http://revistas.userena.cl/index.php/logos/index
Issn Impreso: 0716- 7520
Issn Electrónico: 0719-3262
Artículo de Investigación
First Person and Body Ownership
La Primera Persona y Posesión Corporal
Recibido: Marzo 2019 Aceptado: Septiembre 2019 Publicado: Noviembre 2019
Sebastián Sanhueza Rodríguez
Universidad de Concepción, Chile
sebastian.rodriguez.10@ucl.ac.uk
Abstract: Bodily and mental self-ascriptions are forms of first-person thought
where a subject attributes physical properties and psychological states to herself.
The body-ownership view argues that a necessary and sufficient condition on such
self-ascriptions is the existence of causal links between a spatio-temporal body and
the self-ascribed properties or states. However, since P.F. Strawson’s influential
attack, this view has been dismissed as a bad philosophical idea. The goal of this
brief piece is to outline the body-ownership view and neutralise two classic lines
of objection against it: on the one hand, that the stance is incoherent; and, on the
other, that it has counterintuitive implications.
Keywords: first-person thought - body-ownership - causal links - P.F. Strawson Animalism
Citación: Sanhueza Rodríguez, S. (2019). First Person and Body Ownership. Logos: Revista de
Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura, 29(2), 230-237. DOI: 10.15443/RL2919
Dirección Postal: Departamento de Filosofía, Universidad de Concepción, Beltrán Mathieu #15-A,
Barrio Universitario, Concepción, Chile
DOI: doi.org/10.15443/RL2919
Este trabajo se encuentra bajo la licencia Creative Commons Attribution 3.0.
First Person and Body Ownership
Resumen: Las auto-atribuciones corporales y mentales son formas de pensamiento
en primera persona donde un sujeto se atribuye propiedades físicas y estados
psicológicos a sí mismo. La teoría de posesión corporal sostiene que una condición
necesaria y suficiente de tales auto-atribuciones es la existencia de conexiones
causales entre un cuerpo espacio-temporal y las propiedades o estados autoatribuidos. Sin embargo, desde el influyente ataque de P.F. Strawson a esta teoría,
ella ha sido descartada como una mala idea filosófica. El objetivo de este breve
artículo es delinear la teoría de posesión corporal y neutralizar dos líneas clásicas
de crítica contra ella: por una parte, una según la cual la teoría es internamente
incoherente; y, por otra, una según la cual ella tiene implicancias contraintuitivas.
Palabras clave: pensamientos de primera persona - posesión corporal - nexos causales - P.F. Strawson - Animalismo
1. Introduction
Bodily and mental self-ascriptions are forms of first-person thought where a person attributes
physical properties and psychological states to herself. On one account of self-ascriptions,
known as the no-ownership or body-ownership view, a necessary and sufficient condition for
the possibility of this form of first-person thought and its resulting reports, is the existence
of causal links between a spatio-temporal body and the self-ascribed properties or states (cf.
Strawson, 1959; Ayer, 1963; Foster, 1979). Although this account promises to solve problems
regarding the synchronic and diachronic identity of persons in terms of the synchronic and
diachronic identity of spatio-temporal bodies, it was also the target of an influential critique
in P.F. Strawson’s Individuals. I’m not sure whether the body-ownership view—from now on,
(BOV)—is correct. But I do think it was dismissed way too swiftly. Again, this account of selfascription fits well with currently popular animalist views of personal identity (cf. Olson, 1999,
2007; Snowdon, 2014; Blatti & Snowdon, 2016). As such, the goal of this modest piece is to
articulate (BOV) and partially defend it from classic objections.
The previous task is divided into three sections. First, I formulate what I take to be (BOV)’s
crucial positive claim. Next, I turn to two classic objections. On the one hand, I assess whether
Strawson is right in claiming that (BOV) is incoherent. Then, I examine whether (BOV) opens the
door to counterintuitive possibilities such as those of subjectless and transferable experiences.
2. Stating the Body-Ownership View
(BOV) primarily accounts for bodily and mental self-ascriptions: that is, it aims to capture the
conditions of possibility of the ways in which we think about ourselves, as opposed to the ways
in which we think of or ascribe things to other items. As previously anticipated, this view also
says something about the concept of a person, for (at least in the Anglo-American philosophical
landscape) the latter is often understood as that of a subject capable of self-ascribing actions,
intentions, sensations, thoughts, feelings, spatial location, among other (propositional or nonpropositional) attitudes (cf. Strawson, 1959, 1966; Ayer, 1963). To focus the present discussion,
however, this piece will be mainly concerned with what (BOV) has to say about self-ascriptions.
Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 29(2)
231
Artículo de Investigación
Again, for the sake of simplicity, I shall assume that there is a one-to-one correlation between
propositional thoughts and the statements that express them, whereby bodily and mental selfascriptions may refer here either to ‘I’-thought or to ‘I’-sentences.
(BOV)’s core claim could be characterized in terms of two claims:
(1) Self-ascriptions explanatorily depend on a causal relation between self-ascribed properties/states
and a spatio-temporal body.
(2) (1) is contingent.
As I try to show throughout this piece, most problems surrounding (BOV) spring from
difficulties in understanding the precise way in which (2) qualifies (1). The meaning of (1) is
comparatively less controversial. Strawson formulates it as follows:
The ‘no-ownership’ theorist may be presumed to start his explanation with facts of the sort which
illustrate the unique causal position of a certain material body in a person’s experience. The theorist
maintains that the uniqueness of this body is sufficient to give rise to the idea that one’s experiences
can be ascribed to some particular, individual thing, can be said to be possessed by, or owned by, that
thing (Strawson, 1959, p. 95).
Meanwhile, A.J. Ayer described (1) as the idea ‘that personal identity depends upon the identity
of the body, and that a person’s ownership of states of consciousness consists in their standing
in a special causal relation to the body by which he is identified.’ (Ayer, 1963,pp. 116-117) The
general thought seems to be that bodily and mental self-ascriptions are possible if and only if a
given spatio-temporal body A is causally related to the self-ascribed features.
By contrast, (2) is far more problematic at least for two reasons. (a) Since there are several types
of modality—e.g. logical, metaphysical, nomological, epistemic—it is unclear what specific type
of contingency (2) refers to. (b) It is unclear what the contingency of (1) would specifically
amount to. To say that (1) is contingent is to say that, even if (1) is true as a matter of fact, it
could be false—in other words, even if (1) is true in the actual world, there are possible worlds
in which (1) would not be true. The problem at hand is that, since there are in principle different
ways in which (1) could fail being the case, it is unclear which of those ways (2) allows for.
Regarding (a), I suspect that Strawson takes (2) merely to attribute metaphysical contingency
to (1) insofar as his account of persons and self-ascription is part of an essay on descriptive
metaphysics. Furthermore, he doesn’t say anything that contradicts the idea that the relevant
modal qualification should be a metaphysical one. Ayer, on the other hand, seems to have
something else in mind. After stating (1), he qualifies it by saying that: ‘I am not maintaining, of
course, that this is how one actually becomes aware of one’s own experiences, but only that the
fact that they are one’s own, or rather the fact that they are the experiences of the person that
one is, depends upon their being connected with this particular body.’ (Ayer, 1963, p. 116; also
cf. 124) The underpinning thought here is, I believe, that (1) is epistemologically—rather than
metaphysically—contingent: it would be possible to have knowledge of a given self-ascription
token without having knowledge of the causal link between the spatio-temporal body and the
self-ascribed features on which such a token relies. Bearing both readings of (2) in mind, it
turns out that (BOV) could actually be described as the conjunction of (1) and either one of the
following two claims:
(2e) (1) is epistemically contingent;
(2m) (1) is metaphysically contingent.
If (2) splits into (2e) and (2m), so does the problem referred to in (b): on the one hand, there
is a problem of understanding what the claim that (1) is epistemically contingent, specifically
amounts to; and , on the other, there is one of understanding what the claim that (1) is
Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 29(2)
232
First Person and Body Ownership
metaphysically contingent, specifically amounts to. In the remainder of this section, I pause on
both issues.
By endorsing (2e), (BOV) would endorse (1), but simultaneously reject that, in order to perform
a given bodily or mental self-ascription, a person must become aware of a causal link between
those experiences and the spatio-temporal object which happens to be her own body. That is,
by endorsing (2e), (BOV) would commit to the following claim: for a subject S, undergoing a
psychological state s without there being a causal link between s and S’s body b is not ruled
out by what S knows. (2e)’s rationale seems to be the need for limiting the explanatory scope
of an account of self-ascriptions such as (BOV). That is, the thought seems to be that, even if
the nature of the logical subject and the logical predicate of self-ascriptive statements specified
what the first-person pronoun refers to in such statements and what kind of subject such a
referent is, it would not follow that bodily and mental self-ascriptions logically entail which
particular subject perform such utterances. In other words, the logical and semantic properties
of these statements would not settle in and by themselves the question which specific individual
these self-ascriptions refer to. (2e) epistemic limitation on (1)’s explanatory scope, in the sense
that it would reject the assumption that the identification of the specific spatio-temporal body
that bodily and mental self-ascriptions refer to is a condition of possibility of self-ascriptions.
(2e)’s epistemic limitation to (1) could perhaps be better understood with the help of two ideas:
on the one hand, the idea that one could draw a distinction between three different (albeit
closely related) questions concerning bodily and mental self-ascriptions; and, on the other, the
idea that an account of bodily and mental self-ascription such as (BOV) has to answer the first
and the second, but not the third question. The three questions at stake are: (i) whether the
first-person pronoun of a self-ascriptive ‘I’-statement refers to something; (ii), if it does, what
kind of thing it refers to; and (iii), which particular individual of the aforementioned kind it
refers to. If we give a negative answer to (i), then (ii) and (iii) don’t take off. Such a stance
is unpopular, though (Anscombe 1975 is an emblematic exception). As such, I shall assume
that the first-person pronoun involved in self-ascriptions has a reference, and hence, that (ii)
and (iii) do get going. (ii) is the kind of question which an understanding of self-ascriptive ‘I’thoughts or ‘I’-sentences is supposed to solve, at least by a philosophical mainstream according
to which the question what kinds of entities the first-person pronoun of self-ascriptions refer
to is to some extent settled by the kind of self-ascribed properties and states. For instance, a
number of Oxford philosophers have stressed that an important component of the antidote
against a Cartesian view of persons consists in realizing that such entities ascribe to themselves
physical no less than mental predicates (cf. Evans, 1982; Martin, 1995; Brewer, 1995). Now,
the point of (2e) would be that, unlike (i) and (ii), (iii) is not the kind of question that (BOV)
should be required to answer. This wouldn’t constitute an objection to (1), but only a modest
acknowledgement of its explanatory scope. From our self-ascriptive performances, we could
only read off whether the subjects of ‘I’-statements refer to something and the kind of items
they refer to: a subject would not be supposed to be capable of reading off an answer to (iii) from
such utterances. The classic thought experiment of the amnesiac subject in a dark tank would be
a case in point of someone who could answer (i) and (ii), but not (iii).
Turning now to (2m)—that is, the claim that (1) is metaphysically contingent—recall that
even if it was clear that (BOV) should be understood as endorsing (2)’s metaphysical version,
it would still be unclear what such a claim specifically amounted to. The gist of (2) seems to be
something like this: (1), the claim that a particular spatio-temporal body is causally related to a
physical property or a psychological state, is a metaphysically contingent one. That is, although
a particular body could in fact be causally related to those features, there are possible worlds
metaphysically accessible to ours in which that claim is false. Thus stated, there seems to be
nothing especially controversial about (2m). As I previously mentioned, however, things are
a bit more delicate, for, when we say that a given claim could be false, we have not said yet
what could be the case. In short, to say that p could be false is just to say not-p: it is not yet to
say that q, r, or s, are the case. The claim that a marble sphere is not black doesn’t decide what
colour the marble sphere actually is; for all that, it might be white, green, blue, etc. Likewise,
Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 29(2)
233
Artículo de Investigación
from the claim that (1) could be false, it does not follow what could alternatively be the case.
This point seems crucial to me, for, according to one popular line of reasoning against (BOV),
if (1) is metaphysically contingent, some unpalatable metaphysical possibilities loom. Section
III will elaborate on this line of objection. For the time being, it is important to stress this:
by holding that (1) is contingent, (BOV) does not specify what metaphysical possibilities it
allows for; in other words, (2m) does not seem to determine in and by itself what metaphysical
possibilities (BOV) allows for. I hope to show that, whenever it is said that (BOV) allows for a
given (perhaps unpalatable) possibility, such a possibility doesn’t actually rise from, but from
additional metaphysical assumptions.
3. Is the Body-Ownership Internally Incoherent?
In what is left of this piece, I shall assess two well-known types of objections against (BOV): on
the one hand, this view is said to be incoherent for endorsing (2); on the other, it is accused of
entailing unpalatable metaphysical possibilities (e.g. subjectless and transferable experiences).
This section focuses on the first kind: in a nutshell, my reply will draw on Ayer’s 1963 response
to the same kind of worry.
Strawson set forth the famous objection that (BOV) is incoherent because it endorses (2):
in particular, it could not coherently endorse (2) because (1)—that is, the claim that bodily
and mental self-ascriptions are made possible by the causal relatedness between some spatiotemporal body and the self-attributed properties and states—is analytic, and hence (assuming
that it is a true claim) a necessary truth. According to (BOV), the identity of a person depends
on the identity of a spatio-temporal body; persons’ bodily and mental self-ascriptions, in turn,
would depend on spatio-temporal bodies’ ownership of the self-ascribed features. Strawson
thinks that (BOV)’s core claim—that is, (1)—is captured by something like the following slogan:
(P) All my experiences are those which are owned by a spatio-temporal body B.
According to (BOV), he continues, (P) is a contingent proposition which aims to account for the
sense of ownership which distinguishes self-ascriptive from other-ascriptive practices. (P) itself
is problematic, though: by talking of ‘my experiences’, (BOV) reintroduces into the explanans
the notion to be explained. Suppose that the sense of ownership which emerges in (P) was again
rephrased in (BOV)’s terms. This would make of (P) circular, but not ipso facto self-defeating.
What makes it self-defeating is that, by cashing the demanding sense of ownership in terms
of body-ownership, (P) turns out to be equivalent to something like the following proposition:
(Pa) All the experiences owned by a particular spatio-temporal body B are those owned by a particular
spatio-temporal body B.
This proposition is naturally analytic, and hence, fails to satisfy (2). (BOV) could not make use of
another sense of ownership in order to dodge this objection, for this view is precisely driven by
the rejection of other senses of ownership beyond body-ownership. Thus, (BOV) would endorse
(2), the claim that (1) is contingent, when (1) actually fails to be contingent. Contradiction!
In reply, it seems to me that Ayer offers an elegant assessment of how and why the previous
objection is off-key. First, he assumes that (1) is supposed to be contingent and that (P) is partly
analytic; however, he denies that (P) exclusively captures (1). In a slogan, his diagnosis could
be described as follows: although (BOV) implies (P), the latter would not be equivalent to (1),
nor, a fortiori, to what (BOV) claims to be contingent (cf. Ayer 1963, 116-117). Ayer apparently
thinks that (P) should be analyzed into two propositions: on the one hand, (Pa), and, on the
other, the contingent proposition
(Pc) Given a particular bodily state p instantiated by a spatio-temporal body B, a psychological state e
would follow.
Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 29(2)
234
First Person and Body Ownership
In other words, Ayer concedes two things: first, that (BOV) implies (P); and secondly, that
(Pa), which captures part of (P), is analytic. However, he disagrees with Strawson in supposing
that (P), and by extension, (Pa), is what (BOV) claims to be contingent; rather, Ayer thinks
that (2) only qualifies another part of (P) besides (Pa), namely, (Pc): what is contingent is
that, given a physical state p of a spatio-temporal body B, a psychological state e has to follow.
Hence, (Pa) would be analytic but not contingent; (Pc), contingent but not analytic. Hence,
no contradiction. Strawson of course understands (P) in a different way: a given psychological
state, e, is my experience if it is owned by a certain spatio-temporal body B; by claiming that this
is metaphysically contingent, what (BOV) would claim to be contingent is that my experience e
has to be causally related to the body it is actually related to and not some other body.
The issue concerning what (2m) specifically amounts to reemerges here, for Strawson and Ayer
ake (2m) to mean different things: the former, that my experiences could exist detached from
the body they happen to be causally related to—a possibility I term here (S); the latter, that it
is merely contingent that my body caused the experience it actually caused—a possibility here
termed (A). (S) and (A) are different possibilities: indeed, one could be the necessary and the other
merely contingent. It could be merely contingent that a given state of consciousness is realizable
by different bodies or by none at all; and, at the same time, necessary that, given a bodily state p
instantiated in a spatio-temporal body B, a certain psychological state e had to follow. Again, it
might be merely contingent that, given a bodily state p instantiated in a spatio-temporal body
B, a certain psychological state e has to follow; and, at the same time, be necessary that a given
psychological state e has to be realized in one and only one spatio-temporal body. Ayer would
deny that (2) entailed (S), and he tries to explain why Strawson reads off that entailment in
(BOV): Strawson assumes the possibility of identifying one’s own experiences independently
of the identification of the body to which they belong—in other words, he thinks that it is
possible to understand what ‘my experiences’ means with independence of understanding the
causal link between such experiences and my body. The latter assumption, however, would be
ungrounded: Hume to the contrary, (BOV) holds that a subject of experiences could not latch
onto a heap of experiences and take them to be her experiences independently of their causal
relatedness to a spatio-temporal body (cf. Ayer, 1963).
Ayer’s diagnosis seems sound to me, but it might require further support, insofar as the
entailment between (2m) and (S) still needs to be rejected in a principled way. Thus far, it
has only been said that (BOV) would not entail the possibility of unowned or transferable
experiences only if (2m) failed to entail (S): the latter entailment has not actually been rejected
yet. If unowned and transferable experiences were metaphysically possible, it would be unclear
why, as Ayer contends, we should reject the assumption that my experiences could be identified
as mine independently of the body to which they are causally related to. Thus, although different
lines of objection, the charge that (BOV) is incoherent and the charge that it entails strange
metaphysical possibilities seem to complement each other. Accordingly, the corresponding
replies in defense of (BOV) are mutually dependent. That’s why I briefly pause on the second
line of objection next.
4. Is the Body-Ownership View Counterintuitive?
(BOV) also seems unpalatable for some of the apparent metaphysical possibilities it allows for,
such as the possibility of subjectless and transferable experiences. Whether it allows for such
possibilities turns out to be all the more important insofar as Ayer’s reply to the objection from
incoherency seems to depend on it. This section thus focuses on this worry.
John Foster, for instance, objects that (BOV) allows for the possibilities of experiences which
have no subject (cf. Foster 1979, 171). I take the main thought to be something like this: once
it is granted, as (BOV) seems to do, that there is a distinction between mental states and bodily
states, it is logically possible that there were exact duplicates of mental states which were not
causally related to any body, and hence, to any subject at all. Thus, there could be a mental item
which, by definition, is different from a bodily state; insofar as it is not a bodily state, such an
Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 29(2)
235
Artículo de Investigación
item would not necessarily be tied to a body; furthermore, such a mental item would not have
to be defined in terms of a person or a subject of experiences. All this seems to entail that (BOV)
allows for the possibility of subjectless experiences. Another possibility (BOV) apparently allows
for is that of transferable experiences. By rejecting the necessary link between an experience
and a particular body, (BOV) seems to allow for the logical possibility that one temporally
extended experience (say, a burning pain) was owned now by this body, then by another one.
This kind of possibility makes Strawson uncomfortable: he rejects this view, in part, because it
does away with the non-transferable or private character of one’s own experiences.
I suspect that the previous line of objection could be met by contending that the metaphysical
possibility of unowned and transferable experiences does not actually arise if (BOV) denied that
experiences could be individuated apart of the causal links which relate them to bodies. The
‘body-ownership’ theorist could contend that such mental items could not exist apart of their
causal relationship to some body, for that causal relationship individuates the mental item at
stake. This would not be ad hoc: if we take experiences or psychological states in general to be
Davidsonian events or states conceived as property- or relation-instantiations, it would follow
that experiences could not be individuated independently of their corresponding causal links to
the objects in which they occur (cf. Davidson, 1969; Tye, 1996; Bennett & Hacker, 2003).
The previous proposal would preempt the possibility of unowned experiences, for the latter
states would, by definition, lack any causal relation to a (bodily or mental) substance. It would
also cut off the possibility of transferable experiences: unless it was thought that an experience
e could be related to bodies b1 and b2 by means of the exact same causal relation c1, the ‘bodyownership’ theorist could hold that e could not be transferable. Different causal relations,
different experiences: since transference would entail different causal relations, it would also
rule out the transference of one and the same experience e from one body to another. All that
could happen is that an experience e1 of a certain type E—say, of a pain-type—instantiated in
a body b1 would somehow be causally responsible of the emergence of a numerically different
experience e2 of type E in another body b2; however, if the individuation of experiences
does depend on their causal relations to a body, as ex hypothesi (BOV) contends, it would be
impossible that the same experience e1, now related to b1 by means of a causal link c1, was later
related to b2 by means of a causal relation c2.
The previous reply seems plausible as far as things go, but it is important to note how much
is at stake by endorsing it: specifically, it requires rejecting a Humean account of object- or
event-individuation which was independent of the causal relations which bring those objects
or events about. In principle, I do not see any reason to stick to the Humean thesis, but, as
anything in philosophy, actually showing that we shouldn’t do so surely requires harder work
than I’ve put here.
5. Conclusion
To sum up. My goal was to articulate a body-ownership view of mental and bodily self-ascription
and partially defend it from some prominent objections. I divided this task into three sections:
first, I articulated (BOV)’s core claims, namely, (1) and (2); secondly, I discussed Strawson’s famous
objection according to which (BOV) is incoherent for endorsing (2); and thirdly, I focused on
the charge that (BOV) allows for counter-intuitive metaphysical possibilities, such as unowned
and transferable experiences. Both objections are different, but their replies complement each
other. The driving force of this piece is to vindicate an account of self-ascriptions which, in spite
of nicely fitting with currently popular metaphysical accounts of persons, has been dismissed
rather too swiftly. I suspect that (BOV) is germane to physicalist accounts of personal identity,
such as animalism. Since the latter accounts have several theoretical advantages, it seems to be
high times to revisit the prospects of (BOV).
Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 29(2)
236
First Person and Body Ownership
Acknowledgements
For encouragement and helpful comments on this piece, I am indebted to Elena Cagnoli, Rory
Madden, and Paul Snowdon.
References
Anscombe, G.M.E. (1975). The First Person. En D.M. Rosenthal. (Ed.), (1991). The Nature of
Mind (pp. 71-81). New York: Oxford University Press.
Ayer, A.J. (1963). The Concept of a Person and Other Essays. London: Macmillan.
Blatti, S. & Snowdon, P. (Eds.) (2016). Animalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brewer, B. (1995). Bodily Awareness and the Self. En J.L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel & N. Eilan.
(Eds.), The Body and the Self (pp. 291-309). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Davidson, D. (1969). The Individuation of Events. En D. Davidson. (1980). Essays on Actions and
Events (pp. 163-180). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Evans, G. (1982). The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Foster, J. (1979). In Self-Defense. En G.F. Macdonald. (Ed.), Perception and Identity: Essays
presented to A.J. Ayer with his replies to them (pp. 161-185). London: Macmillan.
Bennett, M. & Hacker, P. (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Malden, MA:
Blackwell.
Martin, M.G.F. (1995). Bodily Awareness: A Sense of Ownership. En J.L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel &
N. Eilan. (Eds.), The Body and the Self (pp. 267-289). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Olson, E. (1999). The Human Animal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Olson, E. (2007). What Are We? Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Snowdon, P. (2014). Persons, Animals, Ourselves. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Strawson, P.F. (1959). Individuals. London: Macmillan.
Strawson, P.F. (1966). Self, Mind and Body. En P.F. Strawson. (1974/2008). Freedom and
Resentment, and Other Essays (pp. 186-195). London: Routledge.
Tye, M. (1996). Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 29(2)
237