in the icy waters of
the Hudson River, with no loss of life. Asked, in a 60 Minutes interview
by Katie Couric, whether he had been thinking about the passengers
as his plane was descending rapidly towards the Hudson, Captain
Sullenberger replied, “Not specifically. … I mean, I knew I had to solve
this problem. I knew I had to find a way out of this box I found myself
in. … My focus at that point was so intensely on the landing … I
thought of nothing else.”67
While the fact that many lives depended on his successfully landing the aircraft
undoubtedly provided Captain Sullenberger with a reason to do so, it is also clear
that it was a very good thing that the Captain was not in fact motivated by this
reason as he guided the plane onto the water. Indeed, it seems likely that years of
training in emergency preparedness coached the Captain, with good reason, not to
think about the ultimate reasons for successfully handling a crisis situation when
faced with the need to do so.
The lessons of Soldier in a Just War and Emergency Landing generalize. A
specialist in a rarely curable disease may be able to cure more patients if she’s in it
for the social prestige than if she’s in it chiefly to save lives, since her low success
rate might otherwise drive her to quit. A surgeon may operate more successfully if
she learns to suppress some normal sympathy for patients in unavoidable pain68,
and she may be less likely to make nervous mistakes in delicate procedures if she is
not thinking of the life that is at stake. In fact, many of us have found ourselves in
Katie Couric interviewed Captain Sullenberger on 60 Minutes, airdate February 8th, 2009, copyright
CBS News. A summary of the interview that includes the quoted passages can be found at:
http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2009/02/08/60minutes/main4783580_page2.shtml?tag=conten
tMain;contentBody (retrieved September 17th, 2009).
67
68
As Kavka also suggests – see “Some Paradoxes of Deterrence”, note 20, p. 278.
60
situations in which we were fortunate that we were driven by ulterior motives,
habit, instinct, or “auto‐pilot” rule‐following to make decisions or react to threats
which we would have likely reacted to less well if we had be responding
motivationally to our reasons for doing so. If a child runs into the street right in
front of my car, I hit the brakes automatically – I am not motivated by a concern for
the well‐being of the child. In a surprising number of cases, there is much to be said
for not being motivated by our reasons.
2.4 What These Counterexamples Can Teach Us
What can we learn from these counterexamples? Has anything survived of
the intuitions that supported the Motivating Intuition?
The examples of the Student of Reasoning and the Sore Loser show us that “A
has a reason to φ” cannot mean “A would be motivated to φ if she were rational,” as
Williams suggested, and that the Motivating Intuition does not state a “platitude”
about practical reason, as Smith suggested. We readily ascribe reasons to the
Student of Reasoning and the Sore Loser despite the fact that we are perfectly aware
that they would not be motivated to act on those reasons if they were perfectly
rational (because they would not have those reasons).
While the Student of Reasoning and the Sore Loser would not be motivated by
their reasons if they were perfectly rational (because the reasons would, in that
case, no longer apply), their reasons could nonetheless serve as explanations of
their actions in their actual circumstances – the circumstance in which they do
apply. So does the conceptual link between normative reasons and possible
61
explanations of actions, to which Williams also appeals, hold up? No: the examples
of the deluded “James Bond” and of My Fallibility show that we can have reasons for
both action and belief that could not possibly serve as explanations of our actions or
beliefs, even in the circumstances in which they do apply to us.
Moreover, the problem is not just a result of our imperfect rationality, as the
cases of the Student of Reasoning, the Sore Loser, “James Bond”, and My Fallibility
might suggest. The predicaments presented by Nuclear Deterrence, the Toxin Puzzle,
and the problem of Pragmatic Belief show that even if we’re fully rational, we might
have reasons to act or believe that could not motivate us to act or believe
accordingly. It won’t always be possible for us to do as we have reason to do, for the
reason we have to do it.
And finally, as the cases of the Soldier in a Just War and the Emergency
Landing show, and as our own experience will confirm, even when we can be
motivated to do something by the reason we have for doing it, it’s not always true
that we ought to be motivated by that reason. Sometimes, we are significantly more
effective in doing what we have reason to do if we train ourselves to be motivated
differently. If it’s not always true that we ought to be (rationally) motivated by the
reasons that apply to us, we cannot appeal to the ought‐implies‐can principle to
derive the conclusion that we can always be (rationally) motivated by the reasons
that apply to us.
Remember that the First Argument for internalism about reasons, the one
explicitly made by Williams in “Internal and External Reasons,” depended on the
claim that the Motivating Intuition captures what our reasons‐statements mean:
62
that what we mean when we ascribe a reason to φ to someone is that they would be
motivated to φ if they were rational. And remember my suggestion that the Second
Argument for internalism about reasons, which also includes the Motivating
Intuition as a premise, gained support from the ought‐implies‐can principle. As the
counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition show, both of these influential
arguments for internalism about reasons fail before we’ve even considered their
controversial Humean premises. If, as Williams and Johnson have suggested and as
structure of the debate about internalism implies, internalism’s ability to
accommodate the Motivating Intuition was its chief virtue, then considering the
counterexamples I’ve described should lead us to abandon internalism about
reasons.
But I don’t think we should abandon internalism. I believe internalism still
receives some direct support from some of the considerations to which I appealed in
defense of the Motivating Intuition in §2.2. And I believe we have other good
grounds for taking internalism about reasons seriously.
63
Chapter 3
Why Be An Internalist About Reasons?
3.1 Internalism without the Motivating Intuition
I’ve argued that Bernard Williams was wrong to present the Motivating
Intuition as an account of what our reasons‐statements mean. But a different
version of the internalist thesis may still receive some direct support from some of
the considerations that motivated the Motivating Intuition. Nonetheless, the simple
version of internalism with which I began – the version defended by Williams ‐ must
be false, since it entails the Motivating Intuition. A reason cannot be a consideration
that would motivate me if I were deliberating in a procedurally rational way from
my existing ends and motivations.
Remember that the essential feature of an internalist account of reasons is
that it ties the truth of a reasons claim to the presence of a suitable element in an
agent’s motivational set: according to internalism, what we have reason to do
depends fundamentally on what ends, broadly understood, we already have.
Externalism, by contrast, holds that facts about our reasons do not fundamentally
depend on facts about what we care about. The distinction is sometimes put
differently: internalism embraces a procedural conception of practical rationality,
according to which the rational requirement to hold certain ends is generated
indirectly by the relation of those ends to other ends we already hold, as a result, in
particular, of requirements of internal consistency and coherence. (One might
compare this to the case of theoretical reason, which may require us, by means of
64
standards of internal consistency and coherence, to hold certain beliefs in virtue of
their relationship to other beliefs that we hold.) According to an externalist,
substantive notion of rationality, reason may require us to hold some (moral and
prudential) ends directly, and regardless of what else is true about us.
These ways of thinking about the disagreement between internalists and
externalists make clear that the internalists’ claim about the necessary motivating
or explanatory power of reasons is not an essential feature of the view. Our reasons
may depend on our antecedent ends not because those ends are the source of the
(supposed) motivating force of normative reasons, but rather because those ends
are the source of the justifying force of those reasons. As the example of a non‐
motivating theoretical reason provided by My Fallibility shows, a consideration (in
that case – the fact that I have the unsupported belief that Elvis lives) can throw its
justificatory weight behind my performing or believing some action or proposition
(in that case, the proposition that I have some unjustified beliefs), even if it cannot
move me to perform the action, or convince me of the proposition.
According to the version of internalism about reasons for action that I am
most interested in defending,
a reason for an agent to φ is a consideration that counts in favor of φ‐
ing – that throws its justificatory weight behind φ−ing – in virtue of
the relation it shows φ−ing to stand in to the agent’s existing ends (for
example, by showing that φ−ing is a means to one of those ends, or
constitutive of it, or valuable in consequence of the value of that end).
This thesis is internalist, because it takes what we have reason to do to depend
fundamentally on what ends we already have. But unlike many internalist accounts
of reasons, my account does not rely on the claim that reasons must be capable of
65
motivating rational agents, or necessarily motivate agents who recognize them: on
this view, facts give us reasons when they are the source of a certain kind of evidence
(given our other ends), not when they are the source of a possible motivation (given
our other ends).
It may be helpful to think through how this version of internalism, unlike
Williams’, can recognize the reasons for action and belief I’ve appealed to as
counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition in the cases I’ve discussed. Take, for
example, the case of Captain Sullenberger: although the Captain should not and
perhaps could not have been motivated to take the necessary actions to land the
plane safely by the fact that over a hundred and fifty lives depended on his doing so,
it is clear that the fact that his taking those actions would save those lives was
evidence, relative to his antecedent value commitments, that taking the actions in
question would be a valuable thing to do. The value of that end, in other words – of
doing what was necessary to get the plan safely on the Hudson – was entailed by the
value of his other ends and the consistency and coherence requirements of
procedural rationality.
Similar arguments can be used to show that the soldier in my Just War
example has an internal reason (as I understand it) to fight effectively (provided by
the common humanity of the inhabitants of the enemy state); that the sick person in
my example of Pragmatic Belief has a (practical) internal reason to believe her
disease is curable (provided by the survival benefits of believing this); that I have an
internal reason to intend to drink the toxin when face with the Toxin Puzzle
(provided by fact that so intending will win me the million‐dollar prize); that the
66
defense strategist in Nuclear Deterrence has an internal reason to intend to retaliate
(provided by the deterrence benefits of the intention); that Johnson’s James‐Bond‐
delusional patient has an internal reason to see the psychiatrist (since, presumably,
it is one of his important ends that he not be deluded); that the Sore Loser has an
internal reason to leave the court without shaking hands (since this will prevent him
from punching his opponent); and that the Student of Reasoning has an internal
reason to take rationality‐improving lessons. In each case the agents have value‐
commitments that, taken together with requirements of consistency and coherence
and the reason‐providing fact, entail the value of their taking such actions, despite
the fact that they either should not, cannot, or could not if fully rational be
motivated by those reason‐providing facts to act.69
3.2 Remotivating internalism: epistemic humility
This revised version of internalism about practical reasons has a lot more to
be said for it. It retains some of the features of Williams’ internalism about reasons
that made it an attractive view – some of the features that motivated the Motivating
Intuition. It avoids alienating us from our reasons: on the picture of reasons it
presents, reasons are firmly rooted in facts about what matters to us. It also allows
that reasons are action‐guiding, though they may not guide us to the action they
provide us with reason to do. So, for example, while the agents in the Toxin Puzzle
I omit the case of My Fallibility because it concerns epistemic reasons for belief, and I am not
concerned with the possibility of internal epistemic reasons here. I return to the case of epistemic
reasons in §3.3, below.
69
67
and Nuclear Deterrence cases can’t motivated to form the valuable intentions by the
reasons they have to form those intentions, they can be guided by those reasons to
do what it takes to bring it about that they form the relevant intentions for other
reasons. (The agent in the Toxin Puzzle might, I suggested, make a side bet with a
friend that makes it worth her while to actually drink the toxin, thereby ensuring
that she will, at the relevant time, intend to drink it.) Johnson’s imagined patient in
the James Bond case admittedly can’t be guided by his reasons in this way. But here
Michael Smith’s suggestion that when we deliberate about our reasons, we’re
interested in the advice of people who share our basic commitments but are better‐
informed and more rational than we are may be helpful, and may provide some
direct support for the internalist view of reasons. This thought may spell out one
way in which reasons may be action‐guiding – not irrelevant to moral deliberation –
even when they can’t motivate the agent whose reasons they are: an agent’s
reasons should at least guide us, when we advise her about how she should act.
More importantly, the revised version of the internalist thesis still captures
Williams’ thought that when we attribute a reason to someone, we intend to appeal
to a shared standard of conduct that that person must, as a rational agent, recognize
as authoritative.
Remember that the notion of rationality that plays a central role in the
internalist account of reasons is procedural, not substantive (that is, it concerns
standards for proper relations between ends, but doesn’t specify any end as
rationally required, per se, regardless of its relation to things we already care about).
Despite being irreducibly normative, the standards of procedural rationality may be
68
both less controversial and, like their theoretical counterparts, significantly harder
to question than the substantive standards of rationality to which externalists
appeal – standards declaring us to be irrational simply in virtue of not caring about
some end, like the well‐being of others, regardless of that end’s relation to our other
ends and commitments. As Nagel had put it, in The Last Word, his defense of the
objectivity of reason, “it is necessarily employed in every purported challenge to
itself.”70
To be sure, some substantive reasons claims (we have reason not to torture
others for fun) seem decidedly uncontroversial. And we might question quite how
uncontroversial the standards of procedural rationality really are. But
uncontroversial cases are not the problem cases for externalists. The difficulty
emerges instead in the context of disputes about reasons. The procedural standard
of rationality, if not exactly uncontroversial, may nonetheless be one that someone
who disagrees with the internalist at the outset about what her reasons are might
agree on. So it could serve as a kind of Archimedean point against which we might
brace ourselves in disputes about reasons. Externalists, by contrast, if they want to
appeal to a supposedly shared standard of rationality, must appeal to a substantive
standard – one that simply incorporates, as a rational requirement, the need to
respond to the very reason whose existence their interlocutor disputes. If she
disputes the existence of the reason, she’ll also dispute the existence of the
70
Nagel, The Last Word, p. 233.
69
corresponding rational requirement. So internalism offers important dialectical
advantages over externalism.
Relatedly, internalism about reasons seems less presumptive than
externalism. We should not assume that some of us have special epistemic access to
what matters, especially in the absence of any criterion for making such a judgment.
It’s better – less dogmatic – to start from the assumption, as internalism does, that
everyone’s ends are equally worthy of pursuit – and correct this assumption only by
appealing to standards that are as uncontroversial as possible, or at least don’t beg
the very question that is under debate.
According to externalism about reasons, what matters normatively – that is,
what we have reason to do or pursue or protect or respect or promote – does not
depend in any fundamental way on what in fact matters to us – that is, what we do
do and pursue and protect and respect and promote. Some of us happen to be
motivated by what actually matters, and some of us are “wrongly” motivated. But
externalists can offer no explanation for this supposed difference in how well we
respond to reasons – no explanation of why some of us have the right motivations
and some of us the wrong ones – that doesn’t itself appeal to the views about what
matters that they’re trying to justify. (They can explain why some people have the
right motivations by saying, for example, that they’re good people, but that assumes
the truth of the normative views that are at issue.71)
71
The same problem confronts the Aristotelian view, according to which well‐motivated people have
their good upbringing to thank for it. What counts as a good upbringing seems itself to be a moral
question.
70
A comparison to the epistemic case helps bring out what is unsatisfactory in
the externalist position. We sometimes attribute greater epistemic powers to some
people than to others despite not being able to explain why they’re more likely to be
right in their beliefs about a certain topic. Chicken‐sexing is a popular example of
this among philosophers. We think some people are more likely to form true beliefs
about the sex of chickens than others even though we can’t explain why they are
better at judging the sex of chickens. But in the case of chicken‐sexing, we have
independent means of determining the truth, and so we have independent
verification that chicken‐sexers usually get things right. Externalism seems to tell us
that some of us are better reasons‐sensors than others, but without providing the
independent means of determining which of us are in fact more reliably motivated
by genuine normative reasons (or even that some of us are).72
Internalism paints a different and more informative picture of what’s going
on when some people are more responsive to genuine reasons than others.
According to internalism, what matters normatively depends in part on what in fact
matters to us: on what we are motivated to do and pursue and protect and respect
and promote. Something’s mattering to me provides a prima facie reason to
72 What counts as an “independent means” of determining the truth? After all, the chicken‐sexer and
the biologist both reply on sensory experience when investigating the sex of chickens – are their
means really independent? If not, then the chicken‐sexing example may not provide the contrast‐
case to externalism that I am looking for.
It is true that both chicken‐sexers and biologists rely on their senses for determining the sex
of chicks. So the fact that they usually agree cannot be appealed to in support of the supposition that
sensory experience is a good way to gather information about the sex of chickens. If such experience
is in general illusory, that discredits the biologists as much as it does the chicken‐sexers. But I am
assuming here that sensory experience is a good way to gather this information. The question is
whether the particular way in which chicken‐sexers employ their senses is a good way of sexing
chickens. And the fact that biologists employ their senses to do this in a different way, and yet arrive
at the same result, gives us some reason to think that chicken‐sexers are good at sexing chicks.
71
promote it, but only a prima facie reason. I might care about some things whose
mattering is incompatible with the mattering of other things I care about – that’s an
inconsistency. Or I might fail to care about some things whose value is entailed by
the value of other things I care about (failure to intend to take the necessary means
to my ends provides one example of this). So the set of ends whose value is entailed
by the standards of procedural rationality, applied to my actual ends, is very likely
not identical to the set of my actual ends. The internalist picture offers an account of
what goes wrong when we fail to be motivated to act as we have reason to act. And
according to internalism, we’re all equally good at responding to our reasons so long
as we’re equally procedurally rational.73
Internalism recognizes the well‐motivated agent – the person who responds
well to practical reasons – the same way we recognize a talented logician. Unlike in
the case of chicken‐sexing, we have no independent means of verifying that the
talented logician gets at the truth about logic – no means that don’t employ the same
procedure as the logician uses herself. But we do have a view about what makes
someone good at getting at logical truths: superior reasoning skills. In other words,
they’re particularly good at following the relevant procedure. In fact, we think
superior logical reasoning skills make people better at identifying logical truths
precisely because we think it’s plausible that such truths are constituted by what
following the procedure produces – by the conclusions at which someone following
73
It does not help to say that the person who responds well to what matters is the person who is
more substantively rational, since the standards of substantive rationality build assumptions about
what matters in from the start. To call someone substantively rational is just to say that (in addition
to being procedurally rational) they respond well to what matters. So calling someone substantively
rational cannot explain this fact.
72
the procedure perfectly would arrive. Similarly, internalism holds that being
procedurally rational will make a person more likely to respond appropriately to
her reasons because it holds that what a person’s reasons are depends on what
matters to her and the requirements of procedural rationality, and so is often
determined by what matters to a person when she’s fully procedurally rational
(though not always, as the arguments of the last chapter showed). The situation
resembles what Rawls called “pure procedural justice.” In cases of pure procedural
justice, a decision procedure is just not because it allows you track or identify
outcomes that are independently just; rather, the outcomes it produces are just
because they result from the right procedure.74
3.3 Remotivating internalism: the analogy to theoretical reasons
Internalism about reasons is usually presented as a thesis about practical
reasons. This is not surprising, since the standard arguments for internalism appeal
to theories concerning what can motivate us to act, and concerning the supposed
motivating force of moral judgments. But it is useful, I think, to think about what
internalism about theoretical reasons might look like. Doing so helps illustrate
another advantage internalism offers over externalism: I will argue that while there
might be some external reasons for belief, any plausible candidate for an external
reason for belief will have special features that can have no parallel in the practical
74
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 86.
73
case. So considering the case of theoretical reasons should lead us to conclude that
there are no external practical reasons.
Remember that an internal practical reason to φ is a consideration that
counts in favor of φ‐ing in virtue of the relation it shows φ‐ing to stand in to our
antecedent ends. So, according to internalism about reasons, what we have reason
to intend, or what ends we ought to adopt, depends only on what ends we already
have and the requirements of procedural rationality. If we’re procedurally rational
(rational relative to our ends), then we’re rational all‐things‐considered.75 (We’ll be
complying with our subjective reasons, and, if we’re also fully informed, we’ll be
complying with our objective reasons.) An external practical reason to φ would be a
consideration that counts in favor φ‐ing regardless of the relation it showed φ‐ing to
stand in to our antecedent ends. According to externalism about practical reasons,
what we have reason to do or intend – what ends we ought to be motivated to adopt
– does not depend, fundamentally, on what ends we already have. And someone
who fails to act as he has conclusive reason to act need not be procedurally
irrational or ignorant of any relevant facts.
75 As the examples in Chapter 2 show, there may be circumstances in which we cannot be fully
procedurally rational, because complying as well as we can with some of our reasons requires us to
bring it about that we’re not motivationally responsive to those reasons. We may sometimes have
internal reasons to bring it about that we’re locally procedurally irrational. Derek Parfit’s discussion
of what he calls “Schelling’s Answer to Armed Robbery” (after the game‐theorist Thomas Schelling)
provides a striking example: he imagines a case where taking a drug that temporarily causes severe
irrationality may be the best way to prevent a violent attacker from carrying out the threats he hopes
will help him achieve his aims. (Reasons and Persons, pp. 12‐13.) In such cases, we cannot be fully
procedurally rational, since, by deciding against making ourselves locally procedurally irrational, we
would still be behaving procedurally irrationally – we would be failing to respond to some of our
internal reasons.
74
What would an internal epistemic reason look like? Let’s call an epistemic
reason to believe some proposition P an internal reason if it’s a consideration that
counts in favor of believing P (by providing evidence for P) in virtue of the relation it
shows P to stand in to our existing beliefs. (So, for example, the fact that shining a
coherent beam of light through two parallel slits produces a certain pattern on the
screen behind them may give the physicist performing the experiment an internal
reason to believe that light is a wave, given her background beliefs about the
behavior of waves.) According to internalism about epistemic reasons, what we have
reason to believe depends only on what we already believe and the standards of
procedural rationality. We believe in accordance with our evidence (that is, we
respond appropriately to our subjective epistemic reasons) whenever our set of
beliefs is fully procedurally rational – maximally internally consistent and coherent
(however that’s best spelled out).
As a view about epistemic reasons, internalism seems problematic. This is
because it seems possible for our system of beliefs to be internally consistent, but
for us nonetheless to be wildly deluded – even relative to our evidence. If we’re to
count as properly responsive to reasons, our beliefs must somehow be “tied to the
world” (or rather, tied to the world as it appears to us to be) by means of experience.
In other words, experience alone seems to give us some reasons for belief, regardless
of what else we believe, and these reasons can fix certain of our beliefs, and so
constrain what sets of beliefs we can have and still count as fully rational.
This thought might be put differently:
75
It seems like, for some P, there are some external reasons to believe P –
considerations that count in favor of believing P (by providing evidence for P) but
not in virtue of the relation they show P to stand in to our antecedent beliefs. Here
are some plausible examples: The fact that I feel pain seems to give me a reason to
believe I’m in pain, regardless of what else I already believe. And the fact that I have
an experience of redness gives me a reason to believe I’m having an experience of
redness regardless of what else I believe.
It’s worth stepping back a bit at this point and thinking again, quite generally,
about what reasons are. Most generally, reasons are considerations that count in
favor of things. Practical reasons count in favor of forming certain intentions or
adopting certain ends. Epistemic reasons count in favor of forming certain beliefs,
by providing evidence for them. Both kinds of reasons count in favor of things in a
particular way: by providing justification. Normative reasons can be thought of as
justificatory forces – they’re in the business of providing justification.
Internal and external reasons differ in how they provide justification.
Internal practical reasons, internalists claim, justify some intention or end by
showing the relationship it stands in to some other end we already hold. (So, when
people like Parfit, for example, say that “there are no internal reasons,” they mean
that no end‐adoption can ever be justified fundamentally in virtue of the relation it
stands in to some other end we already have; they think this would amount to a kind
of boot‐strapping.) Internal epistemic reasons are very similar: they justify a belief
in virtue of the relationship they show it to stand in to our other beliefs. In both
cases, the relationships that can transmit justification in this way are established by
76
the standards of procedural rationality (modus ponens, in the epistemic case, and the
instrumental principle, in the practical case, provide familiar examples).
External practical reasons (externalists claim) justify the adoption of some
end differently: they purport to justify it directly, and regardless of our other ends –
that is, not in virtue of the relationship they show it to stand in to those other ends.
In this way, they are like external epistemic reasons, which, as I’ve said, provide
justification for some belief directly, and not in virtue of the relation they show it to
stand in to our other beliefs.
Describing the disagreement between internalists and externalists about
practical reasons this way – in terms of the kind of justification they recognize as
possible – makes it begin to resemble a familiar dispute about the nature of
epistemic justification. Coherentists about epistemic justification might be
understood as defending an internalist view of epistemic reasons: they argue that
all beliefs are, ultimately, justified in virtue of the relationship they stand in to our
other beliefs. In other words, all beliefs are justified by internal reasons. They deny
the existence of external reasons for belief – of reasons that can justify a belief
directly – not in virtue of the relationship they show it to stand in to our other
beliefs.76 Foundationalists, by contrast, might be thought of as externalists about at
least some epistemic reasons – they think that some of our beliefs – those that are
basic – are not justified in virtue of the relationship they stand in to our other
beliefs, but rather, are justified in some other way: perhaps they are justified
At least, coherentists think that no belief is sufficiently justified externally: there are no sufficient
external reasons.
76
77
directly by experience, or perhaps they are self‐justifying. And just as externalists
like Parfit worry that internalism about practical reasons entails a kind of boot‐
strapping, so foundationalists in epistemology suspect coherentism of a kind of
boot‐strapping: if the beliefs we already have aren’t justified or supported by
reasons, how can new beliefs be justified in virtue of the relationship they stand in
to the old ones?
As I said earlier, I’m inclined to agree that internalism doesn’t tell the whole
story of epistemic justification: not all our beliefs can be internally justified, and
sensory experience seems to play an important role in anchoring our beliefs in the
real world. But looking at the kinds of beliefs foundationalists suggest might be
basic – that is, justified fully by external epistemic reasons – teaches us something
about the possibility of external practical reasons. The first thing to note is that
there is no obvious analog in the practical case to the source of justification that
plays the essential anchoring role in the case of belief: sensory experience of the
world. Our senses may give us access to the world as it is, but don’t seem to give us
access to the world as it should be.
Moreover, the beliefs that foundationalists point to as the most likely
candidates for basicality – justification by external epistemic reasons – have
something in common: they are not merely uncontroversial, but tend to be self‐
evident, incorrigible, indubitable, or in some other way plausibly immune to error.
Because of this, they are the sorts of beliefs that we usually accept as true as soon as
we take them to be asserted sincerely: if you tell me something hurts you, I will
believe it so long as I believe your assertion is sincere, even if I did not believe you
78
were in pain before. Beliefs that are plausibly supported by external reasons are not
the sorts of beliefs we think require further justification, beyond their sincere
avowal. The fact that these beliefs seem almost self‐evident in this way is what
makes them plausible candidates for support by external reasons.
Is there a practical counterpart to beliefs supported by external reasons? Are
there ends or intentions that seem to fit the model provided by such beliefs? That is,
are there any ends that are uncontroversial, largely immune to erroneous adoption,
and therefore not the kinds of things we feel people must offer further justification
for caring about, beyond telling us they care about them? I don’t think there are any
such ends. There are some ends that many of us share, and which are so widely
understood, that it might not occur to us to ask for or require further justification
once they’re appealed to (the well‐being of our children, maybe, or maybe pleasure).
But this case is different – here, we don’t feel the need to ask for further justification
to believe the ends are supported by genuine reasons because we share the ends (or
very similar ones) at the outset. In the case of beliefs supported by external reasons,
by contrast, the sincere avowal of the belief was itself enough to persuade someone
of its justification even if that person did not share the belief at the outset: even if I
don’t think that, say, hiccups can hurt, if someone says they do then, unless I think
they are being insincere, that’s enough to convince me. Because such beliefs have no
counterpart in the practical case, thinking about the parallel to epistemic reasons
should lead us to conclude that there are no external practical reasons, even if we
think there are external epistemic reasons.
79
More recent versions of foundationalism, however, are more permissive with
regard to what kinds of beliefs might count as basic. They don’t require that beliefs
be immune to error, for example, to be candidates for basicality. According to these
versions of foundationalism, simple sensory beliefs – for example, the belief that
there is a table over there – might be basic. And some foundationalists77 allow that
(reliable) memory can be a source of basic, non‐inferentially‐justified belief.
Foundationalists of this stripe might allow that there could be beliefs that are open
to doubt, but basic nonetheless.
But even these more permissively‐identified basic beliefs have no practical
counterpart. Although my basic belief that there is a table over there might count as
justified, on these versions of foundationalism, regardless of whether I inferred this
in part from my belief that my sense‐experience is veridical, or whether I also
believe that I’m, say, not in a brain‐in‐vat world, it seems to me we (philosophers)
would accept the claim that this belief is basic only because we (philosophers)
generally agree that simple sense experience is reliable in most circumstances, and
that we’re not in brain‐in‐vat worlds. There is no corollary to this agreement in the
practical case; there’s no consensus among philosophers on a reliable means of
directly forming simple, uncontroversial, unlikely‐to‐be‐mistaken aims and
intentions.78
77
For example, Alvin Goldman, “What Is Justified Belief?”
Moral intuitions certainly could not play this role – they are at best a starting‐point in moral
reasoning.
78
80
I’ve argued that comparing the cases of practical and epistemic reasons, and
in particular, considering the dispute between foundationalists and coherentists
about epistemic justification (which, I’ve suggested, runs parallel to the dispute
between externalists and internalists in the practical case), gives us some grounds
for preferring the internalist account of practical reasons. But does it also leave
internalism about practical reasons vulnerable to the same kind of boot‐strapping
objections faced by defenders of coherentism (as some externalists have
suggested)? I don’t think so. Our beliefs, even when we’re fully procedurally
rational, play no (non‐trivial79) role in determining the way the world is. But the
same may not be true of our ends. It may be that what makes some end valuable –
one that we have reason to pursue – is that it stands in the right relation to what
already matters to us. What we care about, in other words, does play a non‐trivial
role in determining what matters, and what we have reason to do. This is, in fact,
the picture of normative practical reasons that I sketched a moment ago. I
suggested then that responding to practical reasons is like a case of what Rawls
termed “pure procedural justice” – that in those cases where reasoning well ensures
willing in accord with our reasons, it ensures this because what we have reason to
do is determined by how we would will if we were reasoning well.
79
Of course, since what we believe is part of the way the world is (it is a fact about the world that I
believe Michael Jordan was the greatest basketball player ever to play the game), our beliefs do affect
the way the world is in trivial ways.
81
3.4 Remotivating internalism: the motivating force of moral judgments
The intuitions to which I have been appealing in defense of internalism have
been largely epistemic; they haven’t concerned motivation. But the version of
internalism I’ve defended here may still lay partial claim to a virtue that drew many
philosophers to the Motivating Intuition, and via it, to Williams’ internalist thesis:
its ability to explain the apparent motivating force of moral judgments. If, as the
Motivating Intuition claims, considerations that provide reasons must be such as to
motivate rational agents, we should expect rational agents to be reliably motivated
to act as they have reason to act: rational agents’ judgments about their reasons are
true, and are the discovery of facts that themselves have the power to motivate
those agents when they are rational. Even on the account of reasons I’ve defended
here, which rejects the Motivating Intuition, this will often be the case. But
counterexamples to the Motivating Intuition like those presented by the Nuclear
Deterrence, Just War, and Emergency Landing show that even when we are
motivated to act as we judge we have reasons to act, it may not be those reasons
doing the motivating. The Motivating Intuition cannot explain the motivating force
of such moral judgments. However, the version of internalism I have sketched,
which does not rely on the Motivating Intuition, should lead us to expect that the
agents in these examples will be motivated to act as they judge they ought: after all,
they have such reasons, on my account, because they each have ends that will be
furthered by acting in this way, and (we’ve assumed) have the means to bring it
about that they act as they ought – just for other reasons.
82
3.5 Categorical internal reasons?
I’ve argued that internalism has important advantages as a theory of what
practical reasons are, despite the failure of the standard arguments for internalism.
Internalism avoids alienating us from our reasons, by rooting reasons in facts about
what we care about, and it captures the fact that when we attribute a reason to
someone, we intend to appeal to a shared standard of conduct that that person
must, as a rational agent, recognize as authoritative. It offers a non‐reductive
analysis of what it is for some fact to be a reason for acting which is attractive, in
part because it helps bring out one important way in which we’re all equally sources
of claims on others. The analysis appeals to the relatively uncontroversial
normative standard provided by the procedural conception of rationality – or at
least to standards the bindingness of which is not the controversy at issue in
disputes about what we have reason to do. So it may also act as a kind of
Archimedean point against which we can brace ourselves in such disputes.
Internalism, unlike externalism, gives an explanation of what makes some people
better at responding to reasons than others. And thinking about what internalism
and externalism about epistemic reasons might look like gives us some reason to
doubt that there could be external practical reasons. Internalism can also help us
make sense of the action‐guidingness of reasons and the motivating force of
reasons‐judgments.
Each of these considerations gives us reason to embrace an internalist
account of reasons, even if we aren’t persuaded by reductive naturalist accounts of
normativity, the Humean Theory of Motivation, or the Motivating Intuition. But
83
what does all this entail for our substantive question? If my internalist account of
what reasons are is right, what reasons are there? What do we have reason to do? In
particular, if we accept internalism about reasons, can the threat of relativism – or
worse: nihilism – be avoided?
To sum up the argument of the preceding chapters: Philosophers have
generally responded to worry that the internalist conception of reasons leads to
moral relativism in one of three ways. Some (notably Gilbert Harman) have
embraced moral relativism, arguing that the plausibility of the internalist
conception of reasons confirms the truth of relativism. According to these
philosophers, some agents—agents whose moral commitments differ sufficiently
from our own—may not be acting wrongly when they cause others to suffer
unnecessarily and undeservedly. I find this solution intuitively unacceptable.
A second class of philosophers has responded to the threat of relativism by
divorcing claims about what we ought morally to do from claims about what we
have reason to do. (Philippa Foot, Bernard Williams, and Harman himself have all
made suggestions along these lines.) These philosophers might agree that the same
moral rules apply to all of us, but must allow that we may not all have reason to
comply with them. I’ve rejected this solution as well, because it too seems to me
inadequate as an escape from moral relativism. It assimilates moral rules with
other only conditionally binding rules, like the rules of a game, or rules of
etiquette—rules governing practices participation in which is merely optional.
Maintaining the tie between what we ought to do and what we have reason to do
emphasizes the categorical force of moral rules, gains support from the relation
84
between our practice of moral judgment and our practice of blaming, and also seems
to me independently plausible.
An alternative is to respond to the threat of moral relativism by rejecting
internalism about reasons, and with it the procedural account of rationality. This,
I’ve argued, is not an appealing option: internalism has much to be said for it.
What’s more, externalism provides only a very unsatisfactory response to the threat
of moral relativism. Externalist accounts of reason seem to merely insist that we
have reason to be moral, rather than to argue for the conclusion from premises
moral skeptics or relativists might accept. This is not the response to the amoralist’s
challenge – why should I be moral? – that we may have hoped for.
In a way, the unsatisfactoriness of the externalist response to the threat of
relativism, amoralism, or nihilism mirrors that of the anti‐moral‐rationalist
response favored by Foot, Williams, and (at times) Harman. I argued (in §1.4) that
attempting to preserve the universal bindingness of moral‐ought‐judgments by
divorcing such judgments from reasons‐ascriptions threatened to demote morality
to the status of, say, rules of etiquette. These rules may have universal or
“categorical” application, in that they are about, or refer, to all of us, regardless of
our desires; but they seem to lack universal normative force. It seems entirely open
to us to declare that we don’t care about such nonsense, and if we do declare this,
then while our table manners may continue to be gauche, this will, it seems, be a fact
of little practical import. Is insisting, with the externalist, that moral rules have
universal‐external‐reason‐giving status, regardless of what we happen to care about
85
– that failing to comply with moral rules is substantively irrational – any more
satisfying?
I’m not sure that it is. Faced with such insistence, the amoralist may well
respond, “whose reasons? Which rationality?”80 An assertion that rules of some old‐
fashioned religion – a religion that in no way reflects what I care about – belong to
the requirements of (substantive) rationality and are reason‐giving for me would do
little to convince me of the normative import of those rules. What makes the
externalist response to the amoralist any better?
Hume sought to avoid skepticism about universal moral requirements by
identifying an end that everyone cares about, at least to the extent that they are
rational, and that could therefore serve as the foundation for universal moral
internal reasons. Hume thought that the general good could play this role (if only
contingently). I doubt that it can, though I’ll come back to this suggestion in the
chapters that follow. Still, I believe Hume was on the right path. I think internalists
and externalists alike have been too quick to assume that there is no end we’re all
required to care about, on pain of procedural irrationality. If there is such an end,
then, as Williams puts it:
it might turn out that when we properly think about it, we shall find
that we are committed to an ethical life, merely because we are
rational agents. Some philosophers believe that this is true. If they
are right, then there is … something to which even the amoralist or
the skeptic is committed but which, properly thought through, will
show us that he is irrational, or unreasonable, or at any rate mistaken
[in his amoralism].81
À la Alasdair MacIntyre (cf. MacIntyre’s Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, Notre Dame: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1988).
80
81
Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, p. 29.
86
Williams, of course, isn’t optimistic. But I think there are grounds for
optimism that internalism needn’t force us into relativism, especially once we
realize that being procedurally rational involves much more than mere instrumental
rationality. And as in the case of beliefs, sets of ends can exhibit looser procedural
“virtues” than mere consistency: considerations of coherence and systematic
justifiability, as well as inference to the best explanation, can make it more rational
for us to abandon certain ends and adopt others. The example of mathematics in the
theoretical case should give us some hope about the possibility of building up
complex, substantive‐seeming practical principles on a foundation provided by
relatively thin and hard‐to‐question set of axioms.
Kant’s ethical theory provides a model for arguments for the existence of
categorical moral reasons that proceed from within a procedural conception of
rationality. He thought that a commitment to the value of any ends whatsoever also
committed us the value of humanity. In the next chapter, I’ll explore the Kantian
argument, and try to bring out its internalist form. Kant’s argument, as he makes it,
does not, I believe, succeed in establishing the existence of categorical internal
reasons. But it can serve as the skeleton of a more promising argument. I develop
that argument in Chapters 5 and 6. Because it is internalist in form, building its
defense of categorical moral reasons from things we’re all committed to, even the
amoralist, given what we antecedently care about and on pain of procedural
irrationality, this argument provides a more satisfying answer to the amoralist’s
87
question and the relativist’s challenge.82 Finally, in Chapter 7, I turn to our
substantive question about reasons: if the internalist argument for categorical moral
reasons works, what is it we have reason to do?
82
The answer is more satisfying, because it connects the rational requirement to be moral to the
amoralist’s own commitments. But I do not intend to claim too much for it, or for the power of
philosophy. As Bernard Williams points out, even after we have come up with our justification for
morality – even one that builds from the amoralist’s own commitments, “why should we expect him
to stay where we have put it?” He continues, with characteristic drama:
…The amoralist, or even his more theoretical associate the relativist, is represented
in these writings as an alarming figure, a threat. Why should it make any difference
to such a person whether there is a philosophical justification of the ethical life? …
—That is not the point. The question is not whether he will be convinced, but
whether he ought to be convinced.
—But is it? The writers’ note of urgency suggests something else, that what will
happen could turn on the outcome of these arguments, that the justification of the
ethical life could be a force. If we are to take this seriously, then it is a real question,
who is supposed to be listening? Why are they supposed to be listening? What will
the professor’s justification do, when they break down the door, smash his
spectacles, take him away?
(Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, pp. 22‐23.) I concede the point. Philosophical
argument is only one possible force for moral change in the world, and by no means always the most
effective.
88
Chapter 4
Kant’s Argument
4.1 The problem of obligations
In his “Prize Essay” (1763), written long before the Groundwork of the
Metaphysics of Morals, Kant identifies obligation as the fundamental concept of
moral philosophy. There, Kant notes that while we express obligations in terms of
“oughts,” “ought” itself is capable of two meanings:
Either I ought to do something (as a means) if I want something else
(as an end), or I ought immediately to do something else (as an end)
and make it actual. The former may be called the necessity of the
means, and the latter the necessity of the ends. The first kind of
necessity does not indicate any obligation at all. It merely specifies a
prescription as the solution to the problem concerning the means I
must employ if I am to attain a certain end. … Now since no other
necessity attaches to the employment of means than that which
belongs to the end, all the actions which are prescribed by morality
under the condition of certain ends are contingent. They cannot be
called obligations as long as they are not subordinated to an end
which is necessary in itself.83
For Kant, the project of moral philosophy is to clarify the concept of obligations,
understood as unconditional “oughts,” and to explain how (given the apparent
contingency of our ends) obligations are possible.
For externalists, this of course poses no great puzzle. Whether we have some
end may be a contingent matter. But that contingency in no way undermines the
possibility that there are ends we’re rationally required to have. And moral oughts –
Kant, Immanuel, An Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and
Ethics (the so‐called “Prize Essay,” 1764), p. 272 (2:298), emphasis in the original.
83
89
obligations – simply reflect the ends we’re required to have, regardless of whether
we in fact do have them, or any related end.
Kant’s internalist vision of nature of moral obligation comes through more
clearly in a famous passage from the Groundwork, in which Kant diagnoses what he
thinks gone wrong with past attempts to identify a universally binding moral
principle. He writes:
If we look back upon all previous efforts that have ever been made to
discover the principle of morality, we need not wonder now why all of
them had to fail. It was seen that the human being is bound to laws by
his duty, but it never occurred to them that he is subject only to laws
given by himself but still universal and that he is bound only to act in
conformity with his own will, which, however, in accordance with
nature’s end is a will giving universal law. For, if one thought of him
only as subject to a law (whatever it may be), this law had to carry
with it some interest by way of attraction or constraint, since it did
not as a law arise from his will; in order to conform with the law, his
will had instead to be constrained by something else to act a certain
way. By this quite necessary consequence, however, all the labor to
find a supreme ground of duty was irretrievably lost. For, one never
arrived at duty but instead at the necessity of an action from a certain
interest. But then the imperative had to turn out always conditional
and could not be fit for a moral command.84
This (rather grandiose) appraisal has provoked considerable frustration in
some of Kant’s less sympathetic readers. Parfit, for example, says of it:
[S]ince I knew that Kant believed in a Categorical Imperative, I was
surprised by Kant’s second sentence. I asked a Kantian, ‘Does this
mean that, if I don’t give myself Kant’s Imperative as a law, I am not
subject to it?’ ‘No’, I was told, ‘you have to give yourself a law, and
there’s only one law.’ This reply was maddening, like the propaganda
of the so‐called ‘People’s Democracies’ of the old Soviet bloc, in which
voting was compulsory and there was only one candidate. And when I
Kant, The Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (hereafter, Groundwork), pp. 40‐41, (4: 432‐
433), emphasis in the original.
84
90
said ‘But I haven’t given myself Kant’s Imperative as a law’, I was told
‘Yes you have’. This reply was even worse.85
Parfit’s irritation, is, I think, understandable, if we take Kant to be claiming both that
the law is up to us, and that we all, by some sort of necessity, choose the same law.
But there is, I think, another, less maddening, way to read Kant’s claims. I
read the passage, instead, as an expression of Kant’s non‐reductive internalist way
of thinking about reasons and obligations: his view that what we are morally
obligated to do cannot be totally divorced from facts about what motivates us. Kant,
as I read him, thought that for a law to be binding on us, it must reflect our
motivational set – it must connect to what we care about. To put the point in the
language of the last chapter, we have reason to do as the moral law requires only if
there are considerations that count in favor of our doing so – that throw their
justificatory weight behind our complying with the law – in virtue of the relation
they show doing so to stand in to our antecedent ends (for example, by showing that
doing as the law requires is a means to one of those ends, or constitutive of it, or
valuable in consequence of the value of that end). This is the sense in which the law
must have its source in us – the sense in which it must “arise from [our] will” – if
we’re to be obligated to obey it.86
85
Parfit, On What Matters, Volume One, xlii‐xliii.
86
Note that it does not follow from this that we “give the law to ourselves” or are the source of its
normativity. We aren’t, on the view I defend and the reading of Kant I am exploring, the authors of
the law or source of its normativity, because we are in no way the authors of the requirements of
procedural rationality, or the sources of their normativity. This is the sense in which the internalist
view I defend, and (tentatively) attribute to Kant, is non‐reductive. (See Chapter 1, §1.2, above.) This
makes my project less ambitious, in a way, than some Kantian constructivist projects, such as
Korsgaard’s: unlike Korsgaard, I am not trying to identify the “sources of normativity.”
91
Now, as Kant points out in the quoted passage, there are two ways in which
we can have internal reasons, in the sense just described, to comply with the law.
The first applies when the content of the law itself does not arise from our will –
from what we care about. In that case, Kant says, the law can bind us – we can have
reason to comply with it – only if we have some incentive, external to the law, to do
so: perhaps a threat of punishment for non‐compliance or promise of reward for
compliance.87 But the moral law can’t be binding on us in this way, for two reasons.
First, if this was the source of our reason to comply with the law, it would bind us
only conditionally, depending on whether we had the relevant external end – the aim
of avoiding the threatened punishment or winning the offered reward. But the
moral law, if there is one, must bind unconditionally and categorically. Hence Kant’s
claim that, on this way of conceiving of the bindingness of the law, “all the labor to
find a supreme ground of duty was irretrievably lost.”
A second consideration weighing against conceiving of the moral law this
way – as binding us by means of providing an external incentive to comply – is not
one Kant fully explains here, though it is in keeping with views he defends
elsewhere in the Groundwork. We might wonder, in response to Kant’s first worry
about this conception of the moral law, whether there could be such an incentive
that does bind everyone, because everyone shares the incentive‐providing end (say,
a desire for heavenly rewards or a fear of eternal damnation). If there is such an end
87
Some Hobbes‐inspired moral theories may take this form.
92
shared by everyone, might such a law bind categorically after all, by giving us all
(internal) reason to comply with it?
On reflection, however, we should reject this possibility. Even if the
incentive‐providing end were universally shared, it would establish, as Kant puts it,
no “duty” to act in conformity to law, but rather only “the necessity of an action from
a certain interest.” That is, the universal reason to be moral would, in such a case,
still be a kind of ulterior motive – a reason external to morality – not a genuine moral
reason. The reason I’d have to keep a promise, for example, wouldn’t be that it’s the
moral thing to do. Nor would my reason be the fact that not keeping the promise
will disappoint someone who is relying on me, or fail to show proper respect for
that person, or improperly make an exception of myself, or cause unhappiness, or
any of the other plausible reasons why keeping the promise is the moral thing to
do.88 My reason to keep the promise would be that if I do, I’ll be rewarded, or if I
don’t, I’ll be punished. Of course, many people are motivated to do the right thing by
such considerations. But surely these aren’t the normative moral reasons why we
should keep our promises. Surely the reason we have to do as morality requires
isn’t ulterior in this way. If it were, the moral law would look no different from the
bad laws of an illegitimate and violent dictator, which we might have reasons to
follow, but only self‐interested reasons. Or like some set of in themselves arbitrary
– perhaps even absurd – rules of etiquette, which a fear of ostracism may give us
instrumental reasons to obey, but which have no value in themselves. When we
88
Unless I happen, contingently, to care about these things.
93
asked, with Kant, whether there can be genuine moral obligations if something like
the internalist picture of reasons is the right one, this is surely not what we had in
mind!89
What about the second way in which we might have internal reasons to
comply with the moral law? We might have such reasons if the content of the law
itself reflected a universally‐shared end. If there was some end all rational beings
had to adopt, on pain of procedural irrationality – in virtue of the relation that end
stands in to our existing ends and motivations – then it could provide, as Kant might
put it, the matter of a moral law that is universally binding in form, without needing
to provide ulterior motives to act rightly. The search for this end is one of the
central tasks of Kant’s Groundwork. The need to identify such an end is suggested, I
have argued, by the categorical form of the moral law, coupled with Kant’s
internalist conception of practical reason.
4.2 Kant’s “formula of universal law”
So: if there is to be a universally binding moral law, it must be universally
binding in virtue of its content. That is, it must tell us to pursue an end to whose
It’s worth noting that if our reason to be moral were ulterior in this way, then even if we were
motivated to do the moral thing by the reasons we have to do it, our action would have no moral
worth. It would have no moral worth on Kant’s view, since Kant thinks that actions have moral
worth if they are performed “from the motive of duty” – that is, for the sake of doing as the moral law
requires. It would also have no moral worth on what I think is a more plausible view, according to
which morally worthy actions are performed for the reasons that morally‐justify their performance
(since, as I said, the fact that I’ll be rewarded in heaven if I keep my promises isn’t what makes
keeping promises the morally‐right thing to do). Since it seems very implausible that actions
performed for all and only the reasons that justify them wouldn’t have moral worth, this, too, counts
against the possibility that our reason to obey the moral law could be ulterior in the sense described.
For more on the criteria for morally worthy action, see my “Acting for the Right Reasons.”
89
94
value all procedurally rational beings are committed. But how are we to determine
if there is such an end, and what such a law might say? Can we discover anything
from the very little we have to go on: that if there is indeed a moral law, it will be
categorical in form – that is, universally and unconditionally binding – and that it
will be so in virtue of the universality of the end it tells us to pursue?
In Section II of the Groundwork, Kant asks what we can figure out about the
content of the moral law by considering merely its formal properties, namely, the
fact that moral principles, if there are any, must be categorical in form. “[W]e first
want to inquire,” he says, “whether the mere concept of a categorical imperative
may not also provide its formula containing the proposition which alone can be a
categorical imperative.”90 We want to consider whether we can learn anything
about what the moral law (if there is one) says by considering the fact that the moral
law (if there is one) must be universally binding, regardless of people’s contingent
ends and commitments.
Kant notes that identifying the content of an imperative by means of an
analysis of the general concept of that imperative is impossible in the case of
“hypothetical imperatives” – imperatives that tell us what to do in order to achieve a
certain optional end – because they operate only within particular “conditions.”91
Hypothetical imperatives generally take the form of if‐then statements of means‐to‐
end relations, such as “if you want to quench your thirst, drink.” They aim at the
attainment of particular ends and hold only if the agent in question wills those ends.
90
Kant, Groundwork, pp. 30‐31 (4:420).
91
Ibid., p. 31 (4:420).
95
So no claim can be made about the content of a hypothetical imperative without first
knowing the specific end at which it is aimed. But since categorical imperatives
apply any person’s actions unconditionally, Kant seems, in pursuing his first attempt
to identify the content of the moral law, to hope he can proceed without considering
the end at which it aims.
Kant continues:
Since the imperative contains, beyond the law, only the necessity that
the maxim be in conformity with this law, while the law contains no
condition to which it is limited, nothing is left with which the maxim
of action is to conform but the universality of the law as such; and this
conformity alone is what the imperative properly represents as
necessary.92
This is a somewhat difficult passage to unpack. It is clear, however, that we
can get from this analysis of the concept of a categorical imperative no picture of
what the moral law actually says (in a positive sense)—that is why Kant writes only
of what the imperative contains “beyond the law,” without attempting to indicate
what the content of the law itself is. Kant does tell us what the law does not
contain—namely, it contains “no condition to which it is limited”—that is, it holds
regardless of what particular ends an agent has. This points to the only fact we
know about the categorical imperative from an analysis of its concept: it is
universally valid for all rational agents, and hence any maxim for action – any fully‐
spelled‐out intention of the form “I will φ in order that p” – that an agent has must
conform with it if that maxim is to be morally permissible. “[T]his conformity
alone,” Kant writes, “is what the imperative properly represents as necessary.”
92
Ibid., p. 31 (4:421).
96
So far, we have not learned very much. We’ve learned only that there’s one
element in the content of a hypothetical imperative – the conditions of its
applicability – that is missing from the categorical imperative, and thus that all our
intentions must comply with the moral law, whatever it says, and whatever we
happen to care about or aim at. Kant’s first attempt to move beyond this rather
uninformative piece of analysis – his so‐called “formula of universal law” – is
famously thinly defended and counterexample‐prone. The “formula of universal
law” states: act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the
same time will that is should become a universal law.93 In defending it, Kant claims
that what we know about the form of the categorical imperative – that it is
universally binding – tells us something about the content of that imperative: that it
tells us that our maxims must be universalizable. But why think this? It is not at all
clear why the universality of the categorical imperative itself should demand that
any maxim that conforms to it be universalizable.
A maxim’s conformity to a universal principle does not obviously have
anything to do with its own universalizability. It may follow from the universal
bindingness of the moral law that the law itself must be universalizable, in that it
must be possible or even desirable that everyone act on it. That is, we might think
that if the moral law requires that I φ in circumstances C, then, because (given its
universal bindingness) it will also require that everyone else φs when similarly
placed (at least under some suitably general description of φ), it must be possible
93
Ibid.
97
and desirable that everyone φ in such circumstances. For example, we might think
that it could be a moral requirement that people keep their promises except when
the consequences of doing so are very grave only if it is possible for everyone to
keep their promises except when the consequences of doing so are very grave, and
only if the world in which everyone does, generally, keep their promises is a morally
desirable one. In fact, I have my doubts about even this inference. From the claim
that it’s true of each agent that that agent ought to φ, together with the principle that
‘ought’ implies ‘can’, it may follow that its true of each agent that it’s possible that
she φ. But it does not follow that it’s possible that all agents φ, much less that it
would be desirable for all agents to do so.94
But even if we allow that the universally binding form of the moral law
entails the universalizability of that law, we should conclude from that only that
moral requirements must be universalizable. The claim of the formula of universal
law, that all morally permissible maxims must be universalizable, is much stronger
and more contentious. Consider the example of telling a white lie in order to protect
someone’s feelings. Kant, of course, infamously suggested that lying even in these
94
Consider, for example, Peter Singer’s famous case of the child drowning in the pond. If 100 people
are standing at the pond’s edge, and no one is helping, it may be true of each person that she ought to
try to save the child, and that she can try to save the child. But it may not be possible for all the
bystanders to try to save the child (if the pond is a small one), and in certainly would not be desirable
for them all to do so (since they’ll only get in each other’s way).
Perhaps this case does not show that moral requirements needn’t be universalizable.
Perhaps the case instead suggests that I’ve mis‐described the relevant moral requirement: it should
instead be “each person ought to try to save the child if no‐one else is doing so”, or something like
that. (Singer suggests a similar amendment to the requirement that we donate a significant
percentage of our income to famine relief, in response to the worry that if we all gave that much, we’d
end up giving more than was needed, and resources would go to waste. See “Famine, Affluence, and
Morality,” p. 698.) Furthermore, we might think the claim that it must be morally desirable for
everyone to do as they ought has independent plausibility, since surely the world in which everyone
does as they ought must be a morally appealing one. My point here is that none of this follows
merely from the claim that the moral law, itself, binds universally.
98
circumstances is forbidden.95 It is forbidden, according to the formula of universal
law, because if everyone lied in order to spare feelings in such cases, no one would
believe the lie, and no comfort would be taken from it – the lie would defeat its own
purpose. But telling such lies is not impermissible; and it seems irrelevant what
would happen if everyone told such lies, since not everyone does tell them. The
parade of counterexamples that have been offered to Kant’s formula reinforces this
suspicion: what could be wrong with playing tennis on Sundays to avoid crowds at
the courts, or always holding the door open for others, or being the last person to
leave any sinking ship?96 Perhaps the dictates of the moral law must be
universalizable, because it must be possible for everyone to conform to them. But
my own (merely permissible) maxims need not be universalizable, since not
everyone must or should act as I intend to.97
The formula of universal law does not, I think, present a plausible test for the
permissibility of maxims for action; nor is Kant’s derivation of it from the mere
95
Though elsewhere Kant may be more lenient. He seems to allow, for example, that when an author
asks, “how do you like my work?”, and is likely to “take the slightest hesitation is answering as an
insult,” one might, perhaps, “say what is expected of one.” See The Metaphysics of Morals, p. 430
(6:431).
The first example is due to Barabara Herman (The Practice of Moral Judgment, p. 163), the last to
Derek Parfit (On What Matters, Vol. 1, p. 277).
96
97
Allen Wood suggests that in making this transition Kant is in fact looking ahead to the Formula of
the Realm of Ends, which maintains that the ends of all human beings should harmonize and
converge into a community, thus making sense of the idea that maxims towards those ends should be
universalizable, i.e., not conflict with themselves when shared by all people (Wood, Kant’s Ethical
Thought, p. 82). I’m not sure I find even this reverse argument convincing. From the perspective of a
unified and mutually reinforcing system of maxims and ends, it is not just important that my maxim
to act in a certain way not conflict with your identical maxim to act in the same way (i.e., that each of
my maxims be universalizable) but also important that none of my maxims conflict with any of your
maxims, or any of anyone else’s. This seems to me, however, to be an impossibly restrictive criterion
for moral action—it is impossible for me to act in such a way that I never effect or limit the
opportunities for action available to others.
99
concept of a categorical imperative or moral law convincing.98 But Kant’s second
attempt at trying to determine what the content of the moral law must look like if it
is to be categorically binding in form is, I believe, much more promising. It begins
from the insight I have already discussed: that the moral law can be categorically
binding on me, in right way, only if its content reflects an end there is rational
pressure on us all to share, regardless of our contingent ends and motivations, in
virtue of the relation it stands in to those ends, whatever they happen to be. Only if
there is such an end can there be a universal internal reason to be moral that is not
problematically ulterior to morality. Establishing the possibility of a categorically
binding moral law depends, Kant concludes, on discovering an end that is itself
necessary in this sense. This end, if there is one, will then provide the “matter” of
the moral law – the end for the sake of which we act when we act morally, just as we
act for the sake of quenching our thirst when we follow a hypothetical imperative
telling us to drink. In this way, Kant eventually arrives as the content of the moral
law via an analysis of its form, culminating in his second formulation of the
categorical imperative, the so‐called “formula of humanity,” which states:
So act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the
person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely
as means.99
98
But for a valiant attempt to at least partially defend the formula of universal law, and a very
interesting explanation of the connection between the universalizability of maxims and the law‐like
form of moral requirements, see Kenneth Walden’s “Laws of Nature, Laws of Freedom, and the Social
Construction of Normativity”. Walden argues that it is a constitutive norm of agency that our actions
be “interpretable”, in the sense that it be possible to offer rationalizing explanations of them. He
argues that (as with other sorts of naturalistic explanations, like biological explanations) our actions
are amenable to rationalizing explanations only if they conform to certain patterns also exhibited by
other actions subject to the same explanations.
99
Kant, Groundwork, p. 38 (4:429).
100
In a moment, I will examine Kant’s derivation of that formula, as well as its
compatibility with the internalist conception of reasons. But it will be helpful to
begin with a closer look at Kant’s conception of imperatives and Kant’s conception of
ends.
4.3 Three imperatives
Kant distinguishes between three different kinds of imperatives early in
Section II of the Groundwork. He explains that imperatives are “commands” of
reason, which carry normative force, observing, “[a]ll imperatives are expressed by
an ought and indicate by this the relation of an objective law of reason to a will that
by its subjective constitution is not necessarily determined by it.”100 The Kantian
imperatives, then, express standards of practical rationality for beings who are
capable of rational action but who sometimes fail to act rationally. I will briefly
discuss the three imperatives, because they draw distinctions that are important to
understanding Kant’s argument for the formula of humanity.
The first (and most narrowly binding) kind of imperative is the instrumental
imperative, which Kant also calls the imperative of skill. With regard to imperatives
of skill, Kant writes, “[w]hether the end is rational and good is not at all the
question…, but only what one must do in order to attain it.”101 The general form of
this kind of imperative is: if you fully will an effect or end you must also will the
100
Ibid., p. 24 (4:413).
101
Ibid., p. 26 (4:415).
101
action or means requisite to it.102 Kant regards this as an analytically (and therefore
necessarily) true statement. That is, he thinks that contained within the idea of
willing an end is the idea of also willing the means to that end.103 The example of an
internal reason discussed earlier, the reason I have to leave my office now if I want
to catch the 6 o’clock train home, can be restated as an instrumental imperative: if
you want to catch the 6 o’clock train home, leave your office now. Here’s another
example: if you want white teeth, brush them regularly. Kant points out that
instrumental imperatives like these are hypothetical. Their bindingness is
conditional on the adoption of certain discretionary ends, in this case, that of
catching the 6 o’clock train home, or of having white teeth. If I don’t intend to catch
the train, or don’t desire to have white teeth, then, in the absence of other ends these
actions serve, the imperatives “leave your office now” and “brush regularly” do not
apply to me.
The instrumental imperative is, then, a law of reason that has a lot to say
about how we may deliberate without saying anything about what it is we are
deliberating about. In other words, it determines the proper procedure for our
deliberation without determining its substance. Kant’s first imperative of practical
102
Ibid., p. 28 (4:417).
103
In calling his imperative “analytic,” Kant is not making an empirical claim about the extent to
which people actually adhere to the instrumental imperative, nor is he making the non‐empirical
claim that it is impossible to fail to comply with it. Willing is an act of reason, and Kant believes that
the imperative applies (a priori) to any act of reason. People must adhere to it to the extent that they
are acting rationally. Kant is not claiming that people always act rationally, nor would he. He
specifically states that the imperative is the proper way of expressing “the relation of an objective
law of reason to a will that by its subjective constitution is not necessarily determined by it” (Kant, p.
24 (4:413)), that is, to beings who have the capacity to be fully rational, but are not always fully
rational. See Thomas Hill’s Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant’s Moral Theory, pp. 18–19, for further
discussion.
102
reason, the instrumental imperative, underlines the fact that Kant, like internalists
Hume and Williams, believes that the scope of the normativity of a reason statement
extends to include corrections of instrumental reasoning. Because it reflects a
procedural restriction on rationality, Kant’s instrumental imperative is compatible
with an internalist conception of reasons.
Although Kant’s characterization of the instrumental imperative suggests
that his conception of rationality is procedural, his discussion of the second
imperative of practical reason, the prudential imperative, is more ambiguous
between procedural and substantive notions of rationality. The general form of this
imperative is: promote your own happiness, or take the means to your own greatest
well‐being.104 As with the instrumental imperative described above, Kant attributes
a certain necessity to our adherence to this principle. That is, he thinks that willing
one’s own happiness is as necessarily true for rational beings as is willing the means
to the ends one wills. There is an obvious difference between instrumental
imperatives like the ones given above and imperatives of prudence. The former
address discretionary ends, like having white teeth, which human beings may or
may not set themselves according to their individual preferences or inclinations,
whereas the latter refer to ends that Kant thinks that all human beings (indeed all
rational beings) “necessarily” set themselves.
Nonetheless, there is a distinct similarity between Kant’s argument
concerning instrumental imperatives and his argument concerning prudential
104
Kant, Groundwork, pp. 26‐27 (4:415‐416).
103
imperatives. When discussing instrumental imperatives, he appealed to what he
considered to be analytically true about the nature of rationality: that one cannot, if
one is rational, fail to will the means to a willed end. In making the case for the
bindingness of the prudential imperative, Kant again appeals to an analytic truth
about rational nature. He writes of happiness that it “can be presupposed [as an
end] surely and a priori in the case of every human being, because it belongs to his
essence.”105 In other words, the idea of setting one’s happiness as an end is
contained within the idea of a rational being itself. Kant also characterizes this
imperative as hypothetical, because it also is conditional on the willing of an end,
albeit an end every rational being actually—even necessarily—sets himself.
Kant’s positing of a prudential imperative of reason raises some concerns for
an internalist interpretation of his argument. By maintaining that all rational beings
necessarily set happiness as their end, isn’t Kant demonstrating a substantive notion
of rationality?106 Kant’s discussion of prudence and happiness provokes a further
Ibid., p. 26 (4:415‐416). This formulation makes it sound like Kant thinks the pursuit of happiness
is part of the essence of human nature, as opposed to rational nature. So why interpret Kant as
claiming that the bindingness of the prudential imperative is an analytic truth about rationality, as
opposed to humanity? It helps to bear in mind that when Kant refers to our humanity, he has our
rational capacities in mind. Our humanity, according to Kant, simply is our (distinctively human)
capacity for self‐directed rational behavior.
Kant is reluctant to characterize the prudential imperative as fully analytic or even as
binding fully a priori, because, he writes, the indefinite and subjective nature of happiness makes the
question of what it is to set one’s happiness as an end a partially empirical one. If the idea were less
“indeterminate,” Kant states, then this proposition would be “just as analytic” as the previous one
concerning instrumental imperatives. See p. 28 (4:417‐418).
105
106
Kant himself seems reluctant to characterize happiness as an end that is “required by reason,” in
the same way that he thinks we are rationally required to treat humanity as an end. He writes of
happiness that it is an end rational beings hold by a “natural necessity.” The notion of natural
necessity suggests at least an analogy with the laws of nature, which would seem, given Kant’s
picture of the natural world, to put happiness out of the realm of rational choice entirely (and into,
perhaps, the realm of inclinations). But if this is the case, it’s not clear why Kant believes in the
(continued on next page)
104
question, about what kind of thing he took happiness to be, and why he associated it
with prudence. Although clues may be difficult to find in Kant (they are certainly
difficult to find in the Groundwork), thinking about how the question might be
answered is useful in understanding the role the prudential imperative plays in
Kant’s conception of rationality. In particular, it suggests to me ways in which
prudential concerns can be accommodated by a procedural conception of
rationality. But happiness is not, ultimately, the end on which Kant thinks the moral
law is built, for reasons that I will come to in a moment. So the substantive element
in Kant’s notion of rationality that is suggested by his discussion of happiness in the
Groundwork does not pose a threat to my main purpose in examining his argument:
to defend the compatibility of an internalist conception of reasons (and a procedural
notion of rationality) with universally‐shared moral reasons. For this reason, I will
set the question of prudence aside for the time being, though I’ll return to it briefly
in the next chapter.107
The last kind of imperative that Kant discusses is the categorical imperative.
Kant writes of this imperative that only it “declares an action to be itself objectively
necessary without reference to some purpose, that is, even apart from any other
end.”108 Kant uses language like this repeatedly in describing the categorical
imperative. For example, at 4:414, he defines it as representing an action as
existence of a prudential imperative of practical reason at all. I will return to this issue in Chapter 5
(§5.3).
107
See especially §5.3 below. I should note that a commitment to substantive rationality is usually
accompanied by a commitment to procedural rationality, the narrower of the two notions.
108
Kant, Groundwork, p. 26 (4:415).
105
“objectively necessary of itself, without reference to another end,”109 and at 4:416,
he writes that it, “without being based upon and having as its condition any other
purpose to be attained by certain conduct, commands this conduct immediately.”110
There are a couple of things which all of these descriptions have in common.
First, all three description suggest that the basis of a categorical imperative does not
lie in a desired effect of some action, be it possibly desired (as in the case of
instrumental imperatives) or actually desired (as with prudential imperatives), but
rather has something to do with the nature of rational action itself. Secondly, all
three descriptions deny the dependence of the categorical imperative on some
“other end” or “other purpose.” Kant’s choice of phrasing leaves us asking, ‘other
than what?’
Other than the action itself? Kant’s phrasing certainly suggests this reading.
And Kant does seem to think that, in a sense, morally required actions should be
performed for their own sakes. But this certainly shouldn’t be read as entailing that
the moral law never tells us to perform some action for the sake of achieving
something else, or for the sake of its beneficial effects – that, say, the moral law tells
me to jump into the pond for the sake of jumping into the pond, not for the sake of
saving the drowning child. That would be a crazy view. Kant may mean that I
should perform the morally required action for the sake of performing the morally
required action. Indeed, this seems, for better or for worse, to be entailed by his
109
Ibid., p. 25 (4:414).
110
Ibid., p. 27 (4:416).
106
view of moral worth, defended in Section I of the Groundwork.111 Or he may mean
that when the moral law tells me to jump into the pond to save the drowning child, I
have reason to do this without needing some further, external incentive (like a
promised reward) to do it. This is, I think, the most plausible way of reading Kant’s
claims here. It ties Kant’s account of the nature of the categorical imperative
together with his diagnosis of where previous accounts of the bindingness of
morality have gone wrong, which I discussed in the last section.
In any case, Kant’s wording suggests that even categorical imperatives relate
to some kind of end, but one which is not an effect of the action to which they refer.
Kant has not yet explained what sort of end this might be, or in what way it is
inherent in rational actions rather than a consequence or effect of them, or even
what an end that is not an effect might look like. Although these intimations are
unargued for at this early stage, they foreshadow Kant’s discussion of the formula of
humanity later in Section II of the Groundwork.
For now, Kant simply tells us that if there is moral law, it must take the form
of a categorical imperative. What exactly is it about the categorical imperative that
gives it a better claim to universality or law‐likeness than the hypothetical
imperatives of skill or prudence? For to say that the former is unconditionally
binding, whereas the latter two are binding only under certain conditions is, I think,
misleading. Both hypothetical imperatives can, according to Kant, be shown a priori
to apply to all rational beings. That instrumental imperatives are demonstrable a
111
This view of moral worth is, I think, a mistake, and in particular, should not be embraced by a
Kantian, but the reasons for this are not relevant here. See my “Acting for the Right Reasons.”
107
priori is clear because their validity is an analytic certainty. Kant thinks that part of
the essence of (rationally) willing an end is also willing the means to that end. This
therefore holds for any rational act of willing at all, a priori, that is, regardless of the
particular end in question. Similarly, Kant states that the prudential imperative is
applicable a priori to the actions of any rational being, because, again, it is part of the
“essence” of a rational being that she desire her own happiness.
The difference in generality cannot lie in the generality of bindingness of
categorical as opposed to hypothetical imperatives. It lies instead in the disparity in
generality among the kinds of ends to which each imperative refers. Kant argues
that neither the discretionary ends that underlie particular instrumental
imperatives nor the “naturally necessitated” end of happiness, which underlies the
prudential imperative, can serve as the foundation for the moral law. In the case of
instrumental imperatives this seems clear enough. The adoption of the ends
involved in these is dictated purely by the particular inclinations of the particular
agent and involves no rational necessity at all. One could never, for example,
establish a moral law to act in a certain way based on a desire for white teeth,
because many rational beings may simply, and without irrationality, not desire to
have white teeth, and therefore have no reason to adhere to the law – or at least, as
Kant notes, no reason in the absence of external incentives to do so. This line of
thinking suggests, however, that the case for the failure of prudential ends to
establish moral laws is much less clear. After all, Kant explicitly states that “[t]here
is …one end that can be presupposed as actual in the case of all rational beings…by a
108
natural necessity, and that…is happiness.”112 Why can’t the end of happiness, which
seems, by Kant’s own admission, to be completely universal among rational beings,
be used to ground the moral law?
This is, after all, arguably what some utilitarians try to do. Utilitarians might
argue, like Kant, that all rational beings necessarily set happiness as their chief end,
and that therefore a universal moral principle (a categorical imperative, in fact) can
be based on the notion of maximizing that happiness. So their categorical
imperative states: act so as to maximize the happiness resulting from your actions. In
other words, utilitarians might contend that since it is true that rational beings
categorically prefer their happiness to any other end, then the hypothetical
imperative which says ‘if you value happiness above any other end, then act so as to
maximize happiness’ becomes the categorical imperative I just stated. That is, it
applies universally to all actions and all persons. Utilitarianism gains a large part of
its appeal from the seemingly uncontroversial importance almost everyone attaches
to the end that its categorical imperative promotes.
In fact, John Stuart Mill sets out to “prove” the principle of utility along just
these lines. “[T]he sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable,”
Mill says, “is that people actually do desire it.”113 And then he proceeds, infamously,
to argue from this premise, plus the rather dubious empirical claim that happiness is
the only thing all people desire and desire for its own sake, to the conclusion that
the moral law requires that we maximize happiness. The objection has often been
112
Kant, Groundwork, p. 26 (4:415‐416).
113
Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 34.
109
pressed, against Mill, that the purely descriptive, psychological, fact (if it is one) that
everyone desires happiness (and only happiness) for its own sake cannot establish
the normative conclusion that only happiness ought to be desired for its own sake.
But we could, instead, put an internalist spin on Mill’s argument, and some things
Mill says suggest that such a spin may be appropriate. “[Q]uestions of ultimate ends
do not admit of proof,”114 he says, echoing Hume’s claim that “the ultimate ends of
human actions can never, in any case, be accounted for by reason,”115 and presaging
the common internalist claim that the choice of ultimate ends, itself, lies beyond
rationality. But if happiness is the ultimate end of every person, as Mill argues that
it is, then it could serve as a source of reasons everyone can share.
The question this imperative immediately raises, however, and the question
the Kantian may ask concerning the prudential imperative, is ‘whose happiness?’
The utilitarian categorical imperative tells us maximize happiness in general. But
even if it is true that I necessarily value my own happiness above any other finite
end, and that it is the only thing I value non‐instrumentally, this says nothing about
how I value your happiness or anyone else’s. Sidgwick convincingly dismantles
Mill’s “proof” along these lines. That the general happiness ought to be desired,
Sidgwick argues, “is not established by Mill’s reasoning, even if we grant that what is
actually desired may legitimately inferred to be in this sense desirable”:
For an aggregate of actual desires, each directed towards a different
part of the general happiness, does not constitute an actual desire for
the general happiness, existing in any individual; and Mill would
114
Ibid.
115
Hume, Enquiry, p. 293 (Second Enquiry, Appendix I).
110
certainly not contend that a desire which does not exist in any
individual can possibly exist in an aggregate of individuals. There
being no actual desire – so far as this reasoning goes – for the general
happiness, the proposition that the general happiness is desirable
cannot be in this way established.116
Mill seems at times to recognize this problem. At the start of Chapter III of
Utilitarianism, immediately preceding his “Proof” of the principle of utility, Mill asks
what the source of the obligation of the moral law is, what the motives to obey it are,
and how it derives its driving force. (Tellingly, he treats these questions as more or
less equivalent.117) He does not say that the universally‐shared end of happiness is
the source of the motivation and the obligation to maximize happiness. Instead, he
claims that the binding force of the principle of utility, and our motivation to obey it,
depend on the presence of “external” sanctions (such as the threat of punishment or
disapproval by others) and “internal” sanctions (such as an attack of guilty
conscience).118 But as we have seen, both these incentives to obey the moral
principle are external in Kant’s sense, and Kant has argued, in my view convincingly,
that such ulterior motives cannot be the source of the normativity of the moral law,
if it exists.
So Mill’s view that we all value our own happiness non‐instrumentally, which
Kant shares, does not establish that happiness is the end on which the moral law is
built, and cannot explain why we have reason to value and promote the happiness of
others. Happiness, even if it is at some general level a universally shared end,
116
Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, p. 388.
117
A slide between talk of obligating or justifying and motivating force is a common internalist ‘tell.’
118
Mill, Utilitarianism, pp. 27‐28.
111
cannot be the foundation for the moral law because what I in fact value when I set
happiness as my end is not the same thing as what you value when you set
happiness as your end. For I value my happiness and you value your happiness.
Moreover (as Kant also suggests119), our concept of happiness is so nebulous that
what I think constitutes happiness may be very different from what you think
constitutes happiness, and whether it is or isn’t is an entirely empirical question,
which cannot be settled a priori. In any case, Kant says, we do not value happiness
wherever we find it. Sadistic pleasures, for example, surely have no value. Kant
writes:
an impartial rational spectator can take no delight in seeing the
uninterrupted prosperity of a being graced with no feature of a pure
and good will, so that a good will seems to constitute the
indispensable condition even of worthiness to be happy.120
So happiness is not really a case of an end that all rational beings share. It cannot
provide every rational being with the same internal reason, and so it cannot form
the basis of a categorical imperative.
Whether or not we agree with Kant’s concession to the utilitarian that we
always value our own happiness (and I’ll return to this question in §5.3, below), or
with his harsh assessment of the value (or lack thereof) of the happiness of wrong‐
doers, Kant’s argument suggests a reason we have to value the happiness of others
to which the utilitarian, who takes happiness to be fundamentally valuable and
indeed the only unconditionally, non‐instrumentally valuable thing, cannot appeal.
119
Kant, Groundwork, p. 28 (4:418).
120
Ibid., p. 7 (4:393).
112
We have reason to value the happiness of others because they value their own
happiness, and we (for some reason) value them. As Parfit has pointed out, the
classical utilitarian seems to have to prefer a world with many millions of
inhabitants who are only slightly happy to a much less populated world in which all
the inhabitants were extremely happy.121 But this is very counter‐intuitive. As Jan
Narveson has put it, what matters, morally, is making people happy, not making
happy people.122 These worries about utilitarianism already point strongly in the
direction of Kant’s conclusion that humanity, rather than happiness, should be the
end on which moral laws are built.
But I am jumping ahead of myself.
4.4 Humanity as an end
At this point it is useful to take a much closer look at what Kant has in mind
when he is speaking of ends. Kant’s account of ends is somewhat ambiguous. At
4:427 he defines an end as that which “serves the will as the objective ground of its
self‐determination.” This can perhaps be loosely translated like this: an end is the
motive from which we perform a certain action. Kant adds that ends, “if given by
reason alone, must hold equally for all rational beings.”123 In other words, if the
121 This is the so‐called “Repugnant Conclusion.” As Parfit expresses it, this version of utilitarianism
commits its defender to the view that “for any possible population [of a reasonably large number of]
people, there must be some much larger imaginable population whose existence, if other things are
equal, would be better, even though its members have lives that are barely worth living.” (See Parfit,
Reasons and Persons, p. 388.)
122
See Narveson, “Moral Problems of Population,” p. 80.
123
Kant, Groundwork, p. 36 (4:427).
113
motive from which we perform an action is purely rational (i.e., is given to us by the
requirements of rationality alone, and so is in no way based on individual
inclination), then it is a valid reason for every rational being to perform the same
action. The standard conception of ends is as effects of actions – the things at which
our actions aim. But Kant has already hinted to us that the end that is to support the
categorical imperative does not take the form of a desired effect of a possible action.
So one question that our investigation of Kant’s understanding of ends should
answer is this: what does an end look like that is not the desired effect of an action?
Another confusing aspect of Kant’s discussion of ends in 4:428 is that he
seems to waver between searching for an end that is necessarily shared by all
rational beings (that is, a universal end) and searching for something he calls an
“end in itself.” So another question our discussion of Kant’s conception of ends
should answer is how these two could amount to the same thing.
As I say, we are used to thinking of ends as the effects of our actions, or as
things at which we aim. For example, in the case of the instrumental imperative I
mentioned earlier—if you want white teeth, brush them regularly—having white
teeth is the end at which we aim, and of which the action of regular brushing is to be
the cause. Similarly, in the case of the prudential imperative, we see our happiness
as our end because it is the thing at which we aim and which we hope our actions
will bring into effect. Kant’s conception of ends is somewhat different, and, though it
can account for the kinds of things we generally see as ends, it allows for a larger
114
variety of candidates. Allen Wood usefully explains Kant’s broader conception of an
end as “anything for the sake of which we act.”124
This understanding of ends sits nicely with the version of internalism about
reasons I have explored and defended. It is worth noting that it comes very close to
Bernard Williams’ own conception. Williams, remember, allows for the possibility
that we have reason to perform actions that serve our ends in ways that are not
straight‐forwardly instrumental (perhaps, for example, the action in question is
constitutive of some end or commitment, or expresses that commitment),125 and
thus argues that the kinds of things that can occupy an agent's motivational set go
beyond mere possible desired effects of actions. He thinks that principles,
commitments, values, indeed (to borrow again from Wood), anything for the sake of
which we act may belong in a motivational set.126 The Wood interpretation gives a
good general account of how Kant thinks of ends. But the function Kant’s concept of
ends plays in his argument is a more specific one. Kant thinks of ends as worth‐
bestowers—as things that bring value to our actions, or, as I will argue, to our other
ends.127
The Kantian conception of ends as worth‐bestowers will identify as ends all
the things we usually think of as ends. Look, for example, at how this works in the
case of the instrumental imperative just mentioned: if you want white teeth, brush
124
Wood, p. 116.
125
Williams, “Internal and External Reasons,” p. 104.
126
Ibid., p. 105.
127
Kant never defines an end in this way explicitly, but his discussion of ends in 4:428 repeatedly
makes reference to their worth‐bestowing quality, and this understanding is in no way incompatible
with the definition he does give us of ends as reasons for acting.
115
them regularly. Now having white teeth is the end at work in the imperative
because it is what gives value to my act of regular brushing. Without the end of
having white teeth (or some other end), to which regular brushing is the means,
such brushing would have no value for me at all. Again, the prudential imperative
follows a similar course: if happiness were not valuable to me, my actions towards
achieving happiness would have no value.128
But this conception will also allow for other kinds of things to be ends, and
this suggests an answer to the first question about ends that I posed: how an end
may be something other than the effect of an action. If an end is understood as a
worth‐bestower – as something that gives value to our actions or less fundamental
ends, by being the thing for the sake of which we pursue those actions and ends –
then there is no reason to think that only the effect of an action can be an end.
Moreover, as my earlier worries about utilitarianism suggested, in the case of
conditional ends‐to‐be‐affected (such as white teeth or happiness) we will soon
want (as I will argue) to go beyond seeing how they bestow worth on our actions
and ask what it is that gives them (that is, the ends themselves) their worth. And
this will not be the effect of an action; we often – perhaps usually – act for the sake
of ourselves, and other people. We value happiness not as some kind of abstract
It might be argued that we don’t always think of ends as effects of our actions. Sometimes, for
example, we see our actions as intrinsically valuable, as when I paint for the sake of painting.
Painting is not an effect of the activity of painting. If this is right, then Kant’s understanding of ends is
closer to our natural understanding than I suggest. This, if anything, makes the understanding of
ends as worth‐bestowers more persuasive: it can explain how an action can have worth independent
of its effects, which is something utilitarians, for example, have trouble explaining.
128
116
good, for which people are a necessary carrier, but because people value it, and we
value them. That is the sense in which humanity itself can be an end.
These thoughts in turn suggest an answer to the second question I posed:
how the “universal end” and the “end in itself” can be one and the same. For they
suggest that one thing that could be a universal end—that is, a worth‐bestower for
all rational beings—is something to which the worth of all actions and conditional
ends may be traced back, but whose own worth is conditional on nothing. In other
words: the thing that is of value in itself, and not just because it is desired, or, the
end in itself.
The internalist structure Kant’s argument for the formula of humanity will
take is now clear. Its central idea is this: if there is one end whose value to us can
be inferred from the value of all our contingently chosen ends—an end which is
valuable to each of us to the extent that we are rational, because its value is a
condition of the value of those other ends—then this end can perhaps serve as the
basis of a moral law that each of us has internal reasons to uphold.
4.5 The “unconditioned condition” of value
Kant’s argument in 4:428 pulls his ideas about the nature of the end in itself
together into a recognizable form: that of humanity. There are, I think, two kinds of
argument running through Kant’s discussion. The first is a first‐order normative
argument based on Kant’s intuitions about what is valuable; the second is a kind of
structural argument about what our own ends and value‐commitments, whatever
they are, commit us to. As it stands, the first argument is more persuasive than the
117
second. But they are, potentially, mutually reinforcing; and I think that the second,
structural argument can be improved upon. When it is, it can provide an internalist
defense of a first‐order normative principle that the first kind of argument shows to
be independently intuitively appealing. In what remains of this chapter, I will just
set out Kant’s two arguments, and flag some worries they raise and some gaps that
they leave open. In the next two chapters, I’ll try to fill in those gaps with a revised
version of Kant’s second, structural argument. In the final chapter, I’ll begin to
sketch the normative ethical view these Kantian internalist arguments entail.
I’ll begin with the argument from normative‐ethical intuitions about value.
This argument is strongly suggested by a passage from 4:428, in which Kant draws a
distinction between what he calls “subjective” and “objective” ends:
Beings the existence of which rests not on our will but on nature, if
they are beings without reason, still have only a relative worth, as
means, and are therefore called things, whereas rational beings are
called persons because their nature already marks them out as an end
in itself, that is, something that may not be used merely as a means,
and hence so far limits all choice (and is an object of respect). These
therefore, are not merely subjective ends, the existence of which has a
worth for us, but rather objective ends, that is, beings the existence of
which is in itself an end, and indeed one such that no other end, to
which they would serve merely as a means, can be put in its place,
since without it nothing of absolute worth would be found anywhere;
but if all worth were merely conditional and therefore contingent,
then no supreme practical principle for reason could be found
anywhere.129
Kant is pointing here to an intuitively very important distinction between
two different ways in which something can have value. Something might have, as
Kant says, “worth for us.” Or it might, instead, be, like us, the sort of thing to whom
129
Kant, Groundwork, p. 37 (4:428) (emphasis in the original).
118
such other things have worth. The former kind of thing has subjective, conditional
value, because its value depends on our wanting or needing it. We are the condition
of its value. Things like this matter only because they matter to us. But it seems like
their mattering to us could make them matter only if we matter – if we have value.
Otherwise, why would their mattering to us give them value? And on pain of regress
or circularity, our having value cannot be, in the same way, conditional on our
mattering to someone. In other words, the first, subjective kind of value turns out to
depend on the second, objective kind. We must have a special, unconditional value.
John Taurek draws the same distinction very nicely. He points out that when
we are deciding which lives to save or which people to rescue, we reason very
differently from how we reason when we are deciding, say, which objects to rescue
from a fire. In the case of objects, we consider how much they’re each worth to us,
and try to save as much value as we can. But people, he says, are different:
when I am moved to rescue human beings from harm in situations of
the kind described, I cannot bring myself to think of them in just this
way. I empathize with them. My concern for what happens to them is
grounded chiefly in the realization that each of them is, as I would be
in his place, terribly concerned about what happens to him. … The
loss of an arm of the Pietà means something to me not because the
Pietà will miss it. But the loss of an arm of a creature like me means
something to me only because I know he will miss it, just as I would
miss mine. …
… It is the loss to the individual that matters to me, not the loss
of the individual.130
If we accept this distinction, we will recognize a need to treat beings like us, to whom
things matter differently from how we treat things that matter to us. Every person
130
Taurek, “Should the Numbers Count?”, pp. 306‐307.
119
may be an object of value to some other person. (In this regard, Taurek’s “only”
seems mistaken.) But she is always—as someone to whom things matter—at the
same time an original source of value, and therefore an objective end‐in‐herself.
Humanity, Kant concludes, should therefore be construed
not as an end of human beings (subjectively), that is, not as an object
that we of ourselves actually make our end, but as an objective end
that, whatever ends we may have, ought as law to constitute the
supreme limiting condition of all subjective ends….131
It’s worth noting that the intuitive distinction to which Kant appeals in these
passages does not seem to draw the line between types of ends where Kant wants it
to be drawn. If the key distinction is between beings to whom things matter –
objective ends – and the things that matter to them – subjective ends, then some
“beings the existence of which rests … on nature” who are “without reason” should
nonetheless fall on the objective side of the divide. For some such beings – non‐
rational animals, infants – surely are beings to whom things matter. The relevant
question seems not to be whether a creature is rational, but whether it is conscious
and sentient: a center of subjectivity. Humanity, on this line of reasoning, will prove
to be only one kind of end in itself. There will be others.
This strikes me as a salutary, if significant, departure from Kant’s view, which
infamously has difficulties in accommodating our intuitions about our obligations to
infants and lower animals. I will return to it in the last chapter of this book. But for
now, let us take stock of how far this intuitive argument will take us. The answer,
given the internalist goals of my project, is not very far. I’ve sketched an (I think)
131
Kant, Groundwork, p. 39 (4:431).
120
intuitively plausible picture of value. But nothing I’ve said thus far shows that this is
a picture that cannot be rationally rejected. As Taurek notes, some utilitarians reject
the picture. According to such utilitarians, happiness has unconditional value: its
value does not depend on our valuing it. Rather, we have reason to value it because
it is independently valuable. And such utilitarians may not recognize sentient
beings as unconditionally valuable – their value – and our reason for protecting
them – may depend on their ability to ‘produce’ happiness.132 Is there any way of
rationally settling the disagreement, despite the differences in what the disputants
judge valuable at the outset? This, after all, was what I was after: a moral law that
we’re all required to uphold, regardless of our initial value commitments, on pain of
procedural irrationality.
The second, structural argument Kant makes in defense of the formula of
humanity seems designed to fill this need. He argues, as Christine Korsgaard puts it,
by means of a “regress of conditions” – and takes himself to have shown that we’re
all committed to valuing humanity as an end in itself, regardless of what we
contingently value, because of the relationship the end of humanity stands in to our
other ends: its value is the only possible condition of the value of our contingent
ends.
The frustrating thing about the argument for the formula of humanity as Kant
lays it out in 4:428 is that he seems to make only half of it explicitly, and the less
132
See Taurek, pp. 299‐300. Some non‐utilitarians will of course also reject this picture of value:
they may think, for example, that some things, such as the natural world, have value independently of
their having value for any sentient, valuing being.
121
important half at that. Let’s examine that argument piece by piece. After explaining
his conception of ends, Kant begins:
The ends that a rational being proposes at his discretion as effects of
his actions (material ends) are all only relative, for only their mere
relation to a specially constituted faculty of desire on the part of the
subject gives them their worth, which can therefore furnish no
universal principles, no principles valid and necessary for all rational
beings and also for every volition, that is, no practical laws. Hence all
these relative ends are only the ground of hypothetical imperatives.133
Kant is here reiterating the internalist thought that all of my discretionary
ends – the things I happen to try to bring about – matter only because they matter to
me, and they do that only because my faculty of desire happens to be constituted a
certain way: I happen to want them. If I hadn’t had the desires I have, I would have
had no reason to pursue them; the mere fact that these are (as it happens) ends of
mine can’t give other people reason to pursue them. And indeed, even if we all
happened to desire the same thing (as Hume, remember, thought we did134), it
would still be true that had we not happened to share these values, we would have
had no reason to pursue their targets.
Because of this, no such discretionary end can ground categorical principles
of practical reason – moral laws. At most (if Hume is right, and there is a universally
valued end) they could ground imperatives to act that are contingently universal (so
long as we’re constituted the way we are). But the moral imperative, if there is one,
133
Kant, Groundwork, p. 36 (4:428).
134
Remember that Hume thought that all people, at least “while the human heart is compounded of
the same elements as at present,” valued social stability and the public good, at least to some extent
(see §1.4 above).
122
necessarily binds all rational beings – we would not be tempted to withdraw a moral
judgment if we were to learn that its object simply doesn’t care.
Kant continues:
But suppose there were something the existence of which in itself has
an absolute worth, something which as an end in itself could be a
ground of determinate laws; then in it, and in it alone, would lie the
ground of a possible categorical imperative, that is, of a practical
law.135
Here Kant says that if there to be a categorically, unconditionally, necessarily
binding moral law, it must be grounded in an end that we’re all required to value,
because it is valuable in itself, and not just because we happen to value it.
Kant then proposes what this end might be, and what the corresponding law
would look like:
Now I say that the human being and in general every rational being
exists as an end in itself, not merely as a means to be used by this or
that will at its discretion; instead he must in all his actions, whether
directed to himself or also to other rational beings, always be
regarded at the same time as an end.136
We are ourselves the end we were looking for – the things that have that special kind
of value that is not conditional on being valued.
Why think this? Kant begins his defense of this thesis by means of a process
of elimination. First, as we’ve already seen,
All objects of the inclinations have only a conditional worth; for, if
there were not inclinations and the needs based on them, their object
would be without worth.137
135
Kant, Groundwork, p. 36 (4:428).
136
Ibid., p. 37 (4:428).
Ibid. Allen Wood seems to interpret Kant differently here: he suggests that Kant is merely
claiming that no object of inclination considered simply as such is an end in itself (though we may
happen to have an inclination for something that is an end in itself). (See Wood, pp. 123‐124.) But
(continued on next page)
137
123
Kant continues:
But the inclinations themselves, as sources of needs, are so far from
having an absolute worth, so as to make one wish to have them, that it
must instead be the universal wish of every rational being to be
altogether free of them. Thus the worth of any object to be acquired
by our action is always conditional.
Kant’s claim here seems too strong: it’s certainly not true that it’s the wish of every
rational being to be free of inclinations. But it is true that we don’t see our
inclination for something to be a sufficient condition for its worth. We have some
inclinations – like cravings or addictions – we would rather be rid of. Our being
inclined towards an end does not make it good. Even if it did, it would not follow
that our inclinations have absolute worth: something may be valuable because of
my need for it, but that doesn’t make my need valuable. Even if my craving for a
cigarette gives the cigarette some value, surely the craving itself has no value.138
The passage also suggests that the process Kant goes through to identify the
end in itself is the one of tracing value‐dependency indicated by my earlier
discussion of his understanding of ends. The worth of our actions is based on the
worth of the ends or objects at which they aim. The worth of those objects is in turn
that would make Kant’s claim tautologous (at least if we take an “end in itself” to be something that is
intrinsically valuable: valuable by itself, insolation, in virtue of its intrinsic properties. Because Kant
would then be claiming that nothing can be intrinsically valuable (valuable in virtue of its intrinsic
properties) in virtue of being an object of someone’s inclination – a claim that seems fairly vacuous.
What’s more, as Wood acknowledges (p. 124), if this were Kant’s meaning, it would do little to
establish his apparent inference, at 4:428 (below), that the worth of any object to be acquired by our
action is always conditional.
138 This passage shows that Kant does not think that all conditions of value are thereby made
valuable. He explicitly says that inclinations are conditions (though perhaps not sufficient
conditions) for the value of their objects. But he does not think it follows that the inclinations
themselves are therefore valuable. This will be important later (see §5.4).
124
(in part) dependent on inclinations to them themselves, or, ultimately, on our
tendency to have those inclinations, that is, on our neediness. And Kant points out
(it seems to me rightly, although he puts the case too strongly) that neediness is not
something to which we would attribute some sort of absolute worth, but is rather
something we tend to regret.
The conclusion that therefore “the worth of any object to be acquired by our
action is always conditional” is, however, somewhat premature. Because we are
rational beings, some of the ends we set ourselves and the actions they demand are
picked out not just by inclination but by our capacity for rational choice. Willing is,
after all, an act of reason (although it is in some cases triggered by inclination). So
the line of argument Kant follows in the case of inclinations should also be followed
for the case of rational choice. This is the argument Kant fails to make in this
passage. But it would run roughly as follows:
All objects of rational choice have only conditional worth; for if there
were not our rational choices, or rather, our capacity for rational
choice, their object would be without worth. That is, our actions gain
their worth from the rationally chosen ends at which they aim, and
these ends, in turn, gain their worth from the rational natures that set
them. The worth of a rational nature is not based on any outside
source, but rather such a nature is an end in itself, with absolute
worth, and the source of worth of all of our ends and actions.
Therefore, Kant states, it is the rational nature of persons that marks them out as
ends in themselves.
Why must we believe that our rational nature is an end in itself, on pain of
irrationality? Kant says, towards the bottom of the paragraph I have been
examining, that if we failed to attribute absolute worth to rational nature, “nothing
of absolute worth would be found anywhere; but if all worth were conditional and
125
therefore contingent, then no supreme practical principle for reason [i.e., no moral
law] could be found anywhere.”139 But this formulation is surely somewhat
question‐begging. Kant cannot demonstrate the truth of the formula of humanity by
maintaining that if his formulation is not true, then morality itself (or at least any
kind of realist, objective conception of morality) is a fiction. Kant’s argument, as he
himself admits, is not sufficient to show that the moral law is real, but, at best, what
it would look like if it did exist—namely, that it would be a categorical imperative
based on the (conjectural) universal end in itself: rational nature. Kant’s argument
aims to identify the conditions under which the truth of a moral law is possible—the
existence of an end that can serve as the unconditioned condition of value—but he
as yet provides no reason why we should suppose that the conditions for morality
obtain. As yet, that is, he has not provided a response to the skeptical Humean view
that rationality does not demand that we be moral.
Kant’s argument, if it works, would, however, achieve something else that is
of great importance to my project: it links the conditions for morality to the
conditions for practical reason itself. It thereby ties the fate of the view that we all
have reason to be moral to the fates of other less robust forms of faith in practical
reason: indeed, to the very possibility of rational action. Kant argues that if we
failed to attribute absolute worth to rational nature, then there would be nothing on
which to support the worth of the contingent ends which we all value. If the ends
that we set ourselves are valuable—if, that is, it is the case that we have reasons to
139
Ibid., p. 37 (4:428).
126
act on them—then this can only because the absolute worth of humanity can serve
as a foundation for the worth of those ends. We must assume the worth of humanity
if we are to defensibly claim that we value our own contingent ends with reason.
A question arises: let’s grant for the time being that, since I value the ends I
set myself, I must, if I am rational, also value myself as an absolute end. But I don’t
need to value the ends you set yourself, so why need I value you as an absolute end?
In other words, how is the end picked out by this argument any more universal than
the end of happiness we considered earlier?
But, Kant might respond, I have a distinctive kind of value not because my
name is Julia Markovits or because I’m my exact height, or because I was born on a
Sunday, but because my capacity for rational choice gives me a worth‐bestowing
status. That this is so is clear from that fact that not just any end I set myself is
valuable as a result, but only those ends I choose rationally. So Kant’s argument
implies that all rational beings must attribute value to their own persons, at least
insofar as they exercise their capacity for rational choice. But this capacity is, of
course, not unique to me. It is also what makes every other rational being valuable
in their own eyes. As Kant puts it:
rational nature exists as an end in itself. The human being necessarily
represents his own existence in this way; so far it is thus a subjective
principle of human actions. But every other rational being also
represents his existence in this way consequent on just the same
rational ground that also holds for me; thus it is at the same time an
objective principle, from which as a supreme practical ground, it must
be possible to derive all laws of the will.140
140
Kant, Groundwork, pp. 37‐38 (4:428‐429).
127
So it is a characteristic inherent in rational nature as such, and not just my own
rational nature, that it exists as an end in itself (or at least we must assume it to be
an inherent quality of rational nature if we want to rationally act on the basis of our
ends). This means, Kant says, that if I rationally value my own ends, then I must
view rational nature as such, and therefore any rational nature, as an end in itself,
including, for example, yours.
Kant concludes:
The practical imperative will therefore be the following: So act that
you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any
other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means.141
This, then, is how the Kantian argument is supposed to work. It begins from
an optimism about what we have reason to do:
(1) I value the ends I rationally set myself, and take myself to have reason to
pursue them.
It then appeals to an internalist‐flavored premise:
(2) But I recognize that their value is only conditional: if I did not set them as my
ends, I would have no reason to pursue them.
But, Kant asks, why think that we can generate reasons to promote some end just by
adopting it? We must, he says, think that we have the power to confer value on our
ends by rationally choosing them:
(3) So I must see myself as having a worth‐bestowing status.
From this Kant seems to infer that we must accord ourselves unconditional worth:
141
Ibid., p. 38 (4:429).
128
(4) So I must see myself as having an unconditional value – as being an end in
myself and the condition of the value of my chosen ends – in virtue of my
capacity to bestow worth on my ends by rationally choosing them.
But I recognize that the same argument holds from your perspective, and for your
rational nature, and so consistency requires that I attribute the same worth‐
bestowing status, and so the same unconditional value, to you, and to any other
rational being:
(5) I must similarly accord any other rational being the same unconditional value
I accord myself.
Hence the formula of humanity:
(6) So I should act in a manner that respects this unconditional value: I should use
humanity, whether in my own person or in the person of any other, always at
the same time as an end, never merely as means.
What this imperative demands is that one never behave towards another person in
a way that fails to respect the capacity for rational choice in which her humanity
consists. For to neglect in one’s actions to treat humanity (that is, the capacity for
rational choice) as an end would be to disregard the very thing that gave those
actions, and the personal ends at which they aim, their value.142
142
This argument is an example of what Kant has called a “transcendental argument.” It offers as a
premise a description of the world as we take it to be, and works backwards from there to a
conclusion about what must be that case for it to be like that. In this case, Kant argues that we take
the world to be full of valuable ends which we have reason to pursue, and that this can only be an
accurate description of the world if a source for the value of those ends can be identified.
This is perhaps why Kant does not take himself to have conclusively proven the existence of
a moral categorical imperative by the end of Section II of the Groundwork. It might yet turn out that
our vision of the world as endowed with value, and of ourselves as acting for reasons, is simply a
false one. (This might be the case, for example, if there was no freedom in the world, only the
mechanical following of effect upon cause, as determined by physical laws.)
The transcendental nature of Kant’s argument also suggests that Kant’s moral imperative,
although universally binding on all rational beings, is not categorical in the strictest sense of the
word. It does apply to us whatever we want or will, but only provided that we want or will something.
(This reflects Kant’s internalism about reasons: we cannot be rationally bound by a law that is
completely disconnected from any motivational facts about us.) I return to this issue in Chapter 6.
129
4.6 Worries about Kant’s argument
Christine Korsgaard summarizes Kant’s argument this way:
If we regard our actions as rational, we must regard our ends as good;
if so, we accord to ourselves a power of conferring goodness on the
objects of our choice and we must accord the same power – and so the
same intrinsic worth – to others.143
On its face, it exhibits some glaring vulnerabilities. Rae Langton observes that “an
unsympathetic reader may be tempted to view it as a chain of non sequitors.” (She
adds, “a sympathetic one will rightly ask to see more of the argument before coming
to judgment.”) But, she notes,
It seems, on the face of it, that I could regard my actions as rational
without regarding my ends as good. I could regard my ends as good
without according to myself a power of conferring goodness on the
objects of my choice. I could accord to myself a power of conferring
goodness on the objects of my choice without according the same
power to others. I could accord to others the power of conferring
goodness on the objects of their choice without according intrinsic
value to them. I could accord intrinsic value to them without their
having, or acquiring, intrinsic value.144
Langton has a point. The first step of the argument may be relatively
unproblematic, if we understand the claim that an end is good, or valuable, as the
claim that we have reason to adopt (pursue, protect, respect, or promote) it. And
the last worry is one that Kant appears simply to concede: he does not take himself
to have shown that the moral law is “real”, but only that we’re committed to it if we
take any of our ends to be good. But what is supposed to be irrational (especially,
143
Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends, pp. 261‐262.
144
Langton, “Objective and Unconditioned Value,” p. 169.
130
procedurally irrational) about denying Kant’s, second, internalist premise – about
simply taking each of my ends to be valuable in itself, independently of my having
chosen to pursue it? If I think this, then, it seems, I can see my ends as good without
granting myself worth‐bestowing status at all. And even if I concede that my end’s
value is somehow conditional on me, why conclude from this that I must have must
have value, much less unconditional, intrinsic value? After all, hasn’t Kant conceded
(for the case of inclinations) that some conditions of value aren’t, thereby, valuable
themselves? This, at least, seems hard to question: infection makes penicillin
valuable, but infection isn’t therefore valuable, much less intrinsically valuable. And
the cubic press, the machine which turns graphite into diamonds, makes carbon
valuable, but is itself only instrumentally, not intrinsically valuable.
And it is far from clear, in any case, on the basis of what Kant has said, that I
(rather than something else) must be the ultimate source of value of my ends, even
if we allow that the source of their value, whatever it is, is intrinsically valuable.
And even if I am the intrinsically valuable source of the value of my ends, what
commits me to think you are an intrinsically valuable source of value, too? Why
can’t I think it’s something special about me that gives me this status?
To these worries, Langton adds more troubling worries about the conclusion
of Kant’s argument. According to Korsgaard’s Kant, she says,
The ability of choosers to confer value on their choices – the ability of
agents to be value‐conferrers – is … the very source of the intrinsic
value … of persons. We have intrinsic value because we value things
as ends, conferring (extrinsic) value on them.145
145
Ibid., p. 168.
131
As she puts it later: “I do value; therefore I have value.”146 But this, she worries, has
decidedly troubling implications. In particular, and most worryingly for Langton, it
seems to entail that persons who don’t value things as ends – who cease to have
desires – lose their value.
Langton considers Maria von Herbert, Kant’s ill‐fated young epistolary
partner, struggling against an overwhelming depression: “I feel that a vast
emptiness extends inside me, and all around me—,” Maria writes, “so that I almost
find myself to be superfluous, unnecessary. Nothing attracts me….” “Maria,”
Langton tells us, “does not value other things; and she does not value herself.” 147
Must we, if we accept Kant’s conclusion, agree with Maria that she has no value?
Langton argues that this is the implication of the Kantian argument I have
developed:
[Maria von Herbert] does not value other things, and she does not
value herself. We must assume that, in Korsgaard’s terms, she does
not confer value on other things and does not confer value on herself.
But think: if we only have value because we do value ourselves, then
our conclusion is a bleak one. Maria von Herbert does not have value.
Maria von Herbert, acute philosopher, spurned lover, eloquent
correspondent, is nothing. Sunk in apathy and self‐loathing, she has
lost what made her valuable. She thinks she does not matter – and she
is right. Her conclusion that she should put an end to her life is, in
these terms, justified. That is what we should say, and we should not
shed tears when we learn that she put her conclusion into practice a
few years later.148
146
Ibid., p. 169.
147
Ibid., p. 159.
148
Ibid., p. 181 (emphasis in the original).
132
Kant’s conclusion may have other troubling implications. If it’s our
conferring value on other things through acts of rational choice that gives us our
value, must we agree, with Kant, that animals and infants who have no rational
capacities to exercise have no intrinsic value? This seems in tension with the
“intuitive argument” I (loosely) ascribed to Kant – the one echoed by Taurek’s point
about the Pietà – according to which all beings to whom things matter have a special
intrinsic value that things that merely matter to us lack.
The worries raised by Maria’s predicament reach beyond cases of severe
depression. If persons are valuable because they make other things valuable, doesn’t
that suggest that, even when they do confer value on some ends, they themselves
have a kind of instrumental, extrinsic value – that their value somehow derives from
the value they generate? On this picture, people would indeed seem to have the
same sort of value as the cubic press. Such machines are valuable because they
make other things valuable. Are we really to conclude that we’re valuable only in
the way the press is valuable – because we turn lumps of valueless world – like
lumps of graphite – into the good stuff? Surely Kant was after the opposite
conclusion – that the value of our ends derives from our value? Wasn’t that, again,
the point of the intuitive argument – the point about the special sort of value held by
beings to whom things matter?
Kant’s argument can, I think, be defended against some of these charges. And
it can be supplemented and revised to avoid others. In its revised form, it may still
have some counterintuitive implications. But it also, I believe, has significant
intuitive appeal. It gains some of this appeal from its resonance with Taurek’s point.
133
It gains further appeal from its compatibility with the internalist conception of
reasons, which, I’ve argued, we have independent reason to embrace. I will turn, in
the next chapter, to spelling out this revised version of the Kantian view – one
designed more explicitly to fit within an internalist conception of reasons.
134
Chapter 5
Kantian Internalism
5.1 Skepticism about procedural practical rationality
To recap: According to the version of internalism about practical reasons I
am most interested in defending, for some agent A to have a reason to perform some
action φ, that action must be related to A’s “motivational set” in a particular way.
More specifically, a reason for an agent to φ is a consideration that counts in favor of
φ‐ing – that throws its justificatory weight behind φ−ing – in virtue of the relation it
shows φ−ing to stand in to the agent’s existing ends (for example, by showing that
φ−ing is a means to one of those ends, or constitutive of it, or valuable in
consequence of the value of that end). Put in an over‐simplified way, an internal
interpretation of reasons is one that takes an agent A to have a reason to φ if and
only if A has (or would, after procedurally rational deliberation, have) some end the
attainment of which will be served by his φ‐ing. It follows from the internalist
picture that if we are rational relative to our ends (broadly understood), then we are
rational, all things considered. On the externalist view, defended, for example, by
Derek Parfit, what reasons we have need be in no way connected to the ends that we
in fact hold.
I have argued (in Chapter 3) that we have good grounds for accepting this
internalist account of reasons for action. I will not rehearse those arguments in
favor of internalism here. I will instead try to defend the view against perhaps the
most forceful objection leveled at it from the externalist camp: that it commits us to
135
the undesirable conclusion that someone may have no reason to do what is in his
own best interests, or to do as morality requires. I noted in Chapter 1 that the
response of some prominent internalists to this objection, Williams, Harman, Foot,
and Hume among them, has been to simply bite the bullet.149 I believe, however,
internalism about reasons places more restrictions on rational action than most
externalists and internalists have allowed,150 and in particular, that it is compatible
with the view that we always have most reason to do as morality requires.
As I argued earlier,151 the internalist/externalist distinction about reasons
can be re‐characterized as a distinction concerning the nature of practical reason.
Parfit, following Williams, defines the difference between a procedural (internalist)
and a substantive (externalist) notion of rationality as follows:
To be procedurally rational we must deliberate in certain ways, but
we are not required to have any particular desires or aims, such as
149
As I discussed in Chapter 1, Williams has, for example, accepted the possibility of a cruel husband
who in fact has no reason to be kinder to his wife. (See “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of
Blame,” p. 39; on the possibility of people who have no reason to pursue what they need, see also,
“Internal and External Reasons,” p. 105). Harman, notoriously, has claimed that it would be false to
say of Hitler that he had reason not to order the extermination of the Jews, or even that he ought not
to have done so. (See “Moral Relativism Defended,” especially pp. 3‐11) Foot allows that some
people may have no reason to do as morality requires. (See “Morality as a System of Hypothetical
Imperatives, especially pp. 161‐162.) And Hume infamously acknowledged such possibilities, writing
of prudence,
’Tis [not] contrary to reason to prefer even my own acknowledg’d lesser good to my
greater,
and of morality,
’Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the
scratching of my finger.
(See Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature, p. 416 (II, 3, iii).)
150 Michael Smith is a notable exception (see The Moral Problem and “Internal Reasons,” especially
section 2).
151
See §.3.1.
136
concern about our own well‐being. … To be substantively rational, we
must care about certain things, such as our own well‐being.152
Given the goals of my argument, this way of expressing the difference between
procedural and substantive views of rationality is question‐begging. It assumes the
truth of the conclusion I am arguing against: that on a procedural conception of
rationality, we are not rationally required to hold prudential or moral ends or
commitments.153
It is not easy to restate the distinction without relying on this conclusion. I
think that the two conceptions of rationality differ not in their characterization of
whether reason can demand that we hold certain ends, but rather in their
characterization of how and under what circumstances reason can give us ends.
According to a procedural notion of rationality, the rational requirement to hold
certain ends is generated indirectly by the relation of those ends to other ends we
do hold, as a result, in particular, of requirements of internal consistency and
coherence.154 One might compare this to the case of theoretical reason, which may
require us, by means of standards of internal consistency and coherence, to hold
152
Parfit, “Reasons and Motivation,” p. 101. Parfit introduces the labels “procedural” and
“substantive”, but he is drawing on a distinction Williams himself makes (see “Internal Reasons and
the Obscurity of Blame,” p. 36). Williams talks not about “procedural” versus “substantive” notions of
rationality, but about the difference between setting normative standards for what counts as a
“sound deliberative route,” and setting such standards for what should belong in an agent’s
subjective motivational set “from the outside,” as a result of “prudential and moral considerations.”
153
Another way of making this point is by pointing out that, drawn this way, the distinction between
procedural and substantive rationality makes internalism about reasons incompatible with a rational
requirement to be moral by definition.
154
Of course, the standard of procedural rationality places many other requirements on us that may
not be requirements to hold certain ends; it dictates relations between our beliefs and intentions
more generally. One prominent example of a requirement of procedural rationality which need not
be a requirement to hold a certain end is the instrumental requirement that we adjust our means to
our ends (discussed further below).
137
certain beliefs in virtue of their relationship to other beliefs that we hold. According
to a substantive notion of rationality, reason may require us to hold some (moral
and prudential) ends directly, and regardless of what else is true about us. I take
this to be the distinction Williams and Parfit have in mind, expressed now in a non‐
question‐begging way. It is this distinction with which I will work. I will draw on an
expansion and revision of Kant’s argument for the “formula of humanity” in the
Groundwork (spelled out in the last chapter) in support of the view that procedural
rationality can also demand of us that we hold particular ends.
I’ll begin, however, by recalling why Hume thought that it could not. In A
Treatise of Human Nature Hume writes:
A passion is an original existence, or, if you will, modification of
existence, and contains not any representative quality, which renders
it a copy of any other existence or modification. When I am angry, I
am actually possest with the passion, and in that emotion have no
more a reference to any other object, than when I am thirsty, or sick,
or more than five foot high. ’Tis impossible, therefore, that this
passion can be oppos’d by, or be contradictory to truth and reason;
since this contradiction consists in the disagreement of ideas,
consider’d as copies, with those objects, which they represent.155
Beliefs – the ‘inputs’ of theoretical reasoning – can themselves be rational or
irrational, on Hume’s view, because they can reproduce the world they represent
well or poorly. But, because desires for particular ends are “original existences,”
Hume says, rather than interpretations of the world we see around us, they cannot
be true or false in the same way. To say of a desire that it is contrary to reason
would be like saying that it is contrary to reason to be thirsty, or sick, or five foot
155
Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, p. 415 (II, 3, iii).
138
tall. Reason dictates relations between ideas, and hence determines the proper
means of deliberation. But it cannot determine the desires that we deliberate about.
Hume argues that it follows from this that it need not be irrational to be imprudent
or immoral: again, at the very least, if we are rational relative to our desires, then
we are rational all things considered.
Hume sometimes writes as if he thinks we can never be truly practically
irrational—that is, be irrational in our actions and passions. He alleges that
passions can be “unreasonable” only when they (i) are founded on the supposition
of the existence of objects that don’t really exist (as when, for example, we are afraid
of ghosts), or (ii) rest on mistaken judgments of cause and effect (this is Hume’s
explanation of apparent cases of instrumental irrationality—when someone takes
means insufficient to the satisfaction of her desires).156 In both these cases, we
seem to be guilty not of practical irrationality, but rather of holding false beliefs.
Statements like these have led some interpreters (notably Elijah Millgram157) to
class Hume as holding an eliminativist view of practical reason, according to which
only beliefs, and not actions or desires, could ever be rational or irrational.
As Christine Korsgaard has observed, this rather anemic analysis of practical
irrationality seems to leave out some paradigm cases of irrationality, such as
weakness of the will. She points out that practical and theoretical reason both have
what she calls an “internalism requirement”: we are not practically rational unless
our recognition that some action is the means to an end we will is accompanied by a
156
Ibid., p. 416 (II, 3, iii).
157
See Millgram, “Was Hume a Humean?”, especially §1.
139
transmitting of motive force from the end to the means in question, any more than
we are theoretically rational if we are able to perform logical and inductive
operations without becoming convinced of the conclusions of those operations.158
More generally, someone who fails to act as she knows she has most reason to act is
practically irrational, just as someone who fails to believe what she know she has
most (epistemic) reason to believe is theoretically irrational. We are not rational if
we merely pay the requirements of practical reason lip‐service.
Hume’s leanings towards eliminativism are informative: his rejection of the
possibility that desires can be irrational, especially when taken together with his
caveat about the two sorts of cases in which we might say of a “passion” that it is
“unreasonable,” draws attention to a puzzle posed by his discussion. Hume writes
that passions cannot “be oppos’d by, or be contradictory to truth and reason; since
this contradiction consists in the disagreement of ideas, consider’d as copies, with
those objects, which they represent.” Unlike beliefs, desires, the suggestion is,
cannot be true or false. The caveat suggests a similar focus: it notes that while
passions cannot be true or false, they can result from or be explained by false
beliefs. But how does this bear on the question of whether passions can be
“contradictory to reason”? We know from the theoretical case that truth and
rationality come apart. Truth is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for
the rationality of beliefs: we might have a false but rational belief, and we might
158
Korsgaard, pp. 319‐320.
140
have a true belief that is irrational. So the mere fact that passions cannot be true
does not obviously entail that they cannot be irrational.
There may be a way in which beliefs can be irrational that desires and ends
can’t be: beliefs can fail to accurately represent the world (or perhaps, the world as
it appears to be), but desires, since they don’t try to represent the world, can’t be
irrational in that way. But beliefs aren’t just the inputs to reasoning but also its
outputs; and the same, of course, is true of desires, intentions, and ends. Beliefs can
be irrational in virtue of standing in the wrong relation to the world, but they can
also be irrational in virtue of standing in the wrong relation to each other; they can
conflict. And this latter kind of irrationality is also one that desires and ends can
exhibit, even if they are “original existences.”159
Our ends may conflict in a variety of ways, just as our beliefs may conflict in a
variety of ways. My beliefs are irrationally inconsistent when I believe two
propositions that straightforwardly contradict one another. This is the case when I
159
Hume’s choice of analogies suggests another argument for the conclusion that passions cannot be
irrational: he writes that they can no more be irrational than it could be irrational to be thirsty, or
sick, of five feet tall. We are not guilty of irrationality if we find ourselves in these states not because
as “original existences” they cannot be true or false, but rather because we generally have no control
over such states. And it might be argued that our desires are at least often also beyond our control.
But our actions and intentions generally are under our control. (Hume’s word “passions,” because it
seems to be most naturally replaced by the more modern word “desires,” conceals the fact that his
theory, at least in the form adopted by Williams, is intended to describe the conditions not just for
irrational desire, but for irrational action and intention as well.) It may well be irrational, if we are
thirsty and desire not to be thirsty, to decline the offer of a drink. Similarly, it may well be irrational,
if we are sick, to refuse the medicine we need to get better. And while it may not be irrational to have
selfish desires (if we cannot help having them), it may be irrational to act on them. Whether such
actions are irrational is the chief question we set out to answer at the start of this chapter, and
Hume’s argument fails, I think, to establish that it should be answered in the negative.
The Kantian point of view suggests that the Humean picture should be amended. As rational
beings, we deliberate not about desires but about ends. That we may have conflicting desires is,
unfortunately, simply a fact of human psychology. But, according to Kant, we cannot, if we are
rational, will conflicting ends. Willing an end involves must more than desiring it or wishing for it: it
involves a commitment to act towards it should the means be or become available.
141
believe that p and believe that not p at the same time. Similarly, I am practically
irrational when I value an end—that is, take it to provide me with a valid reason for
acting—when deliberating about one case, but overtly fail to value it—fail to
recognize it as providing me with reasons for acting—when deliberating about
another, relevantly similar case. For example, it would be irrational for me to take
the value of a long and healthy life as a reason not to smoke, but not to take it as a
reason to stop drinking excessively. Of course, I may have overriding reasons to
continue drinking which don’t apply in the case of smoking—maybe drinking gives
me significantly greater pleasure than smoking does. But this will not change the
fact that the value of a long and healthy life should give me some reason—albeit a
losing reason—to refrain from excessive drinking. The end of living a long, healthy
life ought always to motivate me, even if it need not always move me.
But our beliefs may also be irrationally inconsistent or lacking in coherence
in other ways. They are so, for example, if (i) I believe that p is true and know that q
and p cannot both be true, but still believe that q is true. They are so, as well, if (ii) I
believe that p is true, and know that the truth of q is a necessary consequence of the
truth of p, but fail to believe that q is true (at least if it matters to me whether q is
true).160 To make a distinct point,161 my beliefs are irrationally lacking in coherence
160
The parenthetical qualification is necessary here because I am probably not rationally required to
believe all of the entailed consequences of my present beliefs when many of those consequences are
irrelevant to me, especially when the entailment is not immediately obvious. (This point is due to
John Broome. An alternative statement of the requirement, also suggested by Broome, is this:
“Rationality requires of you that, if you believe p and you believe (if p then q), and if it matters to you
whether q, then you believe q.” (See Broome, “Does Rationality Give Us Reasons?,” pp. 322‐323.)) In
what follows, I’ll omit the qualification in the interests of simplicity.
161
Is this point really distinct? Formally, it doesn’t seem to be: there’s no formal difference between
q’s being a necessary condition for p and q’s being a necessary consequence of p. Both terms express,
(continued on next page)
142
if (iii) I believe that p is true, know that the truth of q is a necessary condition for the
truth of p, but, again, fail to believe that q is true.162 I believe that a similar set of
restrictions binds the ends we may rationally hold, and that once these restrictions
are identified, not just instrumental, but also prudential and moral requirements of
procedural rationality emerge. I will try to show that this is the case, by examining
the basis for and implications of each of Kant’s three imperatives of pure practical
reason in turn. Here, for ease of reference, are Kant’s imperatives of pure practical
reason:
The Instrumental Imperative: if you fully will an effect or end you must also
will the action or means requisite to it.163
The Prudential Imperative: promote your own happiness, or take the means to
your own greatest well‐being.164
The Moral Imperative, or “Formula of Humanity”: so act that you use
humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the
same time as an end, never merely as means.165
formally, simply the fact that p entails q. But I want to express the idea that if q is the condition for p,
then q is the reason that p, and if q is the consequence of p, then p is the reason that q; consider “If it
rains tonight (p), the park will be muddy tomorrow (q)”—q is a consequence of p; consider the
different claim “if the park is muddy tomorrow (p*), it will have rained tonight (q*)”— q* is a
condition for p*. We might say that in (ii), q is true in virtue of p, and in (iii), p is true in virtue of q.
Alternatively, we might say that in (ii), p explains q, whereas in (iii), q explains p. Read in any of these
ways, (ii) and (iii) do express distinct ideas.
Again, the qualification “if it matters to me whether q” is probably needed; I leave it out for
convenience.
162
163
Kant, Groundwork, p. 28 (4:417).
164
Ibid., p. 26‐27 (4:415‐416).
165
Ibid., p. 38 (4:429).
143
5.2 The instrumental imperative
Of all the species of skepticism about procedural practical rationality,
skepticism about instrumental rationality is the least common. Most internalists,
including Hume and Bernard Williams, would agree that the scope of normativity of
practical reason extends to cover corrections of instrumental rationality. So of
Kant’s three imperatives, the instrumental imperative, which tells us that we must
will the necessary and available means to the ends that we will, has met with the
least opposition. Most people would agree that if I will the end of having good
dental health, and if I know that flossing my teeth regularly is the only available
means to achieving that end, and I nonetheless do not intend to floss regularly, I am
guilty of irrationality.166 Note that Kant’s imperative places a restriction on what we
can rationally will or intend, rather than on what we can rationally do. Rationality is
a property of my overall mental condition, and while actions can, I think, be
irrational, they are irrational only when they result from mental failings, and not the
interference of forces external to the mind. I cannot be rationally faulted for failing
to floss if my hands are bound behind my back, though I may be faulted for
continuing to intend to floss when I know I can’t. Nor can I be rationally faulted if it
is (in some central sense) possible for me to take the means to my ends, and I try to
166
Broome once again draws attention to a possibly needed qualification of this requirement of
reason: he argues that we are only rationally required to intend the means to our intended ends if we
think they will not come about unless we intend them. (See Broome, “Does Rationality Give Us
Reasons?,” pp. 322‐323.)
144
do so, but I fail out of incompetence (if, say, I’m so bad at flossing that, despite my
best efforts, my trying to do so doesn’t actually help promote my dental health).167
The failure of motivating force to carry through from ends to available
known necessary means constitutes a procedural practical irrationality, just as the
failure of conviction to carry through from a belief to the known necessary
consequence of the belief constitutes a procedural theoretical irrationality: the
former reveals a problem in the relationship between my ends, just as the latter
reveals a problem in the relationship between my beliefs. The example runs parallel
to the case of theoretical irrationality described at (ii) above. Just as my conviction
that p, and my knowledge that q is a necessary consequence of p, require me to
believe that q, my setting good dental health as my end, and my knowledge that
regular flossing is a necessary and available means to that end, require me to also
set regular flossing as my end. The point can also be expressed somewhat
differently, in terms of valuing: it would be irrational to value good dental health,
but not (derivatively) to value regular flossing. The (instrumental) value of regular
flossing is simply a consequence of the value of good dental health, just as, in the
theoretical case, the truth of q is a consequence of the truth of p.
There is a worry raised by this characterization of the instrumental
imperative. We can imagine cases in which the only available means to ends that we
167
If the means to some end are not in my power, it is also not possible for me to will them—thus
external restrictions on physical actions can place restrictions on mental actions as well. Just as I
can’t intend what I know I can’t do, I also can’t will what I know I can’t do.
It might be suggested that I could act irrationally without being in an irrational mental state
if I fail to be motivated to do what I will/intend to do, even though I will/intend to do as I have most
reason to do. I’m not convinced that weakness of the will of this sort is even a conceptual possibility:
being motivated to φ may be a constitutive part of an intention to φ.
145
will are prohibitively costly—perhaps even morally abhorrent. (Perhaps there’s a
life‐threatening time‐sensitive emergency I should respond to, and I’m
contemplating flossing before I run out the door.) In such cases, is it still irrational
for me not to take the only available means to my end? The question is a
particularly worrying one from the Kantian perspective, because, if its answer is yes,
then it would seem that Kant’s instrumental and moral imperatives of reason, each
of which he takes to apply universally and a priori to any of our actions, could
conflict.
However, as Thomas Hill has pointed out, the Kantian imperatives need not
conflict in cases like this. This is because the instrumental imperative is disjunctive:
it states not that we must always will the means to our willed ends, but that we must
either will the means or give up the end. Thus it is always possible to comply with
both imperatives by simply giving up the end that requires immoral means, at least
until less problematic means become available. 168 We might in such a case continue
to will the end if we believe that less objectionable means will become available in
the future (though they are not yet available). But in this case, we believe that the
means we refuse to take are not necessary to the achievement of our willed end, so
the instrumental imperative does not require us to take them.
The case of willing an end that can be achieved only by immoral means is
similar to any non‐moral case in which we will conflicting ends. Here a comparison
Hill, p. 24. In giving up the end—that is, ceasing to will the end—one need not give up wanting or
wishing for the end. It is, of course, perfectly rational to want or wish for an end to which no
reasonable means are available—indeed, to which no means at all are available. As noted earlier,
willing an end involves more than this: it involves something closer to a resolved intention to pursue
the end.
168
146
with the theoretical irrationality described at (i) above is useful: I cannot rationally
believe that p is true, know that p and q cannot both be true, and still believe that q
is true (if it matters to me whether q); I must, if I am rational, give up my faith in
either p or q. Similarly, I cannot rationally will each of two incompatible ends. I
cannot will that I arrive at my lecture on time (if a punctual arrival would require
me to ride my bicycle to class), and at the same time will to take a leisurely stroll to
my department building. I must either give up on punctuality, or give up the stroll.
In cases where the achievement of a contingently willed end requires immoral
means—that is, means that violate Kant’s moral imperative as expressed by the
formula of humanity—the end with which my contingent end conflicts is the
rationally required end of humanity itself. In such a case, I can rationally give up
only one of the conflicting ends: my contingent end. (Of course, given the worries
raised by Kant’s argument, as I developed it in Chapter 4, it remains to be
established that humanity is a rationally required end, on the internalist conception
of rationality.)
The preceding discussion significantly oversimplifies the nature of the
instrumental decisions we face. The circumstance in which there is only one means
available to the achievement of a certain end is surely a rather special case. More
commonly, there are a number of available means to take to an end, none of which is
necessary to achieving it. Some means will stand out as better than the alternatives
because pursuing them interferes less with our pursuit of the other ends we will. In
this case, does the procedural conception of rationality I am defending require us to
take means that seem to us at least as good as any of the available alternatives?
147
I think it does. (Forgive the rather reader‐unfriendly use of schematic letters
to represent ends and means, to which I’ll resort for efficiency’s sake.) Let’s say I
will three ends: X, Y, and Z. There are two possible means of achieving each of these
ends, respectively: x1 and x2, y1 and y2, and z1 and z2. While it is possible for me to
undertake all three of x1, y1, and z1, allowing me to achieve all three of my ends,
undertaking any two of x2, y2, or z2 will preclude me from undertaking the third (or
any alternative means to its associated end). What can be said of the scenario in
which I choose to undertake x2 and y2, thereby ruling out the possibility of doing z1
or z2? Is such a choice procedurally irrational? If I make this choice, I achieve X and
Y, but there are means that are necessary for the achievement of Z and that were
available to me that I failed to take. True, z1 and z2 are not available to me given my
decision to pursue x2 and y2; but the means to Z were available to me before I made
that decision. Making that decision amounted to failing to will the available means
to the achievement of Z, despite my commitment to achieving that end. And this
violates the instrumental imperative of rationality.
Sometimes, of course, we find ourselves faced with choices that are not so
straightforward: we are forced to make trade‐offs. Perhaps we can either achieve X
and Y, or achieve only Z. The account of instrumental rationality I am offering
dictates that in cases of conflicting ends, where it is impossible to achieve all of the
ends we set ourselves, we must give up some of the ends, until we are left with a
compatible set. But there is in such a case more than one way to resolve the conflict.
We can stop willing X and Y, or stop willing Z. Which end we give up will usually be
a matter of preference—some of our ends are more important to us than others.
148
But here the externalist worry once again rears its head: aren’t there some ends
which we simply oughtn’t to give up when they come into conflict with others—
ends which we have overriding prudential or moral reasons to pursue? And can a
procedural account of rationality explain why this is the case?
5.3 The prudential imperative
Kant’s prudential imperative is more problematic from an internalist
perspective than his instrumental imperative for two reasons: first, as I noted in the
last chapter,169 it seems at least initially to fit more easily into a substantive
conception of reason than a procedural one; for this reason, skepticism about
prudential rationality is much more common among advocates of a procedural
conception of practical reason than skepticism about instrumental rationality.170
Secondly, the prudential imperative looks more likely to conflict with Kant’s
categorical moral imperative, in the sense that it may sometimes be impossible to
comply with both. Both these difficulties result from the fact that the prudential
imperative appears to posit a necessary end: Kant writes,
[t]here is …one end that can be presupposed as actual in the case of all
rational beings…, and therefore one purpose that they not merely
could have but that we can safely presuppose they all actually do have,
by a natural necessity, and that purpose is happiness.171
169
See §4.2.
170
As I have noted, both Hume and Williams are skeptics about prudential rationality.
171
Kant, p. 26 (4:415).
149
The imperative of prudence tells us to will the means to our own happiness.172 The
quoted passage raises several questions. Firstly, what does Kant mean when he
writes that happiness is an end we hold by “natural necessity”? Are we also
rationally required to hold it, as is suggested by the classification of the prudential
imperative as an imperative of reason? How could this be, given a procedural
conception of rationality? Secondly, what exactly does Kant understand under the
concept of happiness, and why does he link it to that of prudence? Thirdly, given
that the prudential imperative, unlike the instrumental imperative, seems to posit a
necessary end, could the prudential and the moral imperatives conflict?173
I’ll begin with the first of these questions. Kant’s appeal in his discussion of
happiness to the notion of an end we hold by “natural necessity” seems to contradict
his idea of freedom. In The Metaphysics of Morals Kant writes:
An end is an object of free choice; … and since no one can have an end
without himself making the object of his choice into an end, to have
any end of action whatsoever is an act of freedom on the part of the
acting subject, not an effect of nature.174
Ends, Kant says, are – as a conceptual matter – freely chosen. (In the Groundwork,
too, Kant defines an end as “that which serves the will as the objective ground of its
172
It is difficult to state precisely what Kant thinks the prudential imperative requires of us because
he never actually states it in imperative form in the Groundwork.
173
There are any number of competing possible interpretations of Kant’s discussion of the prudential
imperative in the Groundwork. While I think the interpretation that I offer in the pages that follow
has some textual support, as well as the merit of allowing us to read Kant as employing a uniform
conception of practical reason throughout his argument, I acknowledge that other interpretations
may well be better supported by the text. My main interest is not in Kantian interpretation, but in
whether it is possible to build prudential and moral ‘oughts’ on the foundation of a procedural
conception of rationality. Kant’s argument seems to me very suggestive in this regard.
174
Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals (1797), p. 516 (6:385).
150
self‐determination.”175) If our natural inclinations required us to adopt certain ends,
then we would lack the free will that Kant takes to be a necessary condition of moral
responsibility. But Kant seems in the Groundwork to suggest that all human beings
by their nature necessarily will their own happiness, and set it as their end. Does it
follow that the will does not freely choose its ends after all?
Moreover, if we understand happiness in an ordinary way—as an end that
can compete with our other ends—then the claim that all human beings necessarily
will their own happiness as an end (indeed, as the prudential imperative suggests,
prioritize it above their other ends) seems both disconnected from prudential
concerns, and, quite simply, empirically false. We would not describe, say, an artist,
or a scientist, who places more importance on a successful career or on valuable
contributions to her field than on her happiness as imprudent. We might well
describe her as imprudent if she sacrificed her health or future well‐being to the
pursuit of success. Prudence seems much more strongly connected with concern for
these things than for happiness. Moreover, as the example of the dedicated artist or
scientist shows, people often do put other ends before happiness.176
More significantly, if we interpret “happiness” in this way, and take Kant’s
assertion that all rational beings have happiness as their end by “natural necessity”
at face value, this does give rise to the possibility of conflict between the dictates of
Kant’s prudential and moral imperatives. As Thomas Hill notes,
175
Kant, Groundwork, p. 36 (4:427) (my emphasis).
The claim that everyone desires his own happiness (though he may abandon it as an end) is more
plausible, although there again seem to be counterexamples.
176
151
if we understand happiness in an ordinary way, there may be times
when unless we do something immoral we shall lose all hope of
happiness. Then if we cannot abandon the end of happiness, we
cannot satisfy both the [moral] Categorical and the [prudential]
Hypothetical Imperative.177
It was precisely the fact that any of our contingent ends could be abandoned that
secured the compatibility of Kant’s instrumental and moral imperatives. If the
prudential imperative posits a particular end to be achieved that we by our very
nature cannot abandon, then a possible incompatibility between the prudential and
moral imperatives of reason poses a very real threat to Kant’s picture of practical
reason.
One response Kant might make to this worry is that we are required to
abandon some natural end for the sake of a moral one only if it would be possible
for us to do that. If we can’t stop having happiness as one of our ends, we aren’t
then failing to do something we ought to do, since ‘ought’ implies ‘can’.178 But as I
noted earlier, this response doesn’t seem to fit well with Kant’s ideas about the
freedom of the will. It also seems exceedingly unlikely that Kant would have
excused us from doing what was morally best whenever it conflicted with our own
self‐interest. That seems to be resolving the potential conflict between the moral
and prudential imperatives in the wrong direction, in favor of the latter.
The first task in addressing these difficulties will be to try to understand
more fully just what, according to Kant, happiness is. The above objections give us
good reason to doubt that Kant has an ordinary notion of happiness in mind. Kant
177
Hill, p. 25, footnote 3.
178
This response was suggested to me by Derek Parfit.
152
tells us several things about happiness in the Groundwork. At 4:399 he writes of
happiness that
it is just in this idea that all inclinations unite into one sum.179
At 4:405 he reiterates:
the entire satisfaction of [a human being’s needs and inclinations] he
sums up under the name of happiness.180
In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant defines happiness in a similar way, again linking
it to the idea of prudence:
the doctrine of prudence [unifies] all ends that are given to us by our
inclinations into the single end of happiness.181
And at 4:418 of the Groundwork he adds:
For the idea of happiness there is required an absolute whole, a
maximum of well‐being in my present condition and in every future
condition.182
These excerpts suggest that Kant understands happiness to be a kind of
umbrella‐end that gathers all of an agent’s particular contingent (inclination‐based)
ends under one name.183 If this way of understanding Kant’s conception of
happiness is the right one, then Kant’s claim that all rational beings set happiness as
their end seems not only more plausible than before, but indeed, almost trivially
true. It merely amounts to claim that if we value each of our contingent ends‐to‐be‐
179
Kant, Groundwork, p. 12 (4:399).
180
Ibid., p. 17 (4:405).
181
Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787), p. 674 (A800/B828).
182
Kant, Groundwork, p. 28 (4:418).
This seems at least to be one of the central conceptions of happiness with which Kant works. In
other passages he seems to appeal to a purely hedonistic conception. I adopt the conception above
because it is, of course, far more congenial to my purposes.
183
153
effected, then we value all of our contingent ends‐to‐be‐effected. And if, as the
instrumental imperative requires, we must will the available means to each of our
contingently willed ends, then, as the prudential imperative requires, we must will
the means to all of our contingently willed ends.184 We must do so not out of a
natural necessity, but rather out of rational necessity: the inference seems to be one
that is easily accommodated by a procedural conception of rationality.185 The
parallel with theoretical reasoning once again helps bring this out: if I believe p and
I believe q and I believe r, then I am rationally required to believe p and q and r. The
prudential imperative becomes simply a generalized form of the instrumental
imperative.186
184
Remember that the instrumental imperative has already precluded the willing of incompatible
ends (see §5.2 above).
None of this helps explain why Kant claims we will our happiness out of a natural necessity. This
raises further exegetical questions, but I’m more concerned here with piecing together a version of
his view that can help underwrite my internalist argument than with interpreting Kant himself in a
way that allows for consistency across his writings. This sticky task I leave to others.
185
186 Although the conjunction principle of theoretical rationality to which I’ve just appealed seems
intuitive enough, it raises a worry that a version of the familiar paradox about lotteries helps to bring
out. If I rationally ought to believe that each ticket in a million‐ticket lottery won’t win, does it follow
that I rationally ought to believe that all of the tickets won’t win?
The paradox doesn’t present a problem for just the conjunction principle. That principle is
merely a particular case of a more general and equally plausible principle of theoretical rationality
that requires that I believe what is logically entailed by my other beliefs (at least if the entailment
matters to me or is obvious).
How worrying need this be for my parallel account of practical rationality? I think it needn’t
be terribly worrying, because there seems to be no parallel problem raised by the conjunction
principle when it is applied to the practical case. If I am committed to the value of p and committed to
the value of q and committed to the value of r, it is plausible to claim that I am committed to the value
of (p and q and r). The epistemic paradox seems essentially to concern the problem of how we should
respond to extremely small possibilities, and there is no parallel to this problem in the case of the
prudential imperative. Moreover, we feel the lottery paradox presents a paradox, and not merely a
good reason to abandon the conjunction principle, precisely because each step in the story—
certainly the appeal to the conjunction principle itself—are so plausible. In the absence of a good
reason to abandon the conjunction principle in the practical case, I think we can retain it.
154
This understanding of happiness as a kind of umbrella‐end helps to link
Kant’s prudential imperative to our more standard notion of prudence, and to more
commonly recognized prudential ends, such as health and future well‐being. The
prudential imperative recommends the setting of health as an end because it is
instrumentally valuable to many of our most important contingently willed ends:
long life, a successful career, good spirits, and so on. It is true that the imperative
does not give health the inviolable status of a necessary end. Nor do I think it
should: there are certainly imaginable circumstances in which we should be willing
to sacrifice concern for health for the sake of some more valuable end—perhaps a
moral one.
But here a worry I raised at the end of my discussion of the instrumental
imperative resurfaces. I pointed out there that when two or more of our
contingently willed ends conflict, so that we cannot rationally will all of them, there
are usually a number of ways in which we can revise our ends to make them
coherent—it is, from the point of view of instrumental rationality, up to us which
ends we abandon. The instrumental imperative leaves this indeterminate. Imagine
a man who wants a long and happy life, in which he achieves success in his career
and builds good relationships with family and friends. But he also wants a drink far
more often than is compatible with his achieving or even pursuing his other goals.
He cannot rationally will that he drink heavily as long as he rationally wills the
achievement of his nobler ambitions. But can he rationally give up those other ends
in favor of drinking himself into an early grave? Or, to borrow an example from
Williams, can I rationally refuse the medicine I know I need? It seems, and the
155
externalist would insist, that the imagined heavy drinker has good reasons to stop
drinking—much better reasons than his reasons to abandon his other ends;
similarly, it seems I have good reasons to take the medicine I know I need—
prudential reasons that apply to me independently of any desire I have to take it.
Does a Kantian internalist have to be skeptical about such reasons?
There are really two concerns raised by such examples. The first is that,
faced with conflicting present inclination‐based ends, a person could meet the
requirements of procedural practical rationality by giving up the ends we intuitively
feel he has good reasons not to give up. The second is that a person might simply
lack any present inclinations to protect or promote his future well‐being. Could
such a person neglect his future needs and remain procedurally rational? I think
both of these concerns can be addressed, but both will require an appeal to Kant’s
third imperative of practical reason—the moral imperative.
Let’s begin with the case of the conflicted drinker. The first thing to note is
that it is not so easy to give up, at will, a commitment to ends like a long, happy life, a
successful career, and good relationships. So most people in the position of the
heavy drinker will be in violation of Kant’s instrumental and prudential imperatives.
But what to say about someone who really does stop caring for these things, and
prefers, instead, a drunken decline? Remember that the moral imperative required
that we treat humanity as an end not only in others but also in our own persons. (A
fuller examination and defense of that imperative, from within an internalist
framework, will be developed in the next section, and what this entails for what we
owe to ourselves (and others) will be explored in Chapter 7.) And it seems likely
156
that respecting our own unconditional value, either as rational beings, or, more
generally, as beings to whom things matter, will prohibit us from taking actions that
will undermine our ability to achieve much of what matters to us, as well as very
likely interfering with our ability to show the proper respect for others.
I will return to the task of fitting this imperative into a procedural conception
of practical reason in a moment. For the time being, I want to emphasize that
certain kinds of self‐destructive behavior that is not irrational on instrumental or
prudential grounds may turn out to be irrational, on the Kantian account I will
develop, on moral grounds. It is likely that the behavior of the conflicted drinker
will fall into this category. Undoubtedly, not all prudential ends that any externalist
might think we have reason to adopt will be required by procedural rationality in
the manner just sketched—there will likely be some differences between what the
externalist and the Kantian internalist can claim we have reason to do. But I think
the most important and most plausible of such ends will be required by the
internalist conception of rationality I defend. I will say more in defense of this view
in the next section, when I discuss Kant’s moral imperative.
The problem of future ends is somewhat more complex. Most of us are
presently concerned for our future well‐being. Not all the inclinations we presently
have are inclinations for the present. Philippa Foot points out:
[It is] useful to point to the heterogeneity within [the class of Kantian
hypothetical imperatives]. Sometimes what a man should do depends
on his passing inclination, as when he wants his coffee hot and should
warm the jug. Sometimes it depends on some long‐term project,
when the feelings and inclinations of the moment are irrelevant. If
one wants to be a respectable philosopher one should get up in the
mornings and do some work, though just at that moment when one
should do it the thought of being a respectable philosopher leaves one
157
cold. It is true nevertheless to say of one, at that moment, that one
wants to be a respectable philosopher….187
She adds in a footnote, “To say that at that moment one wants to be a respectable
philosopher would be another matter. Such a statement requires a special
connexion between the desire and the moment.”188 This is clearly true, and the
distinction she relies on can clearly be drawn. I may now want to have children. But
I don’t want to have children now.
People who really live only in the present are very rare—indeed, I suspect
there are no such people. But it nonetheless seems possible to imagine someone
who has no concern at all for his future well‐being, at least if that future is
somewhat distant. And certainly, most of us at times discount the disvalue of future
discomforts more than is merited on grounds of uncertainty. This seems like
irrational behavior, but how can its irrationality be explained by the procedural
conception? There need be no irrationality involved in believing that p is true now,
while believing not p will be true at some later time. A commitment to the value of
now being pain‐free doesn’t obviously commit me to the value of being pain‐free at
some time in the future. But Kant implies, in the last of the passages from the
Groundwork (4:418) quoted above, that happiness consists in all of our contingently
willed ends: not only in the ends we will to achieve today, but also in our future
willed ends. Thus he suggests that the prudential imperative requires us to take the
means to these ends, as well as to our current ends.
187
Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” p. 158 (my emphasis).
188
Ibid., p. 168.
158
I don’t think this is correct. The prudential imperative alone does not explain
the irrationality of failing to value the avoidance of future pains, in the absence of
any present concern for that future. Here again, I think we must appeal to a version
of Kant’s moral imperative. When I value the avoidance of a present pain more than
the avoidance of future pain I don’t do so because I believe I will not then mind the
pain as much as I do now. (If I did believe this, I would be guilty of holding irrational
beliefs, and not of acting or willing irrationally.) Usually I recognize that for my
future self, the future pain will be just as bad as the present pain would be for me,
now. I know that that future self will want to avoid the pain, and will will its
avoidance if possible. The requirement that I take that future end into account
when I reason is therefore rather like my moral duties to other people. Just as I am
rationally required, according to both the view set out in Chapter 4 and the
expanded and revised version of it I will defend in a moment, to value the ends other
people rationally set themselves, because I am required to value them, I am also
required to value the ends I know I will set myself at some future time. My imagined
present‐dweller owes his future self the same respect he owes to any other person.
I have now answered the first two of the three questions I posed at the
beginning of my discussion of Kant’s prudential imperative. I’ve tried to explain
what Kant understands under the concept of happiness, and explored the relation of
that end to other ends which we more commonly think of as prudential in nature:
our health and future well‐being. The third question asked whether the prudential
imperative, which posits an end we are rationally required to will, could ever come
into conflict with the moral imperative. The claim that the Kantian imperatives
159
state requirements of rationality will be shaken if it is not possible to comply with
all three imperatives at once, because they instruct us to do conflicting things.
This third question can now be answered: if happiness is understood simply
as an “umbrella‐end” that consists of all our individually willed contingent ends‐to‐
be‐effected, then the prudential imperative could not conceivably conflict with the
moral imperative. The pursuit of the end of happiness would come in conflict with
the moral imperative only if some component end of happiness came into conflict
with that imperative. But as I argued in §5.2, if a contingently willed end comes into
conflict with the moral (categorical) imperative, this simply means we are rationally
required to give up the contingent end. Just as we can be released from the rational
requirement to believe p and q and r by giving up belief in the relevant incongruent
component belief, we can, in cases where the moral imperative conflicts with one of
the component ends of our happiness, simply give up willing that component end.
This does not mean that we need give up the end of happiness – understood as an
umbrella end – since it still remains true that we will the attainment of all our
(remaining) rationally willed contingent ends.
It is important to reemphasize the point that Kant (at least as I interpret him
here) is using the notion of happiness in a very non‐standard way in this
argument.189 It would be absurd to suggest that in doing our moral duty we will
never sacrifice our own happiness (understood in the ordinary way), no matter how
189
As I noted before (n. 183), Kant seems at times to be working with a much more standard,
hedonistic, conception of happiness. It’s not clear to me that a consistent conception of happiness
can be pulled out of Kant’s work. As usual, my goal is not exegetical accuracy: I am borrowing from
Kant only selectively, and interpreting his text with a somewhat loose hand, to suit the purposes of
my own internalist argument.
160
many important inclination‐based ends doing so requires us to give up. And Kant, of
course, allows that morality may require us to sacrifice many of our inclination‐
based ends—perhaps even most of them. The point is, rather, that if the argument
of this section is sound, we can do this without violating the dictates of the
prudential imperative, properly understood.
5.4 The moral imperative
The kind of skepticism about procedural practical rationality that I am most
interested in contesting is, of course, skepticism about moral rational requirements.
Both Williams and Hume argue that the adoption of a procedural conception of
practical reason commits one to skepticism about moral rational requirements. A
successful refutation of that skepticism has two components: firstly, it must show
how there can be a particular moral end that is required by a procedural conception
of practical reason. Secondly, it must show why such an end generates moral
rational requirements, instead of functioning simply as one end among others. Why,
in other words, does practical reason demand that we abandon our contingent and
prudential ends in favor of our moral ends whenever the moral imperative and the
instrumental or prudential imperatives threaten to conflict?
The previous chapter explored Kant’s effort to achieve both these tasks: his
argument for the formula of humanity. Kant’s formula of humanity states:
161
So act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the
person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely
as means.190
I’ll quickly summarize the argument. Kant develops the case for the formula
of humanity through a process of tracing value‐dependency. We pursue most of our
ends because they are instrumental to the achievement of more fundamental ends.
The ends that we pursue merely as means to other ends gain their value from the
value of those more fundamental ends; that is, the value of the more fundamental
ends is a condition for the value of our purely instrumental ends. But these more
fundamental ends‐to‐be‐effected are, according to Kant, also not valuable in
themselves, but have as the source of their value the value of the rational natures
that set them. Our ends are valuable only because we rationally choose to set them
as our ends, and we are valuable. Thus the value of rational nature is, according to
Kant, a condition of the value of the contingently chosen ends of our inclinations.
Here is Kant’s argument again, broken into steps:
(1) I value the ends I rationally set myself, and take myself to have reason to
pursue them.
(2) But I recognize that their value is only conditional: if I did not set them as my
ends, I would have no reason to pursue them.
(3) So I must see myself as having a worth‐bestowing status.
(4) So I must see myself as having an unconditional value – as being an end in
myself and the condition of the value of my chosen ends – in virtue of my
capacity to bestow worth on my ends by rationally choosing them.
(5) I must similarly accord any other rational being the same unconditional value
I accord myself.
190
Kant, Groundwork, p. 38 (4:429).
162
(6) So I should act in a manner that respects this unconditional value: I should use
humanity (that is, rational nature), whether in my own person or in the person
of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as means.
At the close of the last chapter, I raised some worries about this argument.
What’s irrational – more specifically, procedurally irrational – about simply taking
each of my ends to be valuable in itself, unconditionally, and independently of my
having chosen to pursue them? And even if I concede that their value is somehow
conditional on me, why conclude from this that I must have intrinsic value? We’ve
seen that not all sources of value are themselves valuable, much less intrinsically so
(infection makes penicillin valuable, but isn’t itself valuable; the cubic press makes
carbon valuable, but is itself only instrumentally, not intrinsically valuable). And it
is far from clear, in any case, on the basis of what Kant has said, that I must be the
ultimate source of value of my ends, even if we concede that the source of their
value is intrinsically valuable. And even if I am the intrinsically valuable source of
value of my ends, what commits me to thinking you are an intrinsically valuable
source of value, too?
My goal now is to fill in and revise the Kantian argument to provide answers
to these questions. My hope is that once the argument is revised, it will also be less
vulnerable to some of the worries raised by Kant’s conclusion: in particular,
Langton’s worry about the value of the clinically depressed Maria von Herbert. I’ll
return to that worry below. First, let’s see if the value‐dependency‐tracing
argument can be made to work.
I noted when discussing the instrumental imperative that it would be
irrational to value an end, but not value the necessary and available means to that
163
end: thus it would be irrational to value the end of good dental health, but not value
regular flossing. The value of the more fundamental end implies the value of the
instrumental end. Kant’s argument for his moral imperative suggests that the
reverse implication may also hold: the value of an instrumentally valuable end
implies the value of the more fundamental end to which it is instrumental. It would
be irrational to value regular flossing without valuing good dental health (in the
absence of other reasons for regularly flossing), or to value good dental health
without valuing pain prevention or a longer life (or any of the other non‐
instrumentally valuable ends to which good dental health is the means). It would be
equally irrational to value my contingent (non‐instrumental) ends without valuing
the source of their value—the value of the rational nature that set them. If I’m
rational, I’ll value flossing because I value good dental health because I value pain
prevention because I value me.
The procedural nature of the conception of practical reason at work in this
argument can again be brought out, as before, by means of a comparison to the case
of theoretical reason. Just as I am practically irrational if I fail to value the only
possible source of—and thus the condition for—the value of my contingent ends, I
am theoretically irrational if (after informed deliberation) I fail to believe the
proposition whose truth is the condition for the truth of my other beliefs. That is, I
am theoretically irrational if I believe that p is true, know that the truth of q is a
necessary condition for the truth of p, but fail to believe that q is true.
But why think that I am the only possible source of value of my contingent
ends? Why can’t I, rationally, just take them to be valuable in themselves,
164
unconditionally? Let’s start with the easier case: imagine a person who, when
asked why he flosses regularly, responds that he does it for its own sake. And
imagine that he gives a similar response when we ask him why he does all the other
things he does. Such a person’s value commitments would strike us as totally
bizarre, in large part because of their total lack of internal coherence. There’s just
something arbitrary and dogmatic about valuing many such unrelated,
unsystematic, contingently‐chosen ends, without some more fundamental
explanation for why they matter. Compare, again, the epistemic case: imagine a
person who, when asked why she believes each of the things she believes, responds,
“I just do.” Rational people’s sets of beliefs are not so piece‐meal and disconnected;
their beliefs cohere and support each other. Justification may have to bottom out
somewhere; but it had better not bottom out in too many unrelated articles of faith –
especially not articles of faith about which there is irresolvable disagreement
between otherwise rational agents.
So one advantage of valuing humanity as an end in itself, and recognizing it
as the source of the value of my other ends, is that it can lend a kind of unity to my
set of ends. A set of contingent ends that includes the end of humanity is rationally
preferable to one that does not because it is, to borrow a term from Michael Smith,
more systematically justifiable. Smith writes (of desires, as opposed to ends),
we may properly regard the unity of a set of desires as a virtue; a
virtue that in turn makes for the rationality of the set as a whole. For
exhibiting unity is partially constitutive of having a systematically
justified, and so rationally preferable, set of desires, just as exhibiting
165
unity is partially constitutive of having a systematically justified, and
so rationally preferable, set of beliefs.191
The virtue of willing a mutually supportive, systematically justified set of ends is a
virtue of procedural practical rationality, as the analogy to the epistemic case once
again helps bring out: it’s a matter (at least in the first instance) of my ends’
standing in the right relations to each other, not simply of my holding or failing to
hold a particular end. Smith argues that one of the most important ways in which
procedurally rational deliberation can bring it about that we acquire new ends is
through such a process of systematic justification—an attempt to bring unity to our
ends.
If this is right, then there is rational pressure on us, as Kant thought, to
search for “an unconditioned condition” of value – an answer to the string of why‐
questions we might ask about the value of the things we happen to care about. And
Kant’s argument gives shape to the plausible thought that things matter only
because they matter to us, and we matter. A world with no sentient beings in it
would have no value. But it cannot explain on its own why it’s procedurally
irrational to trace the chain of value‐dependency among our ends back to a different
starting‐point. Many ends, it seems, could increase the coherence and systematic
justifiability of our set of ends if we came to see them as the source of value of those
ends.
Smith, The Moral Problem, p. 159. Smith compares his account of this process of acquiring
unifying desires through deliberation to Rawls’ account of reflective equilibrium as a method for
acquiring beliefs in a general principle given a particular set of specific beliefs.
191
166
However, to count as rational, it’s not enough simply to restructure my ends
in a way that makes them systematically unified. Derek Parfit observes:
Consider … Smith’s claim that we can be rationally required to have a
more unified set of desires. Mere unity is not a merit. Our desires
would be more unified if we were monomaniacs, who cared about
only one thing. But if you cared about truth, beauty, and the future of
mankind, and I cared only about my stamp collection, your less
unified set of desires would not be, as Smith’s claim seems to imply,
less rational than mine.192
Parfit’s point shows that not any kind of unity of ends is, intuitively, equally
rational. But he is skeptical that the internalist, committed as she is to a procedural
conception of rationality, has the resources to explain why.193 Nonetheless, I think
the claim that any contingent set of ends will be more procedurally rational for
including a commitment to the value of persons (rather than some other “source of
value”) can be defended.
Recall Hume’s recognition, discussed in the very first chapter of this book,
that moral judgments lay claim to a validity that is non‐parochial – that can be
recognized from any perspective. Hume says:
When a man … bestows on any man the epithets of vicious or odious or
depraved, he then … expresses sentiments, in which he expects all his
audience are to concur with him. He must here, therefore, depart
from his private and particular situation, and must choose a point of
view, common to him with others; he must move some universal
principle of the human frame, and touch a string to which all mankind
have an accord and sympathy.194
192
Parfit, On What Matters, Vol. I, p. 80.
193
Parfit speaks of “subjectivism”, not internalism, but the views are in the relevant respects the
same.
194
Hume, Enquiry, p. 272 (Second Equiry, IX, i).
167
I think Hume’s observation applies to value‐judgments – indeed, to reasons‐
judgments – more generally. If I begin, as Kant says we do, from an optimism that
that some of the things that matter to me really matter – that I have genuine reason
to pursue and protect and respect and promote them – then I am claiming more for
my ends than just that they’re what I’m after. In this way, my ends resemble my
beliefs: if I take my beliefs to be rational, then I take them to be justifiable in a way
that others should be able to recognize; I’m not merely saying they’re what I happen
to think.
Here’s how Onora O’Neill makes the same point:
If thoughts and knowledge claims are to be seen as reasoned, they
must at least be followable in thought by others who hold differing
views... If principles of action are to be offered as reasons for action to
others...they must at least be principles that could be adopted by those
others and used to organise their action.195
Reasons claims, as she puts it, must appeal to “outsiders.” And
‘Outsiders’ would legitimately view any claim that principles of reason
are to be identified with the specific beliefs or norms of groups from
which they are excluded as fetishising some arbitrary claim. … In a
world of differing beings, reasoning is not complete, or we may say
(and Kant said) not completely public when it rests on appeals to
properties and beliefs, attitudes and desires, norms and commitments
which are simply arbitrary from some points of view.196
This doesn’t mean that others must be able to take that very end I see as
providing me with a reason to do something as a reason for them to do the same
thing. That something will benefit my child may be a reason for me but not a reason
(at least, not a reason of the same strength) for a stranger. But the stranger must be
195
O’Neill, “Constructivism in Rawls and Kant,” p. 358.
196
Ibid., p. 359.
168
able to, at least in principle, see how that consideration functions as a reason in my
circumstances – he must see that if it were his child, the fact would provide him with
a reason. There can be agent‐relative reasons, on this view, but there cannot be
reasons that are recognizable as such only from a fully parochial perspective. I
suspect, however, that I can recognize an agent‐relative reason of this sort for
someone to do something only if I recognize a related agent‐neutral value: that is,
for example, I can recognize your agent‐relative reason to do what benefits your
child only if I also think there is some kind of agent‐neutral value in people’s
benefitting their own children. Your action’s share in this value is what makes your
reason non‐parochial.197,198
So much, then, for stamp‐collecting. It doesn’t even provide systematic
justification to my ends, much less make sense from the perspective of anyone else’s.
One of the main arguments I offered in favor of the internalist conception of reasons
197 It doesn’t follow in any obvious way from this that there can’t be deontological obligations:
obligations to benefit one’s own children that don’t amount to obligations to ensure that parents in
general benefit their children. I won’t address this question further here.
198
Compare also Michael Smith’s claim, in “Internal Reasons,” that
[p]art of the task of coming up with a maximally coherent and unified set of desires
is coming up with a set that would be converged upon by rational creatures who too
are trying to come up with a maximally coherent and unified set of desires; each
rational creature is to keep an eye out to her fellows, and to treat as an aberration to
be explained, any divergence between the sets of desires they come up with through
the process of systematic justification. (p. 118)
Smith thinks that this aim of convergence is part of our ordinary concept of a reason – which he
argues is non‐relative. He doesn’t claim to have shown that such convergence is possible, and so
doesn’t take himself to have established that there are any reasons in the non‐relative sense (though
he seems optimistic). See section 2 of “Internal Reasons.” My aim here is to defend this more
ambitious claim.
Kenneth Walden makes a related point in his “Laws of Nature, Laws of Freedom, and the
Social Construction of Normativity.” He argues that to act for reasons is to act in a manner that is
susceptible to a certain kind of explanation – a rationalizing explanation. But explanations, by their
nature, he argues, are general: if my action is to be rationally explainable then the same explanation
must in principle hold for other, similarly situated agents.
169
in Chapter 3 was that it seems less dogmatic than externalism – more epistemically
humble, as I put it there. But to insist that stamp‐collecting is a ultimate worth‐
bestower is very dogmatic. Even if stamp‐collecting became all I cared about, so that
my own value‐commitments looked quite systematically justifiable, I would fail
terribly at demonstrating epistemically healthy humility. I would totally dismiss
most other people’s perceptions of value from the start, with no way of defending
the dismissal.199 So it’s important that the end I recognize as the source of value,
and so of systematic justification, for my ends make sense as potential source of
value for the ends of others.
But stamp‐collecting is, of course, not the only, or most plausible, alternative
source of systematic justifiability. Happiness (understood now in its ordinary, non‐
Kantian sense) seems like a plausible (and philosophically popular!) candidate.
Perhaps we should think our ends are valuable not because we choose them, and
we’re valuable, but because they make us happy, and happiness is valuable. (If this
is right, then there is still a sense in which persons are the condition of the value of
their ends, but only because persons are the vehicle, so to speak, for the happiness
their ends produce. Maybe the most appealing way to think of this is by analogy
with musical instruments: on the utilitarian picture, our value is a bit like the value
of a musical instrument. We’re valueless hunks of matter until we’re “strummed” or
“played” by the world, by life, and then we “sing”—we produce experiences that, like
the music produced by a strummed instrument, are where the real value lies.)
199
In this way, I would be like a chicken‐sexer who thinks she’s always right, even when she
disagrees with other chicken‐sexers and cannot point to any independent criterion to show that she’s
better at chicken‐sexing or to prove her approach gets it right. See §3.2
170
Perhaps Kantian internalism mistakes the value of happiness for the value of getting
what we want, when in fact, getting what we want is valuable only when and
because it makes us happy.
Parfit, in fact, suggests that internalists who claim that our desires or choices
give us reasons are succumbing to just this confusion. He writes:
When people claim that our desires give us reasons, it is very often …
facts about what we would enjoy, or find painful or unpleasant, that
they really have in mind. Such facts give us reasons that are hedonic
rather than desire‐based.
… [S]ome people mistakenly believe that hedonic reasons are desire‐
based.200
In this way, the Kantian argument I’ve laid out may seem to lead us back in the
direction of the utilitarian conclusion I dismissed in the last chapter.
Taking happiness to be the ‘unconditioned condition’ of value makes pretty
good sense of most of my commitments, and of many of the commitments of others.
Sidgwick, for one, thought that it did better, in that regard, that the assumption that
human life was what was ultimately valuable. He argued that it would be a mistake
to value human life in the absence of – even at the expense of – happiness. There
would be nothing good, he says, about preserving a life that is full of misery.201
Sidgwick seems, here, to be assuming that the only reasons for action
provided by values are reasons to preserve or make more of what’s valuable. But, as
T.M. Scanlon has pointed out, many of our values give us reasons that are not
reasons to create more of that value. The value of friendship, for example, does not
200
Parfit, On What Matters, Volume One, p. 67.
201
Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, p. 397.
171
primarily give us reasons to bring about and prolong states of affairs that involve
friendship, but rather gives us reasons to structure our interactions with our friends
in ways that express loyalty, attention, concern, and so on.202 We might even, for the
sake of the value of friendship, perform an action that we know will bring a
friendship to an end. If my friend is in an abusive relationship, the value of our
friendship may give me conclusive reason to report the abuse to the police, because
I know that my friend’s life depends on my doing so. I may be required to do so
even if the inevitable result of my doing so is that she feels betrayed, and no longer
wants to be my friend.
Kant’s broader conception of ends, which I explored in §4.3, and in particular,
his claim that humanity is an end, provides us, of course, with another example of a
value that is not a source of reasons to make more of what is valuable. The value of
humanity as an end in itself does not provide a reason to have as many children as
we can, or to encourage population growth. It may not even (despite Kant’s own
expressed views on suicide) provide us with reasons to extend an existing human
life as long as possible. On the Kantian picture, the value of humanity is not an end
to be produced or effected but rather an “independently existing end,”203 whose
existence as a value must inform our actions if we are to act fully rationally. Thus it
gives us reason not to act in ways that conflict with the recognition of and respect
for that value. How exactly that constrains our actions is not at all clear. I will set
202
Scanlon, What We Owe To Each Other, pp. 88‐90.
203
Kant, p. 44 (G 4:437).
172
this difficult question aside for now. I will take some initial steps towards
investigating it in the final chapter of this book.
And despite the importance almost everyone attaches to happiness, it cannot,
it seems, explain the value we attribute to all our ends. Many people value ends
quite independently of whether they generate happiness. This may be true of some
of the ends they value the most. Think of the theoretical physicist, or indeed the
philosopher, in dogged and laborious pursuit of some fundamental truth. The value
of these ends does not seem to be derivable from the value of happiness. So the
assumption that happiness is “the source of value” will still force us to dismiss many
value‐commitments out of hand.204 The commitment to persons, or humanity, as
the source of value, with the ability to confer value on their chosen ends, fares
better: it allows us to begin with the default assumption that everyone’s ends
matter, and correct that assumption only when it actively conflicts with the
commitment to the value of humanity.
A clarification is in order. The goal isn’t, of course, to find an ultimate end
that will accommodate everything individual people happen to value. The point of a
moral principle, after all, is partly to correct our value commitments. But it
shouldn’t dogmatically rule out some people’s values as mistaken from the start. We
should grant anyone’s ends, not just our own, the benefit of the doubt, as a kind of
working assumption, and correct that assumption only when we need to. This at
least is the goal and appeal of the internalist project, as I have interpreted it. If we
204
I have also argued that the assumption that happiness, as opposed to the persons and creatures
who can be happy, is the end in itself has implausible normative implications. See §4.2.
173
assume that people are the source of value, then their value can, at a first pass,
explain the value of any chosen end, though that end could later turn out to be
irrationally adopted if it (or its pursuit) necessarily conflicted with respect for the
special value of persons.
These considerations may lead you to think, however, that I have been
focusing on the wrong version of utilitarianism. Perhaps the assumption that
happiness is the fundamentally valuable thing dogmatically rules out some people’s
value‐commitments as mistaken from the start, because some people have ends
whose value cannot be explained by the value of happiness. This fact may
undermine hedonistic forms of utilitarianism, but it suggests that a desire‐
satisfaction version of utilitarianism might fare better. There seems to be nothing
problematically dogmatic about the assumption that it’s the satisfaction of people’s
desires (broadly understood), whatever they are, that’s the ultimate source of value;
and doesn’t a commitment to this value serve just as well as a commitment to the
value of humanity as a source of systematic justification for our motley collection of
ends?
But there is, on reflection, something very odd about the idea that desire‐
satisfaction could be the ultimate end – the intrinsically valuable source of value of
all our other ends.205 We might think that it’s valuable to satisfy our desires
because we think what we desire is itself valuable. But this won’t do, of course, for
the present purpose. If satisfying our desires is valuable because our desires point
205
Roger Crisp also notes the oddness in the idea that desire‐satisfaction itself is the ultimate good‐
making property (see “Well‐being,” §4.2).
174
us towards ends that are valuable independently of our desiring them, then our
ends aren’t valuable in virtue of satisfying our desires, and the value of desire
satisfaction isn’t the source of or explanation for their value after all. Coming to
value desire satisfaction can’t then provide greater systematic unity to our set of
ends. 206
If desire satisfaction is to serve as a source of systematic justifiability for our
individual, disunified ends, those ends must be valuable in virtue of their satisfying
our desires. Why should we think the value of our ends depends on our desires in
this way? A natural thought may be that the satisfaction of desire is valuable, not
because of the independent value of the ends we desire, but because of the positive
experiential state it involves – because of what it’s like to have our desires satisfied.
But to answer that way is, of course, to revert to hedonistic utilitarianism and the
problems it brings with it.
According to the view under consideration, the satisfaction of desires is,
instead, intrinsically valuable. And it is all that’s intrinsically valuable. We
ourselves, on such a view, would again be valuable only as vehicles or mediums for
desire—no more intrinsically valuable than the cold stone from which the Pietà was
carved. But if the objects of our desires have no value in themselves, and the
experience of having our desires satisfied has no value in itself, and we, the subjects
of the desire, have no value in ourselves, then why should the satisfaction of our
206
Similar obstacles face the view that preference satisfaction is desirable because certain
experiences or ends can be made valuable by the fact that they satisfy desires of the agent, just as,
say, taking an interest in a game or a sport can make the experience of watching it or playing it
valuable. This gives preference satisfaction the same kind of instrumental value as the cubic press.
175
desires have any value at all? This seems mysterious, unmotivated. The question
brings us back around to the Kantian line of thought I have been pushing, which
provides an answer: it matters that we get what we desire, when it matters, because
we matter.
The argument from systematic justifiability explains why there is rational
pressure on all of us to value humanity as an end, regardless of our contingent ends
and commitments, and so provides the first necessary component of a successful
internalist defense of the thesis that rationality requires us to be moral. But the
argument also provides the second necessary component of such a defense: it
explains why the rationally required end of humanity is not just one end among
others, but trumps those others in cases of conflict, and so can be a source of moral
requirements. Because the value of humanity is, on the view I’ve defended, a
condition of the value of any other end whatsoever, it is always procedurally
irrational to fail to treat it as an end for the sake of promoting some particular (even
prudential) end‐to‐be‐effected. This is because such an end could have no value
(and thus could generate no reasons for acting) independent of the value of
humanity itself.
Consider a miser, who values money because of the good things it can get
him, but then sacrifices those good things for the sake of accumulating more money.
The person who violates the moral imperative for the sake of promoting some
conditionally valuable end – who, say, uses and manipulates others for personal
gain, without regard to their interests – is guilty of precisely the same sort of
procedural irrationality. Thus Kant’s moral imperative can never be overridden by
176
instrumental or prudential concerns. Even on an internalist view of practical
reason, we always have most reason to do as morality requires.
In brief, if I’m procedurally rational, I will try to restructure what I care about
in such a way as to make my ends more systematically justifiable without ruling out
the value of your ends from the start. Assuming that we matter – that is, adopting
humanity as an end and recognizing it as the source of value for the ends we set – is
ideally suited to the purpose. We might well be more procedurally rational if we
came to treat humanity as an end in itself, and as a source of value for our other
ends, as well as the ends of other people; if we learned to give up our contingent
ends when their pursuit is incompatible with respecting the value of others as ends
in themselves; if we learned to recognize that what matters to us isn’t all that
matters; and if we learned to recognize that some of what matters to us doesn’t
really matter, after all.
I have been trying to fill in the gaps in Kant’s argument, to make clear why
there is rational pressure on us – even on an internalist, procedural conception of
rationality – to comply with Kant’s formula of humanity. Along the way, I hope it
has also become clear why Kant is not, in fact, guilty of the mistaken inference that
he is sometimes accused of making: from the claim that X is the source of, or
condition for, the value of Y to the claim that X must therefore be valuable, perhaps
even intrinsically valuable. Kant recognizes, as I’ve noted, that not all conditions of
value are themselves valuable – he thinks inclinations, though conditions of value of
our chosen ends, are not valuable in themselves. Kant’s idea is not that, because
we’re the source of value of our chosen ends, we must therefore be valuable in
177
ourselves. Rather, it’s the way we bestow value on our ends that matters: we do
this by being the more fundamental ends for whose sake we pursue our contingent
ends. By contrast, we don’t value or pursue or create penicillin for the sake of the
infection that is a condition of its value. We do these things for the sake of health,
not illness – health is the more fundamental end that makes the development of
antibiotics a valuable end. And ultimately, Kant might add, our health is valuable
because we are valuable.
This point goes a considerable way towards defusing Langton’s other worry,
about the value of Maria von Herbert.207 Langton, remember, restates the view of
value she attributes to “Korsgaard’s Kant” this way:
The ability of choosers to confer value on their choices – the ability of
agents to be value‐conferrers – is … the very source of the intrinsic
value … of persons. We have intrinsic value because we value things
as ends, conferring (extrinsic) value on them.208
This comes close, I believe, to characterizing the Kantian position. But it’s not quite
right, and the mischaracterization is what leads to the most pressing version of the
problem of Maria von Herbert.
In one sense, I believe, it is in virtue of our ability to confer value on our
choices that we have a special value. But we don’t have this special value because
we make things valuable. Our value is not like the (instrumental) value of the cubic
press, which turns ordinary carbon into diamond. We have the special value we
have, I have suggested, because we aren’t just beings that matter to someone, but
207 I say only “a considerable way” because I don’t think it goes all the way to defusing the worry. A
related worry survives, which I discuss below (see §6.1).
208
Langton, p. 168.
178
rather we’re beings to whom things matter. We are centers of subjectivity. This was
Taurek’s point about the crucial difference between a person and the Pietà. For all
its priceless beauty, if the Pietà survived the nuclear holocaust but no sentient
beings did, it would lose its value. But my value does not depend on my being of
value to anyone – I am, as Kant says, valuable in myself.
What if (unfortunate soul!) I not only matter to no one, but nothing matters
to me? Now we are arriving at Maria’s predicament. But it doesn’t seem to follow
from Taurek’s point, which, I argued, is the driving normative‐ethical intuition
behind the Kantian argument, that Maria has no value. Maria is, after all, still a
center of subjectivity, not a mere thing, even if, at the moment, nothing matters to
her. Things, after all, don’t suffer depression; and though they may self‐destruct,
they don’t commit suicide.
But what of the Kantian internalist argument itself? Does it entail, as Langton
suspects, that Maria has no value? The answer, again, is no. As Langton says, the
Kantian (as I’ve portrayed her) reasons like this: “I do value; therefore I have
value.”209 But the “therefore” in this argument represents an inference from the first
proposition to the second; it does not indicate that the first proposition explains, or
makes true, the second. That is, my drawing the inference shows I’m committed to
the second proposition, about my value, because I’m committed to the first, about
my valuing; it does not show that I’m committed to the further view that I have
value because I do value – that this is what makes me valuable.
209
Ibid., p. 169.
179
In fact, as we’ve seen, Kant would reject this claim. Consider a less
fundamental step in his process of tracing value‐dependency. Say that if I value
flossing, I must value good dental health, because it’s the only (plausible) source of
the value of flossing. It certainly doesn’t follow from this that good dental health is
valuable because or in virtue of its conferring value on flossing. That’s not what
makes health valuable. This would, absurdly, suggest that the value of good health
derived from the value of flossing, in much the same way as the value of the cubic
press comes from the value it confers on carbon (to return to my earlier analogy). If
humanity were valuable in this way, its value would be purely instrumental. But our
value, on Kant’s view, is not instrumental, and it does not derive from the value of
our ends. It is because their value derives from ours that our commitment to their
value puts rational pressure on us to recognize our own.
So we should not conclude, as Langton worries we must, that Maria has no
value because she does not value. We have learned, by reasoning from our own
values, that she has value – indeed, intrinsic, unconditioned value – just like we do.
And we should indeed mourn her suicide as a great loss.
This makes the Kantian argument much more acceptable. But, unfortunately,
it does not entirely defuse the worry Maria’s cases poses. There’s a lingering
question about what Maria herself should think. She, after all, rejects the very first
180
step of the Kantian argument: that there are valuable ends she has reason to
pursue.210 I turn to this worry, and related worries, below.
210
Though Maria seems to embrace the conclusion of the Kantian argument directly. There’s nothing
in the correspondence Langton presents to suggest that she thinks persons, in general, valueless, and
indeed she long refrains from suicide for fear that it would violate the moral law.
181
Chapter 6
Is the Moral Imperative Categorical?
6.1 A first response: the problem of Maria revisited
I want to begin with a final analogy between the picture of procedural
practical rationality that I have sketched and the case of theoretical rationality. It
may seem surprising that, as I have argued, the mere exercise of our faculties of
practical reason in willing, regardless of which ends we contingently will, can
commit us, if we are rational, to willing a particular, substantive end. But there is
again a familiar analog in the case of belief, provided by Descartes’ Cogito. Descartes
argues that there is one substantive belief that we must all hold, on pain of
irrationality, if we believe anything at all: that we exist. I have argued, following
Kant, that there is one substantive end that we must all will, on pain of irrationality,
if we will anything at all: that of humanity.
I say: if we will anything at all. On one prominent and natural understanding
of the claim that moral requirements are categorical, such requirements bind us
regardless of any facts about what we desire or will. In my view, Kant’s internalism
does commit him to rejecting the claim that the moral law is categorical in this sense.
At least, the version of Kant’s argument that I’ve presented and defended commits
me to rejecting this claim, whether or not Kant himself would have wished to retain
it. After all, I’ve argued that our reasons to be moral can be derived from facts about
what we will, combined with facts about what procedural rationality requires of us:
our commitment to the value of our contingently willed ends rationally commits us
to the value of another end—humanity—that forms the foundation for the moral
182
law. The claim that moral reasons are internal reasons is precisely the claim that
they can be derived in some way from the contents of our motivational sets—that
facts about those sets are relevant to establishing that we are subject to moral
requirements, as well as to discovering what those requirements are.
However, according to the argument I have developed, all of us are subject to
the same moral requirements regardless of differences in our contingently willed
ends. It is our commitment to the value of those ends, whatever they may be, that
gives rise to the rational requirement to treat humanity as an end. The Kantian
moral law might therefore be called categorical in a somewhat weaker sense: it is a
law of reason that binds us regardless of what we desire or will, provided that we
will something.
As I’ve said, however, such moral judgments are justified only if and because
we can back them up with claims about what we are rationally required to value
given that we value something, regardless of what that something is, and regardless
of whether we in fact comply with this rational requirement. Thus a true nihilist,
someone who values nothing – whose motivational set is simply empty – and who
thus fails to meet the conditions necessary for the moral rational requirement to get
a hold on her, may escape the “categorical” imperative I have described. On my
view, it seems, I must retract the claim that, say, Jones ought not to torture cats, if I
discover that Jones is a true nihilist. And, to return to the troubling case of Maria
von Herbert, we must, it seems retract the claim that Maria ought not to commit
suicide, if we find, as Langton suggests, that she really values nothing. (We need not
conclude, I argued in the previous chapter, that Maria in fact has no value, or that
183
her suicide is nothing to be mourned, or that we should do nothing to save others
like her. Nor need we think that Jones’ violent acts are nothing we should abhor, or
try to prevent.)
Do Jones and Maria really have no reason to avoid such acts? This is,
admittedly, counterintuitive. But the force of the counter‐intuition can, I think, be
softened somewhat. Firstly, a true nihilist in the sense I have in mind—someone
who really sees no value in anything, and no reason to do anything—is not likely to
go around torturing cats.211 Nor is she likely to commit suicide. As Kant noticed,
suicide is not really the action of a true nihilist; the suicidal person has an end, if it is
only to put an end to her own suffering.212 (And it is worth noting that Maria,
indeed, seems to have felt the force of the categorical imperative: she long refrains
from suicide for fear that it will violate the moral law.) It seems to me that it is not
easy to act (voluntarily) in a way one believes one has no reason at all to act. This is
what makes wagers like that described in Gregory Kavka’s “The Toxin Puzzle” so
hard to win. Of course, performing a random action, such as jumping in the air three
times, in order to disprove this assertion is a hopeless way of disproving it—your
reason for jumping in the air will have been provided by your goal of disproving the
assertion.
A profession to nihilism is, of course, not a way out of moral condemnation.
It is not so easy, I have maintained, to imagine a case of true nihilism. In fact, I am
211 While a fair amount of destruction has certainly been wrought in the world by persons describing
themselves as nihilists, this self‐description is unlikely to have been an accurate one.
212
Kant, p. 38 (4:429). This is why Kant characterizes suicide as using humanity in your own person
as a mere means to your end (of “maintain[ing] a tolerable condition up to the end of life”). It does
not seem clear to me that Kant’s argument entails the hard line on suicide that he takes, however.
184
not at all convinced that true nihilism is even a psychological possibility for
recognizably human agents. But it may be. If we did encounter a true nihilist, how
prepared would we be to say of her that she ought to act in certain ways? I’m really
not sure. I could, of course, make many other normative claims about her case; I
could say that it would be good for the rest of us (and for her) if she did this or
refrained from doing that. I think I would balk at making any claims about what she
ought or has reason to do.
When Bernard Williams introduced the amoralist’s challenge – the challenge
to which this book aims to provide a response – he drew attention to precisely the
difference nihilism and more motivated wrongdoing that concerns us here. “‘Why
should I do anything?’,” he writes:
Two of the many ways of taking that question are these: as an
expression of despair or hopelessness, when it means something like
‘Give me a reason for doing anything; everything is meaningless’; and
as sounding a more defiant note, against morality, when it means
something like ‘Why is there anything that I should, ought to, do?’
Even though we can paraphrase the question in the first spirit
as ‘Give me a reason…’, it is very unclear that we can in fact give the
man who asks it a reason – that, starting from so far down, we could
argue him into caring about something. … What he needs is help, or
hope, not reasonings. …
I do not see how it could be regarded as a defeat for reason or
rationality that it had no power against this man’s state; his state is
rather a defeat for humanity. But the man who asks the question in
the second spirit has been regarded by many moralists as providing a
real challenge to moral reasoning. He, after all, acknowledges some
reasons for doing things, he is, moreover, like most of us some of the
time. If morality can be got off the ground rationally, then we ought to
be able to get it off the ground in an argument against him; while in
his pure form – in which we can call him the amoralist – he may not be
actually persuaded, it might seem a comfort to morality if there were
reasons which, if he were rational, would persuade him.213
213
Williams, Morality: An Introduction to Ethics, pp. 3‐4.
185
I have been hoping, of course, to provide an argument of just this sort: an
answer to this second kind of question. I’m inclined to agree with Williams that a
question of the first sort (if, again, there can be anyone to ask it) is not one we can or
should aim to resolve through moral reasoning.
This conclusion would be a kind of corollary to the thought Williams
expresses in “Persons, Character, and Morality,” about the limits to the demands
morality can make of us. There he writes:
There can come a point at which it is quite unreasonable for a man to
give up, in the name of the impartial good ordering of the world of
moral agents, something which is a condition of his having any
interest in being around in the world at all.214
Morality, Williams thinks, cannot require us to do something that takes away the
condition for our having any interest in the world. And if we have no interest in the
world to begin with? Then, perhaps, morality cannot require us to do anything.
This may also be the seed of truth in Williams’ discussion of blame, which I
considered in §1.4. Pace Williams, we don’t (I argued there) withhold blame from a
person who lacks certain elements in his motivational set: who simply doesn’t care
about the well‐being of others, or their good opinion. But we might withhold blame
from a person, if indeed there can be such a person, whose motivational set is
completely empty: who cares about nothing at all.215
214
Williams, “Persons, Character, and Morality,” in Moral Luck, p. 14.
215 The case of Maria von Herbert—and the shadow of the possibility of true nihilism she casts—
raises a perhaps more fundamental question about the view I’ve been defending. I argued in the last
chapter that Maria has value, even if she truly values nothing, though she may have no reason to
protect or promote or respect that value. We have reason to promote and protect and respect her
(continued on next page)
186
6.2 A second response: the categorical ‘use’ of ‘ought’
Philippa Foot points out that the thesis that moral oughts are categorical is in
part a thesis about how we use such oughts: we don’t think, when we say of
someone that he ought morally to do such‐and‐such, that we must first examine his
desires. And we don’t feel we have to retract our moral ought claims when we
discover that the agent we are describing lacks particular relevant desires, such as
the desire to be moral, or certain concerns, such as concern for the well‐being of
value. But what if we all, like Maria, fall into a motivating‐sapping depression? What if we all cease,
entirely, to care? What if nothing matters anymore to any of us?
If we follow the line of argument sketched above, it seems we must conclude that none of us
have any moral reasons at all—that morality simply ceases to have application in the world like the
one I am imagining. Does it also follow that the world is drained of value? That none of us, after all,
have value, at least until we start to care again?
This even grimmer conclusion need not follow. It follows only if we accept buck‐passing
about value: the view that what it is for something to have value is for there to be reason to respect or
protect or promote it. But it is open to the Kantian internalist to reject buck‐passing about value. She
could then embrace internalism about reasons, but leave the door open to externalism about value.
That is, she could think what we have reason to do depends, in the complicated way described in
Chapter 2, on our antecedent ends, and the constraints of procedural rationality. But there could be
value in the world that is not constrained, in this way, by what we care about, and what we could
reason our way to caring about.
This view is not as disjointed as it may at first appear to be. Most of the arguments I
advanced in Chapter 3 in favor of the internalist picture of reasons were epistemologically, as
opposed to metaphysically, motivated. And it is reasons, in particular, that I take to be epistemically
constrained: what we have reason to do, and correspondingly, what we ought to do, depends to some
extent on our evidence, and on what desires, broadly understood, we can hold on to if we exhibit
certain epistemic virtues, like coherence and humility. It’s not at all clear to me that what is valuable
must be epistemically constrained in the same way.
In this way, the distinction between value and reasons may resemble the distinction between
truth and justification: what is true is in no way constrained by our evidence and our antecedent
beliefs; but what we are justified in believing may well be.
If we were to accept this mixed position, then the arguments of the preceding chapters
would concern what we have reason to do, and what we will value, if we’re rational, as opposed to
what has value; on the view I’m tentatively floating here, these might, at times come apart.
Thanks to Ruth Chang, Jamie Dreier, Alex King, and Alex Mechanick for pressing me on this
point.
187
others. Moral ought claims differ in this way from merely instrumental ought
claims, which we do retract when we find the relevant desire is absent. Foot writes:
Is Kant right to say that moral judgments are categorical, not
hypothetical, imperatives? It may seem that he is, for we find in our
language two different uses of words such as ‘should’ and ‘ought’,
apparently corresponding to Kant’s hypothetical and categorical
imperatives, and we find moral judgements on the categorical side.
Suppose, for instance, we have advised a traveler that he should take a
certain train, believing him to be journeying to his home. If we find
that he has decided to go elsewhere, we will most likely have to take
back what we said: the ‘should’ will now be unsupported and in need
of support. Similarly, we must be prepared to withdraw our
statement about what he should do if we find that the right relation
does not hold between the action and the end—that it is either no way
of getting what he wants (or doing what he wants to do) or not the
most eligible among possible means. The use of ‘should’ or ‘ought’ in
moral contexts is, however, quite different. When we say that a man
should do something and intend a moral judgement we do not have to
back up what we say by considerations about his interests or his
desires; if no such connexion can be found the ‘should’ need not be
withdrawn. It follows that the agent cannot rebut an assertion about
what, morally speaking, he should do by showing that the action is not
ancillary to his interests or desires.216
The internalist moral imperative I defend is categorical in this sense, given a
natural interpretation of Foot’s phrase “considerations about his interests or his
desires.” We are not, I have argued at length, required to back up moral judgments
by pointing to any particular actual desires or interests of the agent we are judging.
So, for example, we are not required to retract our assertion that the cruel husband
of Williams’ example ought to be kinder to his wife when we discover that he has no
desire to be so. He, like the rest of us, is subject to a rational pressure to treat
persons as ends in themselves, including his wife.
216
Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” p. 159.
188
Foot acknowledges that there is truth to the claim that moral requirements
are categorical, at least to the extent that this is an assertion about linguistic usage.
But, she claims, Kantians mean more than this when they insist moral imperatives
are categorical: they intend to attribute an “inescapability,” a “special dignity,” a
“necessity” to such requirements that they take hypothetical imperatives to lack.217
This stronger claim, however it is interpreted, cannot, she argues, be established by
appeal to the observation about linguistic usage alone. (She marks the difference
between the weaker and the stronger theses by distinguishing between the “non‐
hypothetical use of ‘should’ [or ‘ought’],” of which she takes moral judgments to be
examples, and a “non‐hypothetical imperative,” of which, she argues, we cannot
show moral requirements to be examples.218) The linguistic observation, she points
out, can be made of types of judgments and types of rules that clearly lack the
inescapability, dignity, and necessity we want to attribute to moral imperatives.
“For instance,” she notes,
we find this non‐hypothetical use of ‘should’ in sentences enunciating
rules of etiquette, as, for example, that an invitation in the third
person should be answered in the third person, where the rule does
not fail to apply to someone who has his own good reasons for
ignoring this piece of nonsense, or who simply does not care about
what, from the point of view of etiquette, he should do. Similarly,
there is a non‐hypothetical use of ‘should’ in contexts where
something like a club rule is in question. The club secretary who has
told a member that he should not bring ladies into the smoking‐room
does not say ‘Sorry, I was mistaken’ when informed that this member
is resigning tomorrow and cares nothing about his reputation in the
club. Lacking a connexion with the agent’s desires or interests, this
217
See Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” p. 160.
Ibid., pp. 160‐161 (my italics). See also Foot, “A Reply to Professor Frankena,” in Virtues and Vices,
p. 176.
218
189
‘should’ does not stand ‘unsupported and in need of support’; it
requires only the backing of the rule. The use of ‘should’ is therefore
‘non‐hypothetical’ in the sense defined.219
As Foot remarks, if a non‐hypothetical use of ‘ought’ or ‘should’ were sufficient to
make the resulting imperative categorical in the (somewhat nebulous) strong sense
described above, then even rules of etiquette would qualify as categorical
imperatives. Since the defenders of Kantian ethics whom she is addressing would
doubtless deny rules of etiquette this status, they must offer some alternative
account of the sense in which the moral imperative is categorical to that provided by
these observations about use.
Foot has a suggestion to make about what this other account might be that is
very relevant to the project I have undertaken. She writes:
Very roughly the idea seems to be that one may reasonably ask why
anyone should bother about what should (from the point of view of
etiquette) be done, and that such considerations deserve no notice
unless reason is shown. So although people give as their reason for
doing something the fact that it is required by etiquette, we do not
take this consideration as in itself giving us a reason to act.
Considerations of etiquette do not have any automatic reason‐giving
force, and a man might be right if he denied that he had reason to do
‘what’s done.’
This seems to take us to the heart of the matter, for, by
contrast, it is supposed that moral considerations necessarily give
reasons for acting to any man.220
Foot goes on to adopt an internalist conception of what it is to have a reason. She
writes, in a manner reminiscent of Williams,221 that “the man who rejects morality
219
Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” p. 160.
220
Ibid., p. 161.
Foot’s article was originally published in 1972, before Williams’ “Internal and External Reasons”
(which was first published in 1980). As noted earlier, Foot later revised or withdrew some of her
internalist views.
221
190
because he sees no reason to obey its rules can be convicted of villainy but not of
inconsistency.”222 She declares that “[i]rrational actions are those in which a man in
some way defeats his own purposes, doing what is calculated to be disadvantageous
or to frustrate his ends. Immorality,” she concludes, “does not necessarily involve
any such thing.”223
I have argued, in the preceding chapter, that violating the moral imperative
expressed by the formula of humanity does involve us in inconsistencies—in
procedural irrationalities—in a way that simply violating rules of etiquette would
not. The moral imperative is categorical in the stronger sense, while rules of
etiquette are not, because the end on which it is built—the end it asks us to
respect—is one that all rational beings must hold to the extent that they are
procedurally rational. This is not true of the end of propriety, on which rules of
etiquette are built—this end is certainly optional from the perspective of rationality.
6.3 A third response: categorical imperatives and practice rules
The important similarities and differences between moral rules and rules of
etiquette can also be brought out another way, by appealing to a distinction of John
Rawls’, between two types of rules. Rawls distinguishes between what he calls the
“summary conception” and the “practice conception” of rules.224 Summary rules,
also called “rules of thumb,” are guidelines for acting that we form on the basis of an
222
Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” p. 161.
223
Ibid., p. 162.
224
Rawls, “Two Concepts of Rules.” See especially pp. 18ff.
191
assessment of what was generally the best way of acting in similar circumstances in
the past (hence the name). They allow us to decide how to act without reassessing
the relevant reasons anew each time we find ourselves in such circumstances. They
are rules of convenience—allowing us to reach decisions more quickly and easily,
and perhaps also more appropriately, reaping the benefit of past experience.
Summary rules are instrumental to achieving certain ends. An act‐utilitarian might,
for example, advocate making use of the rule “Don’t lie” because lying usually results
in unhappiness, and following a rule against lying makes us better at avoiding
unhappiness than evaluating the potential effects of each possible lie on a case‐by‐
case basis. When the particular end at which the rule aims is known not to be served
by following the rule in a particular case (when, for example, it is known that telling
a lie in particular circumstances will increase happiness) then the rule loses its
binding force.
Hypothetical imperatives of the sort Foot considers above, such as “Take the
7.15 train,” (and hypothetical uses of ‘ought,’ such as “You ought to take the 7.15
train,”) while they do not exactly express rules for action, share some features of
summary rules. Like such rules, they are justified on instrumental grounds—taking
the train is supposed to be required because it is deemed instrumental to the
achievement of some other end, such as arriving at home in time for dinner. Like
summary rules, they lose their binding force when it becomes evident either that
they don’t promote the end in question (perhaps the 7.15 train arrives too late for
192
dinner) or that the end in question is not in fact valued (perhaps the addressee has
made other dinner plans).225
Practice rules have a more complex structure. Such rules serve to define
practices—they establish offices, and specify actions allowed under the practice, and
offenses against it. Practice rules have a different sort of authority from that of
summary rules. They do not depend on their own instrumental value on some
occasion of action for their binding force. We might ask whether the practice that
each subsidiary practice rule contributes toward defining is justified, and the
justification we offer or seek may, for some practices at least, be instrumental in
nature. The practice of baseball, for example, might be thought to aim at the ends of
providing entertainment, and developing, showcasing, and rewarding skills of
certain kinds. These ends might be described as ends external to the practice. Some
practice rules may even be preferable to others on external grounds. That is, there
may be argument among fans of a sport about whether the external ends of the
sport would be better served by some possible rules (perhaps a rule allowing for the
use of a “designated hitter,” or a rule allowing batters a fourth strike) than by others.
But such a disagreement is accurately described as a disagreement about what the
rule should be, and not about what the rule is, and a rule does not cease to apply to a
practice participant on some occasion just because it fails, on that occasion, to best
promote the ends external to the practice. As Rawls says:
225
The analogy is only partial, not perfect. Summary rules can also act as stand‐ins for Kantian
categorical imperatives, without standing in instrumental relations to some end‐to‐be‐effected.
“Always do what your wise Auntie Maud advises you to do,” is one example. “Don’t lie” may be
another. We sometimes have good reasons to make use of such rules. But fundamental moral rules
will never be summary rules. Thanks to Adrian Moore for this point.
193
In a game of baseball if a batter were to ask ‘Can I have four strikes?’ it
would be assumed that he was asking what the rule was; and if, when
told what the rule was, he were to say the he meant that on this
occasion he thought it would be best on the whole for him to have
four strikes rather than three, this would be most kindly taken as a
joke.226
Categorical uses of words like ‘ought’ and ‘should’ are often appropriate in
discussions of practice rules, as Foot’s observations help to bring out. The rules of
etiquette define a practice in Rawls’ sense. As she notes, we are not tempted to
withdraw claims such as “You ought to keep your elbows off the table when you
eat,” when we find out that the person we are addressing would rather keep his
elbows on the table, any more than we would be tempted to revise the rules of
baseball for a batter who wants a fourth strike. But it is equally clear that the ‘ought’
we employ in this case—the ‘ought’ of etiquette—is not the same as the all‐things‐
considered ‘ought’ of moral judgment—the ‘ought’ I have equated with ‘has
conclusive reason to.’ We might, in such cases, perfectly consistently, though
admittedly somewhat confusingly, maintain that we ought not to do as we ought.
When do categorical uses of ‘ought’ in expressing practice rules signify the
presence of genuine reasons? Answering this question might help to distinguish
such mere categorical uses of ‘ought’ of from true categorical imperatives—oughts
that are categorical in the strong sense of giving everyone (barring the hypothetical
nihilist) reasons for acting. I have said that the usual way to justify a practice is to
appeal to ends external to that practice that are valuable, and to indicate how the
226
Ibid., p. 26.
194
practice is instrumental to achieving those ends.227 In the case of baseball, those
external ends are, let’s say, providing entertainment and developing certain skills.
In the case of etiquette the external end justifying the practice might (to take a
generous view of the matter) be the avoidance of giving offense, the easing of social
interaction, or perhaps (to take a less generous view) the establishment of a readily
recognizable social stratification. Practice rules are designed to advance such ends.
Practice rules serve another purpose as well—they define ends internal to
the practice—ends the pursuit of which requires adherence to the rules. These ends
can only be achieved by means of obedience to the rules of the practice, and
contribute to the instrumental value of the practices—practices would not serve to
promote the ends external to them nearly so well if the internal ends were not
established. One cannot win a game of baseball by taking advantage of the
allowance of a fourth “strike”. One cannot avoid defeat in a game of chess by moving
one’s king two spaces instead of one. Nor can one achieve propriety while eating
with one’s elbows on the table. Winning is an end internal to the practice of most
games, and propriety is the end internal to the practice of etiquette. In each case,
the presence of the internal end contributes to the instrumental value of the
practice: baseball and chess would be much less fun, and would build fewer skills, if
was not possible to win at them in a fair contest; and it could at least be argued that
if everyone simply tried to avoid giving offense, and tried to put others socially at
227
Here, as is generally the case throughout this book, I intend “instrumental” to be broadly
understood—practices may serve ends by being somehow expressive or constitutive of them, as the
practice of playing a game may be constitutive of the end of expressing enthusiasm for life.
195
ease, they would be less successful at doing so than if they aimed instead at
propriety.
When we take the internal perspective to a practice, we come to value the
ends internal to it, and so come to have reasons to comply with its rules—there is no
other way for us to obtain the internal end. But in most cases, we need not take the
internal perspective to a practice. Some practices purport to be justified by external
ends we don’t think are valuable—this may be true of etiquette, on the less
sympathetic picture presented above. In such cases, we will have no reason at all to
obey its rules, despite their categorical form.
Some practices promote external ends that are valuable, but these ends can
be achieved by means of participation in any one of several practices, as is the case
with most games and sports. Taking up baseball or taking up basketball may be
equally good means of having fun. Alternatively, some practices aim at ends which
are valuable, but which give us only sufficient and not most reason to pursue them.
The development of the logical reasoning skills that can be achieved by means of
taking up chess is a valuable goal, but the development of musical skills that would
result from taking violin lessons may be just as valuable, and it would not be
irrational for me to spend my limited time and energy in pursuit of this goal instead.
In both of these cases, while we have sufficient reason to adopt the internal
perspective to such practices, we are not rationally required to do so. We can
choose, rationally, not to participate in them. Thus their rules need not provide us
with reasons, again, despite their categorical form.
196
I may have sufficient reason to violate the rules of a practice even if I
(generally) take the internal perspective towards that practice – even if, that is, I’m a
participant in the practice in question. This will be the case, at least sometimes,
when the goals external to the practices are better served by my violating its rules
(and ceasing, temporarily, to participate in it) than by my adhering to them, or when
new, more important goals interfere.228 Rawls is right that we would not usually
withdraw our claim that a player ought to be ruled out after taking a third strike
when we discover that a relevant desire is lacking. The rules of baseball don’t make
exceptions for or cease to apply to such cases. But we might decide that, all things
considered, we ought not to declare the player “out” in special circumstances
(though we ought, as far as the rules go to rule him out)—when, for instance, the
player is a five‐year‐old kid in a backyard game who hasn’t hit the ball all day. In
such a case, we have most reason not to do as the rules demand, once again, in spite
of their categorical form.229
228
Thanks again to Adrian Moore for drawing my attention to this last possibility, and for illustrating
it with a real‐life example from football: when West Ham played Everton in December of 2001, Paulo
di Canio intentionally caught the ball in the middle of play, in obvious violation of the rules, when an
opposing player went down with what looked to be a very serious head injury.
229
Rawls sometimes seems to argue that though “one can be as radical as one likes” about practices,
“in the case of actions specified by practices the objects of one’s radicalism must be the social
practices and people’s acceptance of them” and not the particular actions themselves. (See Rawls,
“Two Concepts of Rules, p. 32) This suggests that when a practice is justified, all actions required by
its rules are also justified. The above example is intended to show that this may not always be the
case. Here the practice of baseball is surely justified, but one ought, in this instance, to break its rules.
Rawls might respond that the justified action provided by the example is not one of ‘allowing
a fourth strike,’ as there is no such action (‘strikes’ exist only within the practice of baseball, and its
rules allow only three of them). The justified action of the example might be described instead as ‘an
additional throwing of the ball after three strikes have been pitched, for the purpose of persuading
the player he has not yet struck out.’ This answer strikes me as unsatisfactory: the principle
suggested above—that all actions required by the rules of justified practices are themselves
justified—still fails under the redescription of the example: we still have an example of a case where
(continued on next page)
197
It seems that many practice rules—rules connected with what Foot would
call categorical uses of ‘ought’—do not constitute categorical imperatives: we may
not have most reason to comply with them. What’s different about the moral
categorical imperative? I have argued that it is a rule of reason. It is one of many
rules that define the practice of procedural rationality. These rules are rules of
practice, not rules of thumb: they serve to define types of actions—willing, acting
for reasons—that are not available to people who do not adhere to them, at least to
an extent. Like the other examples of practice rules I have discussed, they take the
categorical form. But the moral imperative, as a law of reason, also differs in
important respects from the other examples of practice rules. Firstly, moral rules,
and other rules of reason, are not binding on us in virtue of being instrumentally
valuable. Our participation in the practice of morality, and more broadly, that of
rationality, is not justified on instrumental grounds. One sometimes finds morality
or a particular moral principle defended on instrumental grounds, for example, by
appeal to self‐interest, or even evolutionary theory. Even if having certain moral
dispositions were in the agent’s best interests, or were fitness‐promoting, nothing
normative would follow from this alone. It cannot be the case that fundamental
moral laws derive their normative force from their tendency to promote such goals.
The value of such goals must itself first be established by means of moral argument.
(Recall also Kant’s argument, discussed in §4.1 above, against the possibility of
an action required by the rules of a justified practice—calling the player out—is not justified, all
things considered.
198
grounding the bindingness of moral requirements in some external end or ulterior
motive.)
It might be objected here that our reasons to be rational must sometimes be
based on the value of ends to which rational behavior is a means. This is clear from
the fact that we can sometimes have powerful instrumental, prudential, or even
moral reasons to be at least locally irrational, as Derek Parfit has shown. He
imagines cases in which what we have most reason to do is to cause ourselves to be
for brief periods deeply irrational (perhaps by taking a pill).230 However, in these
cases we are still being rational, broadly speaking, even if we are temporarily and in
some respects irrational—we are, after all, doing what we have most reason to do.
If, in such a case, we decided against being locally irrational—if, that is, we behaved
in a way that was locally rational, we would be guilty of broad irrationality—of
failing to do what we had most reason to do. Let’s imagine a case where my only
reason to be rational is clearly instrumental in nature—I’m taking a mathematics
prize examination, and my only reason to do well in it is to obtain the prize. Even
here, it is, I think, a mistake to conclude that the laws of rationality, which guide me
as I tackle the questions on the exam, get a grip on me only because I value the prize.
After all, the instrumental reason I have to do well on the exam—the reason
provided by the prize—itself gets a grip on me only because I take the internal
perspective to the practice of rationality. It is not because of my desire for the prize
that I occupy that perspective.
230
Parfit, Reasons and Persons, pp. 12‐13.
199
This brings us to a second, closely‐related way in which the moral categorical
imperative differs from the practice rules that I discussed earlier, in which we find
categorical uses of ‘ought,’ but, it seems, no genuine categorical imperatives. The
practice of rationality, of which the moral imperative is one rule, cannot be
questioned from the outside. When we ask ‘is the practice of rationality justified?,’
as we did of those other practices, we appeal to the very standards whose reason‐
giving force we are trying to question. Justification is a matter of providing
sufficient reason—it is itself part of the practice of rationality. This does not mean
that we can never question proposed principles of rationality—some philosophers
spend a good deal of their time doing just that. But such questions must necessarily
be asked from within the practice of rationality, and must appeal to principles of
rationality that we do not doubt. As Thomas Nagel has put it in The Last Word, his
defense of the objectivity of reason, the “validity [of reason] is unconditional
because it is necessarily employed in every purported challenge to itself.”231
Nagel goes on to address an obvious worry this line of argument raises. He
grants:
This response to subjectivism may appear to be simply question‐
begging. After all, if someone responded to every challenge to tea‐leaf
reading as a method of deciding factual or practical questions by
appealing to further consultation of tea leaves, it would be thought
absurd. Why is reasoning about challenges to reason different?
The answer is that the appeal to reason is implicitly authorized
by the challenge itself, so this is really a way of showing that the
challenge is unintelligible. The charge of begging the question implies
that there is an alternative—namely, to examine the reasons for and
against the claim while suspending judgment about it. For the case of
231
Nagel, The Last Word, p. 7.
200
reasoning itself, however, no such alternative is available, since any
considerations against the objective validity of a type of reasoning are
inevitably attempts to offer reasons against it, and these must be
rationally assessed. … In contrast, a challenge to the authority of tea
leaves does not itself lead us back to tea leaves.232
Nagel argues that it is not possible for us to look at reasoning as simply
something we do—something without normative force. If we are fully committed to
the validity of, say, the principle of modus ponens, then we cannot at the same time
think of this commitment as simply a psychological fact about us, a fact that has
nothing to do with the normative force of the principle. “This,” Nagel writes, “is
merely an instance of the impossibility of thinking ‘It is true that I believe that p; but
that is just a psychological fact about me; about the truth of p itself, I remain
uncommitted.’”233
The strangeness of the question “Is the practice of rationality justified?” is
clear if we take rationality to consist in responsiveness to reasons. If being rational
is a matter of doing what one has sufficient reason to do, and if a practice is justified
if we have sufficient reason to participate in it, the question appears to read, “Do we
have sufficient reason to do what we have sufficient reason to do?” The question
seems tautological. John Broome has recently questioned whether the above
interpretations are the right ones to make.234 He argues that being rational is a
matter of complying, in our reasoning processes, with certain requirements (of
which the law of non‐contradiction and the principle of modus ponens are prominent
232
Ibid., p. 24.
233
Ibid., p. 32
234
Broome, “Does Rationality Give Us Reasons?,” especially §5.
201
examples). Doing what we have sufficient reason to do, he maintains, is an entirely
different matter. Conflating the two is simply a matter of mixing up reason, the mass
noun (we might call this “Reason with a capital ‘R’”), with reason, the count noun.
The requirements of rationality describe Reason, and need not tell us anything
about what reasons (small ‘r’) we have.
Broome’s doubts are worth raising. But I have tried, in the last four chapters
of this book, to argue that the assumption of a close relation between what reasons
we have and what rationality requires of us is well founded, and furthermore, that
the fact of this close relation does not significantly limit the scope of normativity of
practical reason. I have argued that what we have reason (small ‘r’) to do depends
on the (purely procedural) requirements of Reason (capital ‘R’), as they apply to our
existing ends and commitments. I have also argued that this account of when we
have a reason is compatible with the existence of universal moral reasons—of a
moral imperative that is categorical in the strong sense.
202
Chapter 7
What Do We Have Moral Reason To Do?
7.1 Persons and things
If the internalist argument for categorical moral reasons I’ve developed in
the preceding chapters succeeds, what is it we have reason to do? I’ve argued that
we all have internal reasons to comply with a version of Kant’s categorical
imperative. Kant’s formula of humanity tells us:
so act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the
person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely
as means.235
But taken on its own, this instruction is somewhat cryptic. What exactly do Kant’s
formula and the Kantian internalist argument I’ve developed entail about which
actions are morally permissible or required?
What I will have to say about this important question will be provisional and
exploratory in nature. For this reason, it may, I am afraid, disappoint. But the
exploratoriness is, I think, inevitable. As Allen Wood has argued, Kant’s formula is
not designed to provide, on its own, clear answers to specific questions about what
to do. Despite Kant’s efforts to explain his various formulations of the moral law by
applying them particular examples in the Groundwork, Kant’s categorical imperative
doesn’t provide a straight‐forward, ‘plug and chug’ test for the permissibility of
maxims. This, Wood says, simply reflects Kant’s conception of the system of moral
philosophy, which consists both of a fundamental, a priori principle and of a body of
235
Kant, Groundwork, p. 38 (4:429).
203
empirical information about humans and the circumstances in which they act
(which Kant called “practical anthropology”). We can get a specific set of moral
rules or duties or verdicts out of the former only by carefully and non‐deductively
interpreting it in the light of the latter.236
So, Wood argues, we should not mistake Kant’s proposed fundamental
principle for the kind of ‘scientific’ principle from which we could simply deduce a
conclusion about what to do in any given circumstance (of the sort that Sidgwick
and some modern‐day utilitarians, and perhaps some Kantians, too, are arguably
after). Instead, Wood says,
The first principle is … fundamentally an articulation of a basic value.
The rules and duties represent an interpretation of the normative
principles applying that basic value under the conditions of human
life. In their application, moreover, the rules or duties themselves
require interpretation, and admit of exceptions, by reference to the
first principle.237
This seems to me exactly right: the best way to characterize the formula of
humanity – certainly in the role it plays in my defense of it – is as “an articulation of
a basic value.” And what I hope to do now is to take some initial interpretive steps
towards exploring what recognition of that basic value requires of us given the
circumstances of our lives.238
236
Wood, “Humanity As End In Itself,” p. 61.
237
Ibid., pp. 59‐60.
238
In doing so, I will draw significantly from the work of others, including Christine Korsgaard
(“Creating the Kingdom of Ends: Reciprocity and responsibility in personal relations,” in Creating the
Kingdom of Ends), Rae Langton (“Duty and Desolation”), Peter Strawson (“Freedom and
Resentment”), Onora O’Neill (“Between Consenting Adults”), Thomas Hill (Dignity and Practical
Reason in Kant’s Moral Theory), and Derek Parfit (On What Matters).
204
Kant’s argument, as I have developed it, tells us that all people are ends in
themselves, intrinsically valuable, the source of the value of all the other things we
pursue, and the ends for the sake of which we ultimately act. They have their
special value in virtue of being the kinds of beings to whom things matter ‐ who
have ends of their own that matter to them – as opposed to merely mattering to us,
having value for us. This distinguishes persons from things, and establishes persons
as “ends in themselves.” Kant’s principle as I read it is, at heart, an anti‐
objectification principle. Kant tells us that we must, in all our actions, respect the
status of persons as ends in themselves, by never using them merely as a means, as
we might a mere thing, but always, at the same time as an end – as something whose
special value as a person we recognize and respect.
It seems clear enough what is involved in using someone as a means – we do
this whenever we make use of their body or attributes or capacities to help serve
our own ends. There are, surely, plenty of harmless ways of doing this. When I hug
you on a cold night, I may be using you to keep me warm. When I ask you how to
spell a word, I am using you as a means to avoid an embarrassing error. When I ask
you for an introduction to your friend, I am using you as a means to get to know
someone new. When I pay you to drive me to the station in your taxi, I am using you
as a means of getting there. Indeed, I use others as means in all of the myriad ways
in which I rely, every day, on their help. When I act in these ways, I may, in one
respect, be treating others as I would a thing – using you as a dictionary, or a hot
water bottle. But my attitude to you, more generally, is quite different from my
attitude towards things, and this would be reflected in this and other interactions I
205
have with you. Kant’s formula, accordingly, does not forbid treating someone as a
means, but rather treating someone merely as a means, and not at the same time as
an end.
It is important to notice that the requirement that we treat others as ends
goes well beyond the prohibition on treating them as mere means. After all, I can, it
seems, avoid using people as mere means by simply ignoring them altogether. But if
I do that, I am not treating these people as ends, and so am not complying with the
formula of humanity. As this brings out, Kant’s formula is in fact quite demanding.
It tells us that we shouldn’t just use people, and so issues a negative prohibition on
certain forms of exploitation and objectification, which I’ll consider more carefully
below. But the formula calls for considerably more than this: it adds, to its
prohibition on treating others as mere means, a positive exhortation to also treat
them as ends.
What is it to treat another person as an end?
This question has, I think, many answers. First and perhaps most
straightforwardly, treating someone as an end, rather than a means, may be a
matter of valuing that person non‐instrumentally. If I keep you as a friend only
because you’re useful to me as a source of introductions to a social circle to which I
would not otherwise have access, I am merely using you in a way that is condemned
by the formula of humanity.239 The phrase “trophy wife,” used to describe a young,
239
Does this formulation condemn too much? My interest in my cab driver, for example, does not
seem to stretch much beyond my interest in getting to the station. Do I then use her merely as a
means? I would hope not. If I did, then I would, for example, not pay my fare, if I could get away with
it. But I do pay my fare, and not just as a matter of convenience. If, in fact, I pay it only because it’s
(continued on next page)
206
attractive woman who is valued merely as a status symbol by her older husband,
picks out another example of this sort of objectionable objectification of persons. I
should, instead I want you for my friend (or wife) and value you in your own right,
not (or not primarily) as a means to some further good, like your social connections
or my social status. If I value you in your own right, non‐instrumentally, I am not
treating you merely as a means.
But this can’t be all that’s involved in recognizing the special value you have
as a person, since we often value things as ends in this way, not just people. I may
value a painting non‐instrumentally ‐ in its own right, and not, say, as an investment,
or status symbol, or because of some other further good it can bring me. So it is
possible for me to treat a person as my end in this way while still, in an important
sense, objectifying her – that is, without respecting the special status she has, as an
end in herself, that objects, like paintings, lack. It is easy enough to objectify people
in this sense in the context of personal relationships. We do this when we focus
exclusively on what someone means to us, rather than on their interests (except to
the extent that their interests affect their value to us). This, too, is a familiar enough
failing in personal relationships.240
the easiest option, then I may well be treating her as a mere means, and my behavior may well be
objectionable under the formula of humanity.
240 This book’s cover image (??), David Hockney’s painting “American Collectors (Fred and Marcia
Weisman), explores this slide between the way we value people and the way we value objects – even
those objects we value non‐instrumentally. Look once at the painting, and you see two art collectors,
standing amongst objects from their valuable collection. Look again, and the collectors themselves
can seem to belong to the collection, echoing the form of other statues, colorful and static and
carefully, precisely placed. Perhaps the husband is surveying his collection, his wife now its prized
member. Or perhaps it is she who standing amidst her possessions, husband included, looking out at
the viewer.
207
Christine Korsgaard points out that it is this sort of objectification, rather
than merely using people, that Kant sees as the chief danger posed by sexual
relationships. She writes:
what bothers him is not the idea that one is using another person as a
means to one’s own pleasure. That would be an incorrect view of
sexual relations, and in any case any difficulty about it, would, by
Kant’s own theory, be alleviated by the other’s simple act of free
consent. What bothers Kant is rather that sexual desire takes a person
for its object. He says: “They themselves, and not their work and
services, are its Objects of enjoyment.”241
The quote is from Kant’s Lectures on Ethics, and she includes a longer passage, too,
that makes the point quite clear:
Man can, of course, use another human being as an instrument for his
service; he can use his hands, his feet, and even all his powers; he can
use him for his own purposes with the other’s consent. But there is no
way in which a human being can be made an Object of indulgence for
another except through sexual impulse … it is an appetite for another
human being.242
The potential problem with sexual love is that it sees its object not as a mere
means, but as an end to be possessed, rather than as and end in itself. Recall Kant’s
distinction between “objective” and “subjective” ends, which John Taurek picked up
on and which played such a crucial role in the arguments of Chapters 4 and 5:
[Persons] … are not merely subjective ends [like things], the existence
of which as an effect of our action has a worth for us, but rather
objective ends, that is, beings the existence of which is in itself an end,
and indeed one such that no other end, to which they would serve
merely as means, can be put in its place…243
Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends, p. 194. The quote from Kant in this passage is from his
Lectures on Ethics, p. 162.
241
242
Kant, Lectures on Ethics, p. 163, quoted by Korsgaard, ibid., p. 194.
243
Kant, Groundwork, p. 37 (4:428) (emphasis in the original).
208
He draws the same distinction between kinds of value again in somewhat different
terms, in a later passage from the Groundwork, this time distinguishing between two
different kinds of “subjective” ends:
What is related to general human inclinations and needs has a market
price; that which, even without presupposing a need, conforms with a
certain taste, that is with a delight in the mere purposeless play of our
mental powers, has a fancy price; but that which constitutes the
condition under which alone something can be an end in itself has not
merely relative worth, that is, a price, but an inner worth, that is,
dignity.244
As Korsgaard explains, regarding someone as a sexual object is less like
regarding him or her as a tool, valuable to us because it serves our needs – as having
what Kant called a “market price” – and more like regarding him or her as an
aesthetic object, something whose value to us does not depend on its serving some
purpose – as having what Kant called “fancy price.” This is more problematic than
being seen as a tool, because it’s not clear how someone could consent to being
regarded as an end to be achieved or possessed without giving up her respect for
her own status as an end in herself. As Korsgaard puts it in a footnote: “Being useful
is no threat to your dignity, but being delectable is.”245
So treating someone as an end in herself, as having dignity, rather than price,
in the manner required by the formula, goes beyond not merely using her as a
means, and also beyond treating her as an end in the sense of valuing her non‐
instrumentally. What more does it involve? Remember that on Kant’s broader
conception of ends, as those things for the sake of which we act, I may pursue
244
Ibid.,p. 42 (4:434‐435) (emphasis in the original).
245
Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends, p. 214 (note 11).
209
something as an end, non‐instrumentally, but still for the sake of some more
fundamental end. When I pursue a painting that I value as an end, I do so for my
sake – I am, in Kant’s sense, the ultimate end for the sake of which I act. In this
second, non‐instrumental, kind of objectifying relationship I’ve been discussing, we
pursue people in the same way: for our own sakes, ultimately, and not theirs. This,
then, is one way in which we can treat others as ends in themselves: we can act for
their sakes, rather than (just) for ours. We can recognize them not only as beings
that matter to us, and have value because of that, but also, at the same time, as
beings to whom things matter, who therefore confer value on their own ends.
An element of that, as Kant emphasizes, is acknowledging the value of others’
ends by making them our own. Kant’s formula is, in this way, notably demanding.
Kant writes:
Now, humanity might indeed subsist if no one contributed to the
happiness of others but yet did not intentionally withdraw anything
from it; but there is still only a negative and not a positive agreement
with humanity as an end in itself unless everyone also tries, as far as he
can, to further the ends of others. For, the ends of a subject who is an
end in itself must as far as possible be also my ends, if that
representation is to have its full effect in me.246
This is one way in which I can act out of recognition of other’s value‐conferring
status.
There are of course incredibly difficult and important questions to be asked
and answered here about the extent of our obligations to help others achieve their
ends. These are precisely the sorts of questions to which Kant’s categorical
246
Kant, Groundwork, p. 39 (4:430).
210
imperative, on its own, provides no clear answer. I will not try to tackle them here.
But as Kant argues, and Onora O’Neill has emphasized, there is another tricky line to
be walked here, a thin line between (to use Kant’s labels) too much love for others
and too much respect. In The Doctrine of Virtue, Kant writes:
The principle of mutual love admonishes [rational beings] to
constantly come closer to each other; that of the respect they owe one
another, to keep themselves at a distance from one another.247
Both love and respect are ways of recognizing the status of others as ends in
themselves; but each on its own also threatens to lead us into violations of the
formula of humanity. Love, says O’Neill, “requires us to make the other’s ends,
whose achievement would constitute his or her happiness, in part [our] own.”
Respect, on the other hand, requires that we “recognize that others’ maxims and
projects are their maxims and projects. [We] must avoid merely taking over or
achieving the aims of these maxims and projects, and allow others the ‘space’ in
which to pursue them for themselves.”248
So one aspect of treating others as ends in themselves – as opposed to merely
ends of ours – is doing things for their sake, while leaving them room to exercise
their capacities for free choice. But the anti‐objectification principle that underlies
Kant’s formula – that persons have a special value, as beings to whom things matter,
that mere objects, which may matter to us, lack – is more generally suggestive. To
think about what it might entail, it helps to think about what is distinctive about
247
Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, pp. 568‐9.
248
O’Neill, “Between Consenting Adults,” p. 265.
211
persons, and our interactions with them, and what it might mean to treat a person
as we’d treat a mere thing.
When Kant draws the distinction between persons and things, he emphasizes
one difference in particular: a person, he says, is a “being the existence of which is
in itself an end, and indeed one such that no other end … can be put in its place.”249
Persons, unlike things, in other words, are non‐fungible. This, in fact, is the main
point of the related distinction between price and dignity that he later draws:
“[w]hat has a price,” he says, “can be replaced by something else as its equivalent;
what on the other hand is raised above all price and therefore admits of no
equivalent has a dignity.” Persons, Kant tells us, are essentially irreplaceable; but
things are replaceable – another with the same properties would do just as well.
This seems clearly true of things we value purely as means – as instruments.
It’s less clear that this is true of those things we value as ends – not in themselves,
but for our sakes. Rae Langton points out:
We often value particular items in such a way that they aren't
replaceable by a duplicate: it is this very teacup that I value, this very
house, this very painting.250
This is true. But usually, when it is true, it’s true because of the relation of the object
to a person – it’s that relation that makes the object irreplaceable. I value that very
painting, and not a copy, because that one is a genuine Leonardo. I value this very
house, because it’s the one I grew up in. I value this very teacup, because we brought
it back from that holiday we took together. Objects whose value to us depends on
249
Kant, Groundwork, p. 37 (4:428) (my emphasis).
250
Langton, “Duty and Desolation,” p. 486 (note 9).
212
their relation to a person inherit some of the non‐fungibility of that person. They
become non‐fungible because they are, in a sense, non‐duplicatable. We may find an
identical cup, with all the same properties; the house for sale next door may look
just like mine; an unusually skilled forger may paint a faithful copy of the Mona Lisa;
but the objects themselves will have different relational properties – they will be
related to different people. This teacup didn’t make it back with us from Cornwall.
Someone else imported it. This house was not the scene of my childhood memories,
but of someone else’s. And even if our forged painting is produced, it turns out, by
Leonardo’s identical twin brother, the copy will differ from the original in a crucial
respect – it’s author will be a distinct center of subjectivity, with a distinct, unique,
perspective on the world.
Persons have value that is non‐fungible not only because each person is
unique, but also, perhaps more importantly, because of the value they have as ends
in themselves. They not only matter to us, in their own special way, but things
matter to them. In addition to the unique value they may have for others, the fate of
each person is of course of special and terrible significance to himself. It is this
insight that led John Taurek to conclude that respecting the special value had by
persons, as opposed to objects, has dramatic implications for how we may make
tradeoffs between the competing interests of different people. When fungible goods
are threatened, he says, as certain aggregative, maximizing attitude seems like the
right one to adopt: these things have value to us, and our goal is to preserve as
much of what is valuable as we can. But to make the same sort of calculation when
213
it’s people’s interests at stake is to fail to respect them as not just having value for us,
but being, themselves valuers.
Taurek writes:
It seems to me that those who, in situations of the kind in question,
would have me count the relative numbers of people involved as
something in itself of significance, would have me attach importance
to human beings and what happens to them in merely the
[aggregative, maximizing] way I would to objects which I valued. …
But when I am moved to rescue human beings from harm in
situations of the kind described, I cannot bring myself to think of them
in just this way. I empathize with them. My concern for what happens
to them is grounded chiefly in the realization that each of them is, as I
would be in his place, terribly concerned about what happens to
him.251
Taurek thinks it follows from this difference that the number of people whose good
is at stake should not be taken into consideration when making decisions that
involve trade‐offs between the interests of different people. It’s far from clear to me
that this does follow. Scanlon, for example, draws a very different conclusion from a
very similar premise. He writes:
respecting the value of human life is in [a] way very different from
respecting the value of objects and other creatures. Human beings are
capable of assessing reasons and justifications, and proper respect for
their distinctive value involves treating them only in ways that they
could, by proper exercise of this capacity, recognize as justifiable.252
Scanlon makes it clear that “the justifiability of a moral principle depends only on
various individuals’ reasons for objecting to that principle and alternatives to it.”253
In discussing tradeoffs between the interests of different people, he writes:
251
Taurek, “Should the Numbers Count?”, pp. 306‐307.
252
Scanlon, What We Owe To Each Other, p. 169.
253
Ibid., p. 229.
214
Utilitarianism, and most other forms of consequentialism, have highly
implausible implications, which flow directly from the fact that their
mode of justification is, at base, an aggregative one: the sum of a
certain sort of value is to be maximized. … A contractualist theory, in
which all objections to a principle must be raised by individuals,
blocks such justifications in an intuitively appealing way. It allows the
intuitively compelling complaints of those who are severely burdened
to be heard, while, on the other side, the sum of the smaller benefits to
others has no justificatory weight, since there is no individual who
enjoys these benefits [summed together] and would have to forgo
them if the policy were disallowed.254
But Scanlon goes on to argue that we can justify to each individual a decision to save
a greater number of lives rather than a lesser.255 I won’t try to weigh in on whether
Taurek or Scanlon has better understood what’s involved in respecting the unique
value of persons.256 Allen Wood is right that Kant’s formula is unlikely to settle
questions like this one its own, without a lot of additional normative‐ethical leg‐
work. He is also right that the formula of humanity “provides us with the right
value‐basis for settling difficult issues, and that on many difficult issues, it is an
advantage of [the formula] that different sides can use it to articulate their strongest
arguments.”257
So far, we have seen that the requirement to value persons as ends in
themselves involves not merely using them as instruments in our plans; it involves
not merely treating them as valuable to us – to be pursued and protected for our
own sakes – but also as valuable in themselves, independently of our interest in
them, with ends of their own, and the moral status to confer value on those ends.
254
Ibid., p. 230.
255
See ibid., Chapter 5.
256
My sympathies are with Scanlon (though not with all the details of his argument).
257
Wood, “Humanity as End in Itself,” p. 65.
215
We have seen that recognition of this status requires us to adopt others’ ends as our
own, but without taking over those ends. Our recognition of other people as ends in
themselves, with the capacity to choose their own projects and plans, requires us to
give them space to carry out those plans without too much interference from us.
And we have seen that respecting the special value had by persons, as opposed to
things, requires recognizing them as non‐fungible, though the implications of this for
how we may treat them are far from clear.
There is still more we can say. In discussing what it is involved in treating
persons as ends in themselves (rather than as mere means, or as merely having
value to us), both Christine Korsgaard258 and Rae Langton draw on Peter Strawson’s
classic essay “Freedom and Resentment,” in which Strawson perceptively describes
two different attitudes we can adopt in our interactions with other human beings.
Here’s Strawson:
What I want to contrast is the attitude (or range of attitudes) of
involvement or participation in a human relationship, on the one
hand, and what might be called the objective attitude (or range of
attitudes) to another human being, on the other. Even in the same
situation, I must add, they are not altogether exclusive of each other;
but they are, profoundly, opposed to each other. To adopt the
objective attitude to another human being is to see him, perhaps, as an
object of social policy; as a subject for what, in a wide range of sense,
might be called treatment; as something certainly to be taken account,
perhaps precautionary account, of; to be managed or handled or cured
or trained; perhaps simply to be avoided, though this gerundive is not
peculiar to cases of objectivity of attitude. The objective attitude may
be emotionally toned in many ways, but not in all ways: it may include
repulsion or fear, it may include pity or even love, though not all kinds
of love. But it cannot include the range of reactive feelings and
attitudes which belong to involvement or participation with others in
258
Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends, p. 196; Langton, “Duty and Desolation,” p. 486.
216
inter‐personal human relationships; it cannot include resentment,
gratitude, forgiveness, anger, or the sort of love which two adults can
sometimes be said to feel reciprocally, for each other. If your attitude
towards someone is wholly objective, then though you may light him,
you cannot quarrel with him, and though you may talk to him, even
negotiate with him, you cannot reason with him. You can at most
pretend to quarrel, or to reason, with him.259
Strawson’s “objective” attitude has much in common with our attitudes
towards things, or inanimate forces of nature. We may fear the falling rock, or the
flooding waters, we may seek to avoid them, or “manage” them, guarding as best we
can against the damage they threaten to do, but we don’t, ordinarily, resent them, or
blame them, for that damage. (Sometimes, we do: we kick the door that slams on
our finger; we shout at the computer that, crashing, loses our work; we kiss the goal
post the blocks our opponent’s shot. But when we do these things, we are making
the inverse mistake to the one Kant’s formula warns us against: instead of
objectifying persons, we are anthropomorphizing objects.)
Sometimes though, as Strawson notes, we take the objective attitude towards
another human being: we see his behavior as something to be feared, perhaps, or
managed, or just waited out, but not to be blamed or resented. In some cases, this
may be the appropriate attitude to take, as when we’re dealing with very young
children, or with the clinically deranged – with people who lack the ordinary
rational capacities of persons. As Williams noted (and I discussed in Chapter 1),
blame assumes the presence of a reason to which its target is capable of responding.
The same is true of resentment, and of the other reactive attitudes that are
259
Peter Strawson, “Freedom and Resentment,” p. 9.
217
characteristic of the “participant” attitude Strawson describes. When we take the
objective attitude towards people who lack normal rational capacities, we do
objectify them in a way – we treat them, in one respect, as we would an object; but
in this respect – in that we cannot reason with them – they are like objects. (In many
other respects, including those I have discussed, they are still like people, and not
like objects. In those respects, Kant’s formula tells us we must still treat them as
ends in themselves: we may not treat them as mere means, nor as mere ends to be
possessed; we must recognize them as ends in themselves, and so as sources of
value for their ends; and to that extent, we must make their ends our own.260)
But sometimes we adopt the objective attitude towards people with whom
we could instead reason – towards people with whom taking the participant attitude
is open to us. We do this, for example, when we judge others (or ourselves) to have
been overcome by their emotions. It is common to think of the emotions as a kind of
internal weather – as forces of nature that move us against our will. I recall an irate
teacher once railing at a student for having failed to follow the argument of a lesson.
When the student, bewildered, asked, “Professor, what is it you want me to do?” he
responded, with some self‐awareness, “Just wait until the storm blows over.” This
teacher was taking the objective attitude towards himself, and advising his student
to do the same. But it is hard not to see such behavior in a psychologically healthy
human being as involving a voluntary ducking of responsibility, a willing abdication
260
For more on how we must treat such people, see §7.3, below.
218
of the capacity to respond to reasons – and as such, a kind of objectification of
himself, a failure to treat himself as an end.
A more insidious form of this species of objectification, discussed by Langton,
to great effect,261 is the characterization of women as governed by their emotions,
rather than by their rational wills, and so as beyond the reach of reasoning. The
widespread diagnosis of female hysteria in the eighteenth, nineteenth, and early
twentieth centuries illustrates this phenomenon. Any number of “symptoms” of
“nervousness” or dissatisfaction were attributed to this “malady.” In 1908, the
London Times published an editorial claiming that suffragettes protesting for the
right to vote were “suffering from hysteria;” such questioning of the mental health of
feminist activists was not unusual. And a notorious article written by the renowned
professor of pathology Almwroth Wright attributed feminist demands to the
“physiological emergencies” that constantly threatened women.262 Not only did
such treatment objectify women by failing to recognize their status as rational
261
See her description of the case of Maria von Herbert in “Duty and Desolation.” Herbert writes to
Kant for moral advice, both about the permissibility of deceiving a friend, and about the moral status
of suicide (which she contemplates in the desolation that results in part from the damage done to her
friendship). Kant at first responds to her with seriousness, but later dismisses her letters as the
communications of a woman suffering from female hysteria. Langton writes:
It is hard to imagine a more dramatic shift from the interactive stance to the
objective. In Kant's first letter, Herbert is 'my dear friend', she is the subject for
moral instruction, and reprimand. She is responsible for some immoral actions, but
she has a 'heart created for the sake of virtue', capable of seeing the good and doing
it. Kant is doing his best to communicate, instruct, and console. … He treats her as a
human being, as an end, as a person. This is the standpoint of interaction.
But now? Herbert is die kleine Schwirmerin, the little dreamer, the ecstatical
girl, suffering a 'curious mental derangement', lost in the 'wanderings of a sublimated
fantasy', who doesn't think …. Herbert, now deranged, is no longer guilty. She is
merely unfortunate. She is not responsible for what she does. She is the pitiful
product of a poor upbringing. She is an item in the natural order, a ship wrecked on
a reef. She is a thing. (“Duty and Desolation,” p. 500)
262
Elaine Showalter, “Hysteria, Feminism, and Gender,” in Hysteria Beyond Freud, p. 320.
219
beings, capable of responding to reasons, filling roles of responsibility, and making
plans and setting ends of their own. It also, consequently, resulted in another kind
of objectification: a failure to treat women as sources of value, and thus a failure to
recognize their ends as valuable, to recognize those ends’ frustration as the more
likely source of women’s dissatisfaction, to share those ends, and to help further
them.
As Strawson emphasizes, adopting the objective perspective towards
someone dramatically changes the nature of the interactions that we can have with
her. Sometimes, this is exactly the point. As Strawson says, we sometimes adopt the
objective perspective towards someone “as a refuge … from the strains of
involvement.”263 Resentment, certainly, can be draining, and absolving someone of
responsibility is sometimes easier than forgiving. But adopting this attitude comes
at a cost, both to its object and to ourselves. Over time, it makes genuine friendship
impossible. This is because friendship necessarily involves some sharing of ends.
Langton writes:
When you hold someone responsible, you are prepared to work with
them, view them as someone who has goals of their own that you
might come to share, or as someone who might come to share your
goals. You are prepared to do something with them, in a sense very
different from the sense in which you might do something with a tool.
When my friend and I make a cake, I'm doing something with my
friend, and I'm doing something with flour, chocolate, cherries, brandy
– but there is a difference. My friend, but not the flour, is doing
something with me. My friend, and not the flour, is doing what I am
doing, sharing the activity. As a human being, she can choose ends of
her own, and can choose to make them coincide with mine. The
263
Strawson, “Freedom and Resentment,” p. 9.
220
standpoint we take towards human beings is interactive, and it is
different from the standpoint we take with things.264
We cannot do things with people, in the sense that entails their also doing things with
us, if we adopt the objective perspective towards them. Doing things together, in
that sense, is another way of showing respect for the special value had by persons –
another way of treating them as ends in themselves.
Indeed, it represents a kind of apotheosis of treating others as ends in
themselves, which is why Korsgaard tells us that “[t]o become friends is to create a
neighborhood where the Kingdom of Ends” – Kant’s moral ideal – “is real.”265 If you
are genuinely my friend, I will value you as an end, not just a means. And I will value
you not just for my sake, but also for yours. I will see you as an end in yourself, and
the things that matter to you will matter to me too, for your sake. I will make your
ends my own, and will try to secure them. But I will not take them over, leaving you
no space to pursue them yourself. Because as your friend, I will want us to do things
together – that is, after all, what friends do. And if we’re to do things together, then I
cannot, as we have seen, take Strawson’s objective attitude to you – see you a thing
buffeted by the forces of nature. For I cannot act together with a thing that has no
will of its own.
264
Langton, “Duty and Desolation,” p. 487.
Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends, p. 194; Langton concurs; see “Duty and Desolation,” p.
492.
265
221
7.2 Consent
I also can’t act together with a thing that has a will of its own but that does
not share my ends. So even if I adopt a participant attitude in our relationship – even
if I treat you as responsive to reasons and having a will and ends of your own – I will
still fall short of the ideal of cooperation if I coerce you into acting as I wish or
deceive you about what it is we are doing. If I coerce or deceive you into helping me
pursue my end, then it cannot be one of your ends, too. As Kant writes of one kind
of deception:
he whom I want to use for my own purposes by [a false] promise
cannot possibly agree to my way of behaving towards him, and so
himself contain the end of this action.266
Rae Langton says: “To deceive is thus to make a person thing‐like:
something that cannot choose what it does.”267 What if, she imagines, she enlists her
friend’s help to bake a cake, but without revealing that her intent is to use that cake
to seduce her friend’s notoriously sweet‐toothed boyfriend? “Now,” she says, “I am
doing something with my friend in the very same sense that I am doing something
with cherries and chocolate, flour and brandy.”268
Langton is partly right: when we deceive or coerce people, we make use of
their capacities to serve our own ends, just as we might make use of a tool with
certain handy functions. Langton’s imagined friend is a good baker, just as her oven
might be. But in another respect, when we deceive or coerce people we are not
266
Kant, Groundwork, p. 38 (4:430).
267
Langton, “Duty and Desolation,” p. 489.
268
Ibid., p. 490.
222
treating them as we would a thing, or as something that cannot choose what it does.
We can’t, after all, coerce or deceive a thing. And it is precisely because people can
choose what they do, and have ends of their own, that we can coerce them, and
would choose to deceive them.
Coercion, unlike force, uses a person’s ends against her; it persuades her to
act, by upping the stakes, for her, of non‐compliance. Far from overriding a person’s
rational capacities, coercion asks her to employ them – a person generally has good
reason to do as she is coerced to do, though she would not have such reason, of
course, were it not for the coercive threat. Deception is, in this respect, a little
different: the person who is deceived may act as she has no (objective) reason to
act. But she, like the victim of coercion, acts rationally – she responds correctly to
her subjective reasons. And again, the deceiver is making use of her victim’s rational
faculties – convincing her to act a certain way, by controlling her evidence about
how she should act.
As this brings out, there are ways of using people that are very different from
the ways we can use objects. Consider the two senses of the word “manipulation.” In
one sense of the word, we can manipulate an object: the surgeon manipulates her
scalpel when she performs an operation; in the same sense, the physical therapist
may manipulate her patient to loosen a joint. But the kind of manipulation we
usually have in mind when we speak of manipulating people – the kind involving
coercion, deception, seduction – is not something we can do to things.
Coercion and deception nonetheless undermine Kant’s ideal of cooperation,
in which respect for the humanity of another is most fully realized. Coercers and
223
deceivers make it impossible for their victims to act together with them, by
preventing the sharing of important ends. They also, usually, fail to treat their
victims as sources of value, by failing to properly take into account how what they
do matters to their victims. And they use their victims, and especially, their victims’
rational capacities – a central manifestation of their personhood – as a mere means
to their ends.
We may be able to avoid these pitfalls if we give others an informed say in
how we treat them. This thought, coupled with the examples to which Kant himself
appeals to illustrate the formula of humanity, have led many Kantians to interpret
the formula as entailing a kind of consent requirement.
Kant says, in explanation of his formula:
rational beings … are always to be valued at the same time as ends,
that is, only as beings who must be able to contain in themselves the
end of the very same action.269
And (again) to account for the wrongness of making false promises:
he whom I want to use for my own purposes by [a false] promise
cannot possibly agree to my way of behaving towards him, and so
himself contain the end of this action.270
And finally, in the Critique of Practical Reason:
[a] rational being … is not to be subjected to any purpose that is not
possible in accordance with a law that could arise from the will of the
affected subject himself; hence this subject is to be used never merely
as a means but as the same time an end.271
269
Kant, Groundwork, p. 38 (4:430).
270
Ibid., p. 38 (4:430).
271
Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, p. 210 (5:87).
224
In all three of these passages, Kant can be read as claiming that treating
others as ends is in part a matter of treating them only in ways to which they can
consent.272 But formulating a plausible, meaningful consent requirement can be
surprisingly tricky. Is a person able to share the ends of my action only if he actually
has consented to it, or at least would actually consent to my performing it if I asked
him?
This may be an ideal to aim for, but it cannot be a requirement for morally
permissible actions. The fact that a very self‐interested person would refuse to
consent to an act that would greatly benefit someone else at minor cost to himself
does not entail that we ought not to perform it. As Derek Parfit points out, even in
those cases where the withholding of consent to an action is not something for
which we would blame a person, we often feel that we are morally required (or at
least morally permitted) to perform the action anyway. Rescue cases, in which the
rescuer must choose between saving one person or a group of five people, might
take this form. The one may perfectly justifiably withhold consent to our leaving her
272
One difference between Kant’s various appeals to consent, which I will not address in what
follows, concerns the question of what it is that the persons affected by our actions must be able to
consent to. The two passages from the Groundwork suggest that the targets for moral evaluation
under the consent principle are particular actions. The passage from the Second Critique, by
contrast, suggests that the target of evaluation might be broader—it might be the “law” in accordance
with which we act. The first, narrower, interpretation is reflected in Korsgaard’s and Parfit’s
versions of the principle. The second, broader, interpretation is reflected in the work of
contractualists such as John Rawls and T.M. Scanlon. Rawls argues that the basic structure of society
should be organized according to the principles that would be agreed upon by rational, mutually
disinterested agents who are ignorant of specific facts concerning their social status or contingent
aims and desires. Scanlon’s consent principle states that an act is wrong if it would be disallowed by
any principle that no one could reasonably reject. (See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, and Scanlon, What
We Owe To Each Other.) Parfit also considers an interpretation of Kant’s argument that applies the
test of the consent principle to principles for acting rather than to specific actions. He calls this the
“Kantian Contractualist Formula.” According to this formula, “Everyone ought to follow the
principles whose universal acceptance everyone could rationally will.” See Parfit, On What Matters,
Volume 1, p. 342.
225
to die, but we are still morally required, or at the very least morally permitted, to
save the five. As this last case brings out, there will also be many occasions for action
in which we cannot possibly secure everyone’s consent, because the only actions to
which some parties would be willing to consent will be rejected by others.273
Moreover, as Onora O’Neill has argued,274 actual consent often does little to
secure the permissibility of actions. She points out that even in the case of explicit
contracts, where the actions consented‐to are supposed to be explicitly spelled out,
ignorance and duress can lead people to consent to things they would never have
agreed to under conditions of full information and free choice. Indeed, the legalese
of explicit contracts often makes informed consent particularly hard to obtain in
these cases. Sometimes, one suspects, intentionally so: too much information can
deceive as assuredly as too little. O’Neill mentions the “widespread European use of
‘treaties’ to ‘legitimize’ acquisition of land or sovereignty by seeking the signatures
of barely literate native peoples with no understanding of European moral and legal
traditions.”275 The baffling complexity of modern‐day mortgage and credit card
contracts with variable interest rates provides a more recent example.
Even where the best efforts to obtain genuine informed consent are made,
serious obstacles to meaningful consent remain. It can be impossible to strike a
working balance between too much information and too little: “Patients,” O’Neill
points out, “cannot easily understand complex medical procedures; yet if they
273
See Parfit, On What Matters, Volume One, p. 180.
274
O’Neill, “Between Consenting Adults,” pp. 254‐256.
275
Ibid., pp. 254‐255 (note 1).
226
consent only to a simplified account, they may not consent to the treatment
proposed.”276 And often, even when parties are making a genuinely informed
choice, they are choosing from a dramatically limited set of options. (O’Neill gives,
as examples, a choice of husbands in a society where there is a firm expectation that
women will marry, and a choice of jobs in an economic system where non‐
employment is not an option for most people.) Sometimes, just how limited our set
of options is can be difficult to discern from within the walls the limits build,
throwing up yet another obstacle to meaningful, informed consent. Adaptive
preferences present a related worry. And some people will, even with clear eyes,
repeatedly allow themselves to be taken advantage of.
Of course, treating people in ways to which they do not consent isn’t the only
way of violating the dictates of the formula of humanity. Taking advantage of
someone may well fail to respect his status as an end in himself in other ways, some
of which I discussed in the previous section. But we may nonetheless think that
poorly informed consent, or consent among severely limited options, or the consent
of a self‐denier or ‘push‐over’ do no work justifying an action – that whatever moral
work consent can do, it is not doing it here. If so, we will want to look beyond the
appeal to actual consent to understand the role consent and its absence play in
determining the permissibility of action.
Some philosophers have pushed a weaker interpretation of Kant’s formula:
perhaps it requires us merely to make it possible for others to consent to our
276
Ibid., p. 256.
227
treatment of them. The second passage from the Groundwork lends some support to
this interpretation. Kant, remember, writes that I violate someone’s status as an end
in himself when I make a lying promise to him because he “cannot possibly agree to
my way of behaving toward him, and so himself contain the end of this action.”
Korsgaard’s reading of Kant’s principle puts emphasis on the “possibly.” Thus she
writes:
Kant’s criterion most obviously rules out actions which depend on
force, coercion, or deception for their nature, for it is the essence of
such actions that they make it impossible for their victims to consent.
If I am forced, I have no chance to consent. If I am deceived, I don’t
know what I am consenting to. If I am coerced, my consent itself is
forced by a means I would reject. So if an action depends on force or
deception or coercion, it is impossible for me to consent to it. To treat
someone as an end, by contrast, is to respect his right to use his own
reason to determine whether and how he will contribute to what
happens.277
On Korsgaard’s interpretation of Kant’s formula, we may not treat people in
ways to which their giving consent is impossible. This principle has the advantage
that it seems to fit Kant’s discussion of examples well, particularly in the case of the
lying promise. It also has the more significant advantage that it reinforces some of
the intuitions that made the formula of humanity appealing in the first place. If what
is most valuable and inviolable in human nature is a person’s capacity to rationally
choose ends for himself, then force, deception, and coercion do seem to be
particularly grave offenses.278
277
Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends, pp. 295‐296.
278
Onora O’Neill also interprets Kant’s formula in terms of a Possible Consent Principle (see
“Between Consenting Adults,” pp. 105‐125).
228
A possible consent requirement seems, however, both too permissive and too
restrictive. It is too permissive because it does not condemn any actions that were
consented to, and thus, a fortiori, it was possible to consent to, even if their victims
should not have consented to them. Appeals to possible consent thus seem to
inherit all the difficulties of actual consent.
Such a requirement looks too restrictive because it condemns actions to
which the affected person could not possibly consent, but to which he or she should
have or would have consented had consent been possible. Parfit points out that
Korsgaard’s test, as it stands, would condemn life‐saving surgery on people who are
unconscious.279 The same may be true of acts that protect the interests of people
whose whereabouts we don’t know.
Korsgaard might respond to this objection that it is not “the essence of such
actions that they make it impossible for their victims to consent,” as it is in the case
of “actions which depend on force, coercion, or deception for their nature.” In the
first example, it is the patient’s unconscious state, rather than the act of performing
life saving surgery, that makes consent impossible. Similarly, in the second example,
it is our ignorance of the whereabouts of the beneficiaries, not our beneficial act
itself, which makes consent impossible. Crucially, in both these cases, we are not
responsible for the impossibility of consent. What we may not do, according to
Korsgaard’s Kant, is make it impossible for others to consent to our actions.
Coercion and deception do just that. What’s more, this shift in emphasis to what we
279
Parfit, On What Matters, Volume One, p. 178.
229
make possible or impossible may help alleviate some of the worries the possible
consent requirement seemed to inherit from the actual consent requirement. We
may not withhold crucial information from people with whom we interact; we may
not dramatically limit their options, and thereby coerce them into giving consent; we
may not bully them into self‐denial. We must do our best to give them genuine
power of choice over their situation. But if their information is lacking, their options
are limited, and they are self‐denying independently of us, we cannot be faulted for
that.
It’s not clear, however, that this response can do the work that Korsgaard
needs it to do. It seems we are sometimes morally required to deceive a person,
even though our act of deception is what makes their consent impossible. Parfit
offers an example that helps bring out this intuition:
[C]onsider
Fatal Belief: I know that, unless I tell you some lie, you
will believe truly that Brown committed some murder.
Since you could not conceal that belief from Brown, he
would then murder you as well.
If I say nothing, you could reasonably complain with your dying
breath that I ought to have saved your life by deceiving you. I could
not defensibly reply that, since I could not have deceived you with
your consent, this way of saving your life would have been wrong. My
life‐saving lie would be like life‐saving surgery on some unconscious
person. Just as this person would consent to this surgery if she could,
you would consent to my deceiving you. It is a merely technical
problem that, if I asked you for your consent, that would make my
deceiving you impossible. … Since you would consent to my deceiving
you if you could, my lie would be morally as innocent as some lie that
was needed to give someone a surprise party.280
Ibid., pp. 178‐179. Korsgaard suggests that Kant’s formula, and her interpretation of it via the
consent principle, run into the greatest difficulties when dealing with evil (see Korsgaard, Creating
(continued on next page)
280
230
Korsgaard’s consent requirement might be reformulated to avoid some of
these worries. In some cases, she could argue, a general, tacit, advance consent to
harmlessly deceptive actions of a certain type may be inferred. In this way, for
example, celebrating a surprise party may after all be something that we do together
– an end that we can share. Whether this response generalizes is unclear – it seems
much more far‐fetched, for example, to suggest that you had a genuine opportunity
to tacitly accede, in advance, to my plan of deception in Fatal Belief.
In any case, the fact that you would have good reason to condone my
deception in Fatal Belief after I acted281 makes the fact that you could not have
consented to it before I acted seem morally irrelevant.282 Moreover, as with actual
consent, securing the possibility of genuine consent or dissent, in what Parfit calls
the “act‐effecting sense” – where the person’s consent or dissent will effectively
determine my course of action – may be impossible in cases where different parties’
interests conflict. A may dissent from my performing the only action to which B
would give her consent. If that’s the case, then I cannot give both A and B the power
to determine how I act. What’s more, often I should not give others such veto power
the Kingdom of Ends, p. 100; also, Ch. 5: “The Right to Lie”). But Parfit’s Fatal Belief example could be
restructured so that it doesn’t rely on the presence of evil. We can imagine, instead, the following
case of Vertigo: You must cross a deep ravine by means of a narrow bridge, but suffer from severe
fear of heights. Half way across the bridge and afraid to look down, you ask me how deep the ravine
is. I know that if I answer you truthfully, you will be paralyzed with fear and dizziness, and may well
lose your balance. If I tell you instead that the ravine is quite shallow, and you safely cross to the
other side, have I done a moral wrong?
281
Parfit points out that if you had the ability to make yourself lose particular memories, you could
have and would have consented to my lying to you without making that lie impossible.
282
Although consent after the fact raises its own problems: in particular, when, as in some cases of
adaptive preference or cognitive dissonance, the act itself secures the later consent.
231
over what I do: if I can prevent grave harm to A at a small cost to B, then I should do
so, whether or not B, selfishly, dissents from my plan of action. And if I can save A
only by deceiving or coercing B, then I should do so.283
A reexamination of the objections raised against the first two interpretations
of Kant’s formula as a consent principle points in the direction of a formulation that
avoids the problems of both. I objected to an actual consent requirement on the
grounds that a person might fail to consent to some act to which she should consent.
I objected to both an actual consent requirement and a possible consent
requirement that a person may in fact consent to an act to which she should not
consent. And finally, I objected (following Parfit) to a possible consent requirement
that a person might have good reason to approve of an act to which she could not
possibly consent, and good reason to consent to an act to which she would not
actually consent, so that I ought not make it possible for her to exercise power over
what I do. All these objections suggest that there is a standard for consent, and that
what matters for the moral permissibility of an action is whether the person
affected by it has sufficient reason to consent to it, not whether she would consent
to it, or subjectively could consent to it.
Parfit offers a third interpretation of Kant’s formula that takes this
conclusion into account. According to his principle, which I will call the Rational
Consent Principle, “It is wrong to treat anyone in any way to which this person could
283
For example, we should (contra Kant) surely deceive the murderer at the door, who has come to
ask to whereabouts of our friend. Korsgaard agrees, and explains this departure from Kant as a move
from ideal to non‐ideal theory. See “The Right to Lie,” in Creating the Kingdom of Ends.
232
not rationally consent.”284 The emphasis here is on “rationally.” The question is
whether our actions are rationally justifiable from the perspective of the people
whom they affect. Parfit elaborates: “[w]e ought to act with some aim that other
people could rationally share, so that they could rationally consent to our way of
treating them.”285 (If he is to avoid the objections he raises to the possible consent
requirement, Parfit must mean here to appeal to what we could rationally choose, if
we were in a position to choose, as if from outside our lives, what happens to us.286)
He argues that, in many cases, we have sufficient reasons to do either what is best
from our own point of view, or what would be best from an impartial point of view.
We could rationally consent to acts that would be best from an impartial point of
view, as well as to acts that, though not impartially best, would be significantly
better for us or for those we love.287
His test therefore produces the right answer in the case of the person who
allows himself to be taken advantage of by consenting where he did not have
sufficient reason to consent—consent in this case, though possible, and indeed
actual, was not rational. His test also produces the right answer to cases where the
affected person either should have consented, but did not consent, or would have
consented, but could not consent. If the act under evaluation is best by far from the
point of view of the person affected (as is the case in the life‐saving surgery
284
Parfit, On What Matters, Volume One, p. 181.
285
Ibid., p. 182.
286
We might compare this to Michael Smith’s appeal to the well‐placed advisor who shares are
values, which I discuss in §2.2 above. Thanks to a reader for OUP for this point.
287
Parfit, On What Matters, Vol. I, p. 186.
233
example, and in Fatal Belief), then that person could rationally have consented to it,
and the act is permissible under the Rational Consent Principle. If the act under
evaluation is best from an impartial point of view (as, for example, in rescue cases
like the one described above), then again, according to Parfit, any person affected by
it could rationally consent to it, even at great cost to himself.
Parfit’s Rational Consent Principle provides a more satisfying interpretation
of Kant’s formula than appeals to actual or possible consent, largely because it does
a better job of matching our intuitions about particular cases. Moreover, it seems to
capture much of what was appealing about Kant’s formula of humanity. It resonates
with Scanlon’s observation, which I quoted earlier:
respecting the value of human life is in [a] way very different from
respecting the value of objects and other creatures. Human beings are
capable of assessing reasons and justifications, and proper respect for
their distinctive value involves treating them only in ways that they
could, by proper exercise of this capacity, recognize as justifiable.288
But it might be objected to Parfit’s principle that it is no longer, strictly
speaking, really about consent. That is, Parfit’s test is a test for the sufficiency of
reasons, and could in fact be rephrased without making reference to consent at all.
We might, for example, restate it as the Rational Justification Principle: an act is
permissible only if there is sufficient reason for it to be performed from the
perspective of the persons whom it affects.
Of the versions of the consent requirement I have discussed, only the first,
the actual consent requirement, really allows the concept of consent, as we usually
288
Scanlon, What We Owe To Each Other, p. 169.
234
understand it, to do work in establishing the permissibility of actions. That
principle, we have seen, is problematic. But in some cases, the fact of consent does
seem to make a difference to the moral permissibility of an action. Thus in most
cases, a doctor may operate on a man to remove one of his kidneys for donation only
if he actually consented to the operation. And a rapist cannot defend his act by
claiming that his victim could have rationally consented to having sexual intercourse
with him. Hypothetical consent is no kind of consent at all.289
This does not strike me as a devastating objection to the Rational Consent
Principle. For one thing, some acts are by their nature consensual, in that non‐
consensual versions of them are not plausibly described as the same act‐type. Rape
is not the same act‐type as consensual sex, and a fist‐fight counts as a boxing match
only if consent was given first. Moreover, as Parfit notes, we can sensibly ask if
someone could have rationally consented, in advance, to our treating them a certain
way without their consent, and while the answer will often be ‘no’ (as in the case of
rape, and in most cases of organ donation), it may sometimes be ‘yes.’ So the
Rational Consent Principle will not collapse into an actual consent requirement. We
may sometimes have sufficient reason to consent to limiting our future freedom in
this way.290 “Before the discovery of anaesthetics,” Parfit points out, “many people
freely consented to being later coerced during painful surgery.”291 We might
This is not to say that tacit or implicit consent—the fact that I would have consented had I been
asked, and that this is known about me—cannot in some cases do the work of consent in justifying
actions.
289
290
Parfit, On What Matters, Volume One, p. 193.
291
Ibid, p. 179.
235
similarly argue that we could rationally consent, in advance, to a policy of saving the
greater number of people, even over the objections of the members of the smaller
group, so long as we didn’t know, in advance, which group we’d be likely to belong
to should the need for a rescue arise.
It seems to me plausible to interpret Kant’s formula of humanity as implying,
in part, a test for the sufficiency of reasons. It would not be the first of Kant’s
formulations of the categorical imperative that was intended to play just this role.
Christine Korsgaard, for one, has interpreted Kant’s formula of universal law as “a
test of the sufficiency of the reasons for action and choice which are embodied in
our maxims.”292 That formula, remember, states: “act only in accordance with that
maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law.”293
Kant’s arguments begin from the premise that we are all equally bound by the
requirements of morality. His worry, when arguing for the formula of universal law,
is that we may make exceptions for ourselves as moral agents. It is this tendency to
make exceptions of ourselves that the test proposed by the formula is supposed to
check. But the test seems to have stated its requirement the wrong way around.
According to it, we are to ask ourselves before we act, “Could I rationally will that
everyone act this way?” But the more natural question to ask, when seeking to
determine whether our reasons for acting are sufficient, is “Could everyone
(affected by my actions) rationally will that I act this way?” And this, as we have
292
Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends, p. 79.
293
Kant, Groundwork, p. 31 (4:421).
236
seen, is the requirement established by the formula of humanity, if we take it to
entail Parfit’s Rational Consent Principle.
As an interpretation of Kant, however, the Rational Consent Principle runs up
against a significant concern, which can be brought out by responding to an
objection to hypothetical consent principles raised by Onora O’Neill. O’Neill objects
to a version of the Rational Consent Principle on the following grounds:
Many conceptions of rationality presuppose a given set of desires. If
these are the actual desires of the consenter, appeal to hypothetical
consent will not overcome the worry that a consensus may be
iniquitous or reflect local ideology. Yet if there is no appeal to the
consenter’s actual desires, then the theory may be too weak to
determine what would rationally be consented to. Given that there
are many rationally structured sets of hypothetical desires, rational
structure alone cannot determine what would rationally be consented
to.294
This concern appears to be a recreation of the worry about internalism that
is brought out by Williams’ example of the cruel husband. If what we could
rationally do is relative to our desires (or, more broadly, our motivational sets), then
might it not turn out that what we can rationally consent to reflects iniquities in our
character or local ideologies? Just as the Kantian argument can, I think, provide a
solution to the worry raised by Williams’ example, it can also respond to O’Neill’s
worry. According to Kantian internalism, the motivational sets of fully procedurally
rational persons contain only those contingent ends that are compatible with the
laws of procedural rationality, of which Kant’s moral categorical imperative is one.
294
O’Neill, p. 109.
237
Thus the possibility that the consent of (hypothetical) fully rational beings reflect
iniquities or local ideologies is ruled out by Kant’s internalist argument.
But viewed in this light—that is, taken as a piece in Kant’s larger moral‐
rationalist project—the Rational Consent Principle gives rise to a different problem:
it seems to be circular over at least a subset of the cases it is supposed to evaluate.
Here is one way the principle could be problematically circular: it could tell us that
an act is wrong if and only if it treats someone in a way to which she could not
rationally consent; and then it could tell us that we could rationally consent to be
treated a certain way if and only if the act in question is not wrong. The circularity
worry raised by the Kantian principle is similar. The Rational Consent Principle is,
on Kant’s view, not only a moral law, whose content depends on what it is rational to
do, but also itself a law of reason, which at least in part determines what it is rational
to do. The formula of humanity, from which the Rational Consent Principle was
derived, is, after all, one expression of Kant’s categorical imperative of practical
reason. Kant’s argument has this structure:
(i)
The Formula of Humanity: It is a law of reason that we must in our
actions always take humanity to be an end in itself. We are behaving
rationally only to the extent that our actions respect the status of
humanity as an end in itself.
(ii)
The Rational Consent Principle: Treating humanity as an end in itself
means treating human beings only in ways to which they could rationally
consent.
(iii)
The giving of consent is one of our actions which, if we are fully rational,
must be governed by the Formula of Humanity. Our consent is rational
only to the extent that it compatible with respect for humanity as an end
in itself.
238
(iv)
Therefore, we can only rationally consent to actions that treat humanity
as an end in itself.295
But, according to (ii), treating humanity as an end in itself involves treating
human beings only in ways to which they could rationally consent. Hence the
circularity arises. It arises despite the fact that this way of spelling out the Rational
Consent Principle determines which acts one could rationally consent to without
appealing an act’s “rightness” or moral permissibility as grounds for rational
consent. The grounds for rational consent to an act are, according to Kant, the same
as the conditions for the moral permissibility of that act. But this is a different claim
from the claim that the grounds for rational consent to the act are that it is morally
permissible.
None of the versions of a consent requirement on action that I’ve explored
offer completely satisfactory rules for action. But we’d do well to remember Allen
Wood’s admonishment that we should not be searching for such rules in Kant’s
formula of humanity in the first place. We ought to try, as far as possible, to interact
with others through cooperation, rather than manipulation:
•
We should try, where possible, to influence them by appealing to their
rational faculties, rather than through means that undermine or circumvent
those faculties.
•
When only one person’s interests are at stake, we should aim, when possible,
to give that person power over how our acts affect him – to offer him the
genuine possibility of meaningful consent or dissent.
295
This condition for rational consent (provided by the categorical imperative) includes the
limitations on rational consent provided by the instrumental and prudential imperatives. That is, we
could not rationally consent to any action that undermines our subjective ends when their promotion
would not conflict with the necessary end of humanity.
239
•
When many people’s interests are at stake, we can try to give each person as
much power over the proceedings as is compatible with the same power for
others.
•
We should leave others as much freedom to pursue their chosen ends as is
compatible with these and other requirements of the formula of humanity,
and where possible, aid them in their pursuit of those ends.
7.3 Infants and animals
Before closing, I’d like to briefly consider what the Kantian formula I have
defended tells us about our treatment of non‐rational beings: of infants and young
children, of those who are severely mentally incapacitated, and of animals. In Kant’s
argument for his formula of humanity, only rational nature is a source of value. And
in case we missed the point, he reiterates it when he draws his crucial distinction:
Those beings whose existence rests not on our will but on nature, if
they are non‐rational beings, have still only a relative worth, as means,
and are therefore called things, while rational beings, on the contrary,
are called persons, because their nature already distinguishes them as
ends in themselves….296
But, I have maintained, Kant was wrong to draw the line between persons and things
– between ends in themselves and everything else – where he does. Kant’s argument,
at least as I have revised and redeveloped it, relies on drawing it in a different place:
between beings to whom things matter and the things that matter to them. We are all
committed, I’ve argued, to the non‐fungible, non‐instrumental, intrinsic, and value‐
conferring value of beings that value. And that class surely includes not just rational
beings, but any creatures with a mental life sophisticated enough to count as centers
of subjectivity.
296
Kant, Groundwork, p. 37 (4:428) (my emphasis).
240
I believe that the Kantian internalist argument commits us, on pain of
procedural irrationality, to recognizing the moral status of all such creatures as ends
in themselves. But it certainly doesn’t follow that animals, say, or infants, or the
severely cognitively impaired or mentally ill should be treated as “persons” in all of
the respects I have been exploring. Scanlon’s injunction, that we treat human beings
only in ways that they could recognize, through the proper exercise of their rational
capacities, as justifiable, does not apply to animals. Nor, of course, does any
requirement to obtain their consent. And we cannot aim to do things together with
animals, infants, and the insane, as we can with each other. Nor should we adopt
towards them the fully participant perspective. It is understandable but not
reasonable to resent an infant for waking you up six times a night. Or to resent the
dog for destroying yet another pair of shoes. So friendship is not the moral ideal at
which our relationships with non‐rational beings should aim.
But we can recognize such beings as ends in themselves in many other
respects: we may not treat as mere means, nor as mere ends to be possessed; we
must recognize them as having a value that is independent of the value they have for
us, and so as sources of value for their ends; and to that extent, we must make their
ends our own.297 (There is no danger, however, in this case, of allowing love to
inappropriately swamp respect.)
297
Non‐rational beings can’t, of course, bestow value on their ends by rationally choosing them. And
their desires are no surer an indicator of what has value for them than ours are (as any dog‐owner
will know). But they, like us, have interests. We can ask of such beings: what do their actual
motivations, coupled with standards of procedural rationality, entail for what we have reason to do
for them?
241
Our duties towards animals differ, therefore, in important respects, from our
duties towards people. They differ also from our duties towards infants, young
children, and the mentally ill. This is because, in the case of children, we must
respect not just the ends that they are, but also the ends they are starting to become.
Peter Strawson, after distinguishing between the objective and participant attitudes
we can adopt towards others, perceptively writes:
parents and others concerned with the care and upbringing of young
children cannot have to their charges either kind of attitude in a pure
or unqualified form. They are dealing with creatures who are
potentially and increasingly capable both of holding, and being objects
of, the full range of human and moral attitudes, but are not yet truly
capable of either. The treatment of such creatures must therefore
represent a kind of compromise, constantly shifting in one direction,
between objectivity of attitude and developed human attitudes.
Rehearsals insensibly modulate towards true performances. The
punishment of a child is both like and unlike the punishment of an
adult.298
And he adds, considering the case of the mentally ill:
Again, consider—a very different matter—the strain in the attitude of
a psychoanalyst to his patient. His objectivity of attitude, his
suspension of ordinary moral reactive attitudes, is profoundly
modified by the fact that the aim of the enterprise is to make such
suspension unnecessary or less necessary.299
I cannot put it better.
7.4 Immorality as irrationality?
At the outset of this book, I raised a worry: my goal would be to identify
universal moral internal reasons – to show that everyone has reason to be guided by
298
Strawson, “Freedom and Resentment,” p. 19
299
Ibid., pp. 19‐20 (emphasis in the original).
242
the same moral principle, regardless of their contingent antecedent ends and
motivations, on pain of procedural irrationality. But, the worry was, wasn’t it
unsatisfying to suggest that someone who has failed to act as she has a moral reason
to act is guilty merely of a procedural irrationality? Could we possibly be persuaded
by the conclusion of an argument that reduces a moral wrongdoing to an error in
reasoning?
Scanlon discusses this objection to what he calls “formal” accounts of the
importance of moral reasons (he labels Kant’s a formal account). A formal account
is one that “appeal[s] to considerations that are as far as possible independent of the
appeal of any particular ends.”300 Such accounts, he writes,
might provide the secure basis that some have sought for the demand
that everyone must care about morality, [but do] not give a very
satisfactory description of what is wrong with a person who fails to do
so.301
This fault, the thought is, is not just an irrationality (as is the fault of someone who
fails to adhere to the principles of logic); there is something more deeply wrong
with the person. Someone who acts very wrongly is doing something more—
something worse—than behaving very irrationally.
When I flagged this concern in §1.2, I suggested that the worry should be
postponed until the end of the book, after we’d seen what failing to live up to the
demands of procedural rationality could look like. I hope the intervening arguments
will have convinced the reader that there is nothing dryly mechanical about the
300
Scanlon, What We Owe To Each Other, p. 150.
301
Ibid., p. 151.
243
exercise of procedural rationality. Not all errors in reasoning are, in that respect, on
a par. And there are some kinds of procedural concerns that are intuitively moral.
Fairness is one of these. I believe that Kant’s moral theory takes rightness to be a
kind of fairness. Kantian internalism’s central claim is that we behave irrationally
when we fail to recognize others like us as our equals, in the sense that their goals
and needs matter as much, objectively, as ours do. The exercise of our procedural
rationality involves us in the task of examining our own ends in a manner that does
not dismiss those of others. If we accept this task, we can indeed become better
people through the exercise of moral reason.
244
Bibliography
Arpaly, Nomy. 2003. Unprincipled Virtue: An Inquiry into Moral Agency. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Brink, David O. 1986. “Externalist Moral Realism,” in The Southern Journal of
Philosophy, Vol. 24, No. S1, pp. 23‐41.
Broome, John. 2005. “Does Rationality Give Us Reasons?,” in Philosophical Issues,
Vol. 15, No. 1, pp. 321–37.
Chang, Ruth. 2013. “Grounding Practical Normativity: Going Hybrid,” in
Philosophical Studies, Vol. 164, No. 1, pp. 163‐187.
Cummiskey, David. 1996. Kantian Consequentialism. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Crisp, Roger. 2013. “Well‐Being,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer
2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/well‐being/>.
Dancy, Jonathan. 1986. “Two Conceptions of Moral Realism,” in Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. LX, pp. 167‐187.
Darwall, Stephen. 1992. “Internalism and Agency,” in Philosophical Perspectives,
Vol. 6, Ethics, pp. 155‐174.
Falk, W.D. 1947. “‘Ought’ and Motivation,” in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
New Series, Vol. 48, pp. 111‐138.
Falk, W.D. 1986. Ought, Reasons, and Morality: The Collected Papers of W.D. Falk.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Finlay, Stephen and Mark Schroeder. 2008. “Reasons for Action: Internal vs.
External,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition),
edited by Edward N. Zalta, URL =
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/reasons‐internal‐
external/.
Foot, Philippa. 1978. Virtues and Vices. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Goldman, Alvin. 1979. “What is Justified Belief?,” in Justification and Knowledge,
edited by George Pappas. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 1‐23.
245
Harman, Gilbert. 1975a. “Moral Relativism Defended,” in The Philosophical Review,
Vol. 84, No. 1, pp. 3‐22.
Harman, Gilbert. 1975b. “Reasons,” in Critica, Vol. 7, No. 21, pp. 3‐13.
Harman, Gilbert. 1978. “What Is Moral Relativism?,” in Values and Morals, edited by
Alvin Goldman and Jaegwon Kim. Dortrecht, Holland: Reidel, pp. 143‐61.
Harman, Gilbert. 2000. “Is There a Single True Morality?,” in Explaining Value: And
Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 77–99.
Herman, Barbara. 1993. The Practice of Moral Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Hill, Jr., Thomas E. 1992. Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant’s Moral Theory.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Hobbes, Thomas. 1994/1651. Leviathan, edited by Edwin Curley. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company.
Holmes, Richard. 1985. Acts of War: The Behaviour of Men in Battle, New York, NY:
Simon & Schuster, Inc. (The Free Press).
Hume, David. 1975/1777. Equiries Concerning Human Understanding and
Concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by L.A. Selby‐Bigge and P.H.
Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press (Clarendon Press).
Hume, David. 1978/1740. A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by L.A. Selby‐Bigge
and P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press (Clarendon Press).
Johnson, Robert N. 1999. “Internal Reasons and the Conditional Fallacy,” in The
Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 49, No. 194, pp. 53‐71.
Johnson, Robert N. 2003. “Internal Reasons: Reply to Brady, Van Roojen and Gert,”
in The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 53, No. 213, pp. 573‐580.
Kant, Immanuel. 1992/1764. An Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the
Principles of Natural Theology and Ethics (the “Prize Essay”), in Theoretical
Philosophy, 1755‐1770, translated and edited by David Walford. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 243‐275.
Kant, Immanuel. 1997/1785. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, translated
by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
246
Kant, Immanuel. 1998/1793. Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason,
translated by Allen Wood and George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1997/1781/1787. Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Paul
Guyer and Allen Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1996/1788. Critique of Practical Reason, in Practical Philosophy,
edited and translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 133‐271.
Kant, Immanuel. 1996/1797. The Metaphysics of Morals, in Practical Philosophy,
edited and translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 353‐603.
Kavka, Gregory. 1978. “Some Paradoxes of Deterrence,” in Journal of Philosophy,
Vol. 75, No. 6, pp. 285‐302.
Kavka, Gregory. 1983. “The Toxin Puzzle,” in Analysis, Vol. 43, No. 1, pp. 33‐36.
Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Korsgaard, Christine. 2008. “The Myth of Egoism,” in The Constitution of Agency.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 69‐99.
Langton, Rae. 1992. “Duty and Desolation,” in Philosophy, Vol. 67, No. 262, pp. 481‐
505.
Langton, Rae. 2007. “Objective and Unconditioned Value,” in The Philosophical
Review, Vol. 116, No. 2, pp. 157‐185.
Lyons, David. 2001. “Ethical Relativism and the Problem of Incoherence,” in Paul
Moser and Thomas Carson (eds.), Moral Relativism: A Reader. New York:
Oxford University Press, pp. 127‐141.
Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin
Books.
Manne, Kate. 2014. “Internalism About Reasons: Sad But True,” in Philosophical
Studies, Vol. ???, No. ?, pp. ???.
247
Markovits, Julia. 2010. “Acting for the Right Reasons,” in The Philosophical Review,
Vol. 119, No. 2, pp. 201‐242.
Markovits, Julia. 2011. “Internal Reasons and the Motivating Intuition,” in New
Waves in Metaethics, edited by Michael Brady. Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan, pp. 141‐165.
Markovits, Julia. 2011. “Why Be An Internalist About Reasons?,” in Oxford Studies in
Metaethics Vol. 6, edited by Russ Shafer‐Landau. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 255‐279.
Mele, Alfred R. 2003. Motivation and Agency. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mill, John Stuart. 1979/1861. Utilitarianism, edited by George Sher. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company.
Millgram, Elijah. 1995. “What Hume a Humean?,” in Hume Studies, Vol. XXI, No. 1,
pp. 75‐93.
Nagel, Thomas. 1997. The Last Word. New York: Oxford University Press.
Nagel, Thomas. 1970. The Possibility of Altruism. Oxford: Oxford University Press
(Clarendon Press).
Narveson, Jan. 1972. “Moral Problems of Population,” in The Monist, Vol. 57, No. 1,
pp. 62‐86.
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
O’Neill, Onora. 1985. “Between Consenting Adults,” in Philosophy and Public Affairs,
Vol. 14, No. 3, pp. 252‐277.
O’Neill, Onora. 1989. Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical
Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
O’Neill, Onora. 2003. “Constructivism in Rawls and Kant,” in The Cambridge
Companion to Rawls, edited by S. Freeman. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, pp. 347–67.
Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press
(Clarendon Press).
Parfit, Derek. 1997. “Reasons and Motivation,” in Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, Supp. Vol. LXXI, pp. 99‐130.
248
Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters (Volumes One and Two). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Railton, Peter. 1986. “Facts and Values,” in Philosophical Topics Vol. 14, No. 2, pp. 5‐
31.
Rawls, John. 1955. “Two Concepts of Rules,” in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 64,
No. 1, pp. 3‐32.
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
(Belknap).
Raz, Joseph. 1979. The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford:
Oxford University Press (Clarendon Press).
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Raz, Joseph. 1990. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Scanlon, T.M. 1998. What We Owe To Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press (Belknap).
Shafer‐Landau, Russ. 1998. “Moral Judgement and Moral Motivation,” in The
Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 48, No. 192, pp. 353‐358.
Shafer‐Landau, Russ. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defense. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Elaine Showalter. 1993. “Hysteria, Feminism, and Gender,” in Hysteria Beyond
Freud (by Sander L. Gilman, Helen King, Roy Porter, G. S. Rousseau, and
Elaine Showalter). Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 286‐336.
Sidgwick, Henry. 1981/1874. The Methods of Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Company.
Singer, Peter. 1972. “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,” in Philosophy and Public
Affairs, Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 229‐243.
Smith, Michael. 1993. “Realism,” in A Companion to Ethics, edited by Peter Singer.
Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
Smith, Michael. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, Ltd.
Smith, Michael. 1995. “Internal Reasons,” in Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, Vol. LV, No. 1, pp. 109‐131.
249
Stratton‐Lake, Philip. 2000. Kant, Duty, and Moral Worth. London: Routledge.
Strawson, Peter. 1974. “Freedom and Resentment,” in Freedom and Resentment and
Other Essays. London: Methuen & Co., Ltd., pp. 1‐25.
Sturgeon, Nicholas. 1994. “Moral Disagreement and Moral Relativism,” in Social
Philosophy and Policy 11, pp. 80‐115.
Sullenberger, C. 2009. Interview with Katie Couric, 60 Minutes. New York: CBS
News.
Taurek, John. 1977. “Should the Numbers Count?,” in Philosophy and Public Affairs,
Vol. 6, no. 4, pp. 293‐316.
Walden, Kenneth. 2012. “Laws of Nature, Laws of Freedom, and the Social
Construction of Normativity,” in Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 7, edited by
Russ Shafer‐Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 37‐79.
Williams, Bernard. 1981. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, Bernard. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Williams, Bernard. 1993. Morality: An Introduction to Ethics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press (Canto).
Williams, Bernard. 1995. “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame,” in Making
Sense of Humanity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 35‐45.
Williams, Bernard. 2002. “’Ought,’ ‘Must,’ and the Needs of Morality.” Unpublished
lecture.
Wood, Allen. 1996. “General Introduction,” in Immanuel Kant’s collected Practical
Philosophy, ed. and translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, pp. xiii‐xxxiii.
Wood, Allen. 1999. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Wood, Allen. 2011. “Humanity as End in Itself,” in On What Matters, Volume Two,
edited by Samuel Scheffler, pp. 58‐82.
250