TRADITIONAL THEORETICAL APPROACHES
IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
David Pataraia
Jus Press
© David Pataraia 2017
All rights reserved.
No reproduction, copy, transmission or translation
of this publication may be made without written permission
First published 2017 by Jus Press
Jus Press is the academic imprint of
Non-entrepreneurial (non-commercial) legal person Jus Press
Library of Congress Control Number: 2017908799
ISBN-13: 978-0-9990865-0-6
ISBN-10: 0-9990865-0-2
Printed in the United States of America
by CreateSpace
Available from Amazon.com,
CreateSpace.com, and other retail outlets
Translated by Giorgi Murghvashvili
Proofreaders: Dr. Trevor Cartledge (Introduction and Chapter I),
Dr. Giorgi Nakashidze (Chapters II, III, IV)
Technical editor: Tamaz Chkhaidze
This book represents the translation of one part of the book:
International Relations: Discipline and Theory / David Pataraia,
published in 2015,
and is a revised English edition
The three most prominent theories in International Relations have long been analyzed and
discussed. These theories represent the three pillars on which the theoretical foundation of this
scientific discipline was built. Of course, theories can be observed and are developed beyond
these three traditions; however, realism, liberalism and idealism retain their honorable position
on the pedestal of the International Relations theory.
II. Thomas Hobbes
1588 – 1679
41
42
“So that in the first place,
I put for a general inclination of all mankind
a perpetual and restless desire of power after power,
that ceaseth only in death...
And from hence it is that kings, whose power is greatest,
turn their endeavours to the assuring it at home by laws,
or abroad by wars: and when that is done,
there succeedeth a new desire;
in some, of fame from new conquest;
in others, of ease and sensual pleasure;
in others, of admiration, or being flattered for
excellence in some art or other ability of the mind.”
Thomas Hobbes 55
Leviathan or the Matter, Form and Power of a Commonwealth, Ecclesiastical and Civil (First published in 1651), draws a fully-fledged picture of
Thomas Hobbes’s view on the political philosophy. This work provides
Hobbes’s complete and complex vision of individual–world–state relations
and draws the finalized model of his epistemological and ontological visions
in this realm.
Thomas Hobbes selected as a title of the book for the word “leviathan”,
which itself was an object of endless scientific discussions in mythological and
theological scientific studies. The only consensus that remains beyond doubt is
the biblical origin of the word, where “leviathan” denotes the image of the
55
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XI, pp. 52-53.
43
immense sea creature.56 Scientific discussions have also been concentrated on
the underlying reasons for selecting “leviathan” to denote a state in his work.
Therefore, scientific research has been duly focused on the analysis of the
multiple perceptions of “leviathan”, definitions provided by him, as well as the
gravure placed on the titular page of the first English publication of the book,
which pictures a gigantic human not a sea creature. The man from the gravure
is not a common individual but a sovereign with a scepter in his hands. The
sovereign himself is being composed of innumerous number of small men. In
his right hand, he holds a sword and crosier in the left hand. The sovereign is
placed behind the mountains, and overlooks a town on the gravure. Down under the right hand of the sovereign, the symbols of secular power for example,
citadel, cannon and crown are placed, while under the left hand the symbols of
ecclesiastical power e.g. church, episcopal cap and synod/ecclesiastical gathering can be observed.
56
“As a symbol of a political entity, the leviathan is, on the other hand, not just any
"corpus” or just any kind of beast. It is an image from the Hebrew Bible, one garbed
during the course of many centuries in mythical, theological and cabbalistic meanings. In the Book of Job, Chapters 40 and 41, it is depicted as the strongest and most
tremendous sea monster. Portrayed in vivid detail beside him is a land animal, the
behemoth.”, “How do the monsters, leviathan and behemoth, relate to each other in
Hobbes' theory? That the leviathan signifies the state and the behemoth represents
revolution has obviously not been derived by Hobbes from mythical speculations. Yet
it is no accident that for the seventeenth-century Englishman the sea animal becomes
the symbol of a peacemaking order, for the leviathan, “the huge whale”, was not an
animal alien to the imagination of the English people. In essence, however, both the
peace-enforcing function of the state and the revolutionary, anarchistic force of the
state of nature are comparable elementary forces. According to Hobbes, the quintessential nature of the state of nature, or the behemoth, is none other than civil war,
which can only be prevented by the overarching might of the state, or the leviathan.”, Carl Schmitt, The Leviathan in the state theory of Thomas Hobbes: meaning
and failure of a political symbol, foreword and introduction by George Schwab; translated by George Schwab and Erna Hilfstein, Greenwood Press, 1996, pp. 6, 21.
Scholars also point to the different appearance of “leviathan” in the Jewish and Christian traditions and the Jewish and Greek bibles.
44
The Gravure on the Title Page of Leviathan
45
Thomas Hobbes himself provides the definition of “leviathan” three times
in the book. First, in the introduction, he writes that “For by art is created that
great “Leviathan” called a “Commonwealth”,57or “State” (in Latin, “Civitas”),
which is but an artificial man; though of greater stature and strength than the
natural, for whose protection and defence it was intended; and in which the
“sovereignty” is an artificial “soul”, as giving life and motion to the whole
body; the “magistrates” and other “officers” of judicature and execution, artificial “joints”; “reward” and “punishment”, by which fastened to the seat of the
sovereignty, every joint and member is moved to perform his duty, are the
“nerves”, that do the same in the body natural; the “wealth” and “riches” of all
the particular members are the “strength”; salus populi, “the people’s safety”,
its “business”; “counsellors”, by whom all things needful for it to know are
suggested unto it, are the “memory”; “equity” and “laws”, an artificial “reason” and “will”; “concord”, “health”; “sedition”, “sickness”; and “civil war”,
“death”. Lastly, the “pacts” and “covenants”, by which the parts of this body
politic were at first made, set together, and united, resemble that “fiat”, or the
“Let us make man”, pronounced by God in the Creation.”58
Accordingly, in the introduction of the book, Thomas Hobbes presents leviathan as a gigantic human, and further (in chapter XVII) also as a mortal
57
Separate attention should be paid to Thomas Hobbes’s selection of the term “Commonwealth” for expressing the essence of a state. This English word signifies a state, a
community, etc. But if we break it up it is comprised of the words common and
wealth, which in itself is indicative of the meaning that the author attaches to a state,
as a virtue/good. Therefore, commonwealth is the first selection in this book for expressing the essence of a state. In its turn, this choice for “Commonwealth” was not
spared of criticism during his era from the supporters of traditional absolute monarchy (the divine and the natural power of kings/Crown) who managed to find the
sources for the “state for the people/popular state” or principles for human equality
within the confines of hobbesian “Commonwealth”. More that, some authors linked
this term with the Latin term – res publica. That is the reason some encouraged Thomas
Hobbes take out the term from the book (e.g. Robert Filmer (1588–1653) in his work –
Observations concerning the Original and Various Forms of Government (1652), as de-
scribed, viz. 1st. Upon Aristotles Politiques. 2d. Mr. Hobbs's Leviathan. 3d. Mr. Milton
against Salmatius. 4th. Hugo Grotius, de Jure Bello. 5th. Mr. Hunton's Treatise of Monarchy, or the Nature of a limited or mixed Monarchy, to which is added the Power of Kings.
With directions for Obedience to Government in Dangerous and Doubtful Times. [Together with:] Patriarcha: or the Natural Power of Kings. Published: London: Printed for
R.R.C. and are to be Sold by Samuel Keble and Daniel Brown [Patriarcha:] Printed for Ric.
Chiswell, Matthew Gillyflower and William Henchman,1680 & 1696).
58 Thomas Hobbes, cited, Introduction, p. 11.
46
god, when he says that “this is the generation of that great “Leviathan”, or rather,
to speak more reverently, of that “mortal god”, to whom we owe, under the “immortal God”, our peace and defence.”59
Finally, in the other part of the book, he identifies additional reasons behind the comparison between a state (governor) and leviathan, when he says
that “Hitherto I have set forth the nature of man, whose pride and other passions have compelled him to submit himself to government; together with the
great power of his governor, whom I compared to Leviathan, taking that comparison out of the two last verses of the one-and-fortieth of Job; where God,
having set forth the great power of Leviathan, calleth him king of the proud.
“There is nothing”, saith he, “on earth to be compared with him. He is made so
as not to be afraid. He seeth every high thing below him; and is king of all the
children of pride.”60
Meanwhile, by linking the provided definitions with each other, we will
be able to detect the underlying motivation for selecting “leviathan” for the
title, as well as the primary image framing the substance of the book. However, additional analysis upon the subject will be provided below.
Setting the task to account on the notion of nature and importance of a
state, the point of reference for Thomas Hobbes, is the bodily realities/characteristics, however, on the other hand, he places and analyzes a human being in this reality; this is the way he selects to apprehend/study the human nature which ultimately presents itself a path leading to his notion of a
state. On this path, he provides the autonomous and systemic description of
many foundational/core notions. For example:
Sense – “Which object worketh on the eyes, ears, and other parts of
man’s body, and by diversity of working produceth diversity of appearances. The original of them all is that which we call sense, (for
there is no conception in a man’s mind which hath not at first, totally
or by parts, been begotten upon the organs of sense). The rest are derived from that original.” 61
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVII, p. 84.
“But because he is mortal, and subject to decay, as all other earthly creatures are; and because there is that in heaven, though not on earth, that he should stand in fear of, and
whose laws he ought to obey; I shall in the next following chapters speak of his diseases
and the causes of his mortality, and of what laws of nature he is bound to obey.”, Thomas
Hobbes, cited, XXVIII, pp. 146-147.
61 Thomas Hobbes, cited, I, p. 15.
59
60
47
Imagination – “For after the object is removed, or the eye shut, we still
retain an image of the thing seen, though more obscure than when we
see it. And this is it the Latins call imagination.”62
Memory – “But when we would express the decay, and signify that
the sense is fading, old, and past, it is called memory. So that imagination and memory are but one thing, which for diverse considerations
hath diverse names.”63
Experience – “Much memory, or memory of many things, is called experience.”64
Speech – “But the most noble and profitable invention of all other was
that of “speech”, consisting of “names” or “appellations”, and their
connection.”65
Reason – “By this it appears that reason is not, as sense and memory,
born with us; nor gotten by experience only, as prudence is; but attained by industry: first in apt imposing of names; and secondly by
getting a good and orderly method in proceeding from the elements,
which are names, to assertions made by connection of one of them to
another”66
Science – “The signs of science are some certain and infallible; some,
uncertain. Certain, when he that pretendeth the science of anything can
teach the same; that is to say, demonstrate the truth thereof perspicuously to another: uncertain, when only some particular events answer to his
pretence ...”67
In providing an epistemological model, Thomas Hobbes As an empiricist
builds his system in the space between the object–sense–imagination–
experience–reason, since, as Hobbes argues “we conceive has been perceived
first by sense, either all at once, or by parts, a man can have no thought representing anything not subject to sense.”68 Therefore, in this way he underlines
the boundaries for human knowledge, since everything imagined by a human
Thomas Hobbes, cited, II, pp. 16-17.
Thomas Hobbes, cited, II, p. 17.
64 Thomas Hobbes, cited, II, p. 17.
65 Thomas Hobbes, cited, IV, p. 22.
66 Thomas Hobbes, cited, V, p. 29.
67 Thomas Hobbes, cited, V, p. 30.
68 “as I said before, we conceive has been perceived first by sense, either all at once, or
by parts, a man can have no thought representing anything not subject to sense.”,
Thomas Hobbes, cited, III, p. 22.
62
63
48
is finite; therefore, as humans, we are in no possession of an idea, or a notion
about an object that might be called infinite. A human is impossible to possess
the ability to imagine by reason ideas of infinite size, speed, time, power and
might. When we say that something is infinite, we only confess that we have
no ability to imagine the finite borders of a given object and therefore, we are
only in possession of our imagination on our inability to comprehend. In the
same manner, “the name of God is used, not to make us conceive Him (for He
is incomprehensible, and His greatness and power are unconceivable), but that
we may honour Him.”
For Thomas Hobbes, reality is a matter that can be conceived of only in
some place. He subsequently argues that “No man therefore can conceive anything, but he must conceive it in some place; and endued with some determinate magnitude; and which may be divided into parts.”69 Therefore, matter
existing in reality is either a natural body or an artificial body (e.g. a state).
Therefore, Hobbes’ understanding is materialistic.
On the path to his notion/conception of a state, Thomas Hobbes complexly
interlinks a bodily reality, previously discussed and multiplicity of other notions to which he manages to find autonomous definitions within the confines
of his system; for example, the conceptions like Power, Worth, Dignity, Honour, Worthiness, etc. and, in this way, this work turns into some kind of a personal glossary, at the same time representing a complexly interlinked whole in
his system. This leads him to the notion of the Natural Condition of the Mankind, thus the road from the state of nature towards a state is being articulated.
Still, what is the state of nature and the essence of a human in the state of nature for Hobbes? The answer to this question, first and foremost, for him hangs
on two pillars, that is – freedom and equality.
Analyzing freedom in general (not solely the human freedom), for Thomas
Hobbes this notion signifies the non-existence of barriers or opposition. Opposition in its turn is defined as an external impediment to motion. Hereby, he
proceeds that freedom defined in this way, can be applied no less to irrational
69
“No man therefore can conceive anything, but he must conceive it in some place; and
endued with some determinate magnitude; and which may be divided into parts; nor
that anything is all in this place, and all in another place at the same time; nor that
two or more things can be in one and the same place at once: for none of these things
ever have or can be incident to sense, but are absurd speeches, taken upon credit,
without any signification at all, from deceived philosophers and deceived, or deceiving Schoolmen.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, III, p. 22.
49
and inanimate creatures than to rational.70 Therefore, he links the notion of
freedom only with bodily; since, on the one hand, only bodies have the ability
for movement, and, on the other hand, only a thing that is capable of movement can come across the opposition, therefore, only body can come across the
opposition. Thereby, he accentuates the mechanical and materialistic nature of
freedom.
Extending his definition of freedom to the human beings, Thomas Hobbes
considers a freeman to be one, “which by his strength and wit he is able to do,
is not hindered to do what he has a will to.”71 Consequently, Hobbes argues
that liberty, or freedom is the existence in the absence of external impediments; these “impediments may oft take away part of a man’s power to do
what he would, but cannot hinder him from using the power left him according
as his judgement and reason shall dictate to him.”72
Thus, according to the wider definition of freedom by Thomas Hobbes,
and its application to a human, an emphasis is being put on external impediments. However, it does not mean that there are no rational internal factors
for human freedom. For example, his concept of the natural law provides us
with the same rational structure/framework. However, since he deducts the
natural laws from the human nature (these laws are the general laws discovered by reason and its obligatory power lives internally in a human- in one’s
own consciousness) and the divine origins, they are not barriers or impediments, but a part of the human will. Therefore, they are not a check on freedom, but make its constituent part; consequently, in his opinion, in the state
of nature, humans are free to do whatever they want to in accordance with
the constituent part of their will and this freedom might be constrained only
with the external impediments.
Meanwhile, the second major characteristic of the state of nature for him
is the physical, as well as mental equality of the human beings (“equal in the
faculties of body and mind”). It follows, that the nature has created human
beings to be equal, gifted with equal abilities. Though, in reality some might
be more intelligent or strong, however, even the physically weak a person,
has enough power to kill a stronger human being with a secret machination
or by confederacy with others; on the other hand, the intellectual capabilities
“Liberty, or “freedom”, signifieth properly the absence of opposition; by opposition, I
mean external impediments of motion; and may be applied no less to irrational and
inanimate creatures than to rational.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXI, p. 100.
71 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXI, p. 100.
72 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIV, p. 66.
70
50
suggest even more equality between the human beings with some exceptions: “setting aside the arts grounded upon words, and especially that skill
of proceeding upon general and infallible rules, called science, which very
few have and but in few things, as being not a native faculty born with us,
nor attained, as prudence”.73
The equality between the human beings generates the lack of trust among
them, conditioned by the equality in capabilities or the chances that gives birth
to the equality of hopes for reaching the desired ends. Specifically, for that
reason, if two human beings wish for the same thing, which cannot be in the
possession of both together, they will turn into enemies. The path to the desired end, which lies primarily in the desire for “conservation, and sometimes
their delectation only”, ends in the endeavor to destroy or subdue one another.
Consequently, each and every human being faces the same threat.74 The result
of this distrust is “the war of all against all”. Thus, the state of war is also conditioned by the human manners,75 from which Thomas Hobbes singles out a
perpetual and restless desire of power after power as well the “competition of
riches, honour, command, or other power inclineth to contention, enmity, and
war, because the way of one competitor to the attaining of his desire is to kill,
subdue, supplant, or repel the other.”76
In sum, Thomas Hobbes finds the three principal causes of quarrel in the
human nature: 1) competition; 2) diffidence; 3) glory.77 “The first maketh men
invade for gain; the second, for safety; and the third, for reputation. The first use
violence, to make themselves masters of other men’s persons, wives, children,
and cattle; the second, to defend them; the third, for trifles, as a word, a smile, a
different opinion, and any other sign of undervalue, either direct in their persons
or by reflection in their kindred, their friends, their nation, their profession, or
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIII, p. 63.
“From this equality of ability ariseth equality of hope in the attaining of our ends. And
therefore, if any two men desire the same thing, which nevertheless they cannot both
enjoy, they become enemies; and in the way to their end (which is principally their
own conservation, and sometimes their delectation only) endeavour to destroy or
subdue one another.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIII, p. 63.
75 In this context, for Hobbes manners do not depict etiquette or general norms of behavior but the very human characteristics linked with their desire for peace and living in societal unity: “those qualities of mankind that concern their living together in
peace and unity.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XI, p. 52.
76 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XI, p. 53.
77 “So that in the nature of man, we find three principal causes of quarrel. First, competition; secondly, diffidence; thirdly, glory.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIII, p. 64.
73
74
51
their name.” Consequently, “during the time men live without a common power
to keep them all in awe, they are in that condition which is called war; and such
a war as is of every man against every man,”78 since war is not only the act of
fighting, but the tract of time when the will to contend by battle is sufficiently
known.
Thus, one of the principal characteristics of this concept – the war of all
against all – is that nothing can be unjust. Such notions like right and wrong,
justice and injustice have no application there, since, when there is no common
power, no law (law guaranteed by the state government), injustice cannot exist.
The war values only two cardinal virtues – force and fraud.
Thomas Hobbes does not argue that the mankind has experienced as a
common developmental stage a historically universal existence in the state of
nature described by him, however, he is certain that some societies existed in the
same state of nature in his age. To give more weight to his arguments, he brings
the example of the savage tribes in America, whose manner of existence, in his
opinion, was brutish. In addition, he argues that the state of the human existence
in the state of nature can easily be observed during a civil war; by observing the
human existence without a fear for the common power and the degeneration of
the lives of people accustomed to live under the peaceful government.79
But, the state of nature drawn by Thomas Hobbes is a rather complex construct, which should not simply be understood as a human against every other
human; there is a more complex insight attached to this construct. In this context, the human aspiration for security in the state of nature is of utmost important. As-yet, in the Manners chapter (XI: Of the Difference of Manners),
Hobbes observes the desire of ease and sensual delight, the fear of death and
wounds, the desire of knowledge and arts of peace, etc. in the human nature. He
concludes that the state of war cannot bring peace to a human; and, security under
such condition depends only on one’s own strength and own invention; which, in
their turn, are very constrained and a conditional state. Hobbes argues that “In such
condition there is no place for industry, because the fruit thereof is uncertain:
and consequently no culture of the earth; no navigation, nor use of the commodities that may be imported by sea; no commodious building; no instruments of moving and removing such things as require much force; no
knowledge of the face of the earth; no account of time; no arts; no letters; no
78
79
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIII, p. 64.
“It may peradventure be thought there was never such a time nor condition of war as
this; and I believe it was never generally so, over all the world: but there are many
places where they live so now.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIII, p. 65.
52
society; and which is worst of all, continual fear, and danger of violent death;
and the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.”80 In sum, according to Hobbes, the human passions, which drive them towards peace is “fear of
death; desire of such things as are necessary to commodious living; and a hope
by their industry to obtain them.”
Thus, Thomas Hobbes’ complex picture of the state of nature is characterized
with two primary dimensions: on the one hand, with war between the humans and
on the other hand, with the human aspiration for security stemming from the state of
war. The second dimension leads him to come up with construct of the natural law.
Herein, he offers an important differentiation between the right of nature (jus naturale) and the law of nature (lex naturalis)81. The former denotes “the liberty
each man hath to use his own power as he will himself for the preservation of
his own nature; that is to say, of his own life; and consequently, of doing anything which, in his own judgement and reason, he shall conceive to be the aptest means thereunto”,82 and the latter means “a precept, or general rule, found
out by reason, by which a man is forbidden to do that which is destructive of
his life, or taketh away the means of preserving the same, and to omit that by
which he thinketh it may be best preserved.”83
Consequently, the natural right denotes the liberty of action, while the law
(laws) places liberty in frames, in such a way turning it into an obligation. In
that way, if the right of nature is present in the first dimension of the state of
nature (and alongside other reasons also pushes a human to the state of war),
the law (laws) of nature, being an offspring of rationality is linked with the
security dimension as an obligatory, general rule, creating the specificobligatory normative part for the state of nature.
The specific-obligatory insight of the laws of nature, first and foremost
consists in its influence on the conscience, consequently, “the laws of nature
oblige in foro interno; that is to say, they bind to a desire they should take
place”. Therefore, since these laws only oblige desire and endeavour, in his
opinion, they are easy to be observed. On the other hand, “in foro externo”,
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIII, p. 64.
In this context, Hobbes employes two alternative insights: the law of nature and natural laws. Thus, in this context law can only be employed only in a sense that for
Hobbes law as a fully-fledged source of justice is only established after the formation
of a state. In its turn, the “natural laws” is a specific category; it is a characteristic,
quality and Hobbes considers these laws to be a frame of the moral philosophy.
82 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIV, pp. 65-66.
83 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIV, p. 66.
80
81
53
these laws do not always require to be implemented.84 Since, if the laws are
not observed proportionally, that is, in a given time and place is only observed
by some and not all, then the life and security of those observing the law will
be defenseless and in this way, will come into conflict with the law of nature
or the priorities for the self-defense and preservation of one’s life. Therefore,
under such conditions, these laws do not oblige in foro externo, “which everyone hath then kept, when he has the will to keep them, when he can do it safely”.85
Herein, Thomas Hobbes proves that “the science of them is the true and only moral philosophy”. Since, in his words the moral philosophy is “the science
of what is good and evil”; and, until humans exist in the state of nature, the
measure to good and evil is one’s private appetite. Therefore, Hobbes suggests
all men agree that peace is virtue/good, and, therefore, moral virtues are the following means leading to peace: justice; gratitude; modesty; equity; mercy and
the rest of the laws of nature.86
In parallel, Thomas Hobbes emphasizes another aspect of the laws of nature,
namely, “for natural laws, being eternal and universal, are all divine.”87
Still, what is the substance of the laws of nature? Hobbes first develops
nineteen laws and subsequently adds the final one in the conclusive chapter of
his book (“To the Laws of Nature declared in the fifteenth Chapter, I would
have this added: that every man is bound by nature, as much as in him lieth, to
protect in war the authority by which he is himself protected in time of
peace.”).88 I will direct the attention of the reader to the first three laws which
are central for his notion of the law of nature.
The first and the fundamental law of nature is basically observed from two
primary perspectives; the first perspective speaks of the right of nature (“The
right of nature, which writers commonly call jus naturale, is the liberty each
man hath to use his own power as he will himself for the preservation of his
own nature; that is to say, of his own life; and consequently, of doing anything
which, in his own judgement and reason, he shall conceive to be the aptest
means thereunto”) and the second perspective – of the law of nature in itself
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XV, p. 78.
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVII, p. 82.
86 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XV, p. 78.
87 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXVI, p. 132.
88 Thomas Hobbes, cited, A Review and Conclusion, p. 316.
84
85
54
(lex naturalis), which is a precept, or general rule, found out by reason.89
Therefore, since the state of nature is the war of all men against all men, everyone follows the dictate of one’s own right of nature and there is nothing that
is prohibited to preserve one’s life in a struggle against the enemies; consequently, everyone has the right to do anything, including the right to encroach
on the bodies of the others (“a right to one another’s body”). And therefore, as
long as the right of nature of every man to anything endures, no security to
anyone might exist of living out the time, at least not as much as the nature
ordinarily allows men to live. And consequently, it is a precept, or a general
rule of the reason that “every man ought to endeavour peace, as far as he has
hope for obtaining it; and when he cannot obtain it, that he may seek, and use,
all helps, and advantages of war”. The first branch of the rule contains the first
and fundamental law of nature, that is “to seek peace and follow it”; and, the
second law is “the sum of the right of nature, which is: by all means we can to
defend ourselves”.90
The second law is derived from the first law and is reminding a famous
formula from the New Testament: quod tibi fieri non vis, alteri ne feceris
(“Whatsoever you require that others should do to you, that do ye to them.”).
According to Thomas Hobbes, this law should be stated in the following way:
“that a man be willing, when others are so too, as far forth as for peace and
defence of himself he shall think it necessary, to lay down this right to all
things; and be contented with so much liberty against other men as he would
allow other men against himself.”91 Since, as long as the human hold their
right to do whatever pleases them, they are at war with each other. So, as long
as the men as a whole do not lay down their right, there is no reason from anyone to dispose of their rights, since without it one stays defenseless against
robbers, not dispose oneself for peace.
In parallel, analyzing the act of voluntary concession of right, he underlines that any right can be laid aside by simply renouncing or transferring it to
another (person). A simple renouncement act suggests that one does not care
who benefits from that decision. A transfer of right takes place when its bene“For though they that speak of this subject use to confound jus and lex, “right” and
“law”, yet they ought to be distinguished, because “right” consisteth in liberty to do,
or to forbear; whereas “law” determineth and bindeth to one of them: so that law and
right differ as much as obligation and liberty, which in one and the same matter are
inconsistent.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIV, p. 66.
90 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIV, p. 66.
91 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIV, p. 66.
89
55
fit is predestined for certain person or persons. If a human renounces one’s
own right or transfers it to someone, then one should not hinder the possibility
the transferred right be fully exercised and should not renounce a decision that
was already made. Hereby, Hobbes further clarifies that when one renounces
or transfers a right to someone, one does it for some corresponding rights or
some other benefit. For, it is a voluntary act and the voluntary act of every
men aims to get “some good to himself”. Therefore, there exist some rights
which a man cannot make it known by any signs or words, why one wants to
transfer or abandon the right. Of them all, a man cannot renounce a right to
resist attackers willing by force to take away his life, since it is not understandable what corresponding benefit can one expect in exchange for such a
voluntary act of giving up one’s right.
On the whole, Thomas Hobbes links the rationale for transferring the
right with the notion of a contract, opening the door for the third law of nature, which he argues consists in men performing their covenants made. The
third law of nature partly corresponds with the key principle of modern domestic and international law – “agreements are to be kept” (Latin – pacta sunt
servanda). However, for Thomas Hobbes, this law has even a larger application, since according to his approach, the construct of state and law are built
essentially on the agreement (here, law primarily denotes the body of rules
executed by the state not the law of nature to which the third rule itself belongs
and the origins of which lie in another source).
Moreover, the third rule of nature, is the original of justice, since if the
contract is not concluded, that is some of the right of nature are not renounced
by a man, no injustice can possibly exist. Consequently, the foundation of justice, in sum, is created by law (The law executed by the state) and since the
latter for Hobbes is drawn on the renouncement or the transfer of the right of
nature, the third law of nature, consequently is the one, which leads towards
justice.
However, for Thomas Hobbes, the third law in itself is not autonomously
enough for founding law and justice, and that is the main reason he brings the
notion of “actually just” in this context. In his opinion, though the third law of
nature and the covenants followed upon with this rule opens up the path to
justice, “But because covenants of mutual trust, where there is a fear of not
performance on either part..., are invalid, though the original of justice be the
making of covenants, yet injustice actually there can be none till the cause of
56
such fear be taken away.”92 Consequently, justice cannot be founded till a coercive power comes into existence, which for Hobbes is primarily embodied in
a state (commonwealth); “Therefore, notwithstanding the laws of nature …, if
there be no power erected, or not great enough for our security, every man will
and may lawfully rely on his own strength and art for caution against all other
men”.93 Therefore, Hobbes perceives the notion of the “law (laws) of nature”
as very specific conception, not a literally (word for word) the law (or laws).
In sum, in Thomas Hobbes’ conception, men create a state, since in the
state of nature there self-preservance and security cannot be guaranteed because man are primarily directed by passion and the laws of nature and they
exist in the miserable condition. The laws of nature like “justice”, “equity”,
“modesty”, “mercy”, without a coercive power is in conflict with the natural
passions of a man which direct them towards “partiality”, “pride”, “revenge”
and the like. Without a sword, these laws are simply words having no means
for guaranteeing the security of the human beings.
Thomas Hobbes links the founding act of the state with the formation of a
common power. In his opinion, the only way to create a common power,
which will have the power to defend man from the invasion of foreigners, and
the injuries of one another, and thereby to secure them, and allow to
feed/nourish them by their own labour or the fruits of earth and live contentedly, is to confer all their power and strength to one men or the assembly of men,
that may reduce all their wills, by the plurality of voices, onto one will/a single
voice. This means that men should appoint one man or the assembly of men in
their name to act, and each should name oneself author or owner of the actions
(men or assembly of men) taken in the name of defense of the common peace
or security. With that act, they should subject their private wills to his will,
private judgement to his judgement. This act is more than a consent or unity: it
is the real unification unto a single person, when every man enters into agreement with every other. Thus, the delegation of power in this model can only be
realized as the unification into a single person, when every person confers on a
single man or the assembly the right of rule over themselves, but only with a
condition “that thou give up, thy right to him, and authorise all his actions in
like manner.”94
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XV, p. 72.
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVII, p. 82.
94 “I authorise and give up my right of governing myself to this man, or to this assembly
of men, on this condition; that thou give up, thy right to him, and authorise all his actions in like manner.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVII, p. 84.
92
93
57
Thus, “the Commonwealth... is: one person, of whose acts a great multitude, by mutual covenants one with another, have made themselves every one
the author, to the end he may use the strength and means of them all as he shall
think expedient for their peace and common defence.”95 The one who embodies that person is called a sovereign, that is one with a sovereign power, and all
others are his subjects. On the whole, the key to the essence of state for
Hobbes lies in the notion of “sovereign”, and the substance of the commonwealth consists in him, since “the Commonwealth is no person, nor has capacity to do anything but by the representative, that is, the sovereign”96, and “the
sovereign is the public soul, giving life and motion to the Commonwealth”.97
However, still, how a sovereign power is being acquired? Thomas Hobbes
provides two alternative ways to answer the question:
1) By natural force, “as when a man maketh his children to submit themselves, and their children, to his government, as being able to destroy
them if they refuse” (Dominion Paternal), or when enemies are subordinated with the means of war, and giving them their lives on that
condition (Dominion Despotical);
2) By voluntary covenant, when man voluntarily subject themselves to
obey the will of a single man or the assembly of several men.
Thomas Hobbes argues that the first case is an example of a foundation of
commonwealth by acquisition; while the second case embodies a foundation
of political commonwealth, or foundation of commonwealth by Institution.
Theoretical differentiation between the foundation of the commonwealth by
institution or by acquisition do not suggest that in the history of a given state
these models for acquiring a sovereign power have taken place in a pure form.
From the theoretical perspective, every act of state formation is being originally
carried out in accordance with either the model of acquisition or the model of
institution; however, these models might intersect at some later stage of development. Consider, for example, a despotic domination established by the sovereign
and the state over a given people (model of acquisition); however, the sovereign
power of this sovereign and state was previously constituted as such, therefore,
the original founding act might have been either – acquisition or institution.
Thus, other versions for linking the models might also be identified, which, in
sum suggest additional complexity visible in his approach.
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVII, p. 84.
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXVI, p. 124.
97 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXIX, p. 152.
95
96
58
Analyzing the insight of the model of institution of a state by voluntary
covenant (so to say a founding covenant), it should be noted that this model is
a product of theoretical generalization/imagination and autonomously represents a complex theoretical construct. Discussing the nature of this agreement,
Thomas Hobbes underlines its existence in the space between the humans (future subjects) and, in this context, in the relations between subjects and a sovereign, he argues that one who is turned into a sovereigns given the right to
represent people by the covenant made up by the people themselves and without entering into an agreement with sovereign, therefore, the sovereign cannot
breach the agreement (since the sovereign is not a party to the agreement).
Consequently, none of the subjects of a sovereign, on the premise of the nonfulfillment of obligations by the sovereign, have the right to free themselves
from being the subjects of a sovereign. He who becomes a sovereign, does not
conclude a preliminary covenant with his subjects, since in such a case, a sovereign as a separate side would have to conclude a covenant with every subject
individually, or with every subject as a whole. (1) A sovereign cannot enter
into an agreement with the subjects as a whole, since during the state formation they do not yet constitute a whole; and, (2) if a sovereign concludes the
number of agreements that equals the number of human beings in his realm,
then those agreements will be void after one embraces the sovereign power;
and, since, every act which is found by the subjects to violate the agreement,
correspondingly, belongs to this subject, on an individual level, and to all other
subjects too; so, those acts of the sovereign are made, at the same time, in the
name of any particular subject.98
Thus, the opinion which suggests that sovereign earns his power, is conditionally based on the prior agreement with the subjects, flows from the misunderstanding of a simple truth – that, as such, it is senseless the sovereign
power was awarded by the prior agreement. The idea that every sovereign receives its sovereign power based on the conditional prior agreement, flows
from the misunderstanding that “covenants being but words, and breath, have
no force to oblige, contain, constrain, or protect any man, but what it has from
the public sword; that is, from the untied hands of that man, or assembly of
98
“if he make so many several covenants as there be men, those covenants after he hath
the sovereignty are void; because what act soever can be pretended by any one of
them for breach thereof is the act both of himself, and of all the rest, because done in
the person, and by the right of every one of them in particular.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVIII, p. 85.
59
men, that hath the sovereignty.”99 Though, for Hobbes, voluntary covenant
between the people is the basis for founding a state based on institution, and
delegation of the power to a sovereign is the most important precondition in
this case, however, in relation to a sovereign, a contract is just words and
breath and nothing else.
Concerning the model of the state formation, based on the acquisition,
Thomas Hobbes puts a special emphasis on fear, since in this case the sovereign power is acquired by force. This means that human beings accept every
action of a man or an assembly, under whose power their life or freedom exists, because of the threat of death or bonds. Thus, he gives us the further explanation that “this kind of dominion, or sovereignty, differeth from sovereignty by institution only in this, that men who choose their sovereign do it for fear
of one another, and not of him whom they institute: but in this case, they subject themselves to him they are afraid of. In both cases, they do it for fear.”100
In addition, even in case of the acquisition of a state, some kind of a model
for the foundational covenant for the sovereign power is underlined; since, according to the hint made by Hobbes: “every man is supposed to promise obedience to him in whose power it is to save or destroy him.”101 Accordingly, in
case of the acquisition, for example, the conquest or the victory in war, right of
dominion is not itself defined by the victory, but by the own covenant of the
defeated, which declares subjection to a winner. However, even this covenant
does not fully suggest the act of acquisition, without the will of a sovereign
being expressed, “and then only is his life in security, and his service due,
when the victor hath trusted him with his corporal liberty.”102 In this context,
Hobbes offers another version of the contract, which he calls the “covenant of
obedience” and based on which, a future subject is to recognize a winner in a
war, as the sovereign. Therefore, even the model of acquisition leads him to
the institute of a covenant; however, this covenant differs from the covenant in
the institutional model, which, on the one hand, denotes the process of subjection with the use of force and on the other hand, stemming from this, it is not
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVIII, p. 85.
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XX, p. 95.
101 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XX, p. 96.
102 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XX, p. 97.
99
100
60
concluded between the future subjects, but is made up in a space, between the
future subjects and a sovereign.103
At the same time, in the conception of Thomas Hobbes’, no matter how
many different forms of state formation can be there, the figure of sovereign
remains still very important. He clarifies that even in the case of acquisition,
the rights of the sovereign power and its ends are the same as in the case of
institutional model, being undivided, inaccessible, and absolute. Therefore,
without the consent of the sovereign, his power cannot be transferred; the sovereign cannot be accused by the subjects in any of the violations or be punished by them; he is a sovereign legislator and a judge; he decides the questions of war and peace, etc. 104
Meanwhile, Hobbes views the sovereign not only as a secular leader, but also as ecclesiastical. He devotes a significant part of his book to provide the proof
to this thesis, where he engages in the systemic analysis of many religious books
and comes up with arguments (by reviewing the canonical texts), which are rather different from the mainstream Christian interpretations.105 Concerning the
state, he declares the Christian state to simultaneously be/represent a church106,
since there is no such universal church, to which all the Christians should
obey. Christians are under the sovereignty of different states and they cannot
obey the orders of other rulers besides the one they are subjects to. Therefore,
in his conclusion, “a Church, such a one as is capable to command, to judge,
absolve, condemn, or do any other act, is the same thing with a civil Commonwealth consisting of Christian men; and is called a civil state, for that the
subjects of it are men; and a Church, for that the subjects thereof are Christians.”107
“every subject in a Commonwealth hath covenanted to obey the civil law; either one
with another, as when they assemble to make a common representative, or with the
representative itself one by one when, subdued by the sword, they promise obedience
that they may receive life”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXVI, p. 124
104 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XX, pp. 95-96.
105 For example: immortality, hell, salvation, etc. Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXXVIII.
106 “I define a Church to be: a company of men professing Christian religion, united in
the person of one sovereign; at whose command they ought to assemble, and without whose authority they ought not to assemble.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXXIX, p.
211.
107 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXXIX, p. 212.
103
61
By virtue of the above, the sovereigns of Christian states comprise both
the political and ecclesiastical power,108 performing the role of the supreme
pastor based directly on the authority conferred on them by the divine power
that is “in God’s right, or jure divino”.109 In total, he argues that after the Era
of the Jesus Christ (after the disciples of Christ), the Christian faith relied on
the reputation of a spiritual leader and the authority of a sovereign. While, during his era, only the Sovereigns were left with the right to speak in the name of
the god (he also extends this right to those who god spoke to supernaturally).110 However, one thing should be noticed: the Hobbesian way of linking the
sovereign with the divine right of rule, was rather different from the authors of
his era, for whom the point of departure was the divine order, while both the
state and the sovereign were the integral parts in the divine order; while, his
argument reorients the emphasis towards a state and a sovereign. Therefore,
the primary point for him in this relationship is that the supreme power that a
state and its sovereign as the one with the earthly supreme power should not be
hindered by anyone or anything, suggesting that the state and its sovereign
powers are independently the most important supreme good. Moreover, his
argument which states that the sovereign derives its powers from god, also do
not follow the mainstream interpretations of that era. He derives it from his
conception of a human nature, which stands on the pillars of freedom and
equality, and in parallel, from the complex and specific nature of the covenant,
this itself results in the reorientation of the emphasis in the preconditions for
constituting the sovereign power also in this context.111
“From this consolidation of the right politic and ecclesiastic in Christian sovereigns, it
is evident they have all manner of power over their subjects that can be given to
man for the government of men’s external actions, both in policy and religion”,
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XLII, p. 248.
109 “But the king, and every other sovereign, executeth his office of supreme pastor by
immediate authority from God, that is to say, in God’s right, or jure divino.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XLII, p. 245.
110 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XLIII, p. 265.
111 For Example, Robert Filmer in his arguably the most famous book – Patriarcha, or
The Natural Power of Kings (published in 1680, after his death), offers the traditional perspective on the sources of the royal power (divine and natural right), arguing
that the source of it consists in the natural right of father and biblical Adam was the
first King on whom the right to rule was given directly from God. Filmer derives his
theory for the natural (and divine) power by adapting the idea that the divine right
of rule is following the legacy of Adam. Therefore, he argues, neither are humans
naturally equal, nor free.
108
62
Concerning the kinds of commonwealth by the forms of their government,
Hobbes remarks that the difference between the states consists in the difference
between the sovereigns (those who execute sovereign power) and identifies three
types based on these criteria: monarchy, democracy and aristocracy,112 depending whether a sovereign is embodied in a single person or an assembly. Therefore, if the supreme power is embodied in a single person then a state is a monarchy; if it is represented by the general assembly of subjects then it is a democracy; aristocracy, where it is in an assembly of certain persons nominated, or
otherwise distinguished from the rest.113 Engaging in the comparative analysis of
the kinds of commonwealth and discussing them in relation to their primary task
of founding peace and guaranteeing the security of their subjects, he singles out
monarchy among these kinds of state as the form most able to deliver the those
goods. For example, Hobbes argues that in a monarchy private interest coincides
with that of public,114 since in his opinion, no king can be rich when his subjects
are poor, etc.
Thus, it should be noted, that for Thomas Hobbes, the stability or integrity
of the State is the priority higher than the identification (or choosing) of the
better form of government. That is why he argues that once one of the kinds of
commonwealth is being established, it is necessary that this government be
accepted or supported as the best possible form of government; since, the ac-
Hobbes lists the kinds of commonwealth on in relation with the model institution
concerning state formation (Chapter 19), however, herein he argues that there is no
other kind of government besides the ones in his list.
113 Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIX, pp. 89, 92.
114 “Now in monarchy the private interest is the same with the public.”, Thomas Hobbes,
cited, XIX, p. 90.
112
63
tions to overthrow the existing form of government115 are the actions against
the rules of nature and the divine positive law.116
The laws are being passed within the confines of a state. However, in his
opinion, there are rules which oblige subjects not directly to a state, but as the
members of a state. Since, the particular laws should be known only to professionals, or those who study laws of a given state, while everyone else should
know the civil law. It is clearly visibly in this part of the book, that Hobbes
offers an independent differentiation between the civil law and the certain laws
of different states; on the other hand, he adds, that the ancient law of Rome
was called “civil” because of being derived from the word “civitas”, which
can be defined as a state. Its application were preserved in those states which
were the subjects of the old Roman Empire and named it the civil law to distinguish it from the rest of their civil laws.117 Thus, here the civil law is quite
distinguished from the understanding, which is operated by the jurists today,
comprising the law of state in total, not being limited to its part (nowadays
the civil law); on the other hand, for Hobbes, civil law highlights a specific
understanding as the product of generalization (e.g. a comparison with the
Roman civil law).
Consequently, on the whole, Thomas Hobbes needs this differentiation,
since he is interested in the law in general, not from the perspective of laws
in a given country; in its turn, he needs to make a comparison between this
“And of the three sorts, which is the best is not to be disputed where any one of them
is already established; but the present ought always to be preferred, maintained, and
accounted best, because it is against both the law of nature and the divine positive
law to do anything tending to the subversion thereof.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XLII,
p. 249.
116 For Thomas Hobbes, the positive law depicts those laws which have not always existed and have been transformed into laws only depending on the will of a sovereign.
In its turn, he divides positive law into two parts: some are human, some divine. The
one part of the divine laws is eternal and is as well natural law. The other part is not
worldwide, since, according to his arguments, they are neither eternal nor universal
and as such, are not directed at the whole of mankind, but towards certain peoples
and persons; the divine law (being the perception of a god) are declared as laws by
those to whom the god gifts such a right (he includes among them sovereigns as
well). Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXVI, p. 132.
117 “The ancient law of Rome was called their civil law, from the word civitas, which
signifies a Commonwealth: and those countries which, having been under the Roman Empire and governed by that law, retain still such part thereof as they think fit,
call that part the civil law to distinguish it from the rest of their own civil laws.”,
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXVI, p. 123.
115
64
law in general with the law (laws) of nature; therefore, in this work, the idea
of the civil law is pictured as a generalizing and unifying concepts. And, in
this context, every law does not represent an advice, but the order of a person, whose power to make others follow his orders is being recognized by
the addressees of the order. In the idea of the civil law, the notion of civic is
added (more precisely civitatis) which describes the subject (persona civitatis)
responsible for giving out an order. In sum, Hobbes argues, “Civil law is to
every subject those rules which the Commonwealth hath commanded him, by
word, writing, or other sufficient sign of the will, to make use of for the distinction of right and wrong; that is to say, of that is contrary and what is not
contrary to the rule.”118
The Hobbesian connection between the law of nature and civil law is an
especially telling one. This part of his work is specific for delivering a more
informed picture on his laws of nature and the state of nature. First, he remarks, that the law of nature and the civil law contain each other reciprocally
and have equal extent. Then he clarifies the substance of the laws of nature
and implies “not properly laws, but qualities that dispose men to peace and to
obedience”. In its turn, for Hobbes “law, properly, is the word of him that by
right hath command over others.”119
Thus, the laws of nature are transformed into actually laws by the state.
Consequently, the law of nature will turn into a state order, and will parallelly
be a civil law. On the other hand, the civil laws derive from the dictates of nature. Since, justice or the fulfillment of the covenants and giving to every man
his own, is transferred to us by law of nature. In its turn, the obedience to civil
law is part of the law of nature. Consequently, civil and natural law are not
different kinds, but different parts of law, of which the former, being written is
called civil, while the latter, an unwritten law, is called natural and a very
complex relation of intersection between them exists. Therefore, the natural
118
119
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXVI, p. 123.
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XV, pp. 78-79. in another context, Thomas Hobbes links the
laws in a direct sense only with those norms that are instituted by the Commonwealth: “none can make laws but the Commonwealth, because our subjection is to
the Commonwealth only; and that commands are to be signified by sufficient signs,
because a man knows not otherwise how to obey them.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited,
XXVI, p. 123.
65
right (jus naturale) is being constrained by both, civil and natural law (though
with differing scale of success).120
From Human to State, according to Thomas Hobbes
Commonwealth
Sovereign
Forceful way of
The way of
The way of
acquisition of power
Acquisition
Institution
Dominion
Despotical
Covenant
Forceful way of
War of all against
all
acquisition of
power
Law of Nature
Domionion
Paternal
State of Nature
Freedom
Peace – Pursuit of
Security
Equality
Human
Let us now get back to a previously outlined question why Thomas
Hobbes, in order to denote a state/commonwealth selected for the word – leviathan in this work. As being mentioned previously, he offers the image of le-
120
“Civil and natural law are not different kinds, but different parts of law; whereof one
part, being written, is called civil the other unwritten, natural.”, Thomas Hobbes,
cited, XXVI, p. 124.
66
viathan in several forms, namely: 1) an artificial gigantic man; 2) a sovereign
with a crown; 3) a king of all the children of pride; 4) a mortal god; 5) a huge
biblical creature. Meanwhile, in each and every model of comparison there is a
possibility to observe some key points of his political philosophy.
1.
A comparison of a state with a gigantic but still with a human
being, consists in a clear indication on its bodily nature, though,
artificial, but still bodily. Since, for Thomas Hobbes, only bodily can be studied/comprehended, and a state can be comprehended in as much as it consists of a body. To account on a
bodily nature of a state, Hobbes imagines different parts of a
body of state comparing it with different parts of a human
body. Therefore, in this context, he concentrates his choice on a
human, not on any other creature, or for example, an image of a
biblical sea creature. This can be interpreted, on the one hand,
as a suggestion that a state is similar to the human nature; and,
that, concentration only on the bodily, and ignoring spirituality
or rationality will not provide the full picture of a state; on the
other hand, in the context of apprehension, and for the purpose
of comparing the organs of a state, with that of a mysterious,
mythical image of a colossal sea creature, would have been
much more difficult. Therefore, though he picks up the image
of leviathan from the bible, in figurative comparison he employs the image of a gigantic human;
2.
Meanwhile, this gigantic human portrayed on the title page of
the book, is not a simple, huge sized mortal, but a sovereign
with a crown on his head; the author, points out in here that the
spirit of state/commonwealth is a sovereign, that confers life
and motion on him. Since a state is neither a person, nor has the
ability for action without its own representative, or without a
sovereign. This sovereign is constructed by innumerous small
man, which serves as an indication from the author to the ways
of forming a leviathan by the people (subjects) themselves (the
way of institution) or by the people (subjects) and a sovereign
(the way of acquisition) before the sovereign power is established. Meanwhile, on the gravure the sovereign holds a sword
in his right hand, and in the left hand a crozier. These holdings
67
should indicate the materialization of both of secular and ecclesiastical power.
3.
On the faces of a king of all the children of pride, there is a
possibility to observe that by forming the state, people refuse
the pride awarded by the equality and freedom in the state of
nature. In such an understanding, a state is a suppressor of pride
in all its subjects not some of them. Suppression of pride, is a
path leading to peace and security and therefore, to selfsurvival. Hobbesian rational basics of a human, with the help of
laws of nature, and therefore, with the help of a divine hand selects a way leading to the king of pride.
4.
However, leviathan is bigger than a human. He is fearless and
looks from anything tall from above and to express its greatness, comparison with a human is not be enough. Therefore, we
should not forget about the point of departure for Hobbes in
this context; namely, that leviathan (as a symbol of political
unity) firstly denotes the image of the enormous biblical sea
creature (not simply a body or an animal), to which there was
no comparison and in this sense, he is a god, but a mortal god.
In this way, the author points to the power of a state, on the
other hand, adorning it with a crown of good. Since, a comparison of a state with a god should describe it, being virtue. Therefore, for Hobbes, a state is the immeasurable virtue in itself,
while a perfect state represents the crown of the socio-political
practice.
After we are through with representing the complex conception of leviathan by Thomas Hobbes, we can direct our attention to his vision of international relations and international law, which are not the main subjects for the
author in this work. Hobbes, however, touches upon the important topics in
these directions in a natural way and represents some interesting suggestions/considerations.
First of all, for him the kings and other holders of the sovereign power, due
to their independence, live in the condition of continual jealousies with each
other and alike gladiators threaten each other with their looks and weapons; the
castles, that are erected on the borders, their garrisons, artillery and the spies sent
68
in their neighbors represents “a posture of war”. Therefore, Hobbes transfers the
state of nature to international relations, however, also points to some specific
conditions in this context, remarking that the sovereign takes care industry of
their subjects, which serves as a check and consequently, international relations
do not end up in such a misery which the human liberty in the state of nature is
accompanied with. 121
Analyzing the responsibilities of a sovereign, he specifically argues on his
rights in the questions of war and peace. He argues, that the sovereign power
has the competence to declare a war and take the measure for securing the
peace with other nations and commonwealths, meaning the sovereign has the
right to decide what is best for the common good in a given situation for the
state, how many people should be mobilized, the weaponry needed and funds
necessary. Herewith, Hobbes remarks that in reality, the guarantee for defending every nation is its armed forces, while the force of an army consists in its
unification under the common command, which is the sovereign.122
In the chapter “on manners”, he outlines the human inclination for the power
on the top, remarking that the kings, though they have enormous power, do not
spare their efforts to maintain it: inside the country – with the help of laws, and
in international relations – with the help of war.123
Discussing the obligations of a sovereign, Thomas Hobbes again touches
upon the question of the International Relations emphasizing those obligations
between the sovereigns are determined by the law, which is commonly called
the law of nations. Herein, he remarks, that “the law of nations and the law of
nature is the same thing.” Therefore, for guaranteeing the security of their subjects every sovereign has the same rights, what every human has in the state of
121
122
123
“yet in all times kings and persons of sovereign authority, because of their independency, are in continual jealousies, and in the state and posture of gladiators, having their weapons pointing, and their eyes fixed on one another; that is, their forts,
garrisons, and guns upon the frontiers of their kingdoms, and continual spies upon
their neighbours, which is a posture of war. But because they uphold thereby the
industry of their subjects, there does not follow from it that misery which accompanies the liberty of particular men.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XIII, p. 65.
“For the power by which the people are to be defended consisteth in their armies,
and the strength of an army in the union of their strength under one command;
which command the sovereign instituted”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVIII, p. 87.
“and when that is done, there succeedeth a new desire; in some, of fame from new
conquest; in others, of ease and sensual pleasure; in others, of admiration, or being
flattered for excellence in some art or other ability of the mind.”, Thomas Hobbes,
cited, XI, p. 53.
69
nature. Therefore, the laws of nature extend to sovereigns, as well as to states
in international relations. Herein, Hobbes employs the notion of “conscience”,
and suggests that “there being no court of natural justice, but in the conscience
only, where not man, but God reigneth; whose laws, such of them as oblige all
mankind, in respect of God, as he is the Author of nature, are natural; and in
respect of the same God, as he is King of kings, are laws.”124
Speaking of the liberty, Thomas Hobbes argues that only the states, because of living like the humans in the state of nature are afforded with the
absolute liberty. He emphasizes, that whenever humans leave the state of
nature and become the subjects of a state or the sovereign power, that is
when humans lose and states acquire absolute freedom to act in accordance
with their judgement and for their benefit only. Therefore, states are under
the perpetual threat of war and preparation and upon the confines of battle,
clear illustration being perpetually armed frontiers and cannons pointed at
their neighbors. 125
Therefore, we can make the following generalizations on the Hobbesian
approach to international relations:
1. States and sovereigns exist in the conditions of mutual continual jealousies and threats in international relations; Thus, the thirst for power
of the sovereigns leads them to wars against each other;
2. The interstate obligations are being defined by the law of nations (international law), which at the same time is the law of nature;
3. Implementation of the law of nations, and therefore, the laws of nature
in international relations depend on the conscience of the sovereigns;
4. The laws of nature in international relations is the same as for the humans in the state of nature;
5. Conditions in international relations are different from state of nature
between the humans, since the sovereigns take care of the industry of
their subjects, which is an additional constraining factor.
124
125
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXX, p. 161.
“every Commonwealth, not every man, has an absolute liberty to do what it shall
judge, that is to say, what that man or assembly that representeth it shall judge, most
conducing to their benefit. But withal, they live in the condition of a perpetual war,
and upon the confines of battle, with their frontiers armed, and cannons planted
against their neighbours round about.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXI, p. 102.
70
The Complex Idea of Law, according to Thomas Hobbes
“Law” of
Nations
Sovereign
Power
Written
Positive
law
“Law” of
Nature
Eternal
Unwritten
Civil
Law
Divine
“Law”
Certain Laws
of Different
States
Divine
Positive Law
Shortly and precisely, these are the basic ideas that could be derived from
his work concerning international relations, other opinions primarily being the
generalizations of different authors (sometimes correct, sometimes incorrect)
based on their own interpretations of his ideas. Moreover, sometimes the scientific research into this work comes up with a diametrically different scientific results (however, according to the mainstream view, Thomas Hobbes is
widely accepted as one of the founders of the realist tradition). It seems that
the complexity of the Hobbes’ political philosophy and some foundational
notions of his work feeds misunderstandings, for example: beginning with the
foundational covenant for the sovereign power and continuing with his conceptions on a sovereign and a state, to a complex connection with the law of
nature, the divine law, the law of nations and the positive law; and finishing
with the non-homogenous picture of the state of nature. For additional exam71
ple, when we speak of the state of nature, this conception cannot be reduced to
a simple understanding of the war of all against all. Hobbes for example, singles out separately a human inclination for striving for a security (and the desire of ease and sensual delight, the fear of death and wounds, the desire of
knowledge and arts of peace, etc). In this context, he develops the laws of nature
and though, they are not the laws in the full meaning of this word, however,
they have their presence in his perception on the state of nature and serve as
the natural-moral checks on the natural right (natural liberty) of man.
Therefore, if we extend this picture to the interstate relations, on the one
hand, we might come up with many of the key postulates of the realist tradition (and indeed, he is widely accepted to be one of the founders of the realist
tradition): in international relation states exist in the conditions of continuous
mutual jealousies and seeking of power resulting in the perpetual posture of
war and the only guarantee for defending the people is the armed forces; wars
are the result of human (sovereign) inclination for power and though, international law creates legal framework for international relations, however, there is
no effective system for its implementation (Hobbes bases it on the conscience
of sovereigns) etc. Moreover, some resemblance can also be discovered in the
terminologies employed, when for example Hobbes sums up his conception;
he uses the term “anarchy”. He argues that the state of nature is “anarchy and
the condition of war”.126 Since, in international relations states exist in the
state of nature, it logically follows that they exist in anarchy and the condition
of perpetual threat of war. However, one thing should additionally be emphasized, that the “term” anarchy is not used often and as such, is not dominant in
his work.
On the other hand, analyzing the Hobbesian conception of the international relation, we also come across a model conditioned by rationalism, the model
of a rational human being, but still international relations colored with the
moral philosophy (doctrine on the natural laws), differentiation between interstate space from that of conditions in the state of nature (consider for example
the care of the sovereign for the industry of their subjects), and two of the driving dimensions of international relations: on the one hand, the condition of
war, and, on the other hand, inclination for security (and the desire of ease and
sensual delight, the fear of death and wounds, the desire of knowledge and arts of
peace, etc), with ensuing analytical results.
126
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXXI, p. 162.
72
However, in order to provide the complete picture of Thomas Hobbes’
views in political philosophy, analysis should be extended further. Separate
aspects of discussion being the relation between his doctrine and political liberalism. Some authors even credit Hobbes as the co-founder of liberalism.
However, Thomas Hobbes is definitely not a founder, he can accurately be
described as one of the predecessors of liberalism or the author, whose ideas
paved the path for the eventual birth of liberalism, in many respects. This argument is supported by many of his fundamental conceptions, for example: 1.
In the conception of the foundational covenant in the institutional model (the
way of Institution) of a state formation; 2. In the ideas concerning the obligations of a sovereign, the freedom of subjects; 3. ideas on the human nature;
this list can further be extended.
1. it is true, that for Thomas Hobbes the foundational covenant concluded by the way of institution for the sovereign power exists only in the
space in between the humans, and it, as the source of obedience (obligations) of the sovereign power does not exist in itself at the moment
of its conclusion; though, to some degree, Hobbes also links the sovereign with the divine authority for the integrity, indivisibility, earthly
supremacy, and overall, for the priority of strengthening the sovereign
power, however, his arguments on the origins of the state and the sovereign power formation differ significantly from the dominant interpretations prevalent during his and previous eras. In this work, special
emphasis is put on the covenant between the humans and their complex relationship with the sovereign.
2. In parallel, though, Thomas Hobbes argues that the subjects do not have
the right to change the form of the government, protest or discuss the
orders of a sovereign or punish him,127 however, Hobbes still assigns
some obligations towards his subjects for the sovereign, for example:
the need to guarantee the security for his subjects, founding of the
rules/laws, organizing taxation on equal basis, etc.128 Subjects in their
turn, are not fully disposed of rights. Speaking of the liberty of the sub-
127
128
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XVIII.
“To equal justice appertaineth also the equal imposition of taxes; the equality whereof
dependeth not on the equality of riches, but on the equality of the debt that every
man oweth to the Commonwealth for his defence.”, Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXX, p.
157.
73
jects, Hobbes’ main argument is built around the following principle: –
everything that is not prohibited or regulated by the sovereign is allowed; meaning that the subject has the freedom there the sovereign
does not make his will known. Moreover, subjects have the right to defend their lives, the right to disobey any order promulgating the selfinjuries (“covenants not to defend a man’s own body are void”, “If the
sovereign command a man, though justly condemned, to kill, wound, or
maim himself; or not to resist those that assault him; or to abstain from
the use of food, air, medicine, or any other thing without which he cannot live; yet hath that man the liberty to disobey.”), etc.129
3. moreover, by declaring freedom and equality the basic pillars of the
human nature in his political philosophy, he undermines the aristocratic-hierarchical system of his era and the middle ages as well the
doctrine of the divine or natural right of rule, for which inequality between the humans was declared central/natural. Therefore, even from
this perspective, he develops a philosophy which differs significantly
from the mainstream approaches prevalent in his era.
Consequently, even from the preselected angles outlined here, he in some
sense knocks on the door of liberalism without opening it. But he did not try to
pass over the threshold on the road that would lead to liberalism.
129
Thomas Hobbes, cited, XXI.
74