Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Comment on "Comments on Thomas Teo's Critical Psychology" by

Comment on "Comments on Thomas Teo's Critical Psychology" by Andy Blunden, July 2019.

Comment on “Comments on Thomas Teo’s Critical Psychology” by Andy Blunden, July 2019 I personally don’t find critical exchanges of one’s work helpful when they are ad hominem arguments and defenses, friendly or unfriendly. Often such exchanges are about positionality, where arguments about a missed context, or that someone did not read z (and would have a better understanding), did not understand y, missed the point of x, etc., with multiple iterations, are intellectually not helpful to me and don't solve any social or psychosocial problems. Rather than pointing at mistakes, I prefer to articulate my intellectual intentions. Such exchanges strangely embody a traditional form of “methodological” individualism (as do my reflections below) as does the idea that we can find current answers in the works of one or a few scholars who lived decades or centuries ago. I remember a famous colleague in philosophical psychology who suggested that all psychological answers can be found in Aristotle; I know Marxists who think that everything can be solved with Marx. The practice of going beyond methodological solipsism means to learn from (critical) approaches that are radically different from one’s own standpoint and experience. Indeed, I learned a lot from feminist theory, critical disability studies, as well as from queer theory about human subjectivity. The project of the “psychological humanities” as a counter-concept to the “psychological sciences” that are so prevalent now in the discipline builds on the idea that we need and cannot ignore the humanities, concept-driven social sciences and the arts to make sense of the psyche. On this background, I should mention that I learned a lot from Andy Blunden’s book on “Concepts” - which does not mean that I agree with all his ideas, and I contrast them with alternative frameworks such as Danziger, K. (1997). Naming the mind: How psychology found its language. London, UK: Sage. My own work has been focused on the notion that one’s ideas are embedded in history, culture, and society. It would be odd to exempt oneself from that. Knowledge involves the impossible task to incorporate all the relevant knowledge that exists in the psychological humanities and sciences. Thus, it is easier to commit to one research program, or one or a few scholars to avoid the overflow of information, to be a specialist rather than a generalist. I believe we all do that to some degree. My own framework is a critical one, in its widest sense (critical theories and critical psychologies) but I learned a lot from the German critical psychologist Klaus Holzkamp, whose books were not translated into English. To a certain degree it is my tradition. This does not mean that I understand myself as a Holzkampian when I draw on his work, nor a Kantian, Marxist, Foucauldian, Habermasian, etc. My primary goal is to learn something about the psyche. If someone says you can learn everything from Vygotsky, or Holzkamp, or Habermas, or Freud, it does not reflect my experiences. More generally, I believe that the amount of knowledge in the science and the humanities should lead us to embrace epistemic modesty as a virtue. I have attached my “in press” chapter on this topic below as an argument why I believe this to be the case and why this is difficult to do (this is not the final record but close enough): Teo, T. (in press). Academic subjectivity, idols, and the vicissitudes of virtues in science: Epistemic modesty versus epistemic grandiosity. In K. O’Doherty, L. Osbeck, E. Schraube & J. Yen (Eds.), Psychological studies of science and technology. Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. My primary goal is to learn something about the psyche (or subjectivity) and to articulate those insights. I hope that people can learn from them as well – but if not, I can accept that, too. The learning takes place in the context of deconstruction, reconstruction, and construction. Deconstruction means the critique of mainstream psychology, which is in my view obvious because of its many shortcomings. I hope that my works on epistemological violence have aided in deconstructing the myth of a naive empiricism in psychology. I would not credit this work to one single framework but to a variety of intellectual, albeit critical-theoretical influences. [e.g., Teo, T. (2008). From speculation to epistemological violence in psychology: A critical-hermeneutic reconstruction. Theory & Psychology, 18(1), 47-67. doi:10.1177/0959354307086922] Reconstruction, which often goes hand in hand with deconstruction, refers to historical or to integrative works in psychology. For example, I attempted to provide an overview of critical psychology for a mainstream psychological audience in: Teo, T. (2015). Critical psychology: A geography of intellectual engagement and resistance. American Psychologist, 70(3), 243-254. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/a0038727. I also have suggested how we can re-envision theoretical psychology, individually, Teo, T. (2018). Outline of theoretical psychology: Critical investigations. London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan; and collectively, Teo, T. (Ed). (2019). Re-envisioning theoretical psychology: Diverging ideas and practices. Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. But critical-psychological work cannot solely be about deconstruction and reconstruction. It must be about construction as well, for instance a theory of subjectivity, and what subjectivity means in current times, under neoliberalism. For instance, I tried to suggest that a theory of subjectivity needs to take the social, historical, cultural, as well as its uniqueness and irreplaceability into account (a seeming paradox), as well as inner dynamics (but go beyond what psychoanalysis introduced), the body but not only in its biomechanical but in its phenomenological experience, as well as technology not just as an tool but as a possible element in the constitution of subjectivity (e.g., Han’s digital panopticon). My work is focused on psychology, arguing that we need more than psychology to understand the psychological, especially when psychology has so many problems. I also suggested that the discipline of psychology does not have a general theory of subjectivity, although there are several candidates, and I hope to be able to contribute to such a theory. In my self-understanding my research has been critical-theoretical, metatheoretical, and critical-historical in order to provide a more reflexive understanding of the foundations and trajectories of current psychology, and to envision alternatives to the status quo. My research intends to promote psychology towards becoming a self-reflexive discipline, in which unquestioned assumptions are challenged, problematic concepts and theories are analyzed, research practices are contextualized, and to provide interventions that improve the disciplinary, academic, and societal conditions. I understand that not every reader agrees with that and I will and can learn from such discrepancies. Academic subjectivity, idols, and the vicissitudes of virtues in science: Epistemic modesty versus epistemic grandiosity Thomas Teo York University Address: Thomas Teo, Historical, Theoretical and Critical Studies of Psychology, York University, 4700 Keele Street, Toronto, Ontario, M3J 1P3, Canada. Electronic mail: tteo@yorku.ca. Abstract The subjectivity of the researcher is as much embedded in society, history and the larger culture as any other subjectivity. Political-economic conditions, the Zeitgeist, social characteristics, the academic habitus, personal idiosyncrasies, institutional realities, or politics can influence the questions, methodologies, interpretations, and applications of research. It is argued that internationalization, the historicity of the societal embeddedness of knowledge, and personal limitations should embolden epistemic modesty as a virtue. In contrast, it is argued that epistemic grandiosity is the more common practice of scientists, which is analyzed on the background of the development of new idols, the neoliberal transformation of academia, and a post-truth society. Using instances from the natural and human sciences, the (im)possibility of epistemic modesty as part of epistemic subjectivity, and contours for a new critical psychology of science, are discussed. Academic subjectivity and the vicissitudes of virtues in science: Epistemic modesty versus epistemic grandiosity Epistemic subjectivity has been the nemesis of objectivity. To be more precise: Subjectivity has always been a dialectical part of objectivity (see Daston & Galison, 2007). Objectivity is not only an epistemic category, but also a value that guides science (Teo, 2018a). To demand from the subject to “be objective” is clearly a normative claim and shows the connection between epistemology and ethics, or, what one could label “epistemo-ethics.” Epistemic values become personal virtues once they are considered positive and embodied in concrete subjectivities. Scientists, implicitly and explicitly, have committed to various epistemic virtues over time. Traditional values may include academic freedom, honesty, transparency, truth, or objectivity, while critical researchers may emphasize truthfulness, social, economic, and environmental justice as ideals of research. Whereas objectivity remains a widely endorsed value and virtue, epistemic modesty is hardly mentioned in textbooks, the academic literature, or seminars, although it is a value that emerges when understanding subjectivity in its full complexity, including a recognition of the historical, cultural, and personal limitations of knowledge. While the historicity and the personal limitations of knowledge apply to all sciences, culture-centric knowledge within a complex globalized world impacts the human sciences more deeply. Yet, it also leads human scientists to be anxious about the consequences of humble knowledge claims in the public. Epistemic subjectivity may also compare itself to everyday subjectivity and in this process may align itself with epistemic grandiosity. The dialectics between epistemic modesty and grandiosity in human subjectivity has a long history in European thinking. In Western philosophy this conflict is played out in classical Graeco-Roman expositions. Cicero’s (106-43 BCE) Socrates laid the foundation for understanding the limits of one’s knowledge, for being open to the uncertainty of one’s knowledge, translated from Greek, and later from Latin, as the dictum: “I know that I do not know” (sometimes erroneously translated as “I know that I know nothing”) (see Fine, 2008). This must be contrasted with Plato’s (1997) allegory of the cave, involving Socrates as well, that portrays the knower as belonging to the few who embrace truth, against the many who chain themselves to ignorance and who sacrifice the true knower in a seemingly inevitable course of events. Western philosophy has contributed to this mindset in the works of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), who labeled his own contributions a Copernican revolution, or Georg W. F. Hegel, (1770-1831), who suggested that the absolute spirit was embodied in his works, to Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900), who titled one of his chapters in Ecce Homo (written 1888), arguably ironically “Why I write such good books,” to mention only a few examples. If we put Francis Bacon (1561-1626) at the formation of modern Western science, we find a similar dialectic (one could include Descartes): His idols emphasize the importance of understanding the hinderances to knowledge (Bacon, 1965), whereas the limitations do not apply to himself, and his own statements lack modesty (see also Keller, 1985). It is a common current in scientific thought that the limitations of knowledge, a lack of objectivity or rigor, or incompetence are attributed to other people but not to oneself. Accusing other researchers of bias, ignorance, and speculation has been a tool to diminish the epistemic quality of the work of others (Teo, 2008). This applies equally to “positivist” and empiricist approaches as well as to critical scholarship that should have been aware of its own temporality. The belief that one can assume a point from nowhere, that history, culture, and society do not play a role in epistemic subjectivity, that “I” am objective, whereas others are not, may lead to a feeling of epistemic grandiosity, whereas the assumption that “my” knowledge is always fragile, even when “I” attempt to be objective, might inspire epistemic modesty. In the natural sciences, modesty could include the context of discovery (see Reichenbach, 1938) (what questions are asked and why), and one’s own inevitably narrow expertise, whereas in the human sciences, it applies to the contexts of discovery, justification (how was a claim justified? what methodology or method was used to make this statement?), interpretation (how were results interpreted?), and application (how were findings translated for practical purposes?). Particularly in the human sciences, the temporality and contextuality of objects and events would demand making epistemic modesty a virtue. For instance, postcolonial research has shown the degree to which Western ideas permeate knowledge in the human, social, and psychological sciences. Such research identifies power dynamics against the periphery that include misrepresentations, silencing, structural and epistemic violence (e.g., Spivak, 1999). Scientific projects have played an important role in othering non-Western mental life (Jackson & Weidman, 2004). Western science has shown the cultural, colonial and indigenous impact of knowledge, and how colonial interests have been responsible for the generation of knowledge about dominated people. Even when there is an agreement that European history is not world-history, historians from the “periphery” (e.g., India), still need to address the “center’s” history, which does not hold true for the center (Chakrabarty, 2000). Similarly, human scientists from the periphery must relate indigenous knowledge to mainstream organizations, journals, and practices if they want to have impact, whereas the opposite is not required of the mainstream. Indigenous knowledge has shown that we can have alternative conceptualizations about the human world (e.g., Kim, Yang, & Hwang, 2006), and that much of Western thinking itself is indigenous in its context. The problem is not just one of sampling or organizational structure (Henrich, Heine, & Norenzayan, 2010), but affects the core categories with which disciplines in the human sciences operate. The problem of epistemic ethnocentrism is not confined to the participants of research, but includes distortions and interests that emerge from hypotheses, interpretations, and research practices that psychologists have adopted. Power and culture play a role in the choice of problems, methods, data analyses, discussions, and applications. The solution to the problem of ethnocentrism in the human sciences is not about expanding but about decolonizing such sciences (see Bhatia, 2018). Psychological intuitions, categories, theories, philosophies, and even methodologies have a cultural dimension embedded in power. Thus, for subjects involved in sciences about humans, the value of modesty in regard to one’s knowledge claims should be obvious. Epistemic virtues and values – endorsed or embodied – are one area of research for a new psychology of science. A psychology of the sciences and beyond Attempts to capture some of the subjective elements in the scientific process have been accomplished in a traditional psychology of science. For instance, one of the pioneers of psychology, Galton (1869/1962), proclaimed that scientific genius was inherited, as well as that modern Europeans are in greater possession of it than other races. The botanist Candolle (1873), skeptical of Galton’s nature over nurture arguments, agreed that colored races lack men of scientific discovery and that women have not written any original scientific work. The criminologist Lombroso (1905) believed that the giants of the mind may be burdened with mental illness, while the Nobel Prize recipient and chemist Ostwald (1908) heightened the appreciation of scientists in suggesting that scientific innovators are the most important class of human beings, contributing to epistemic and social grandiosity and not to modesty. In a largely forgotten, systematic book on the psychology of science, Hiebsch (1977) suggested that the subdiscipline studies creative thinking, the ways in which the personality of the problem-solving individual conditions cognitive activity, and how creative thinking and the creation of knowledge can be advanced through working in teams. For instance, Wertheimer (1945) analyzed productive thinking by looking at the thought processes of Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) and Albert Einstein (1879-1955), and how these thought processes led to the beginning of modern physics and the development of the theory of relativity. Guilford (1950) in his Presidential Address expressed the importance of the discovery and development of creative talent, since creativity by scientists and engineers had economic value. Yet, attempts to improve the practice of science have not involved psychologists, but authorities in business and management. The case for a psychology of science was made by Müller-Freienfels (1936), who argued that epistemologies produced abstract systems that ignore living human beings that produce knowledge. In contrast, the philosopher of science Popper (1972) famously banned the psychology of science from epistemology and pleaded for an epistemology without a knowing subject. Yet, Fleck (1979/1935) incorporated with his concepts of thought style and thought collective a social psychology into his understanding of science. Kuhn (1962) can be understood as including within a psychology of science the idea that the inability to find a solution challenges the researcher and not the theory, that students accept theories because of the authority of a teacher, or that most scientists perform normal science. Psychological ideas as core to the study of science have been endorsed by historians of science. For instance, Holton (1973) moved the argument into the direction of psychology by arguing that thematic decisions by individuals are more important than paradigms, and that such commitments emerge from the personality of the individual, rather than from the environment or community of the researcher. A thema, just like in music, is something that may be repeated and may recur throughout a scientific career. Even Feyerabend (1975) employed psychological insights in his anarchistic epistemology, by pointing to the obedience of researchers and the role of money and emotional support in the work of scientists. The question regarding the age at which scientists reach their peak is of psychological interest as well. Albert Einstein, Werner Heisenberg (1901-1976), or Paul Dirac (1902-1984) experienced their peak before the age of 30, and it appears that physicists at that time lost their creativity after the age of 35; chemists reached their peak at 40; and philosophers can improve into their 60’s (Oser, 1988). More recently, the works of Simonton (1988) or Feist (2006) fall under the umbrella of traditional psychology of science. My critique suggests that most of the traditional psychology of science works do not put subjectivity in its nexus at the center. Even some critically-oriented approaches ignore that nexus. Freud (1977) argued that the sublimation of sexual desires is also responsible for the highest cultural, artistic, and social achievements of humanity. More challenging for the mainstream is Devereux (1967), who connected anxiety and methods in the human sciences, and argued that the experiment in psychology is as much an experiment on the experimenter as it is on the participant. The anxieties and defense mechanisms of the researcher, research strategies, and the collection and interpretation of data disclose more about the nature of human behavior than the seemingly objective observation of rats or other human beings. There exists also an important tradition in feminist philosophy of science that points to the gendered psychological dimensions of science. The choice for quantification, the analyses of variables, and the preference for abstract conceptualizations may represent a masculine attitude towards problems (Code, 1993; Harding, 1986; Keller, 1985). A critical psychology of science that embraces subjectivity needs a theory that encompasses the social (socio-subjectivity: culture, society, history, etc.), the interpersonal (inter-subjectivity: groups, peers, organizations, teachers, etc.), and personal dimensions (intra-subjectivity: mind and embodied practices, thinking, feeling, and motivation) in their nexus and in connection with the material worlds. In short, epistemic subjectivity requires the first-person standpoint of researchers in its interconnection with social reality (see also Schraube, 2013; Teo, 2017). For instance, a psychology of science needs to explain why researchers, using scientific methods and standards, have endorsed ideas and “knowledge” that turned out to be false and even violent (e.g., scientific racism, sexism, classism). Is this ideological knowledge the result of personality, cognitive mistakes, or group dynamics? If ideological knowledge were just a matter of personality or cognition, then it would be easy to overturn or combat it. But this type of knowledge has a long shelf-life because it represents historically constituted prejudices that have been materialized in social practices and then corroborated by the existing scheme of hypotheses testing (e.g., group differences; see Teo 2008). I submit that the exclusive focus on traditional psychological topics in research prevents an understanding of ideology, hidden assumptions, and taken-for-granted theories, and requires a theoretical shift from personality to a historical, cultural, and societal concept of subjectivity, a concept that includes interaction with peers and colleagues, but does not neglect unique personal characteristics. Such a concept also includes an analysis of the scientific habitus (Bourdieu, 1988), the embodiment of scientific activities, and the privilege to speak on behalf of truth (see Teo, 2016). Research in the human sciences that fortifies existing privileges cannot be sufficiently understood by focusing on the individual, cognition, or even groups. The concept of subjectivity (in its broad meaning) is able to more adequately capture the problem, and its anchoring in the psychological humanities allows for critical analyses that include the socio-and historical constitution of mental life, while not neglecting individual commitments and idiosyncrasies. Changing epistemic virtues and values express a culture and an individual commitment. New Idols The statement “the more one knows, the more one knows what one does not know” is a play on Socrates and should have consequences for a study of epistemic values. There is an inherent conflict between epistemic modesty, engendered by such sayings, and the need to present oneself as part of the epistemic elite or as one of the grandiose minds of knowledge (especially when one has expert knowledge). The point is not that the system of knowledge deserves no recognition, because it does. Rather, the reality is that the individual scientist can accommodate only a tiny part of any system of knowledge, even within one discipline such as psychology. Scientists are not exempt from cognitive issues and emotional attachments (see also Osbeck, Nersessian, Malone, & Newstetter, 2011). Like all humans, they must deal with realities that emerge in the cultural intersection of socio-, inter-, and intra-subjectivity. In the following, the new idols of research, and the consequences of a neoliberal academia and a post-truth society, as they impact epistemic subjectivity and modesty, are discussed. Epistemic grandiosity encourages and is nourished by various idols that make epistemic modesty a difficult proposition. The first set could be called, (a) “idols of the narcissistic halo,” for which celebrities are known (and are used in advertising), but which also touches academic subjectivity. This concept refers to the tendency for scientists who are recognized experts in one area to appear or present themselves as competent in other knowledge areas as well. Scientists afflicted with this condition bank on their accumulated cognitive capital to convince the public and other audiences about their all-around knowledge capabilities. This tendency may be nourished by the status of scientific methods, which, certainly, do not make the scientist an automatic expert in all knowledge content areas. Doubt and critique, modesty and humility, are abandoned for one’s own thoughts and statements, partial knowledge, rhetoric and exaggerations, which in turn reinforce notoriety in the public. As examples, natural scientists and economists come to mind who claim to possess expertise about gender differences; or, one can consider William Shockley (1910-1989), the Nobel prize winner in physics in 1956, and his epistemic support for a political, scientific racism (see Tucker, 1994). The second set, (b) “idols of ideology,” refers to a process where experts in one area do not challenge their assumptions as experts but rather justify the status quo by providing scientific discourses. In the context of scientific racism, an example would be an expert who misunderstands the history of racism, and the power of the interpretation of results, while neglecting disconfirming evidence. In political economy, where this phenomenon was first observed (Marx, 1867/1962), this refers to the propagation of the sources of the constitution of wealth and the degree to which one’s theoretical preference is embedded within one’s own interest or the interest of the powerful (or see Graeber, 2011, for a more recent example about the origins of debt). This subjectivity is unaware of the assumptions or underlying motives that lead to the promotion of certain knowledges that are used to justify the status quo as natural and inevitable. Although a description can be wrong, it is presented as normative. A recent political example from psychology is the defense of torture, when psychologists’ presence in enhanced interrogations was interpreted as the absence of torture per se and provided the justification for the continuation of enhanced interrogations (Aalbers & Teo, 2017). The third set, (c) “idols of bullshit” (see Frankfurt, 1986/2005), is exemplified by scientists and psychologists in the service of the tobacco industry. These scientists (including psychologists) were bullshitters, in the sense that arguments such as “correlation does not mean causation,” “nothing has ever been proven definitively,” “we have to understand the times,” and so on, misrepresented what actually went on without being false (see also Oreskes & Conway, 2010). The argument that large-scale epidemiological studies do not demonstrate causality in a psychological sense is correct, but it assumes that a psychological understanding of causality (which is different from the understanding of causality in physics) is superior to the one in epidemiology. Another example of this idol would be the concept of heritability. Scientists often suggest, erroneously, that this concept denotes the degree to which an individual has inherited a trait, when in reality it is a population statistic. Bullshiters exaggerate, they present something locally as being true around the world, and they provide misleading statements that appeal to a parochial common sense, all while knowing that they are not doing justice to the complexity of the problem. They pick and choose, ignore disconfirming evidence, take things out of context deliberately, and do all this with a sense of epistemic grandiosity. Sometimes the idols of bullshit cannot be distinguished from the fourth set, (d) “idols of ignorance,” especially when the bullshitter starts to believe that what they are promoting is true, and when bullshit morphs into “truth.” However, this process is neither apolitical nor benign. The production of ignorance is sociopolitical and benefits existing power structures and economic interests. Proctor and Schiebinger (2008) focus on the cultural production of ignorance with scientists having a part in this production. Psychology, for instance, produces ignorance when focusing on the individual and excluding social conditions. The idea that all change begins with individuals, or the focus on individuals, ignores research on inequality that identifies the many negative consequences of inequality for the mental health of individuals (Wilkinson & Pickett, 2009). If mental health issues are embedded in inequality, which is a social and structural category, not a psychological category, then it is ignorance-producing to suggest that one can solve mental health issues on an individual, psychological level. Of course, this finding requires modesty as well. The vicissitude of epistemic modesty We are all ignorant on certain issues at various times and the personal limitations of knowledge should logically lead to modesty and not to grandiosity. Even if we try to overcome personal knowledge deficiencies, our knowledge deficit will always be larger than our knowledge surplus. Epistemic modesty is the consequence of acknowledging subjectivity, culture, history, and society in knowledge-making and -dissemination, especially in the human sciences. Some of the same figures that lacked humility also advocated for modesty (see also Grenberg, 2005). In my argument, epistemic modesty means to be aware of one’s own horizon, the strengths and limitations of one’s own approach, while being knowledgeable beyond one’s own expertise on the history, sociality, and culturality of knowledge. Modesty means having an awareness of one’s own accomplishments without assuming the superiority of one’s own knowledge or taking on a paternalistic attitude towards the other. Modesty, which is based on self-understanding and self-respect (Grenberg, 2005), means being careful about the old and new idols of research. Modesty does not imply relativism, that anything goes, or that one is weak, inferior, self-degrading or self-contemptuous. Modesty does not mean rejecting one’s own knowledge competencies. Rather, modesty refers to a realistic assessment of the possibilities and limitations of “my” knowledge, while neither overestimating nor underestimating these possibilities or limitations. Epistemic modesty is a historical outcome of all the research that has accumulated over the centuries, in different countries, with different groups. In psychological practice, it has been acknowledged that an epistemologically humble clinical approach may be better received by patients (Fowers, 2005; Hersch, 2006). The question emerges as to why scientists have not developed more epistemic modesty. Why do many scientists prefer grandiosity? It should be clear, based on my short description of subjectivity, that virtues or idols cannot be understood without the larger context, and without moving from the internal to the external logic of research. There are reasons why epistemic grandiosity thrives and epistemic modesty starves. The analysis of an epistemic virtue as being endorsed by an individual or as the result of a philosophical argument is insufficient, if one does not take the larger societal context into account. There are at least two important societal factors that counteract epistemic modesty: the neoliberal transformation of societies in recent decades and the emergence of a post-truth cultural reality. The neoliberal transformation of society involves the privatization, individualization, and marketization of common goods (Harvey, 2005), with enormous consequences for the subject’s conduct of everyday life. Neoliberalism denotes materially a political-economic alteration that has taken place since the 1980s, and ideologically to a thought system that emphasizes the self and family in the market place to the degree that a homo neoliberalus has emerged (Teo, 2018b). At the psychological level, neoliberalism means the psychologization, responsibilization, and subjectification of persons. At the institutional level, it means that all public entities are affected by a transformation, universities and colleges included, that demands that they be managed like businesses. A neoliberal academia (see e.g., Smyth, 2017) means that unsuccessful departments or programs are closed, whereby success is defined by financial outcomes and not by the quality of work. The number of administrators is increased to supervise faculty, and likewise the number of performance evaluations are increased for everyone in the name of accountability. A neoliberal academia entails for-profit calculations, academic output that is compared and ranked in contrast to other universities, salaries based on external performance criteria, and the devaluation of academic service work that does not involve money. At the same time, the same service work by administrators is lauded as managerial. Entrepreneurship is celebrated, precarious work for students and part-time faculty is more prevalent, and critically oriented humanities are increasingly devalued if they do not produce something that can be sold. What does a neoliberal university do to academic subjectivity, and what values are thereby promoted? Certainly not promoted is the value of epistemic modesty, which conflicts in significant ways with a neoliberal academia, where advertising, selling, and the impact of one’s research are measured and used as benchmarks for status, success and promotion. Academic subjectivity needs to exaggerate and focus on the impact of one’s research and promote oneself. Epistemic modesty is superseded by an entrepreneurial self that needs to look constantly at citations and impact. One can even ask to what degree fraudulent work in academia can be understood on the background of neoliberalism. Faculty need to market their research, and if not marketable, move to new products that promise grants and higher impact. The work of the world-renown expert on medieval history (with a limited number citations due to the small community) does not count as much as the normal science of the neuroscientist who produces average citations in their field. Incommensurability of research has been reduced to quantifiable measures. In short, neoliberal academia does not provide forms for the embodiment of modesty, and rather promotes an innovative self that is in the business of marketing all accomplishments, to the point where epistemic grandiosity appears as a natural outcome. The second cultural context that counteracts epistemic modesty is the post-truth society (see McIntyre, 2018). Intellectuals who share a scepticism towards a Truth concept with a capital T – a stream of argument one can find not only in postmodern theory, but also in German Idealism and in Popper’s (1935/1992) critical rationalism, – find themselves forced to defend the practice of science, the concepts of truth and evidence, as well as better and worse knowledge, all within a context where truth has lost its meaning, and opinions and feelings have the same status as careful knowledge and well-developed, systematic thought. In the public, this means defending scientific truth as a benchmark against which other claims can be measured. Although the scientist understands the degree to which knowledge is provisional, the public demands authoritative statements, especially when the opponents of scientific truth promote their claims in absolute terms. Epistemic schemes that require the public to buy-in, and for emotional or financial reasons are distributed widely, cannot be overcome through reason, especially when a scheme seems to provide tangible emotional advantages or privileges. In this context, the modest knower, defending distinctions between better and worse interpretations, applications, and knowledge, and perhaps even relevant and irrelevant questions, will always lose against the apodictic claimant who announces truth with grandiosity. Although epistemic modesty emerges from the logic of research, a post-truth cultural reality urges academics to advocate for the authority of science, and the grandiosity of scientists (which is confused with the possible grandeur of science), which itself is a move that some of the critically-oriented sciences must problematize as a political move. The selling of science, itself a new value, needs to learn from entrepreneurship, and modesty or generalizability are not the foremost concerns of business (see also Horkheimer & Adorno, 1947/1982). Sometimes the movement against modesty is supported by unique disciplinary constellations. For example, in psychology, the low disciplinary ranking, the lack of a clear foundation, the fear of not being recognized or taken seriously as a real science, and the clash and confusion with pop-psychology, have all led to an inferiority complex (if one were to remain in the language of psychology). Moreover, such developments have made it difficult for psychology, or psychologists, to promote epistemic modesty. Historically and empirically, we find that psychologists have needed to exaggerate the scientific status of psychology, its comparability to physics and other STEM sciences, and its knowledge claims as a discipline and practice (Teo, 2018). Within such a backdrop, any call for modesty will likely fall on deaf ears. In contrast, the argument I am putting forth here is that a psychology of science needs to include political economy and culture when talking about epistemic virtues. Yet, this does not mean that we cannot address the subject. “I” can realize that “my” epistemic traditions are not the only traditions “I” should rely on, and epistemic modesty remains a value that “I” can choose, despite the realities of academia and culture. To do so will have more negative than positive consequences in the current academic landscape, and may require a subjectivity that embraces courage, a classical virtue (courage is not emphasized in academia either). On an analytical scale, however, the endorsement of virtues must be understood on the background of the dialectics of subjectivity and society. Conclusion Focusing on one aspect of human subjectivity, namely epistemic virtues and values, demonstrates that the academic cannot be subtracted from the world. Yet, a theory of subjectivity also shows that academic subjects have agency inside and outside of their discipline, as narrow as this agency may be. Agency can take on different forms in different disciplines. I suggest that an analysis of epistemic modesty / grandiosity needs to be combined with the critical interests of the psychological humanities. This analysis may reach from when the subject of knowledge is demystified as a universal master-mind who is uninfluenced by extrinsic sources and immune to shortcuts in thinking and doing, to personal reflexivity and interference. From a philosophical point of view, epistemic honesty requires the laying open of the sources of the limitations of knowledge, even when it is politically disadvantageous to do so, and even when it reinforces an attack on academia. Modesty does not entail the seeking only of a narrow-minded expertise beyond which one cannot contribute to the public debate. Yet, critical modesty demands that expertise is augmented with critical thinking, thinking that refuses to just follow a neo-liberal agenda, and that reflects on the assumptions, strengths and weaknesses of science. Emphasizing reflexivity and interference as sources of strength for the sciences is something that critical modesty requires. Such critical reflection does not necessarily provide the assurance for a better science, but rather supports the conditions for its possibility. History has always had a special status in the study of science, and it must also hold such status in psychology, when one traces the history of epistemic subjectivity. A psychology of science identifies how subjectivity has changed over time and how it shapes current research practices. Such a new psychology of science should not be developed in order to denounce science, but rather in order to identify its relevance for addressing current problems, as well as to re-conceptualize problems and apparent solutions that have often hindered truthful action in the world. Psychologists of science, colleagues, and students of psychology should remain careful about researchers whose primary interest is producing, marketing, and selling a product, and who use neoliberal self-promotion to increase shares in the market place. Beyond reflexivity, epistemic modesty requires interference not only in one’s own epistemic shortcomings, which necessitates a constant improvement in terms of the processes and contents of knowledge, but also in terms of knowledge claims that others are making. If those claims are problematic from an epistemo-ethical perspective, then academic and public interrogations are required. The move from the ivory tower to recommendations for practice needs to reflect upon the concept of applicability, which needs to be challenged if it only means support for systems of power and financial interests. In this process, it is important that modesty does not become its opposite, the grandiosity of critique. Critique itself needs to remain modest if it seeks to do justice to its meaning, an equally difficult challenge in a neoliberal, post-truth context. References Aalbers, D., & Teo, T. (2017). The American Psychological Association and the torture complex: A phenomenology of the banality and workings of bureaucracy. Journal für Psychologie, 25(1), 179-204. Bacon, F. (1965). A selection of his works (ed. by S. Warhaft). Toronto, ON, Canada: Macmillan. Bhatia, S. (2018). Decolonizing psychology: Globalization, social justice, and Indian youth identities. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Bourdieu, P. (1988). Homo academicus (P. Collier, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Candolle, A. d. (1873). Histoire des sciences et des savants depuis deux siècles: Suivie d'autres études sur des sujets scientifiques, en particulier sur la sélection dans l'espèce humaine. Genève: Georg. Chakrabarty, D. (2000). Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial thought and historical difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Code, L. (1993). Taking subjectivity into account. In L. Alcoff & E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist epistemologies (pp. 15-48). New York: Routledge. Daston, L., & Galison, P. (2007). Objectivity. New York, NY: Zone. Devereux, G. (1967). From anxiety to method in the behavioral sciences. New York: Humanities Press. Feist, G. J. (2006). The psychology of science and the origins of the scientific mind. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method: Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. London: New Left Books. Fine, G. (2008). Does Socrates claim to know that he knows nothing? Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 35, 49-85. Fleck, L. (1979). The genesis and development of a scientific fact. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1935) Fowers, B. J. (2005). Virtue and psychology: Pursuing excellence in ordinary practices. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Frankfurt, H. G. (2005). On bullshit. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1986) Freud, S. (1977). Vorlesungen zur Einführung in die Psychoanalyse. Frankfurt / Main: Fischer. Galton, F. (1962). Hereditary genius: An inquiry into its laws and consequences. Cleveland, OH: World. (Original work published 1869) Graeber, D. (2011). Debt: The first 5000 years. London: Melville House. Grenberg, J. (2005). Kant and the ethics of humility: A story of dependence, corruption, and virtue. New York: Cambridge University Press. Guilford, J. P. (1950). Creativity. American Psychologist, 5(9), 444-454. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0063487 Harding, S. (1986). The science question in feminism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2-3), 61-83. doi:10.1017/S0140525X0999152X Hersch, E. L. (2006). Philosophically-informed psychotherapy and the concept of transference. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 26(1-2), 221-234. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091276 Hiebsch, H. (1977). Wissenschaftspsychologie: Psychologische Fragen der Wissenschaftsorganisation. Berlin: Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften. Holton, G. (1973). Thematic origins of scientific thought: Kepler to Einstein. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Horkheimer, M., & Adorno, T. W. (1982). Dialectic of enlightenment. New York, NY: Continuum. (Original work published 1947) Jackson, J. P., & Weidman, N. M. (2004). Race, racism, and science: Social impact and interaction. Santa Barbara, CA: Abc-Clio. Keller, E. F. (1985). Reflections on gender and science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Kim, U., Yang, K.-S., & Hwang, K.-K. (2006). Indigenous and cultural psychology: Understanding people in context. New York: Springer. Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lombroso, C. (1905). The man of genius (2d. ed.). London: W. Scott. Marx, K. (1962). Das Kapital: Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (Erster Band) (Marx Engels Werke Band 23) [Capital: Critique of political economy (Volume I) (Marx Engels Works: Volume 23)]. Berlin: Dietz. (Original work published 1867) McIntyre, L. (2018). Post-truth. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Müller-Freienfels, R. (1936). Psychologie der Wissenschaft. Leipzig: Barth. Oeser, E. (1988). Das Abenteuer der kollektiven Vernunft. Evolution und Involution der Wissenschaft. Berlin: Parey. Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of doubt: How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. New York: Bloomsbury Press. Osbeck, L. M., Nersessian, N. J., Malone, K. R., & Newstetter, W. C. (2011). Science as psychology: Sense-making and identity in science practice. New York: Cambridge University Press. Ostwald, W. (1908). Erfinder und Entdecker. Frankfurt am Main: Rütten & Loening. Plato. (1997). Complete works (edited, with introduction and notes by J. M. Cooper; associate editor, D.S. Hutchinson). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Popper, K. R. (1992). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Routledge. (Original work published in 1935) Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Proctor, R. N., & Schiebinger, L. (Eds.). (2008). Agnotology: The making and unmaking of ignorance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction: An analysis of the foundations and the structure of knowledge. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Schraube, E. (2013). First-person perspective and sociomaterial decentering: Studying technology from the standpoint of the subject. Subjectivity, 6(1), 12-32. doi:10.1057/sub.2012.28 Simonton, D. K. (1988). Scientific genius: A psychology of science. New York: Cambridge University Press. Smyth, J. (2017). The toxic university: Zombie leadership, academic rock stars and neoliberal ideology. London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Spivak, G. C. (1999). A critique of postcolonial reason: Toward a history of the vanishing present. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Teo, T. (2008). From speculation to epistemological violence in psychology: A critical-hermeneutic reconstruction. Theory & Psychology, 18(1), 47-67. doi:10.1177/0959354307086922 Teo, T. (2016). Embodying the conduct of everyday life: From subjective reasons to privilege. In E. Schraube & Ch. Hojholt (Eds.), Psychology and the conduct of everyday life (pp.111-123). London: Routledge. Teo, T. (2017). From psychological science to the psychological humanities: Building a general theory of subjectivity. Review of General Psychology, 21(4), 281-291. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/gpr0000132 Teo, T. (2018a). Outline of theoretical psychology: Critical investigations. London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. Teo, T. (2018b). Homo neoliberalus: From personality to forms of subjectivity. Theory & Psychology, 28(5), 581-599. doi:10.1177/0959354318794899 Tucker, W. H. (1994). The science and politics of racial research. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Wertheimer, M. (1945). Productive thinking. New York: Harper. Wilkinson, R. G., & Pickett, K. (2009). The spirit level: Why more equal societies almost always do better. London: Allen Lane.