8
Immersion at work
Affect and power in post-Fordist
work cultures
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
Introduction
This chapter explores some of the ways in which relational affect has been
turned into a subtle device for governing individuals, often such that it is
not easily discernible how or even that power is exerted over them. It
focuses on present-day workplace arrangements in what has been called
network corporatism or, more generally, post-Fordism. Yet, its purpose is
also an expressly theoretical one, namely that of consolidating a philosophical conception of relational affect in the tradition of Spinoza and
Deleuze, with particular emphasis on the nexus of affect and power.
Therefore, the chapter starts with a section on conceptual foundations in
two stages. First, the gist of a Spinozist understanding of affect in relatively
general terms. Then a sketch of the working concept of an “affective
arrangement” – a descendant of both the Deleuzian “agencement machinique” and the Foucauldian “dispositif of power” – as a bridge between a
more abstract conceptual framework and a concrete analytical perspective.
Equipped with this concept, the chapter then presents two case studies of
“immersive” affective arrangements in contemporary white-collar workplaces, drawing on research literature in workplace ethnography, sociology and cultural studies. The first case concerns teamwork and the
seamless blending of networked office work and private life in precarious
part-time employment. The second case study deals with what is tellingly
called “Life at Google”. It concludes with remarks on the prospects of an
immanent critique of contemporary formations of affective subjectivation.
Theoretical framework: researching affective relationality
The notion of affect
The first aim of this approach is to develop a category of affect that is
suitable for an analysis of power and subjectivation. For this purpose, the
notion of affect in the philosophical tradition from Baruch Spinoza to
Gilles Deleuze is particularly useful. This chapter remains neutral on the
156
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
issue of whether one should endorse this view as a metaphysical perspective. What interests us is its potency as a set of working concepts that
can illuminate the complex of affect, power and subjectivity in real-world
settings. Referring to Spinoza’s main work, Ethica,1 and to the interpretations given by Gilles Deleuze (1988; 1990), one can say that in this perspective, affect is mainly characterized by three points.
(1) Relational ontology. First, affect is a dynamic of effectuation in relations, that is, between individuals. Unlike in the mentalistic traditions of
philosophy, affect in the Spinoza-Deleuze descent does not refer to inner
feeling states. Actually, both parts are wrong in using the expression “inner
feeling states,” since affects are not states as they are not static, but dynamic
processes; neither are they inner or internal to an individual as they
unfold as relations. These characterizations are deeply rooted in Spinoza’s
ontological and metaphysical setup of a “substance monism,” which
cannot be reconstructed here.2 Yet one of its important takeaways is that
affect itself is an ontological principle; for Spinoza, being is being in relations of affection. That is, an individual is nothing more or less than how it
manifests in relations of affecting and being affected. This ontology puts relations of affecting and being affected first and individuation (which is a
process) second; it thus presents a radically relational and dynamic, and in
this sense non-individualistic and non-substantial, understanding of individuals and affects.
Another important takeaway of Spinoza’s ontological setup is the
theorem commonly referred to as ontological “parallelism,” in opposition to
Cartesian dualism;3 affects in Spinoza are inseparably both a mental and a
bodily dynamic. More precisely, Spinoza states that “the mind and the body
are one and the same thing, which is conceived now under the attribute of
thought, now under the attribute of extension” (III, prop. 2 schol.).4 This
implies that the “body cannot determine the mind to thinking, and the
mind cannot determine the body to motion, to rest, or to anything else”.
Rather, “motion and rest of the body must [always] arise from another
body,” that is, within a field of bodily relatedness (III, prop. 2 and dem.).
Body and mind – or more technically, extensio and cogitatio –in Spinoza’s terminology are just two attributes under which the “order” and “connection
of things” as part of the one substance may be explicated, and “hence the
order of actions and passions of our body is, by nature, at one with the order
of actions and passions of the mind” (III, prop. 2 schol.). This parallelism
theorem – however technical and abstract it might come across if stated this
plainly – is an important background axiom to our approach to social microdynamics. It gives the reason why the nexus of affective dynamics and concurrent subjectivity must be analyzed in social situations and networks of
relations where affect is a register of reciprocity on a bodily and a mental
level. This is our proposed alternative to framing the phenomenon of affect
and concurrent subjectivity as a psychological problem on the interface of
outer dynamics versus inner subjectivity for each individual.
Immersion at work
157
(2) Affecting and being affected. The second characteristic of Spinoza’s
notion of affect is that affect is always an interplay of affecting and being
affected. Hence an affection is not a one-sided or unilateral impact of one
individual on another. Rather, active and receptive involvement are inseparable from one another. As a consequence of this, the unfolding of an
affective dynamic is never reducible to properties of only one of the
involved individuals. The way one individual is affecting and being affected
in a certain situation co-depends on all the other participating individuals.5 In this conceptual framework, the question is less who is affecting
whom and more how a dynamic of affecting and being affected evolves in
the immanence of a situation, of a given relational setting.
This interpretation is again rooted in the shift from individualistic to
relational and processual ontology. In particular, taking affect as an
irreducible entanglement of affecting and being affected does not simply
boil down to an understanding in which a cascade of “one-directional
affections” of individual A on B with subsequent “counter affections” of B
on A sums up to reciprocity on an aggregate level. The interplay of affecting and being affected must be taken in a strong sense, even to the point
of affecting the implied understanding of causality itself. The prototypically modern idea of causality as transitive (with billiard balls as the
standard model) is to be shifted into a thinking of immanent causality
between things as parts of a higher context of effectuation, of which the
physics of coupled oscillators would be the illustrating textbook model.6
Thus the elementary structure of our notion of affect is not that of an
impact-on, that is, of a directed, asymmetric force across the boundaries of
pre-constituted individuals transferring momentum from A to B at a discrete point in space and time. Rather, it is the structure of a joined
movement-with, that is, of a durational coupling of the individuals’ own
movements in reciprocal modulations and resonances, so that in general
it is impossible to say A is affecting B but not B is affecting A.7 In a Deleuzian terminology, this is to say that affecting and being affected is always
forming an open process, a process of becoming (cf. Deleuze and Guattari
1987, ch. 10).
(3) Power. Most crucially for the purpose of this chapter, the notion of
affect in Spinoza is intimately connected with a concept of power. Spinoza
attributes to each individual a, so-called, potentia, which is a kind of “micro
power”. This potentia is not something that individuals possess besides their
other characteristics. Potentia might best be translated as the individual’s
capacity to enter into relations of affecting and being affected – or affective
capacity in short.8 Now, Spinoza says that this affective capacity is the individual’s ability of being in general (in the sense of an entity’s ontic constitution), “Posse existere potentia est” (“to be able to exist is to have power,”
Ethics I, prop. 11 dem.); but at the same time, the individual’s affective
capacity is crucially also a receptive capacity as affect is always both active
and receptive. Potentia is the individual’s specific susceptibility to affections
158
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
by others as much as it is its power to affect others (through one’s acts or
one’s sheer presence). In combination this makes for the fundamental
heteronomy in the constitution of the individual in Spinoza, whose being
is both an expression of its own potentia and modulated by all the other
individuals (and their potentia) in its vicinity – which fits well with the
present scheme of a relational social ontology. Hence the individual in
Spinoza is always a manifestation within a dynamic of unfolding reciprocal
affect in a situation, co-dependent on the respective powers (potentia) of
all the individuals involved.
By the same token, Spinoza’s understanding of individuation has both a
spatial (or “extensive”) and a temporal dimension to it. The “extensive”
dimension figures prominently in the Deleuzian reception of Spinoza, as
Deleuze stresses that an individual is nothing but a composition of smaller
individuals in specific “relations of motion and rest”.9 Deleuze puts this in
the terms of reciprocal dynamics of potentia:
An existing mode is defined by a certain capacity for being affected
(III, post. 1 and 2). When it encounters another mode, it can happen
that this other mode is “good” for it, that is, enters into composition
with it, or on the contrary decomposes it and is “bad” for it.… Accordingly, it will be said that its power of acting or force of existing
increases or diminishes, since the power of the other mode is added
to it, or on the contrary is withdrawn from it, immobilizing and
restraining it.
(IV, prop. 18 dem.) (Deleuze 1988, pp. 49–50)10
This indicates that in a relational ontology of affect, the notion of the individual is itself variable. It shifts according to the prevalent level of individuation for the explication of a social configuration. Such a configuration
may sometimes be comprised of humans, of parts of humans, of couples,
teams, families, corporations, or states and so on. This is particularly fruitful for the analysis of structural power phenomena in social theory as it
enables an understanding of the fundamental heteronomy of the individual on different scales and layers of relatedness but without rendering
the individual passive or depriving it of an own (ontologically constitutive)
power.
There is also a temporal dimension of individuation evident in Spinoza’s theory. An individual’s specific affective capacity (potentia) is also a
product of the history of this individual’s past relations of affecting and
being affected. The temporal structure of individuation is what makes for
a relative trans-situative coherence of one and the same individual passing
through various situations and contexts of relatedness over time, thereby
counterweighing to some extent the transience and variability of individuals. How an individual can affect and be affected is thus a result of
its past trajectory of involvement in affective dynamics. This diachronic
Immersion at work
159
structure implies a kind of “memory” for specific patterns of affectivity in
past relations. This “memory” – which has nothing to do with mental representations of past events – works by means of inscription of past patterns
of affect into the potentia, which are thus present as potentials in current
relations.11 This suggests an account of how past affective patterns of interaction are not identically repeated, but act as tendencies in present
relations. This diachronic structure of the genesis of an individual’s potentia can be extended to an analysis of social structures, such as gendered or
racialized interaction patterns inscribed and perpetuated as patterns of
affective interaction, also within institutions or social domains of other
kinds (Mühlhoff 2018).
Mapping relational affect: affective arrangements and micro-dispositifs
It is the goal of this chapter to demonstrate how the relational conception
of affect can be applied in concrete social contexts to facilitate analyses
and critiques of contemporary governmental strategies. To this end, one
further theoretical pre-consideration is required. Just as little as affect is –
in our theoretical view – a matter of the isolated individual, it is also not a
matter solely pertaining to isolated binary relations. Rather, affect as a
relational dynamic generally transpires in situations, in micro-social
scenes, within smaller or larger contexts and configurations of individuals
and their histories, and various other material or non-material elements
forming relatively stable domains or milieus. When, in the quotation
above, Deleuze speaks of “encounters” between individuals whose specific
composition of potentia either “increases” or “diminishes” one another,
such an encounter does not unfold in empty space. Rather, it will be situated and mediated in a meshwork of past and present relations, in a field
of affective capacities of many constellated individuals, in which certain
affective dynamics might be rendered more likely and others less so. Such
a situatedness also involves what might seem to be “ephemeral” elements,
such as moods and up-to-the-minute affective dynamics, on the political or
economic embeddedness of the situation, on prevailing atmospheres, on
all sorts of materials and equipment, and medial constraints of the
encounter (such as in online platforms, on the telephone) and so on.12
In short, we propose analyzing relational dynamics of affect with respect
to their embedding in a spatial and structural configuration of various elements and their capacities to affect and be affect, together composing a
local sphere of affective resonance in which certain affective dynamics
between any number of individuals might be amplified, while others might
be diminished.13 We refer to such a relational configuration as an affective
arrangement.14
The term “arrangement” is first of all the English translation of
Deleuze’s and Guattari’s notions of “agencement” and “agencement machinique,” as proposed by Ian Buchanan (1997; 2015). In Deleuze’s and
160
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
Guattari’s work, the concept of agencement, or arrangement, does not so
much refer to an assembly or organic unity of parts – as would be suggested by the English term assemblage – but to a specifically composed
layout of heterogeneous elements that are brought together according to
a mode of composition that is not homogenizing (cf. Nail 2017, p. 22).
While an assemblage flattens its parts into an organic unity, an agencement
is a fragmentary whole, a concatenation of components that remain disparate no matter how densely they are entangled. Yet, there is a certain
mode of relatedness that holds the elements together. In the cases of
interest to us – in affective arrangements – this combining force is a concrete tangle of relations of affecting and being affected. In their dynamic
interplay, the elements of an affective arrangement sustain a local sphere
of affective intensity and thereby both trigger and structure characteristic
agentive routines. Accordingly, both actions and affections are locally instigated and modulated by an affective arrangement.
Combining the Spinozist conceptions of affect and potentia with this
idea of an affective arrangement yields a theoretical framework where the
unfolding of an individual’s potentia is always embedded in, and codependent on, a surrounding milieu of objects and individuals, comprising a heterogeneous field of affective capacities. From the theoretical
point of view of Spinozism, this arrangement comprises a relative sphere
of immanence,15 at the same time as it highlights the internal heterogeneity
of its composition – not by means of an ontic distinction of its objects but
by effective distinction on the level of mutually increasing or diminishing,
affirming or undermining, resonant or dissonant affective capacities.
In referring to an arrangement specifically as an affective one we are
emphasizing that already established affective dynamics and interactive
patterns are vital to the arrangement. Thresholds of affective intensity
demarcate affective arrangements from their surroundings, so that entering into an affective arrangement comes with a notable change in the
degree and intensity with which a person affectively “resonates”.16
Mundane examples are parties, clubs, sports or art events, even lively classroom discussions, meetings at work and so on – the tangle of affective relations on the inside of such constellations is intense and “gripping,” as
opposed to the lower intensity on their outside. We use “immersion” as a
term for capturing the intensive involvement or embeddedness of individuals within affective arrangements. More precisely, immersion is a specific mode of affective involvement, which is characterized by a spectrum
of subjective experiential qualities ranging from uneasiness, to absorption,
up to the complete amalgamation of one’s temporary “being” within an
intensive meshwork of augmenting or diminishing, positive or negative
affective relations (Mühlhoff 2018; Mühlhoff and Schütz 2017).
A second systematic reference point of the concept of “affective
arrangement” is Foucault’s notion of a dispositif. With this notion, Foucault
also refers to a heterogeneous ensemble of elements, constituting a whole
Immersion at work
161
– that is, a “system of relations” of these elements.17 He uses this concept
for his analysis of (historically) specific power formations in which social,
political and institutional practices, discourses of truth and subjective relations to self and others are instigated as part of a decentralized apparatus
of power. Yet Foucault’s construal of the dispositif makes little reference
to the aspect of situated affective dynamics, the hic et nunc of patterns of
affecting and being affected that have been established between elements
of the dispositif. These patterns are not reducible to the comparatively
static aspects of a dispositif on Foucault’s list, they form an ephemeral yet
constitutive part of the dispositif at hand. This holds all the more if the
scope of analysis is less that of a larger historical formation – as evident in
many of Foucault’s works – and is geared more towards short-term microand meso-social constellations, as in the example of workplaces (teamwork, office culture) we are going to discuss in the next sections. An
affective arrangement is therefore a kind of “micro-dispositif ” in Foucault’s
sense but with a dynamic register of affective potentials as its key dimension. That is, the register of affective capacities (potentia) of all the individuals, together with the already established affective relations between
these individuals, are vital to arrangements of this kind.
The theoretical setup outlined in this section not only proposes certain
concepts – such as affective arrangement, or an individual’s affective capacity – but also a methodological perspective. This perspective is based on
the assumption that individuals are modulated in situ by means of reciprocal affective dynamics in local micro-social contexts. These modulations
are part of larger trans-situative strategic ensembles, reproducing overarching patterns. The question we are thus focusing on is, how do relations of exploitation in labor, and structures of differential social roles
(e.g., in gendered interactions, or along power hierarchies in corporations) get actualized and perpetuated on the level of affective microinteractions? We claim that in certain affective arrangements, affective
relationality itself emerges as an operative register of a strategic power, in
which the thinking, acting and feeling of individuals is subtly shaped,
“nudged” and governed. The word “strategic” indicates that this type of
power does not operate as power-over, but in the immanence of the reciprocal (affective) interplay within the respective arrangement. In the next
section we illustrate this point by focusing on the example of affective
arrangements implemented by human resource management (HRM) in
modern workplace contexts.
Working arrangements: the affects of post-Fordist work
cultures
We will now apply our concepts to the discussion of two examples of affective arrangements in contemporary work cultures: first, a typical setting of
part-time work in an office operating under the teamwork concept; second
162
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
the immersive work- and lifestyle of the contemporary IT and startup
sectors. To this end, we draw on recent literature of workplace studies and
their critical reflection from sociological, cultural studies and social philosophy perspectives.
Case study 1: teamwork – Claire’s example
Claire is a 33-year-old marketing professional, working as a part-time
employee for a telecommunications company in Brisbane, Australia. She
is one of the volunteers to a series of workplace ethnographic interviews
conducted by Melissa Gregg in her 2011 study Work’s Intimacy. In a fashion
typical of most contemporary jobs in the knowledge-work sector, Claire’s
marketing department is organized in project teams, that is, in small
groups of co-workers gathered around a short- or mid-range project goal.
Compared to older styles of corporate organization, teamwork is typically
described as a non-hierarchical and quasi-social mode of interaction, “in
which all colleagues work together, sharing responsibility for the organization” (Gregg 2011, p. 74).
Initially, Claire decided to work part-time (Monday to Wednesday) in
order to look after her child the other two days of the week. In her interviews with Gregg, however, she reports that
Thursday and Friday are my days off, but at the moment …, Thursday
morning is a bit of a catch-up morning for me anyway to send out a lot
of emails and get a lot of things moving so that I don’t have to wait
until Monday before I can get momentum happening on things.
(Ibid., p. 49)
Claire describes this unpaid extra work as her free choice. Without it,
Gregg reports, “her return to the office on a Monday would be ‘really
stressful’ ”.
Yeah, and that’s why I do it; it’s not because there’s pressure from the
management team to do it at all, but it’s more just for my own
sanity.… I will sleep better if I spend an hour or an hour and a half at
night just getting on top of that, otherwise I will wake up at 4 a.m. in
the morning and I’ll be just spinning around my head.
(Ibid., pp. 49–50)
Gregg, who saw Claire twice in the space of 12 months for interviews,
reports that in the course of this one year, Claire’s home working practices
even extended to the evening hours of regular working days and “most of
the weekend” (ibid., pp. 49, 77). Claire says that together with her partner,
who is a mortgage broker, she would spend “evenings sitting on our couch
with our laptops on our laps doing work,” explaining that this is a practice
Immersion at work
163
“that just keeps us sane” (ibid., p. 50). Wireless internet and laptop computers enable Claire to follow her work in various locations and situations
at home – from sitting on the couch to hanging out in bed or spending
some time “out the front playing cars with my two-year-old on the
driveway” (ibid.). As Gregg explains, the chance to stay on top of things in
all these micro-situations, enabled by new media technologies, is to Claire
“a way of being at peace and at ease with the family” (ibid.). Connectivity
together with the part-time arrangement is creating specific practices of
sharing time with both her partner and her son while staying “on top” of
her workload.
This custom set of long-grown familial habits and domestic practices
subtly integrating work duties of both partners into an intimate life at
home is one aspect of how Claire’s work engagement is sustained and stabilized in a specific arrangement of personal and affective relations. The
development Gregg reports in the course of one year demonstrates how
affective relationality, together with practices and habits, may arrange themselves around a certain set of external constraints in a reciprocal process of
leveling and balancing. This process of arranging is neither fully passive
nor active on the part of Claire or her family. Partly, things just “fall into
place,” partly things might be initially debated, then deliberately chosen.
Apparently, both are true: the ability to do some work from home sustains
Claire’s family life; and the ability to have some familiar intimacy while
working sustains Claire’s work commitment. Claire is an example case of
how work might blend into leisure in a way which is – as a form of life – sustained by a multi-faceted ensemble of practices, media structures and personal relations through which work entangles with the realm of the
“private” and thus gains “intimacy”.
Yet the family and home sphere is only half of the arrangement of personal and affective relations that characterize Claire’s work situation. It
turns out that the other half is the workplace and her team of co-workers.
Analyzing it as a stylized arrangement of affective relations can reveal why
staying connected with work, even from home, is so important to Claire.
“The team,” as Gregg states, is “paramount” in Claire’s description of why
she logs in to her emails from home in her free time. “A sense of responsibility to others motivates her ‘to keep an eye on what is happening’ ”.
(ibid., p. 76) This is an important clue as Claire insists that she is not formally expected nor directly ordered to be online outside her office hours.
Yet there is a more subtle and implicit form of coercion at work, resulting
from the supplementation of hierarchical work relations (with a top-down
assignment of tasks and duties) by social relations in teamwork (whose
logic is that of being a reliable team mate, being motivated and motivating
others, being resonative).
If the flexible, decentralized workplace has freed employees from
the omnipotent surveillance of the boss …, today it is “the team” of
164
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
co-workers that bear witness to everyday work efforts. The team is the
mythically egalitarian playing field in which all colleagues work
together, sharing responsibility for the organization. It is one of
several coercive dimensions of office culture exacerbated by new
media technologies.
(Ibid., p. 74)
In teamwork, vertical power relations and direct subordination between
managers and workers are replaced (or perhaps only masked) by a
network of horizontal and personal relations between collaborators (see
also Liu 2004). “The perception that other co-workers might be waiting
for responses and actions is a recurring reason employees give for logging
in to read email outside the office,” Gregg reports from her interviews
(2011, p. 74). Claire’s example gives some hints as to the complexity of
affective and psychic dynamics that are involved in such a constellation:
Claire acknowledged that even though the company was “very good
with part-time employment, it’s still not the majority of people. And no
one else really is going to remember what days you work and what days
you don’t.” Her sensitivity to others’ schedules compels her to stay connected: “Even though you’ve got an ‘out of office’ on … it still can be a
bit hard for people.” Staying in touch therefore had the twin benefit of
being “appreciated by the team and it makes me feel better.”
(Ibid., p. 77)
Claire is particularly glad about her opportunity for a part-time arrangement with the company, saying “it is not a typical situation to be able to do
a project-based job and only be there half of the week” which is why she
“feel[s] very thankful” and “want[s] to make it work” (ibid., p. 51). This
thankfulness blends seamlessly into the attitude of “sensitivity to the
others’ schedules,” suggesting she is even feeling guilty knowing that she is
the aberrant one with her exceptional work hours. This mutual entanglement of gratitude, guilt and commitment is fueled even further by her
basic need for recognition that is evident in her longing for “being appreciated by the team”. Given her exceptional work arrangement, Claire goes
on to explain:
[T]here will be people there that will send something through on a
Thursday and they might need it close of business on Friday. So it is
good to be able to – if it is urgent and only I can do it – I can actually
look at it or I can make sure it is sent on to the right people.
(Ibid., p. 77)
This “conviction that ‘only I can do it’,” as Melissa Gregg points out, “gets
to the heart of teamwork’s interpellative power” (ibid.). It is a very specific
Immersion at work
165
form of self-relation and self-narration of Claire’s way of being involved,
entangled and harnessed into the real-time dynamics of team relations
with her specific skills and affective capacities, even when she is at home.
It is not even necessary that really only she can do a certain task. The subjective impression that “only I can do it” suffices, in principle, to make for
its implicitly coercive effect. Together with the constellation of wanting to
be appreciated by the team, wanting to make the part-time arrangement
work and sharing responsibility for the overall project, this form of selfrelation might be referred to as a form of subjectivity that is produced and
exploited in the meshwork of affective dynamics in Claire’s teamwork
arrangement. Through the constitution of this form of subjectivity, a
modality of governing employees emerges in teamwork formations. It is
based on involving everyone in a productive arrangement of microrelations and interpersonal practices based less on their technical skills
(their knowledge, their handcrafting skills, etc.), and more on a specific
affective engagement. That is, a spectrum of personal affective capacities
beyond servility and discipline becomes the driving force of teamwork
relations (in the case of Claire: need for recognition, disposition towards
feeling guilty, etc.). Yet the effect of this engagement as it unfolds in the
immanence of a strategic ensemble of affective micro-powers might also
be that of subtle coercion and servility.
The transition from hierarchical forms of corporate organization to a
teamwork-based topology is one of the most groundbreaking transformations of capitalist production in the 21st century. In today’s, so called, “networked corporations” (Liu 2004), production is no longer organized as a
chain of piecemeal tasks, but is everyone’s shared responsibility to have
the perspective of the whole process in mind.18 Individual roles and the
distribution of specialized tasks within a team are supposed to be selfregulating processes of reciprocal feedback-loop controls (Bröckling
2008). Since the 1990s a full-blown discourse in HRM has emerged, inventing strategies to stimulate and facilitate team collaboration according to
this vision.19 Far from leaving it to self-organization, a trend of training
teamwork is evident in techniques such as team building, bonding events
and coaching in networking soft-skills. HRM strategies even go as far as
the implementation of holistic “company cultures” or “sub-cultural”
spheres at workplaces, orchestrated by companies’ “change managers” and
“Wow!” departments (Gregg 2011, p. 75). The core idea behind these
instruments is to make employees engage not only with their work but
with one another. That is, everyone is supposed to be immersed in their
work as a full person, with their full range of social and affective capacities
and their potentia – fully committed in short.
In critical analyses of post-Fordist work cultures, be it under the name
of a New Spirit of Capitalism (Boltanski and Chiapello 2007) or of The Soul
at Work (Berardi 2009), it is evident that affective relations between coworkers and within work environments have become increasingly central
166
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
in techniques of contemporary workplace governance. Genealogically, the
teamwork paradigm had emerged already in the 1970s and 1980s, due to
the influence of post-World War cybernetic and group dynamic research
(Bröckling 2008). In this first case study, we were revisiting this basic form
of organization in an updated perspective derived from Melissa Gregg’s
recent work, highlighting how digital communication and new media
technology of the 21st century facilitate team collaboration in a new form.
By the same token, we are extending the classic understanding of “affective” and “immaterial labor” by pointing out that it is not so much the
product of this work, but the very modality of workers’ engagement that is
affective in these arrangements.20 Teamwork strategically stimulates and
harnesses the specific affective capacities of co-workers and their social
bonds as an energy resource, exploitable to increase commitment,
responsibility and extra work hours, mostly without managerial orders.
From Claire’s example it is clear how this might make work relations not
only grow into more intimate relations, but also how it makes work relations entangle with private life spheres, forming a whole arrangement of
diverse relations (co-workers, partner, child), practices (doing work from
various places and situations), spaces (office, home, bed, driveway, couch),
narratives (“only I can do it”) and psychological complexes (“sensitivity to
others,” wanting to be appreciated, thankfulness, guilt) of several people.
Case study 2: “Life at Google”
Our second case study emphasizes the importance of a holistic account of
work environments as affective micro-dispositifs. We refer to it as “Life at
Google,” a term derived from the company’s own wording on their
website.21 Google Inc. is a tech company in the New Economy, and it is
well known that alongside its pioneering technological achievements, the
New Economy has always been a major innovator in HRM. In order to
facilitate technological innovations at such a speed, some of the New
Economy’s most valuable assets are its constant inventions of new forms of
organizing, governing and capitalizing the personal potential of their
employees. Yet around the turn of the 21st century and after the crash of
the dot-com bubble in 2000, it was no longer enough to subjectify
employees along the dimensions of availability and commitment, as could
be seen in the teamwork dispositif described above (cf. Gill 2007; Ross
2001; Terranova 2010). Instead, creativity became the new prime target of
the work organization. The dominant HRM ideology of the last two
decades, in line with the new hegemony of a “start-up culture,” is madly
focusing on open spaces stimulating unexpected ideas, putatively cultivating a “power of diversity” (Gardenswartz and Rowe 1994) and even
encouraging deviant forces – which are seen as forces of innovation.22 An
obvious obstacle is that creative processes can be planned or enforced
even less than interpersonal affective bonds in team constellations. In fact,
Immersion at work
167
they require other, more radical techniques of stimulation and orchestration in specific affective arrangements.
For the engineers at Google, the company has been setting up architectural and interior arrangements best described as “kindergarten-style”
work environments with toys, colorful bikes, billiard tables, Star Trek
posters, and “a large, terribly fake-looking replica of SpaceShipOne
hanging in the middle of the main building and a replica dinosaur skeleton standing outside” at the main campus in Mountain View, California
(Swartz 2006). In the mid-2000s, Google became famous for these affective arrangements that turn the workplace into a life environment where
work is supposed to feel like play and where the often 20- to 25-year-old
employees, who have come straight from college, spend as much time as
possible (cf. ibid.; Terranova 2010). Loosely connecting to the spirit of the
hacker movement and the play instinct of the middle-class “millennial
generation,” this environment has been advertised in Google’s hiring campaigns as an extension of college life. The company was providing a holistic environment, covering practical needs from free food, laundry services,
on campus health care and sports sites, up to a corporate bus service to
pick up people from home in the morning. For the (wealthy class of ) IT
engineers, the company has created a space not only for work but for fun,
recreation, leisure and the pursuit of one’s own projects.
Google’s “playful” work environments – which have since been adopted
and imitated by the growing hegemony of a start-up culture in IT branches
and beyond – are exemplary of a local arrangement designed to immerse
employees with their personal and affective potentials, relations and
impulses into a productive apparatus of human relations, thus making
their energies exploitable for company benefit. While teamwork stimulates
and harnesses affective bonds of co-workers around the felt qualities of
reciprocal reliability, guilt, appreciation, insecurities and a shared commitment, the affective arrangement of a “life at Google” additionally stimulates a “play instinct,” and, by that means, “creativity”. In play, three aspects
of subjective involvement are combined: (1) being driven by a deeply
rooted, affectively grounded fascination for technology; (2) the opportunity for non-competitive, “happy-go-lucky” experimentation and trying
beyond market-strategy and economic worries; (3) a specific affective
interpersonal dynamic of “positive” and amplifying social interactions and
identifications, forming a register of belonging to a subcultural sphere of
resonance (see Mühlhoff 2018). “Play instinct” is seen as a personal capital
– as an employee’s marketable set of affective potentials – which is at the
core of the tech industry’s innovation culture. It is remarkable to see how,
in this formation, employees are not addressed as experts of a specialized
knowledge or skill-set, nor as subjects of discipline and obedience. Rather,
they are addressed, produced and harnessed as carriers of affective potentials. The HRM strategy evident in Google’s specific setup is to create a
relational arrangement where these potentials can unfold, promising to
168
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
employees an environment for what feels like self-expression and selforganization, while implementing subtle control of the directions in which
these forces are allowed to unfold and a decentralized structure of their
exploitation and valorization (see Deleuze 1992).
However, as critical voices suggest, this is only one side of the coin.
“Google keeps employees by treating them like kids” is the title of a viral
article by the short-lived programmer, entrepreneur and internet activist
Aaron Swartz (1986–2013). He points out that the immersive stimulation
of a playful work ethos at Google is not only an ephemeral and situative
modulation or intensification of certain behavior traits and affective capacities. Evidence suggests that it is a systematic strategy of “infantilization”
of employees as persons, and this implies a long-lasting, subjectivity
forming feedback of this immersive involvement on the individuals:
The dinosaurs and spaceships certainly fit in with the infantilizing
theme, as does the hot tub-sized ball pit that Googlers can jump into
and throw ball fights. Everyone I know who works there either acts
childish (the army of programmers), enthusiastically adolescent (their
managers and overseers), or else is deeply cynical (the hot-shot programmers). But as much as they may want to leave Google, the infantilizing tactics have worked: they’re afraid they wouldn’t be able to
survive anywhere else.
(Swartz 2006)
However accurate this description might be in the case of Google, it points
to an important dimension of affect-based corporate governance in
general. Immersive environments actively produce – each in their own way
– individuals with a suitable, mutually stabilizing structure of affective
capacities and subjective self-relation. This also connects to what Melissa
Gregg refers to as the “coercive dimension” of contemporary office culture
(Gregg 2011, p. 74). Although these forms of collaboration are subjectively based on free, autonomous, fun and personal interactions at eyelevel, they are not free of coercion. The techniques of coercion have just
become more subtle and implicit compared with how old-school disciplinary regimes outwardly oppressed individuals.
As we argue in the conclusion, this new mode of coercion is based on a
form of affective subjectivation – that is, the genesis of subjectivity in affective
relations – which is molded in such a way that a subjective experience of
fun and self-responsible decisions is seamlessly aligned with what is of
benefit to the company. In our examples this constitution of subjectivity
consists of two aspects, The first is the creation of interpersonal environments, selectively stimulating, amplifying and orchestrating aspects of the
individuals’ potentia to unfold in a meshwork of affective relations. From
teamwork to “Life at Google” this means creating affective arrangements
designed to instigate intensive attachments and joyful self-experiences
Immersion at work
169
within these relations. The second aspect is that, over time, the environment as a whole is feeding back on the potentia (affective capacity) of the
individual, creating an affective lock-in effect. When this lock-in effect sets
in, affective capacities, intrinsic motivations and long-grown life-work
arrangements can be exploited, from the extension of working hours to
what might be called a strategic infantilization of employees. It is now time
to ask how these case studies might inform a perspective on power and
governmentality in the post-Fordist economy.
Conclusion: affect, power and immersion
There are two major conclusions to be drawn from our analyses, one
leading in the direction of critique and empowerment, the other emphasizing theoretical consequences for the field of affect studies and social
philosophy. First, our examples showcase the potency of concepts such as
“relational affect” and “affective arrangement” to reveal a contemporary
form of power relations and a concurrent constitution of subjectivity as
affective and discursive self-relations in certain environments. As vignettes
they exemplify how knowledge work cultures in the post-Fordist era, most
prevalent in the tech, media and advertising industries, are maintained by
a form of governance (and governmentality) operating in a register of
situated, horizontal and potentially pleasurable affective relations. We
refer to this governance principle as immersion to highlight that the mechanism of personal and potentially self-amplifying involvement absorbs individuals in a form of dense relatedness and concurrent subjectivity, which
thwarts the possibilities for critical distancing and sober reflections from
an outside perspective on one’s own way of being involved (Mühlhoff
2018; Mühlhoff and Schütz 2017). Immersive governance by means of strategically arranged affective dynamics does not rely on power-over relations, such as explicit managerial orders (which could in principle be
opposed or criticized on an equally explicit level). Instead, it relies on the
relational modulation of individual behavior by selective stimulation and
intensification of the affective potentials and the character traits of each
individual – from dispositions to self-sacrifice or feelings of guilt to the
entrepreneurial play instinct.
Driven by the hope of facilitating critique and empowerment, our analysis aims to equip the involved and affected individuals with their own
conceptual toolkit. Suitable analytic concepts are a prerequisite for
making relations of affecting and being affected visible and addressable as
micro-techniques of governance. From the point of view of employees
accustomed to the promises of team play and flexible work relations,
such a conclusion is not something that comes to mind immediately.
The deployment of affective techniques displaces the aspect of governance
into the inexplicit – thus evading easy analytic access – and into the personal, where it is masked behind what is supposed to feel like inherent
170
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
motivation or, in case of failure, comes across as personal insufficiency.
Any direct articulation of structural failures, let alone acts of disobedience,
resistance and empowerment in these arrangements, face the paradox of
going against one’s professional self-image and threaten one’s friendly
attachments to colleagues.
Second, with a systematic perspective in mind, our case studies prompt
for a theorization of affect as a register of local micro-dispositifs of power.
This hints at a connection between theories of affect and theories of subjectivating power that is still largely a blind spot between affect studies,
post-structuralist theories of the subject, governmentality studies and postMarxist critiques. Initially, the “turn to affect” was driven by an anti-poststructuralist euphoria to find in affect a notion that overcame the
“deadlock” of (misunderstood) subjectivity (see Massumi 1995; 2002). At
the close of the second decade of the 21st century, however, it is increasingly evident that affect is a politically ambivalent notion.23 In this chapter,
we intended to show how affects (even positive affects) can be stimulated
as a resource of inherent forces in apparatuses of power and exploitation.
Whether affect is an emancipatory and transformative force or a register
of exploitation and harnessing is thus not a property of affect per se but
depends on how affective dynamics are entangled in local microdispositifs. This is why uncovering affective strategies of power is a matter
of studying neither single individuals and relations, nor macroscopic dispositifs at a societal and historic scale alone. The relevant scope is that of
the meso-scale affective arrangements, of micro-social spheres and their
meshworks of situated human relations.
Most notably, the form of governmentality evident in the knowledge
work cultures we studied has undermined the classic dichotomies of work
versus leisure, production versus consumption and duty versus pleasure.
Central achievements of the social welfare states of the Fordist and New
Deal economic eras, such as the spatial separation of work from home
along with the temporal separation of work time from free time, are abandoned without notable resistance. This is what makes critique so difficult.
As a starting point, our analysis suggests that this “voluntary” dissolution of
boundaries must be read as a symptom of a transformed mechanism of
subject genesis in affective relations, evident in modern forms of corporate governance.24 Subjects are produced as carriers of specific capacities
to affect and be affected in the immanence of an affective arrangement
that consists of both affective and discursive elements. Consequently, this
calls for a suitable kind of immanent critique, as the modality of power
evident in the formations of “The New Spirit of Capitalism” acts on people
from without, but through peoples’ affects.
We refer to the form of subject genesis evident in these formations as
affective subjectivation. This term demarcates a theoretical perspective
from which Spinoza’s individual (as constituted in affective relations)
appears as the site of a relationally co-dependent and situated self-relation,
Immersion at work
171
which is as much affective as it is discursive. Along these lines, the Spinozist conception of relational affect, together with the perspective facilitated
by the concept of affective arrangements, provides a framework that can
be combined with a Foucault-style analysis and critique of power formations. The dynamics of potentia unfolding in relations of affecting and
being affected is the micro-social end point (or zoom level) in apparatuses
of relational and productive power. Our approach therefore allows the
introduction of a concept of affect to critical social theory. Following this
route further, as has been argued in detail elsewhere, brings us to a theory
of “immersive power,” which is a modality of post-disciplinary power
dominant in the micro-dispositifs of post-Fordist work cultures in the 21st
century (see Mühlhoff 2018). A lived and embodied critique of this form
of governance, however, can only be presaged by theoretical work like this
in order to dare an adaptation of Foucault’s (1997) notion of critique to
these scenarios. If governance hijacks the way individuals are capable of
affecting and being affected, empowerment calls for a collective practice
based on a shared will “not to be affected like this” anymore.
Notes
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
Spinoza 1677, Ethica, ordine geometrico demonstrata.
See Spinoza 1677 Ethics, parts I–III, cf. also Deleuze 1990.
As a matter of fact, historically Spinoza was an explicit opponent of Descartes.
References to Spinoza’s Ethics follow the common citation scheme using the
work’s internal segmentation in parts (I-V), propositions (prop.), scholia
(schol.), proofs (dem.), definitions (def.) and others.
For detailed elaborations on this point see Deleuze 1990, pp. 91–95, 217–224;
Kwek 2015 and Mühlhoff 2018. In Spinoza’s Ethics, this interpretation refers to
the group of propositions in part III, prop. 49–59 and part IV, prop. 33, which
cannot be reconstructed here in more detail.
For the debate on immanence and immanent causation in Spinoza cf. Ethics,
part I, prop. 18; Deleuze 1990 and, for example, Melamed 2013; Saar 2013.
For the concept of “affective resonance” see in more detail, Mühlhoff 2015.
See Ethics III, post.1 and 2; Deleuze 1988, pp. 49–50; Kwek 2015; Mühlhoff
2018.
See Ethics II axioms and lemmata after prop. 13; Deleuze 1988, pp. 91–92, 123.
A (finite) “mode” (modus) is Spinoza’s term for individual.
Technically, a non post-Aristotelian notion of potentiality is needed here,
which may be taken from Deleuze 1994. See also Protevi 2013 and Mühlhoff
2015 on this point.
See also the related debate in analytical philosophy on “situated affectivity,”
and on embodied, embedded, enactive and extended mind theories. See, for
instance, Griffiths and Scarantino 2009; Mühlhoff 2015 and Slaby 2016 explore
some of the resonances between these theoretical perspectives.
For the concept of “affective resonance” see Mühlhoff 2015. This is not a metaphorical term but a theoretical concept apt for describing the reciprocal modulation of entities in dynamic relations of affecting and being affected.
By introducing the concept of an “affective arrangement,” we are recapitulating briefly what we elaborated in detail in Slaby, Mühlhoff and Wüschner 2017.
172
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
15 More precisely, of immanent causality in its overall ensemble of internal relations of affecting and being affected.
16 Cf. Seyfert (this volume) for more detailed considerations on the role of affective intensity within socio-technical arrangements. As we do as well, Seyfert
takes key hints from Massumi 1995. See also Seyfert 2012, where he proposes
the term “affectif ” for constellations similar to the ones we call affective
arrangements.
17 From Foucault 1980 the French “dispositif ” was translated as “apparatus,” we
substitute the now broadly recognized term again. See Anderson 2014, ch. 2,
for a recent attempt to turn Foucault’s dispositif directly into a concept for theorizing affect and affective relationality.
18 Cf. Liu 2004, pp. 45–46; and for a popular mainstream engagement, Tapscott
2015.
19 See for instance Gardenswartz and Rowe 1994; Boxall et al. 2007. As examples
of critical engagements in management studies, cf. Knights and McCabe 2003.
20 Lazzarato 1996; Hardt 1999. For updated and refined discussions of affective
and immaterial labor in the context of post-Fordism and digitized capitalism in
the 21st century, see Terranova 2004; Dowling, Nunes and Trott 2007.
21 Available from: http://careers.google.com [20 March 2017].
22 Given the well-documented prevalence of white, male, middle-class employees
in the tech sector, talk of “diversity” and “deviant forces” has an ideological ring
to it in this context. Cf. Terranova 2010; Cooper 2000.
23 Feminist sociologist Clare Hemmings (2005) was among the earliest to point
this out in a critical essay on the affective turn.
24 For the notions of subjectivation and subjectivity, cf. Foucault 1982;1984.
References
Anderson, B 2014, Encountering Affect: Capacities, Apparatuses, Conditions, Ashgate,
Farnham.
Berardi, F 2009, The Soul at Work: From Alienation to Autonomy, Semiotext(e), Los
Angeles.
Boltanski, L and Chiapello, E 2007, The New Spirit of Capitalism, Verso, New York.
Boxall, PF, Purcell, J and Wright, PM (eds) 2007, The Oxford Handbook of Human
Resource Management, Oxford University Press, New York.
Bröckling, U 2008, “Über Feedback. Anatomie einer kommunikativen Schlüsseltechnologie” in M Hagner and E Hörl, (eds), Die Transformation des Humanen
Beiträge zur Kulturgeschichte der Kybernetik, pp. 326–347. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt/M.
Buchanan, I 1997, “The Problem of the Body in Deleuze and Guattari, Or, What
Can a Body Do?”, Body & Society, vol. 3, no. 3, pp. 73–91.
Buchanan, I 2015, “Assemblage Theory and Its Discontents”, Deleuze Studies, vol. 9,
no. 3, pp. 382–392.
Cooper, M 2000, “Being the ‘Go-To Guy’: Fatherhood, Masculinity, and the Organization of Work in Silicon Valley”, Qualitative Sociology, vol. 23, no. 4,
pp. 379–405.
Deleuze, G 1988, Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, trans. by R Hurley, City Lights Books,
San Francisco.
Deleuze, G 1990, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. by M Joughin, Zone
Books, New York.
Deleuze, G 1992, “Postscript on the Societies of Control”, October, vol. 59, pp. 3–7.
Immersion at work
173
Deleuze, G 1994, Difference and Repetition, trans. by Paul Patton, Columbia University Press, New York.
Deleuze, G and Guattari, F 1987, A Thousand Plateaus, trans. by B Massumi, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
Dowling, E, Nunes, R and Trott, B 2007, “Immaterial and Affective Labour:
Explored”, Ephemera, vol. 7, no. 1, pp. 1–7.
Foucault, M 1980, “The Confession of the Flesh” in C Gordon, (ed.), Power/
Knowledge. Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–1977, pp. 194–228. Pantheon
Books, New York.
Foucault, M 1982, “The Subject and Power”, Critical Inquiry, vol. 8, no. 4,
pp. 777–795.
Foucault, M 1997, “What is critique?” in S Lotringer, (ed.), The politics of truth,
pp. 23–82. Semiotext(e), Los Angeles.
Gardenswartz, L and Rowe, A 1994, Diverse Teams at Work. Capitalizing on the Power
of Diversity, Society of Human Research Management, Alexandria VA.
Gill, R 2007, Technobohemians or the New Cybertariat? Institute of Network Cultures,
Network Notebooks, Amsterdam.
Gregg, M 2011, Work’s Intimacy, Polity Press, Cambridge.
Griffiths, PE and Scarantino, A 2009, “Emotions in the Wild”, in P Robbins and M
Aydede, (eds), The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition, pp. 437–453. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Hardt, M 1999, “Affective labor”, boundary 2, vol. 26, no. 2, pp. 89–100.
Hemmings, C 2005, “Invoking Affect: Cultural Theory and the Ontological Turn”,
Cultural Studies, vol. 19, no. 5, pp. 548–567.
Knights, D and McCabe, D 2003, “Governing through Teamwork: Reconstituting
Subjectivity in a Call Centre”, Journal of Management Studies, vol. 40, no. 7,
pp. 1587–1619.
Kwek, D 2015, “Power and the Multitude: A Spinozist View”, Political Theory, vol. 43,
no. 2, pp. 155–184.
Lazzarato, M 1996, “Immaterial labour” in M Hardt and P Virno, (eds), Radical
thought in Italy: A potential politics, pp. 133–147. University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolis.
Liu, A 2004, The Laws of Cool. Knowledge Work and the Culture of Information, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Massumi, B 1995, “The Autonomy of Affect”, Cultural Critique, vol. 31, no. 2,
pp. 83–109.
Massumi, B 2002, Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation, Duke University
Press, Durham.
Melamed, Y 2013, Spinoza’s Metaphysics: Substance and Thought, Oxford University
Press, New York.
Mühlhoff, R 2018, Immersive Macht. Affekttheorie nach Spinoza und Foucault, Campus,
Frankfurt/M.
Mühlhoff, R 2015, “Affective resonance and social interaction”, Phenomenology and
the Cognitive Sciences, vol. 14, no. 4, pp. 1001–1019.
Mühlhoff, R and Schütz, T 2017, “Verunsichern, Vereinnahmen, Verschmelzen –
eine affekttheoretische Perspektive auf Immersion”, Working Paper SFB 1171
Affective Societies, 05/17, Berlin.
Nail, T 2017, “What is an Assemblage?”, SubStance 142, vol. 46, no. 1, pp. 21–37.
Protevi, J 2013, Life, War, Earth, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
174
Rainer Mühlhoff and Jan Slaby
Ross, A 2001, “No-Collar Labour in America’s New Economy”, Socialist Register, vol.
37, pp. 77–87.
Saar, M. 2013, Die Immanenz der Macht. Politische Theorie nach Spinoza, Suhrkamp,
Berlin.
Seyfert, R 2012, “Beyond Personal Feelings and Collective Emotions: Toward a
Theory of Social Affect”, Theory, Culture & Society, vol. 29, no. 6, pp. 27–46.
Seyfert, R 2018, “Automation and Affect: A Study of Algorithmic Trading” in B
Röttger-Rössler and J Slaby, (eds), Affect in Relation. Families, Places, Technologies,
Routledge, New York.
Slaby, J. 2016, “Mind Invasion: Situated Affectivity and the Corporate Life Hack”,
Frontiers in Psychology, vol. 7, no. 266.
Slaby, J, Mühlhoff, R and Wüschner, P 2017, “Affective Arrangements”, Emotion
Review, 20 October. Available from DOI: 10.1177/1754073917722214.
Spinoza, B 1677, Ethics, ed. and trans. by E Curley, The Collected Works of Spinoza,
vol. 2., Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ.
Swartz, A 2006, “The Goog Life: how Google keeps employees by treating them
like kids”, Raw Thought, blog post, 13 December. Available from: www.aaronsw.
com/weblog/googlife [1 December 2015].
Tapscott, D 2015, The Digital Economy. 20th Anniversary Edition – Rethinking Promise
and Peril in The Age of Networked Intelligence, McGraw-Hill, New York.
Terranova, T 2004, Network Culture. Politics for the Information Age, Pluto Press,
London.
Terranova, T 2010, “New Economy, Financialization and Social Production in the
Web 2.0” in A Fumagalli and S Mezzadra, (eds), Crisis in the Global Economy,
pp. 153–170. Semiotext(e), Los Angeles.