The Death of God in the Nineteenth Century
Lissa McCullough
A contribution to Edinburgh Critical History of Nineteenth-Century Theology,
edited by Daniel Whistler (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, forthcoming in 2017).
Drive your cart and your plow over the bones of the dead.
—William Blake, ‘Proverbs of Hell’ (1793)
The comprehensive story of the death of God is almost too intricate, elaborate, ambitious, and
ambiguous to be told. It is certainly presumptuous to try. If the referent God as redefined
repeatedly in religious history offers a multitude of distinct meanings, the death of God layers in
as many involutions of those meanings. In terms of the hermeneutic demanded to tell this tale,
we must concede this to be as elusive a topic as can be raised, involving as it does not merely
historical, metaphysical, or semiotic dimensions, but all these at once in fractious, unstable
concert and dissonance. As soon as we get past the jingoism of the phrase ‘death of God’ that
dates back to debates of the 1960s—a legacy interesting in its own right—we face a thousand
decisions and indecisions, ironies and reversals. Symbols are born in human history, live out
their meanings, and die carrying with them the most significant and portentous values under the
sun. Who contributed more to ‘killing’ the God of Jesus: Clement of Alexandria, William of
Ockham, or Friedrich Nietzsche? What contributed more to dooming modern faith: Descartes’s
theism, Hume’s empiricism, or Kant’s ineffectual bid to make room for faith? When was God
most alive in the first place? In the time of Jesus and his followers, before theology got hold of
Him; in the golden age of Thomas Aquinas, when God was most majestically articulated but
already sinking into the abyss of the nominalist challenge; or only today, released at last (in
theory) from the delusory entrapments of ontotheology (Heidegger 1927)? Is the death of God
essentially a revenge of Christian Aristotelianism on Christian Platonism? Or is it rather a victory
to be celebrated of rising global Christianity over the dying star of imperial-colonial
Christendom? ‘Then how should I begin?’ asks J. Alfred Prufrock wisely, ‘And how should I
presume?’
[A] Unless the Seed Dies…
In a sense, historical theology tells the history of thoughtful disavowal of a given God to make
room for a God-reconception or God-idea more worthy and adequate, more actual in the
Hegelian sense. The sociologist of religion, Jacob Taubes, posited this as a key principle when he
wrote: ‘The progress in theological interpretation throughout history runs parallel with a gradual
withdrawal of divine presence. Theological “re-presentation” and theological interpretation are
driven deeper and deeper into the web of dialectics because the divine presence is more and more
veiled’ (Taubes 1954: 25). Arguably—and Nietzsche’s lifelong friend Franz Overbeck did argue
this—the fateful withdrawal of God occurred already at the dawn of nascent Christianity. Marcel
Gauchet offers a complement to Taubes, arguing that with the death of God in western
Christendom the system of religion—religiousness in its most robust original form—has selfdeclared the end of its dominion; we westerners today are inhabitants of a world that ‘at a certain
point completely turned its back on the reign of the gods,’ not at the level of personal belief but
at the level of effective social organization (Gauchet 1985: 199).
For Gauchet, the French Revolution only completed this millennial process, which began
during the Axial Age with the rise of the state. The end of religion’s dominion became possible
2
because religion reached the end of its power as a system built on collective denial or refusal—a
response to something ‘unbearable’—because this dread has been gradually mitigated in the
course of history precisely by the axial transformation (Gauchet 199, 22, 25-6). This unbearable
actuality was, apparently, the terrifying freedom of facing an absolutely an-archic world of
experience. If relative freedom is a blessing, absolute freedom has been forefended historically
by religiousness as an intolerable abyss, an existential black hole. But according to Gauchet’s
thesis, Christianity has proven to be ‘a religion for departing from religion’ (4); the gradual
emancipation from and death of God has trained and conditioned us westerners to withstand the
asphyxiating terror of freedom. Western Christendom is uniquely a civilization of apostates, per
this interpretation.
The import of Nietzsche’s famous madman passage in The Gay Science (§125) is that the
‘murder’ of God, though it has long since occurred, is ‘still on its way’ in the late nineteenth
century, more distant from the murderers themselves ‘than the most distant stars.’ Cultured
despisers in the marketplace mock the madman’s distress because none have awakened to the
corrosive ramifications and consequences about to devastate their Enlightenment values,
purported to be universal. The full terror qua loss, the abyssal implications have yet to be played
out, indeed, to be abjectly suffered. Just as passengers on the Titanic continued to dine as the
unsinkable ship took on water, so by analogy was the death of God a fait accompli long before
the structures of civilization were able to absorb its absolute consequentiality. An omnipotent
God of ultimate concern is invasive of every single relative concern and presupposition of a
civilization. Even if an instant is sufficient to complete the thought-deed in an individual mind,
the social-political-moral layers of society, habituated by vested interests and grounded ab
origine in religious axioms, ensure that historically the deed can only be effected very slowly:
3
during that time the thought-deed will almost certainly be converted by the enchainments of
tradition and entrenchments of the status quo into something fatefully resembling the old idea,
and not merely once but again and again. To offer only one example, Kant’s religion ‘within the
limits of reason alone’ drew all its key terms from the Bible: it consists in ‘a way of living with
the Fall, according to the Law, in the Hope of attaining the Kingdom of Freedom’ (O’Neill 4).
The point to be taken is, even if overt language of the death of God first occurred in the
nineteenth century, the nineteenth century did not kill God. God was banished from this world
virtually overnight as an epochal consequence of late medieval nominalism, commencing in the
late thirteenth century, giving rise to the autonomous domain of modern natural science and its
correlative philosophy, and undermining the conceptual foundations of the revealed God of
sacra doctrina—a disjuncture that proved inexorable and irreparable (Knowles 265-306;
Oberman; Huizinga; Fabro; Gillespie 1995, 2008; Depoortere). On the heels of this ‘exile’ of
God from nature, the ‘death’ of God was effectively confirmed in the scientific-critical
revolutions of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. By the early nineteenth century God had
been demoted to a deistic hypothesis at best—whether a helpful or harmful one remained open to
polemical debate. The century’s most resolutely atheistic humanists and political thinkers
(Feuerbach, Stirner, Proudhon, Marx, Bakunin) were already impatient to banish all residual
vestiges of Christianity, even while the cultural-humanistic-pathetic implications of God’s
banishment had hardly begun to be absorbed within religious, philosophical, and imaginativepoetic thought—that is, as a devastation of value to be responded to with creative energy and
insight. What came to birth in Blake, Schelling, Hegel, and—most paradoxically—in
Kierkegaard were newfound conceptions or envisionments of God as self-transfiguring in
relation to nature and history rather than eternally impassible and immutable.
4
A complex either/or faced nineteenth-century post-theism: either reconstruct human
relatedness to God on new philosophical-theological grounds (Schelling, Hegel, Schleiermacher,
Kierkegaard) or prophesy a new creative vision to supplant the dead divinity (Blake, Nietzsche)
or turn away from God toward a chaste atheistic skepticism (Overbeck) or define a bold
transvaluation of material existence without God (Stirner, Feuerbach, Marx, Comte). Skepticaldeconstructive and creative-constructive dimensions of this mandate operated in tandem.
Skeptical thinking worked to negate the outdated divine presuppositions, purging the received
God of tradition from all equations. Constructive thinking advanced to posit a new hope: a new
God or humanism or egoistic individualism conceived as better or truer or more vital and
defensible than the defunct God whose time has passed.
If the progress of modern philosophy under the relentless pressure of skepticism can be
regarded as an ‘ingenuity of failures’ (Preuss vii), nineteenth-century philosophy’s importance
consisted in the creative ways it confronted and prosecuted an already late moment in the deathof God historical process. With considerable degree of success it rescued, retrieved, and
transfigured God, reviving and reconceiving the unique intentionality of that concept-word in
ways that are experienced even today—more than a century later—as live options. It makes
perfect sense, in retrospect, to pose our leading question in full irony: How did nineteenthcentury thinking rescue God from the death of God by means of death-of-God thinking?
[A] Blake and Stirner
Although Hegel and Nietzsche are first to be mentioned when explicit language of the death of
God is broached, alternate forerunners deserve to be cited in the same breath. The English poet
William Blake, in identifying God with human imagination and postulating divine-human
5
imagination as transcending Lockean sense perception, envisioned an intimate co-embodiment of
human and divine, a God fully incarnate in humanity; expressed in Blake’s own words, ‘God is
Man & exists in us & we in him,’ a coincidence that Blake names elsewhere as ‘The Eternal
Great Humanity Divine’ (Frye 30; Erdman 96). Half a century before Feuerbach offered his
theory of God as human projection in The Essence of Christianity (1841), this far more
sophisticated alternative to Feuerbach shone in the darkness. Blake’s conception of the divine
was inseparable from the ‘death’ or dissolution of God as traditionally conceived. Indeed, the
contemporary death-of-God theologian Thomas Altizer consistently credits Blake with having
been the first visionary to depict the death of God in his 1793 poem America: ‘The Heavens
melted from north to south; and Urizen . . . emerg’d his leprous head / From out his holy shrine,
his tears in deluge piteous / Falling into the deep sublime! . . . Weeping in dismal howling woe
he dark descended howling’ (plate 16, lines 2-9).
So momentous is Blake’s poetic vision of the ‘Self-Annihilation of God,’ melting away
and emptying out his ‘stored snows’ and ‘icy magazines,’ that Altizer closely correlates Blake
with Hegel on the basis of this parallelism: ‘The “Divine Image” dies in Jesus so as to abolish the
solitary God who is the source of judgment and bring about an apocalyptic brotherhood that is a
full coming together of God and man’ (Jerusalem, lines 23-28; Altizer 207). But the selfannihilation of Urizen, the abstract God of Enlightenment reason, cannot be understood as a
simple nullification of divine presence; it is rather the self-transfiguration of God to become
present in human form. Blake wrote quite earnestly, ‘I am in Gods presence night & day / And
he never turns his face away’ (Blake 481). God is transmuted into creative-poetic spirit incarnate,
or in terms of Blakean prophesy, the fiery Los.
6
A profoundly nihilistic counterpoint to Blake’s ‘Human Form Divine’ surfaces with Max
Stirner, another who deserves mention when explicit language of the death of God is broached.
Almost forty years before Nietzsche’s madman announced the death of God, Stirner professed
his radical atheist position in The Ego and His Own (1844). It was Stirner’s conviction, against
the highest hopes of naïve humanism, that the death of God means inexorably that the man in the
God-man equation also must die:
At the entrance to the modern time stands the ‘God-man.’ At its exit will only the
God in the God-man evaporate? And can the God-man really die if only the God
in him dies? They [Man] did not think of this question, and thought they were
through when in our days they brought to a victorious end the work of the
Enlightenment, the vanquishing of God: they did not notice that Man has killed
God in order to become now—’sole God on high.’ The other world beyond us is
indeed brushed away, and the great undertaking of the Enlighteners completed;
but the other world within us has become a new heaven and calls us forth to
renewed heaven-storming: God has had to give place, yet not to us but—to Man
[nicht Uns, sondern—den Menschen]. How can you believe that the God-man is
dead before the Man in him, besides the God, is dead? (Stirner 109; translation
amended)
For Blake, God is embodied in human imagination so as to live on in human form; thus both are
saved. Neither true God nor true humanity is lost. For Stirner, in diametric contrast, it is not only
God who must die but the humanity who loved and lived for him, and indeed who holds anything
7
sacred apart from the individual (der Einzige) since ‘everything sacred is a tie, a fetter’ (ibid.:
142).
Homo religiosus must die. God is a fixed idea that has subjected the individual to itself;
once you recognize this fixed idea to be a folly, you shut up its slaves in an asylum. God will
only be truly dead when the last shadow of the sacred is foresworn in each individual heart and
mind, and this includes every moral conceit since ‘moral people skimmed off the best fat from
religion, and ate it themselves.’ Every nation-state holds itself sacred, higher than the individual,
demanding patriotic self-sacrifice, tyrannical toward the one. For the state, every one in himself
is indifferent, a nothing. But ‘when mankind is buried, I am my own, I am the laughing heir [der
lachende Erbe]!’ (Ibid.: 59, 64, 142-43). With a Kierkegaard-like conviction that the individual
is what counts above all else in the world, Stirner stands absolutely for the anarchistic an-arche
of the existing individual: ‘Up with me!’ (ibid.: 143). Instead of making the leap of faith with
Kierkegaard, he makes the resolute plunge to the dissolution of God without remainder. God and
state are zeroed out and I am the laughing heir.
[A] Political Implications
The arc of ascending Christian Platonism (in the Greek Fathers, Augustine, Eriugena) vaunted
and perfected the doctrine of God’s absoluteness, aseity, and essential immutability. As it
reached systematic apogee, Aristotelian criticism pressed a descent into immanence (in Thomas
Aquinas, Duns Scotus, Ockham). Aristotelian thinking was brought to bear in conceptualizing
the implications of divine incarnation in relation to the world. The gradual collapse of God qua
transcendent asserted pressure and opportunity to reinvent and reestablish God qua immanent.
Thus the death of God is susceptible of being interpreted as the emergence, insistence, and
8
triumph of a commitment to incarnation, enacting the full actuality and palpability of incarnation
in the material flesh of the world (Leahy 2003). The nineteenth century was to take up its portion
of this task: God as immutable metaphysical transcendent was vanquished by God as empirical
change. The century was to generate various this-worldly reformulations of God as selfmanifesting in time and history rather than as known speculatively and metaphysically as he is
necessarily in himself.
Descartes banished the biblical God by philosophizing a purely rational deity in relation
to material nature (extensio) and the human mind (cogitatio) in an inquiry conducted entirely, he
presumed, on natural, strictly nonbiblical grounds. In so doing, philosophy enacted an epochal
liberation of thinking, fostering radical tabula rasa thought-projects that would restlessly
reinvent and recast this material-spiritual dualism in new terms with extraordinary persistence,
initiating a repetition-compulsion of sorts that ended only with Husserl. The radical Cartesian
diremption between extensio and cogitatio meant that, after the close of the seventeenth century,
natural science took charge of material nature and philosophy took charge of cogitating minds
(Whitehead 145). The new cosmology unveiled a universe infinite in extension and duration in
which eternal matter moves endlessly and aimlessly in eternal space in accordance with
necessary and eternal laws (Brague; Funkenstein; Becker 33-70).
This universe inherited all the ontological attributes of deity, but only those—’all the
others the departed God took away with him’ (Koyré 276). The universe under the aspect of
extensio was understood to embody the will of God, but blotted out all moral and spiritual
values, the orienting divine teleology that gave human life purpose and meaning. Descartes’
famous contemporary Pascal witnesses in Pensées to the trembling dread of existing between
two gaping abysses: infinity and nothingness. Having been charged with superabundant value
9
and meaning, God now had to be radically reconceived if this supreme value was not to perish in
the mechanistic indifference of the new godless cosmos. The absolutely transcendent God
vaunted by western monotheism, a deity who does not and cannot change, had to be transformed
or perish of existential irrelevance. Human existence suddenly had too much of impassibility.
God’s metaphysical scaffolding collapsed in the transition from late medieval to early
modern with a swiftness comparable to the collapse of a speculative financial bubble—a telling
analogy that merits elaboration (McCullough 2014). This collapse fomented not only spiritual
and intellectual crises but also crises of political authority that played out in the wars and
repressions of the Reformation and the modern European revolutions. Carl Schmitt’s often-cited
claim that the authority of God is the basis of all authority became increasingly evident as divine
authority began to erode and decay. Schmitt traces out how deism and the banishment of miracle
arose in parallel with the modern constitutional state; a ‘battle against God’ by the likes of
Proudhon, Comte, and Bakunin ensued. For Proudhon, ‘mankind had to be substituted for God’
(Schmitt 36, 50, 53). Proudhon and Bakunin excoriated God, the former inveighing that ‘God is
hypocrisy and falsehood; God is tyranny and misery; God is evil’; the latter seconding, ‘we
believe it our duty to recover from heaven the goods which it has stolen and return them to
earth,’ for ‘God being master, man is the slave’ (Bakunin 36, 24, 25). Bakunin’s epigraph to his
major work reverses Voltaire’s famous dictum, asserting: ‘If God really existed it would be
necessary to abolish him’ (ibid.: 3).
While pure anarchists like Stirner and Bakunin were single-mindedly coherent due to
their ideological clarity, the liberal bourgeoisie was two-faced. Schmitt notes the dual front
fought by the rising bourgeoisie: it was driven leftward by its hatred of monarchy and
aristocracy, yet its fear of being divested of property drove it rightward toward monarchy backed
10
by military might—a ‘curious contradiction.’ In effect, it wanted ‘neither the sovereignty of the
king nor the people.’ The bourgeoisie wanted a God, but its God could not become active; liberal
constitutionalism permitted the king to remain on the throne, but sought to paralyze him through
parliament. The conservative monarchist Donoso Cortés (d. 1853) compared this with the
inconsistency committed by deism when it excluded God from the world but held onto his
existence (Schmitt 59-60). Once victorious over the old regime, the bourgeoisie was happy to
annex both clergy and nobility as soon as they accepted its political, economic, and moral
direction; but hardly having come to power, it betrayed its allies in the very bottom strata of
society by ‘shoving them back into the gulf’ (de Ligt 40). This theopolitical double-face—
‘authority is dead, long live authority!’—has predominated in western liberal societies ever
since.
[A] Maimon and Hegel
The generation opening with Kant brought forth the German idealist movement in the
universities, which Collins declares in his monumental study of the sociology of global
philosophies to be ‘one of the most intense outpourings of philosophical creativity in world
history.’ The movement’s ebullient creativity flew in the face of the dominant themes of the
Enlightenment—the death of the supernatural, the termination of metaphysical speculation, and
the replacement of philosophy by empirical science—and swooped in to wrest theology away
from the churches into secular hands (Collins 613-8, 622). Kant’s response to Hume, in
particular, provoked a renewal not only of epistemology but also of metaphysics. Despite his
valiant effort to refute Hume’s skeptical demolition of causality—a refutation indispensable for
making the world safe for natural science—Kant failed to convince. He did not succeed in
11
accounting for how two utterly heterogeneous faculties, understanding and sensibility, could
cooperate with one another; his strenuous effort to do so ultimately begged the question: he did
not have a criterion to determine when synthetic a priori concepts apply to a posteriori intuitions.
He described what conditions would be needed (quid juris), but did not demonstrate whether or
when it actually occurs (quid facti). This unbridgeable understanding–sensibility dualism in Kant
was patterned on the intractable mind–body dualism in Descartes (Beiser 1987: 288-9, 291, 325;
1993, 11). In fact, far from curtailing Cartesian doubt, Kant ‘extends it infinitely along the new
divide between all transcendental ideas [including God] and the possibility of their realization in
time and space’ (Leahy 2003: 42; Franks 108). This failure of Kant’s transcendental deduction to
bridge a priori and a posteriori knowledge was demonstrated most decisively by Kant’s obscure
contemporary Solomon Maimon (d. 1800), who thereby raised one of the fundamental problems
of post-Kantian idealism—as Beiser, Franks, and Socher separately argue—and who also
proposed the most tenable solution. If the highest formal principle is maximally indeterminate, a
maximally determining ‘lowest principle’ was needed to bridge the gap between form and matter
(Franks 108).
Maimon found the breakthrough in Spinoza, whose thought constituted an early-modern
revolution unto itself, an utterly radical abolition of the Cartesian dichotomy; in a single stroke,
at least when read monistically, Spinoza conflated extensio and cogitatio, God and world, and in
so doing struck a fatal blow against the biblical-historical God and the transcendent-deistic God
alike. Maimon’s breakthrough recuperated an aspect of Spinoza’s monism to defeat Kantian
epistemological dualism, though whether with an intention to destroy or reconstruct Kant
remains ambiguous (Socher 106; Beiser 1987: 286–87; Franks 109). Spinoza had already posited
that mental and physical, subjective and objective, are different attributes of a single infinite
12
substance, and human thought, insofar as it arrives at adequate ideas, approximates the cogitatio
of God qua natura naturans. It is in fact the same act of knowledge by which we and God know
something; this means that the difference between divine and human knowledge is no longer
qualitative, as previously thought, but only quantitative (Funkenstein 290-1). This co-knowing of
God and human cogitatio made possible the main principle of Maimon’s theory: the idea of an
infinite subjective understanding that is immanent in materiality, or in Beiser’s characterization:
If synthetic a priori concepts are to apply to experience, then it is necessary to
postulate Leibniz’s and Malebranche’s idea of an infinite understanding that is
present within our finite understanding and that creates not only the form but also
the content of experience. . . . Thanks to Maimon, the Kantian transcendental ego
acquired a new metaphysical status: it became a single universal subject present
within the consciousness of every individual, unifying the finite subject and
object. Maimon’s infinite understanding is thus the forerunner of Fichte’s Ich and
Hegel’s Geist (1987: 286-7).
The immanent infinite understanding posited by Maimon made him ‘the great
philosopher of immanence’ in the context of the critical tradition, in the judgment of Daniel W.
Smith, since almost all Maimon’s critiques of Kant are aimed at eliminating the illegitimate
vestiges of transcendence that still remain in Kant, the most vexing example of this being the
thing-in-itself (Smith 125; Beiser 1987: 303). Construing insights from Spinoza, Leibniz, and
Maimonides’s adaptation of Aristotle, Maimon posited a holistic solution to the Kantian impasse
as to how a priori concepts can apply to experience, one that was accepted by all the key
13
thinkers of early German idealism: Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and perhaps the Kant of the Third
Critique as well. (Kant admired Maimon, Fichte confessed a respect for him that ‘knows no
bounds,’ Schelling clearly read him, and for Hegel indirect influence is established; Socher 104–
6.) All sought to resolve this irremediable dualism through development of the infinite intuitive
intellect (intellectus archetypus) (Beiser 1993: 11; Socher 89-92).
It would seem hard to overemphasize what happens in the metaphysical movement that
takes place at this moment on the eve of the nineteenth century. From the status of being an
essentially acosmic God a se—who nonetheless de facto created—a perilous crossing is
achieved, an immanental passage, and from here forward it is not only that God’s laws or ideas
imprint the world from outside as a consequence of creation; now, for the first time in
mainstream western thought, divine understanding essentially bursts into, occupies, and indwells
the world and the world becomes, in a qualified sense, God’s body. ‘Without Godhead the world
cannot be thought,’ Maimon wrote, ‘but, without the world, the Godhead cannot be known’
(Franks 109). Spinoza’s rationalistic conflation of God and nature, Deus sive Natura, is
transfigured from an acosmism (an insight that Hegel credited to Maimon) into an
incarnationalism. The world, rather than merely depending on God, expresses materially the
essential nature of God. God requires the substance of the world to become freely revealed to
himself. God’s transcendence, independence, and invulnerability vis-à-vis the world is now
breached absolutely—the old Christian God perishes in this transition—and God now becomes
absolute Subject creatively imbuing all existence, the absolute inhabitant of historical time. This
transition marks the historic eclipse or “death” of God conceived in terms of aseity and the
advent of a modern new God-idea.
14
The God-thinking of Schelling and Hegel hinged on this immanental passage. They
regarded their own new approach to metaphysics as a form of scientific naturalism, insisting that
the metaphysical principles of their philosophies can and should be confirmed through
experience. Both a priori and a posteriori are products of natural reason. All we need to know is
nature; the sum total of human knowledge of God is encountered through experience in the thisworldly context of nature. Both young thinkers appreciated how Spinoza naturalized God,
conceiving God as nothing other than natura naturans, the universe as a whole, making a
religion out of nature itself. Nature is not a mere mechanism, nor is spirit (Geist) a ghost
emanating from outside the machine, but a life sprung up within it. Since natural laws consist not
only of the mechanistic physics of the seventeenth century but also the vitalistic biological
science of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries—concerned with generation, growth, stages of
development, and death—the striving of an absolute subject realizing itself in and through nature
became thinkable (Beiser 2003: 138-41).
In his essay on freedom (1809), Schelling wants to put aside completely the concept of
immanence that expresses a ‘dead conceptual inclusion of things in God’ in favor of seeing
things as having their basis ‘in that within God which is not God himself’ but is God’s basis for
becoming himself (Schelling 33-4). For Schelling, intellectual intuition is an experience-based
form of perception that can provide the basis for a purely immanent metaphysics. The young
Hegel absorbed and critically recast this Schellingian stance in his Phenomenology of Spirit
(1807), which attempted an immanent metaphysics based on experience alone, but one that
claimed to follow the path of rigorous science (Wissenschaft) (Beiser 1993: 15-6, 20; Harris 45).
Although science at its first beginning was bound to have a visionary quality, ‘intuition’ must be
resolved into a truly speculative method of rigorous discursive reasoning (Harris 44). His entire
15
philosophical career thereafter proposed a post-critical take on how the unconditioned truth of
scientific reason can be achieved by, as Orrin F. Summerell puts it, propounding the complete
conceivability of reason’s autonomy, and therewith its unconditional ground in and as the
necessary movement of self-thinking thought: ‘Bearing itself in itself, self-thinking thought . . .
supplies itself with its own Whence and Whither’ (Summerell 180–81). Adapting Maimon’s
immanent infinite understanding, Hegel’s finite spirit (der endliche Geist) qua immanent within
infinite Spirit (der unendliche Geist), is able to tap into the Absolute’s unconditioned contact
with the world, which is identically its contact with itself (Leahy 2003: 54).
Hegel was the first thinker to propose an organic philosophical interpretation of the
global history of religions and to embark on a vast, painstaking scholarly documentation of the
subject (Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, 1821–31); Schelling made a similar effort in the
same era. They were concerned not only with reconstructing the history of religions but with
addressing the question of their relative truth (Pagano 53). Presumably, the ecumenical spirit of
their research was subtended by the new metaphysics they embraced: religions evolve
organically as the self-knowledge of God—Geist—emerges historically from the matrix of
nature. Thus, rather ironically, after Descartes had purged from the domain of reason all
adversion to the historically revealed God of the Bible, Hegel instituted a God who is essentially
the self-revelation of reason in history, telling the old Christian story again but within a truly
omni-comprehensive tale.
History, indeed, becomes the universal theater of divine self-sacrifice in Hegel. This is
because incarnation implies the assumption of finitude, and to achieve finitude to the furthest
extreme implies—even necessitates—death; kenosis in the form of death is thus the climax of
incarnation, wherein God’s divinity is accomplished (ibid.: 65). It is precisely by virtue of this
16
incarnational principle—which sources our life and our death—that we qua finite spirit are
related to God (Yerkes 116-7, 136-7). And yet, despite the explicit pathos-laden language of the
death of God in Hegel’s work (Carlson 22-49; Kosky), it is important to note that Hegel’s God
cannot die in principio: given that the beginning of God is not essentially historical—not
actual—the absolute cannot actually die (Leahy 1996: 596). In Hegel, death is sublated into the
infinity of the divine life by God’s taking death upon himself, as William Franke notes, and
thereby death is negated and overcome, achieving ‘the death of death’ (Franke 217). Hegel’s
God renders the world intrinsically necessary for God’s free self-realization on de facto grounds,
and in so doing Hegel’s God sacrifices absolutely the orthodox God of transcendent aseity. Yet
Hegel’s God himself—der absolute Zombie—can never and will never die. As Alain Badiou
expresses this infinite immanence of God, in Hegel ‘the infinite is merely the void in which the
repetition of the finite operates’; hence ‘the bad infinity is bad due to the very same thing that
makes it good in Hegelian terms: it does not break the ontological immanence of the one; better
still, it derives from the latter. . . . The pure multiple detains in itself the count-as-one’ (Badiou
173, 169). The primordial privilege of the Infinite-cum-Totality is the raison d’etre of every
particular.
[A] Overbeck and Nietzsche
In 1873, Nietzsche wrote to his Basel colleague, Franz Overbeck, ‘Two twins from the one house
went bravely out into the world to tear the world’s paper-tigers [Welt-Drachen] to pieces,’
making reference to the boarding house they cohabited at the time (Overbeck 26). Odd twins in
lifelong fellowship, their temperaments were a diametric contrast. While Nietzsche was
empowered to thought by the bracing energy of detestation, Overbeck held close to the Spinozist
17
credo: non ridere, non lugere, neque detestari, sed intelligere. He was intensely yet
dispassionately curious, quietly but radically skeptical, a strictly scrupulous scholar, indeed, ‘a
self-mortifying monk of scholarship,’ his Basel colleague attested, ‘an absolutely honest mind,’
in Löwith’s estimation (O’Neill 180; Löwith 388). An outsider with no clear religious
conviction, he drifted into the study of theology where, among fellow theology students, he felt
‘like a Hottentot.’ He was appointed at Basel expressly to represent the liberal tendency in
modern Protestant theology, to help the University of Basel keep current with the hottest new
trends, and from then forward, on the grounds of a painstakingly scrutinized historical record, he
worked with keen diligence to expose the critical untenability of that very liberal tendency. His
work was not only a challenge to liberal theology but to all theology per se, and to the possibility
of reconciling authentic Christianity with authentic modernity (Gossman 419-20).
Overbeck’s methodological approach as church historian was to presuppose that
scholarship and religion are mutually destructive (Overbeck 42); therefore, his only theological
function as a professor of theology, he acknowledged in his memoir, was to pronounce the Last
Judgment on Christianity (O’Neill 179). Having no positive theological agenda of his own,
Overbeck demonstrated an extraordinary and rare fidelity to Christianity by means of the
perfectly unbiased scrupulosity of his historical research. He came to view Christianity as a
religion whose original expression was sealed in the past, an inaccessible enigma. He claimed
that historical investigation reveals that Christianity in its original form was fundamentally
apocalyptic in character, and he regarded all later centuries of Christian history as a betrayal of
early Christianity. ‘Original Christianity no more expected to have a theology than it expected to
have any kind of history on this earth,’ he wrote, ‘Indeed, Christianity entered this world
announcing its imminent end’ (Overbeck 34; c.f. Law 224-5). Urchristentum has not existed, has
18
not been possible or retrievable, since the imminent apocalypticism of the original first-century
communities—unrequited by God, let us say—was abandoned.
Overbeck opined that the earliest testimonies of Christianity were created in a kind of
literary vacuum for internal consumption within the community, not for a wider exoteric public;
though drawing on Jewish traditions, these communities showed no tendency to grow into or
fuse with the surrounding Roman-Hellenic culture. There was no call to codify the teachings or
create institutions since there would be no future for the world as they knew it. But the actual
contexts and themes of this Urliterutur were soon occluded in the process of canonization for the
sake of transhistorical and universal applicability, and thenceforward they ceased to be
understood. Thus, Overbeck considered Christianity a historically obsolete phenomenon, a
religion of crisis and immediate decision; he pointed to the unrepeatability of its origins and the
impossibility of extracting any timeless substance from them (Sommer 81, 102).
Based on this view, Overbeck showed the inherent contradictions between the primitive
Church and the manifold forms of its subsequent secularization in ancient and medieval worlds.
A theology was elaborated only when it became necessary to take account of the fact that the
world was not coming to an end, at least not immediately (Gossman 421). The struggle between
faith and knowledge was fought out in the very cradle of Christianity, when Gnosticism
destroyed all the historical presuppositions of early Christian faith, turning it into a metaphysical
system instead of a popular religion, and doing so by quasi-violent means; rational theology was
forced on the church by the earliest Alexandrians through an act of violence (Overbeck 34-5).
Monasticism, by establishing an alternative to literal martyrdom in the form of the martyrium
quotidianum, managed to ensure the church’s survival into the medieval period, saving
Christianity from obsolescence, but only by changing it at the core (ibid.: 84).
19
This unbridgeable distance of Urchristentum held a fortiori for all modern manifestations
of Christian faith (Sommer 88). Again, religious faith and the critical theology that seeks to
construe it conceptually are mutually destructive in his eyes:
While rational knowledge can no doubt destroy a religion, it can never restore it
to what it was before. In the modern period [Christian theology proves this],
though not so much by the devastation science has wrought in the area of
Christian faith, as by the sterility of theology’s own attempt, undertaken in
response, to reconstruct the Christian religion by means of pure, unfettered
scholarship. . . . Of all people, it is the theologians who can turn Christianity into
something which—whatever else it may be—is no longer Christianity. (Overbeck
45-6)
Overbeck and Nietzsche shared the judgment that contemporaries in modern Christendom are
actually incapable of grasping the true nature of Christianity (Henry xxxi), but the two differed
between themselves on this very question. While Overbeck honored the limits of the historical
record and the social-political communitarian nature of original Christianity, Nietzsche’s quest
for transvaluation and his faith in the solitaire destiny of the super-creative individual skewed his
perspective tendentiously beyond the limits of the historical record.
Religiously speaking, Nietzsche shared with Hegel an impatience to transition from the
unglückliche Bewußtsein, the alienated unhappy consciousness of Christian legacy, to what
Nietzsche evokes as geistreicher und glückliche Übermut (Will to Power §1019), a happy
spirited exuberance of post-Christian joyful wisdom (fröhliche Wissenschaft). Nietzsche sought
20
to define a double-edged nihilistic-creative praxis; what we find lauded in his work is not the will
to believe, but ‘the will to create—the will to put meaning into the chaos of existence, and
certainly not to find it there’ (Leahy 2003: xi). Nietzsche invented his own version of the
historical Jesus: a quasi-Buddhist Jesus who liberated himself from ressentiment, who conquered
suffering and achieved ‘blessedness’ by resisting nothing, reacting to nothing (Anti-Christ §2741; Will to Power §207), whose teachings exemplify a ‘way of life, not a system of beliefs’ (Will
to Power §212). The life and teachings of Jesus exemplified a praxis of amor fati. Nietzsche did
not embrace Jesus’s ‘blessedness’ as his own highest ideal because he considered it a decadent
(passive) rather than a creative (active) form of this praxis. His Zarathustra, by contrast,
embodies the creative form, exercising abundant strength rather than hypersensitivity, passivity,
and withdrawal. Yet Nietzsche does admire Jesus for having lived a life free of ressentiment,
likewise free of the illusion of a transcendent world or metaphysical final cause to justify life.
Jesus taught a mode of existence that would render moot and useless everything that later
Christianity came to propagate as ‘divine truth.’ There has been only one Christian, Nietzsche
wrote famously, and he died on the cross (Anti-Christ §39).
The way in which Nietzsche execrated Paul for turning Christianity into a religion (e.g.,
Anti-Christ §42) stems from his contact with Overbeck (as well as the source criticism of Julius
Wellhausen, published in 1878), though Overbeck certainly cannot be held responsible for its
crudity or its vehemence. The perishing of metaphysics and dogmatic theology, Nietzsche
thought, makes possible a recovery of the Christian ideal that was exemplified in Jesus’s life, but
then misconstrued and perverted by Paul into a metaphysical doctrine of Jesus’s death. Hence the
pre-Pauline meaning and value of Jesus’s ideal, the actual witness of Jesus’s life, is available for
the first time only in our era: Christianity has ‘only now attained to approximately the state of
21
culture in which it can fulfill its original vocation . . . in which it can show itself pure’ (Will to
Power §219). For Nietzsche, ‘Christianity is still possible at any time’ (ibid.: §212).
So then, long before Heidegger posited the possibility of a post-ontotheological
Christianity, Nietzsche did so. An authentic Christianity ‘has absolutely no need of metaphysics’
(ibid.: §212). An original Christian ideal not only remains possible after the death of God, but the
death of God actually opens up a post-dogmatic horizon in which Jesus’s life and teachings may
at last receive a nonmetaphysical interpretation, viewed from a nonreligious perspective: ‘a
Christianity is possible, but without the absurd dogmas,’ ‘not tied to any of the impudent dogmas
that have adorned themselves with its name’ (ibid.: §§239, 212). Christian value judgments have
not by any means been overcome by either modern natural sciences or modern values: ‘’Christ
on the cross’ is the most sublime symbol even today’ (ibid.: §219).
Anti-Christianity diatribes became Nietzsche’s spur to envision a new religious praxis, a
passionate faith in overcoming a decadent, domesticated, declining humanity, whether in
accordance with the creative self-sacrificial ideal of Zarathustra (‘abundant strength wants to
create, suffer, go under,’ ibid.: §222), or another ideal. But let us take notice: these are ideals,
highly individualist solitaire ideals. Nietzsche validated the heroic overcoming of the exceptional
individual; Overbeck did not. Distrusting what he considered to be Nietzsche’s megalomaniac
egoism, Overbeck regarded Nietzsche’s Übermensch as a residue of the very philosophical
idealism Nietzsche so tirelessly lambasted. ‘What an idea cannot achieve,’ Overbeck wrote, ‘the
idea of an idea is even less able to achieve.’ Humanity is marked by its solidarity, for
Overbeck—‘humanity [Menschlichkeit] is still our highest title to glory’ (Gossman 435-6)—and
humanity has far more use for the heroism of everyday acts than for superhuman drama. A
quietly stoic knight of infinite resignation, Overbeck forged his career into a remarkable witness
22
to historical Christianity in the full range of its paradoxicality. Meanwhile, he wrote of the
spiritual darkness he experienced as a modern: ‘Our defection from the old and our falling away
from it are irreparable. . . . Having come so far, we have no option but to press on further. . . . If
our falling away has truly extinguished all light for us, we can least expect to receive new
illumination by turning back, and we can be sure that it can only lie ahead of us’ (ibid.: 422).
[A] Schweitzer and Kierkegaard
The more comprehensively the banishment of the metaphysical God registered in modern
sensibility, the more the quest for the historical Jesus heated up. With God qua Father, first
person of the Trinity, undergoing profound assault and radical reconceptualization, one of the
burning questions of the day took shape: Can Jesus be retrieved as the Truth and the Way; can
he, qua God incarnate, become the savoir of God, by means of whom God will be returned to us
via history’s backdoor? The cherished bid was to get close to the God who once walked on earth,
to carry his kerymatic message straight into the present, uncompromised by metaphysical
interventions and undefiled by ‘the inventions of men’ (as Luther called all unbiblical sacerdotal
hocus pocus). As John O’Neill wryly notes, ‘even German theologians who openly or covertly
accepted that God was dead and the crucial events “mythical”—Semler, Eichhorn, David
Friedrich Strauss, Ferdinand Christian Baur, above all Bultmann—showed that the Bible retained
its authority by devoting the enormous scholarly energy of their lives to expounding it’ (O’Neill
3).
Albert Schweitzer, in 1906, published the definitive book on the nineteenth century’s
quest for the historical Jesus, ultimately pronouncing the quest a failure: ‘Those who are fond of
talking about negative theology can find their account here. There is nothing more negative than
23
the result of the critical study of the life of Jesus’ (Schweitzer 398). Schweitzer’s explanation for
the failure closely paralleled the critique of liberal Protestant theology set forth by Overbeck,
though the latter is not mentioned. Through ‘forced and arbitrary interpretations’ of the life of
Jesus, creating a ‘historical Jesus in its own image,’ using ‘artifice, art, artificiality, and
violence,’ modern theology was determined to find its world-affirming ethic in the teaching of
Jesus, and therein lay its weakness; but finally ‘it could not keep him in our time, but had to let
him go’ (ibid.: 398-9, 402). The liberal questers, in their naïve self-satisfaction, sought to know
Jesus after the flesh, Schweitzer judged, whereas his spirit lay hidden in his words.
Jesus’s sayings, speaking as an apocalyptic prophet, were heterogeneous to the world,
Schweitzer insisted, and all the religious force of Jesus lay precisely in this world-negation: ‘that
which is eternal in the words of Jesus is due to the very fact that they are based on an
eschatological worldview.’ The world-negating prophet ‘comes to us as One unknown’ (ibid.:
402–3). But while Schweitzer still believed that a radical eschatological faith can undergo
conversion and choose to ‘follow’ the apocalyptic Jesus, Overbeck stood for an extreme
pyrrhonist doubt with respect to the historical Jesus: he asked whether Jesus’s teachings were not
only strange and unapproachable, or demanding and formidable, but utterly foreign and actually
inapplicable—offering not an unearthly challenge to faith but a historical surd, an irrecoverable
anachronism.
Søren Kierkegaard’s position, as pseudonymously outlined by Johannes Climacus in
Philosophical Fragments (1844) and Concluding Unscientific Postscript (1846), is remarkably
like Schweitzer’s in retrospect. Schweitzer hoped that as a consequence of the failure of the quest
for the historical Jesus, ‘history will force Christianity to find a way to transcend history’
(Schweitzer 401). For Kierkegaard, likewise, any expectation that historical grounds might help
24
to support or justify faith can only fall short and never arrive at the core groundlessness of faith;
hence the need for a leap, an ultimately groundless history-independent decision of faith. On the
one hand, the claim that God ‘has entered into time’ and become incarnate historically is an
axiom of Christian faith; on the other hand, no historical fact—nothing in the eighteen hundred
years of Christian history—can offer or constitute legitimate grounds for believing that the Jesus
of history, who claimed he was God, was God. Far rather, for Kierkegaard, the eighteen hundred
years have only confused the issue, falsifying the faith-conditions of authentic New Testament
Christianity (the requirement of a strenuous spiritual metanoia), while establishing a pseudoChristianity and making a fool of God. Kierkegaard was confident that no historical fact or
discovery could ever stand between the God who entered into time—making the simple claim on
earth that he was God and asking others to follow him—and the faith of the individual follower
that this man was indeed God. But Overbeck cast historical doubt exactly where Kierkegaard did
not question: he denied that the historical Jesus ever claimed to be God, which shifts the core
premise of Kierkegaard’s dialectical paradox off its foundation, leaving it in the lurch on
historical grounds.
Even now, today, a critical faith may experience this question as a living quandary:
whether to honor a decisionist faith in line with Kierkegaard-Schweitzer or a pyrrhonist doubt in
line with Overbeck, who believed that Christianity has long since had its day and should be left
to die in peace (Law 238). Certainly, though, the apocalyptic Jesus professed by Schweitzer on
the threshold of the First World War—the Unknown One who commands ‘Follow me!’—
provides a closing bracket for the long nineteenth century of our present inquiry.
25
[A] Berlioz and Dostoevsky
Besides the ‘historical’ Jesus depicted in the Bible, a wholly-other-than-historical Jesus—the
God-man as figured in art—also reveals dimensions of the death of God. Jesus in art registers the
death-of-God trauma profoundly, as we see in the dramatic legend The Damnation of Faust, with
music and libretto composed by Hector Berlioz, first performed in 1846. When Part 2 opens,
Faust is enveloped in the throes of a suicidal depression, alone and abandoned by the empty
heavens: ‘Oh, how I suffer! And the starless night, which extends from afar its silence and veils,
intensifies my oppressive sorrows.’ [‘Oh! je souffre! et la nuit sans étoiles, / Qui vient d’étendre
au loin son silence et ses voiles, / Ajoute encore à mes sombres douleurs.’] Engulfed in
melancholic despair, Faust hears the church bells of Easter sounding and a hymn being sung by
the chorus as they anticipate Christ about to be raised from the tomb. The believers sing
plangently of their sorrow as they watch Christ, their beloved master, leaving the tomb and
advancing à grands pas toward heaven while his faithful disciples ‘remain languishing here
below’: ‘Alas! He is leaving us behind under stinging barbs of misery. O divine master! Your joy
is the cause of our sorrow. O divine master! You are leaving us behind under stinging barbs of
misery’ [‘tu nous laisses sous les traits brûlants du malheur’]. Hearing the sacred liturgy as a
chance bystander, Faust exclaims with anguish—Ô souvenirs!—overwhelmed by his nostalgia
for the joy of Easter, now recalled as a distant memory of youth, inaccessible to him, locked
away in a past he cannot recapture.
In Faust’s keenest moment of anguish, Mephistopheles appears and snarks ironically on
all this nostalgic piety. He makes an irresistible offer that Faust accepts, taking Faust on a
journey ‘to learn about life.’ Their first stop is in a raucous tavern where they witness a ribald
‘Requiem for a Rat.’ The drinking song tells the story of a kitchen rat who, after living so high
26
on the hog ‘as to make fat Luther jealous,’ is poisoned and roasted, then solemnly laid to rest to
the strains of a beautiful sacred requiem. The moving solemnity of the chorale gives way to
Mephistopheles’s song about a flea who organizes an infestation of the royal court by his whole
family. Faust interrupts the song and demands to leave the saloon, disgusted by the baseness of it
all.
The juxtaposition of genuine religious anguish and nostalgic longing for the sacred with
blasphemous ribaldry and mockery of the sacred is the striking feature of Berlioz’s Faust. After
the death of the rat, blessed are the fleas, for they shall inherit the royal court. If one dares the
comparison, the second part of the opera may be set in parallel with Nietzsche’s madman
passage of 1882, in which God, rich in substance (like the overfed rat), has ‘bled to death under
our knives’ and is laid out to decompose, for ‘Gods, too, decompose’; now the churches are but
sepulchers of God, a place to sing a requiem aeternam Deo. But it is notable that Berlioz, writing
more than a generation earlier than Nietzsche, is if anything more acutely sacrilegious. Both, in
effect, plunge the glib Voltairean embrace of God’s demise into the ominous pathos of authentic
religious dread and remorse. If the mourning is ironic, the dread is not; the death of God has
finally reached the human heart, provoking it to ask: Whither are we moving now? Away from
all suns?
Dostoevsky’s Russia—as ‘backward’ in the East as Berlioz’s France was an epicenter of
zeitgeist in the West—received the impact of modern western atheist ideas in a highly
compressed timeframe as an alien import from abroad rather than a force arising within.
Dostoevsky visited Europe and became a sensitive bellwether of this moral-spiritual shock,
which he expressed in sundry ways in each of his major novels—quintessentially in Ivan’s story
of the Grand Inquisitor in Brothers Karamazov (1880), in which Christ returns to visit his flock
27
during the Inquisition but is sent away by his ecclesiastical lieutenant on earth, the Grand
Inquisitor, and warned not to meddle again in human affairs or he will suffer a repetition of the
fate he met long ago.
When he viewed it in Basel, Dostoevsky was so shocked by Hans Holbein the Younger’s
painting Dead Christ (1521) that he later incorporated it into his novel The Idiot (1869). The
painting asserts an eerily quiet but aggressive power. In an elongated and compressed horizontal
space, which appears to be the confines of a sarcophagus, a gaunt male body is depicted in
greyish-green tones, frozen in the rigor of violent death. Art historians remark on the singularity
of the painting not only within Holbein’s oeuvre but as a peculiarly horrific work of religious art.
Although the Christ figure of Grünewald’s Crucifixion (1512) is more gruesome at first glance,
with its sickening bodily sores and torturously twisted hands and feet, precisely these
exaggerations, along with the massive size and spatial extension of the body, mark it out as a
more-than-human sacred figure. No ordinary man’s suffering flesh is depicted in the Grünewald,
but the God-man’s suffering flesh.
By comparison, the ghastly corpse depicted by Holbein is more disturbing in that it
‘contains hardly any religious thought’ (Reinhardt 21-2). Offering no visible sign of God or
spirit, this Christ is simply a lifeless body on a slab, a cold tortured flesh. It has seemingly
nothing to do with God, or has to do with God only insofar as all organic nature animated by the
ceaseless contest of life against death—with death eventually triumphant—has to do with God.
Before us is a particular in which the facticity of death has won, leaving no room for the
symbolic. ‘All is done with a horrible realistic power’ producing ‘altogether a most revolting
effect’ (Wornum 131-2). And yet, far from being closed up in death, the face lies entirely open
and exposed by invasive reverse lighting. The eyes that recently served for seeing are open and
28
turned upward. The mouth rests agape, as if having just uttered a cry. The head, neck, and
shoulders retain the tension of upward supplication.
It has been speculated that Holbein painted an anatomical study of a cadaver, then at
some point converted it into Christ in the tomb by the addition of stigmata and a religious title. If
so, an unidentified dead man was re-envisioned by the artist as Christ in the tomb—‘christening’
a corpse. Was this an act of sacrilege? One searches the length of the emaciated body, the
extruding navel, the nasty gash in the hand and vacated green-gray face, passively imploring, for
an interpretive clue. The painting seems to pose an antinomy or contradiction for which there is
no possible resolution. It is the very picture of godlessness, the inconceivability of resurrection,
the frankness of death everlasting.
Three principal characters in The Idiot, Prince Myshkin, Rogozhin, and later Ippolit,
reflect on the painting’s religious meaning as provoked by a copy that hangs over the door of one
of Rogozhin’s rooms. Myshkin, who has seen the original while traveling abroad, unable to
forget it, recognizes the copy. While Rogozhin and Myshkin hesitate before it, the reproduction
induces a dark exchange concerning religious faith. Rogozhin asks Myshkin, ‘Tell me, Prince,
I’ve long wanted to ask you, do you believe in God?’ then mutters offhandedly, ‘I like looking at
that picture.’ Myshkin exclaims, ‘At that picture! Why, some people may lose their faith by
looking at that picture!’ ‘Aye, that also may be lost,’ Rogozhin replies (Dostoevsky 236). The
painting’s resonance in the novel extends far beyond explicit mentions of it, as the characters’
collective subconscious is gripped by its abysmal implications. Each finds himself haunted by
the painting as an image and an idea. Only much later in the novel does a full exposition of these
implications occur in the brooding confession of Ippolit, who has seen the painting hanging in
Rogozhin’s place and is consumed with the Christ image as he prepares for his suicide.
29
In Rogozhin’s picture there was no trace of beauty. It was a faithful representation
of the dead body of a man who has undergone unbearable torments. . . . Looking
at that picture, you get the impression of nature . . . as some huge machine of the
latest design, which has senselessly seized, crushed, and swallowed up—
impassively and unfeelingly—a great and priceless Being, a Being worth the
whole of nature and all its laws, worth the entire earth, which was perhaps created
solely for the coming of that Being! . . . And if, on the eve of the crucifixion, the
Master could have seen what He would look like when taken from the cross,
would He have mounted the cross and died as He did? This question, too, you
can’t help asking yourself as you look at the picture. (Ibid.: 418-20, translation
amended)
Ippolit espies in the painting a depiction of nature as an insensible force that cannot be
personified because it is essentially machinelike. Applying Edwin Panofsky’s quip that ‘the man
who is run over by an automobile is run over by mathematics, physics and chemistry’ (Panofsky
23), we might infer that what Ippolit sees in Dead Christ is a God who has been run over by
mathematics, physics, and chemistry. Precisely as such, the painting is an incomparable icon for
Dostoevsky of the God-man as reenvisioned by the apostate modern mind: a God crushed and
conquered by the ‘nature’ of modern science in an anonymous dead body—a Christ-mask of
absolute suffering behind which there is nothing. The shock value of the painting is that we are
already participant in the symbolic reality depicted: a wholly ironic revelation in which graphic
30
realism is the only ‘symbol,’ or rather the naked sign, the positive mark of what is symbolically
negated.
[A] Emerson and the New World
Ralph Waldo Emerson, surveying this intellectual-spiritual history from the New World in the
early nineteenth century, confident in new beginnings, lamented that his age is retrospective; it
writes histories, biographies, and criticism, thus building the ‘sepulchers of the fathers’:
Foregoing generations beheld God and nature face to face; we, through their eyes. Why
should not we also enjoy an original relation to the universe? Why should not we have a
poetry and philosophy of insight and not of tradition, and a religion by revelation to us,
and not the history of theirs? . . . There are new lands, new men, new thoughts. Let us
demand our own works and laws and worship. (1982: 35)
Why should we not enjoy an original relation to the universe, indeed? We are free to turn our
faces forward, to seek the new, to pray for revelation and to prophesy new gods; but the past is
nonetheless a momentously freighted train, making this easier said than done. The story of God
in the twilight of Christendom—which takes the form of the death of God—is a millennial event
still unfurling and still charged with unexpected depths of joy and woe.
Denizens of the nineteenth century, chastened by three centuries of internecine religious
wars, revolutions, and counterrevolutions, occupying a beleaguered post-Enlightenment climate,
still harbored steadfast faith in progress at the level of society, a trust in gradual social
amelioration through advancing humanism and scientific positivism—the paragon here being
31
Auguste Comte with his ‘religion of humanity’ in which sociology replaces theology as the
queen of the sciences. In the latter half of the century, the Darwinian theory of evolution wrought
a decisive coup de grâce, setting in place an alternative naturalistic account for the origin of
life—including the latecomer Homo sapiens—and positing a vast new geologic time that
consigned human presence to a miniscule fraction of Earth’s history. Initially the main impact of
Darwin’s theory, however, was to catalyze the transition to a non-Darwinian evolutionism that
preserved the old teleological view of things, a pseudo-Darwinism in continuity with Romantic
and pre-Romantic Naturphilosophie (Moore 24-6). Once again, the impact of the death of God
was mitigated by a far less radical, fall-breaking compromise or stopgap measure.
The waves of transformation that were widely anticipated to bring human liberation and
deliverance rolled out the battlegrounds, gulags, famines, and death factories of the twentieth
century in which an estimated 262 million souls suffered democide worldwide (Rummel 2016;
Koning 1987). The slow absorption of the demise of God into broader society—enacted through
tumultuous waves of scientific-technological, social-political, economic-legal, spiritualpsychological, moral-religious transformation—has exposed the nerve values of the West and
brought forth fierce reactions for and against, creating cognitive dissonance and societal
conflicts. The Emersonian-Nietzschean will to innovate, armed with naive optimism, has faced
down a Pandora’s box of conservative, nostalgic, and reactionary inclinations: white Christian
imperial supremacism, schizophrenic bricolage belief systems, longing for ‘old time religion,’
anti-scientism, new age spiritualism, narrow-minded axiological faith, and moral-religious
hypocrisies of all sorts. The unbridled nihilistic worship of quantum money and world-historical
military hegemony beyond the reach of any symbolic value system also has its wellspring in the
quest to fill this yawning God-void.
32
Considering the overwhelming seriousness of the task, we must admire how deliberately
the creative minds of the nineteenth century ‘broke the new wood,’ as Ezra Pound wrote of Walt
Whitman’s poetry (in ‘A Pact,’ 1916). They were compelled to daring new experiments in
negating, unthinking, and rethinking God. Unthinking God, negating all the way down in order
to reconstruct, became not only possible but an intellectual duty. This epochal thinking was
boldly carried out primarily by secularizing philosophers in universities rather than theologians
beholden to the church (Collins 618–63). Through them a new theological potency was opened
up for secularizing theologians of the twentieth century, who built on the breakthroughs of these
philosophical forerunners along lines that remain at least partially creative today: Barth the
Kierkegaardian, Tillich the Schellingian, Bultmann the Schweitzerian, Altizer the HegelianNietzschean, John B. Cobb the process thinker, to name only a few.
Although it was strictly inconceivable for fundamental Christian thinkers of earlier
eras—from Athanasius to Augustine to Aquinas—to think in these terms, the nineteenth century
deeply grasped that if God is Becoming and Life, then God is equally Negation and Death. It
registered the final collapse of an arche and confrontation with a void that we cannot yet claim to
be resolved in any way. And yet the new world post mortem Dei is aborning, its promises and
perils astir, along with the new intuition of a passible God who lives, suffers, and dies in
unreserved ontological solidarity with us and indeed with all sentient existence. Thus, the
nineteenth century rescued God from the death of God—at least partially and ambiguously—by
the advent of death-of-God thinking.
33
[A] References
Altizer, Thomas J. J. (1967), The New Apocalypse: The Radical Christian Vision of William
Blake, East Lansing: Michigan State University Press.
Badiou, Alain [1988] (2005), Being and Event, trans. Oliver Feltham, New York: Continuum,
2005.
Bakunin, Michael [1871] (1882), God and the State, translator unknown, New York: Dover,
1971.
Becker, Carl L. (1932), The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century Philosophers, New Haven:
Yale University Press.
Beiser, Frederick C. (1987), The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Beiser, Frederick C. (1993), ‘Hegel and the Problem of Metaphysics,’ in Frederick C. Beiser
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 124.
Beiser, Frederick C. (2003), The Romantic Imperative: The Concept of Early German
Romanticism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Blake, William (1982), The Complete Poetry and Prose of William Blake: Newly Revised
Edition, ed. David V. Erdman, Berkeley: University of California Press.
Brague, Rémi (2007), The Law of God: The Philosophical History of an Idea, trans. Lydia G.
Cochrane, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Carlson, Thomas A. (1999), Indiscretion: Finitude and the Naming of God, Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
34
Collins, Randall (1998), The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change,
Cambridge, MA: Belknap.
de Ligt, Bart (1938), The Conquest of War: An Essay on War and Revolution, trans. Honor
Tracy, New York: Dutton.
Deporteree, Frederiek (2007), The Death of God: An Investigation into the History of the
Western Concept of God, London: T & T Clark.
Dostoevsky, Fyodor (1869), The Idiot, trans. David Magarshack, New York, Penguin, 1956.
Emerson, Ralph Waldo [1836] (1982), Nature and Selected Essays, ed. Larzer Ziff, New York:
Penguin.
Fabro, Cornelio (1968), God in Exile: Modern Atheism; A Study of the Internal Dynamics of
Modern Atheism, From Its Roots in the Cartesian Cogito to the Present, New York:
Paulist Press.
Fichte, Johann [1800] (1987), The Vocation of Man, trans. Peter Preuss, Indianapolis: Hackett,
1987.
Franke, William (2007), ‘The Deaths of God in Hegel and Nietzsche and the Crisis of Values in
Secular Modernity and Post-Secular Postmodernity,’ Religion and the
Arts 11: 214–41.
Franks, Paul (2000), ‘All or Nothing: Systematicity and Nihilism in Jacobi, Reinhold, and
Maimon,’ in Karl Ameriks (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 95-116.
Frye, Northrop (1947), Fearful Symmetry: A Study of William Blake, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
35
Funkenstein, Amos (1986), Theology and the Scientific Imagination: From the Middle Ages to
the Seventeenth Century, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gauchet, Marcel (1985), The Disenchantment of the World: A Political History of Religion,
trans. Oscar Burge, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997.
Gillespie, Michael Allen (1995), Nihilism Before Nietzsche, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Gillespie, Michael Allen (2008), The Theological Origins of Modernity, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Gossman, Lionel (2000), Basel in the Age of Burckhardt: A Study in Unseasonable Ideas,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Harris, H. S. (1993), ‘Hegel’s Intellectual Development to 1807,’ in Frederick C. Beiser (ed.),
The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 25-51.
Hegel, G. W. F. [1807] (1977), The Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller. Oxford:
Clarendon.
Hegel, G. W. F. [1821–31] (1988), Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, 3 vols., ed. and trans.
Peter C. Hodgson, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heidegger, Martin [1927] (1976), ‘Phenomenology and Theology,’ in The Piety of Thinking,
trans. James G. Hart and John C. Maraldo, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 3-21.
Henry, Martin (2005), ‘Translator’s Introduction’ to Overbeck [1873] (2005): xvii-xli.
Huizinga, Johan [1919] (1996), The Autumn of the Middle Ages, trans. Rodney J. Payton and
Ulrich Mammitzsch, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
Kierkegaard, Søren [1844] (1985), Philosophical Fragments / Johannes Climacus, ed. and trans.
Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
36
Kierkegaard, Søren [1846] (1992), Concluding Unscientific Postscript to ‘Philosophical
Fragments’, 2 vols., ed. and trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong, Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Knowles, David (1962), The Evolution of Medieval Thought, London: Longman.
Koning, Hans (1987), ‘Notes on the Twentieth Century,’ The Atlantic (September).
Kosky, Jeffrey (2004), ‘The Birth of the Modern Philosophy of Religion and the Death of
Transcendence,’ in Regina Schwartz (ed.), Transcendence: Philosophy, Literature, and
Theology Approach the Beyond, New York: Routledge, 13-29.
Koyré, Alexandre [1957] (1958), From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe, New York:
Harper.
Law, David R. (2012), ‘Franz Overbeck: Kierkegaard and the Decay of Christianity,’ in Jon
Steward (ed.), Kierkegaard’s Influence on Theology, Tome 1: German Protestant
Theology, Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Leahy, D. G. (1996), Foundation: Matter the Body Itself., Albany: SUNY.
Leahy, D. G. (2003), Faith and Philosophy: The Historical Impact, Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Löwith, Karl (1964), From Hegel to Nietzsche: The Revolution in Nineteenth-Century Thought,
trans. David E. Green, New York: Columbia University Press.
McCullough, Lissa (2014), ‘Twilight of an Axial God,’ in Daniel J. Peterson and G. Michael
Zbaraschuk (eds), Resurrecting the Death of God: The Origins, Influence, and Return of
Radical Theology, Albany: SUNY.
Moore, Gregory (2002), Nietzsche, Biology and Metaphor, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
37
Nietzsche, Friedrich [1882] (1974), The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York:
Random House.
Nietzsche, Friedrich [1888] (1990), Twilight of the Idols and The Anti-Christ, trans. R. J.
Hollingdale, New York: Penguin.
Nietzsche, Friedrich [1888] (1967), The Will to Power, ed. and trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J.
Hollingdale, New York: Vintage.
Oberman, Heiko A. (1963), The Harvest of Medieval Theology: Gabriel Biel and Late Medieval
Nominalism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
O’Neill, John C. (1991), The Bible’s Authority: A Portrait Gallery of Thinkers from Lessing to
Bultmann, Edinburgh: T & T Clark.
Overbeck, Franz [1873] (2005), How Christian Is Our Present-Day Theology?, trans. Martin
Henry, London: T & T Clark.
Pagano, Maurizio (2012), ‘Hegel as Interpreter of Religious Experience,’ in Paolo Diego Bubbio
and Paul Redding (eds), Religion After Kant: God and Culture in the Idealist Era,
Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars, 47-69.
Panofsky, Erwin [1955] (1982), Meaning in the Visual Arts., Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Preuss, Peter (1987), ‘Translator’s Introduction’ to Fichte [1800] (1987): vii-xiv.
Reinhardt, Hans (1938), Holbein, trans. Prudence Montagu-Pollack, New York: FEP.
Rummel, Rudolph J. (2016), ‘Twentieth-Century Democide.,’
https://www.hawaii.edu/powerkills/20TH.htm (accessed March 5, 2016).
Schelling, F. W. J. [1809] (2006), Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human
Freedom, trans. Jeff Love and Johannes Schmidt, Albany: SUNY.
38
Schmitt, Carl [1934] (1985), Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty,
trans. George Schwab, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Schweitzer, Albert [1906] (1960), The Quest for the Historical Jesus: A Critical Study of Its
Progress from Reimarus to Wrede, trans. W. Montgomery, New York:
Macmillan.
Socher, Abraham P. (2006), The Radical Enlightenment of Solomon Maimon: Judaism, Heresy,
and Philosophy, Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Sommer, Andreas Urs (2003), ‘On the Genealogy of the Genealogical Method: Overbeck,
Nietzsche, and the Search for Origins,’ Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 46
(Supplement 79): 87-103.
Smith, Daniel W. (2000), ‘Deleuze, Hegel, and the Post-Kantian Tradition,’ Philosophy Today
44 (Supplement 26): 119–31.
Stirner, Max [1844] (1971), The Ego and His Own, ed. and trans. John Carroll. London:
Jonathan Cape.
Summerell, Orrin F. (2002), ‘Identity, Subjectivity, and Being Other than the Same: Thinking
beyond Hegel and Heidegger,’ The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and
Phenomenological Philosophy 2: 179–95.
Taubes, Jacob [1947] (2009), Occidental Eschatology, trans. David Ratmoko, Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Taubes, Jacob (1954), ‘On the Nature of the Theological Method: Some Reflections on the
Methodological Principles of Tillich’s Theology,’ Journal of Religion 34.1 (January):
12–25.
39
Tillich, Paul [1910] (1974), The Construction of the History of Religion in Schelling’s Positive
Philosophy: Its Presuppositions and Principles trans. Victor Nuovo, Lewisburg:
Bucknell University Press.
Whitehead, Alfred North [1925] (1953), Science and the Modern World, New York: Free Press.
Wornum, Ralph Nicholson (1867), Some account of the works of Hans Holbein, painter, of
Augsburg, with numerous illustrations, London: Chapman and Hall.
Yerkes, James (1983), The Christology of Hegel, Albany: SUNY.
40