TIF - Exodus Constitutionalism
UPENDRA BAXI
July 3, 2020
Multiple disasters and mass catastrophes have been on display in the migrant
crises following the Covid-19 lockdown. In its light, India’s constitutionalism
might be called ‘Exodus Constitutionalism’, a development that threatens to
devalue citizenship.
Exodus, marking the liberation of the people of Israel from slavery in Egypt under the leadership of Moses, is the
foundation of the Hebrew Bible. But as a meaning of dispossession or forcible mass movement of people it
constitutes a universal historical experience.
1.
It is estimated that in 2019 international migrants comprised 272 million. Well over 41 million were internally
displaced persons, and the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees now uses the concept of nexus
dynamics to refer to “situations where conflict and/or violence and disaster and/or adverse effects of climate
change exist in a country of origin”. Recently, the UN Civil and Political Rights Committee ruled that “potential
human rights violations caused by climate change should be taken into account by nations considering the
deportation of asylum seekers”. It is estimated by the World Bank that 143 million people from South Asia, Latin
America, and Sub-Sharan Africa will constitute climate-driven migrants by 2050.
A quick recitation of well-known global statistics is no substitute for a sensitive real-life understanding of the
challenge that migrants face in cheating their way into existence and survival. As Hannah Arendt reminded us all
on the eve of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the abstract figure of the human person obscures from
view, almost to a vanishing point, the lived reality of the stateless and asylum-seeking refugees constituting the
real horror of abject rightlessness. She stressed the basic human right to natality, a right to belong to a political
Page 1
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
community, and expected it to follow the entailments of the “right to have rights” (see Birmingham
2006, Parekh 2004, Michelman 1996).
The phenomenon of the Covid-19 migrant on the move was all about
the senseless social suffering that thingified human beings and
converted their suffering into commodities…
We are treated to abundant and elaborate televisual news and views, constitutionally enriched judicial suo motu
phrases, elaborate rhapsodies of party political performances, social media comments, activist lawyer and citizen
petitions to the courts, a forest of administrative policy and programmes, and the din of dissent, plus more. All
this may not carry the authentic migrant voice. To borrow the words of Ian Anderson, the songwriter of
the 1970s rock group Jethro Tull, all this is “but a whisper” which can “make us feel”, while our “deafness a
shout” that cannot “make us think”.
And the poet says: “In the tidal destruction the moral melee/The elastic retreat rings the close of play”, and
“sandcastle virtues are all swept away”. The migrant workers walk endless miles and miles while all “wise men
don’t know how it feels /To be thick as a brick” Nor ever will they know fully what it means to die on a suitcase in
a railway station and have a toddler uncover the dead body of a migrant mother; or be mowed away on the
tracks by a speeding train while succumbing to a fatigue-induced slumber; or be gang raped while on the move
or in a state shelter.
Jethro Tull and his companions lived in an era in which no social media images went viral, but they developed a
lyric and song where some unwise folks at least sensed what it was “to be as thick as a brick”. The phenomenon
of the Covid-19 migrant on the move was all about the senseless social suffering that thingified human beings
and converted their suffering into commodities in markets of governance, justice, development, and human
rights.
2.
Of necessity, this conversation mainly engages a peculiarly poignant set of contexts, conditions, and
circumstances of what I call ‘exodus constitutionalism’. But in order to get there a few preliminary points need to
be made.
First and most crucial, no one in the world could claim recipe-knowledges that may address a sinister global
pandemic. The state and society have a common agenda to fight a global pandemic. No state action can hope to
succeed without intelligent cooperation of citizens and no constitutionally sincere citizen may justifiably think
that the state managers and institutions are dispensable.
Indeed, the state must exercise great vigil over the situation and seek to provide conditions adequate to the
security of a right to life and living with dignity and security. What is also needed besides rights-based
consideration is ‘resilient’ politics based on empathy.
1
Epistemic humility is then a first virtue of the tasks and labours of governance, development, rights and justice.
What matters is not the willingness to strike accompanied by the fear of being wounded, but the willingness and
ability on all sides to learn from manifest and latent mistakes in law, policy, and governance accompanied by
rapid course-correction.
Epistemic humility requires us all to learn from and listen to each
Page 2
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
other, and not take recourse to antagonistic politics that divides
people into the friend and the enemy.
Second, not just the social activists but the bureaucracy, security, and political elites need always to accept the
accumulated constitutional wisdom of the judiciary. A subservient judiciary and a sycophantic legal profession
(and media) are no friends of a democratic order. If the Supreme Court is to remain a “last resort of the
bewildered and the oppressed” (in the immortal words of Justice P K Goswami), adjudicatory co-governance of
the nation (the wisdom of the people speaking through courts, or demosprudence) is as essential as is
legisprudence (the wisdom of the legislators) and jurisprudence (the wisdom of the jurists). Pooling these
wisdoms is the need of the hour in combating Covid-19.
Third, this pandemic renders political oneupmanship or hyperpartisanship entirely superfluous and downright
dangerous. Epistemic humility requires us all to learn from and listen to each other, and not take recourse to
antagonistic politics that divides people into the friend and the enemy. If nothing else, Covid-19 should teach us
to care for each other and co-learn from fellow-citizens, rather than use the arsenal of law to silence or punish
free and responsible acts of speech and expression, howsoever inconvenient or irritating these may prove to
those who hold power. To accuse each other of defamation, hurting religious or cultural sensitivities, sedition or
even treason is an undemocratic vice not to be celebrated.
3.
All policy formulations must rely on the postulate that constitutional and core human rights are not an adversary
but an ally in the fight against Covid-19 and related evils. An infected body is not just a source of contagion but
also a human citizen, a being with basic rights. A recent report in the Lancet (Gostin, Monahan, Kaldor et al
2019) stresses that the capacity of the law to act as “a social determinant” of health has been “underutilized”
and stresses “evidence-based legal interventions,” which should “build the research case for legal action”. It
appeals to the “global health community” to “oppose laws that undermine the right to health and to equity”,
especially those laws that “stigmatize or discriminate against marginalised populations” as these are “especially
harmful and exacerbate health disparities”.
We also need to attend to the views that tend to place migrants into homogenous and heterogenous categories
for different purposes. For example, as the UN International Organization for Migration (IOM) for whom a
migrant is broadly “any person who is moving or has moved across an international border or within a state away
from his/her habitual place of residence, regardless of (1) the person’s legal status; (2) whether the movement is
voluntary or involuntary; (3) what the causes for the movement are; or (4) what the length of the stay is”.
There is, also, no such thing as ‘migrants’ but only persons and
groups with distinctively (and often disturbingly) different needs and
abilities…
This agency-specific wide definition is useful to map out cross-border and within-nation voluntary and forced
migration. On the other hand, there is another view that accentuates differentiation between voluntary and
involuntary, free or forced, migration. In this sense, we preserve distinct categories such as immigrants, asylumseekers, other necessitous migrants, internally displaced persons (IDPs), stateless peoples, persecuted religious
minorities, and ecological exiles. Further, ‘migrants’ form a heterogeneous mass who have not merely the same
basic material needs (food, clothing, shelter, health. literacy and numeracy) and non-material needs (dignity,
privacy, freedoms, participation, information, and access), but also such vertical needs. There is, also, no such
thing as ‘migrants’ but only persons and groups with distinctively (and often disturbingly) different needs and
Page 3
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
abilities: divided by age (from infants to senior citizens), sex and gender, health (the coexistence of earlier
morbidity), disability, and ways of belonging to religious, cultural, spiritual, and civilizational communities.
We concern ourselves here with forced migration of IDPs. Indeed, every time we use the general appellation
‘migrants’ or ‘internally displaced persons’,2 we must fully know the existential horror reflected in their social
biographies: the economic, social and political conditions and contexts which make people move from the
domicile of birth to the domicile (of their necessitous and precarious) ‘choice’.
4.
How do the anti-Covid-19 strategies and contexts in India cope with both individual human and social suffering?
Some imposition of this suffering has been considered as a necessary evil and bearing it gracefully is considered
as a badge of national unity and patriotism. Some suffering must be classified as ‘surplus’ or unnecessary
suffering.
To point out to some structural limits of the anti-Covid-19
programmes is surely not to indulge in any anti-national, seditious or
treasonable conduct.
Such suffering occurs when every individual person is regarded as a potential carrier of disease and exposed to
state and social management. Epidemiology regards each person as a unit of contagion and the law becomes the
instrument for management of contagion, followed by testing, treatment, isolation, distancing and therapy. Law
emerges as an adjunct of intense public health management, in turn morphed into a public culture of self-care
(frequently washing hands, wearing masks in public places, and ‘social’ distancing). Is sheer survival of individuals
and society as a whole to be considered as paramount to the management of a global pandemic in which all
constitutional values remain secondary? Or, should it also be the case that anti-Covid-19 performances must not
violate basic human rights? For example, the human right to health may not be held incompatible with the
human right to live with dignity, or the new penal laws and action should also bear in view social stigma as a
mechanism of instant control.
Difficult questions are raised concerning the imposition of the lockdown or its partial lifting. Epidemiologists and
health experts continue to differ on different models of scientific uncertainty. But no education in the obvious is
necessary to say that even the simple rules of hygiene are not observable in conditions of extreme
impoverishment or migrants on the move. Governments have done well to launch a campaign for civic education
and in suppling masks, soaps, and even water. But these can do very little in reducing physical distancing in slums
or slum-like conditions which manifest the malaise of unconstitutional mass impoverishment. To point out to
some structural limits of the anti-Covid-19 programmes is surely not to indulge in any anti-national, seditious or
treasonable conduct. Rather, it highlights the importance of more intense implementation of the Directive
Principles of State policy and the performance of fundamental duties as provided by Part IV-A of the
Constitution of India.
[W]hatever one may say about its design and detail, the principle of
federalism as an essential aspect of the basic structure of the
Constitution remains necessary to sustain social diversity and human
dignity.
Page 4
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
Second the pressing need to put an anti-Covid-19 framework in place makes unusually difficult a fresh legal start
for managing the nation. Drastic measures like lockdowns and zoning require taking the toxic dust off from the
four-section colonial Epidemic Diseases Act, 1897, and naming the happening as a ‘disaster’ within the meaning
of the Disaster Management Act, 2005 (DMA). This did help governments acquire an arsenal of discretionary
police powers, enforce social discipline, introduce many new measures of epidemiological surveillance, and
resort to volatile forms of biopower and biopolitics. However, it is good to come across normative constitutional
and statutory limits. For example, section 61 of the DMA prohibits “discrimination on the ground of sex, caste,
community, descent or religion” in the administration of compensation and relief to the victims of disaster, but
this should not remain a prescription more honoured in breach rather than compliance.3
In a deep constitutional irony, a command and control planned national economy — the Essential Commodities
Act, 1955 — now helps neoliberal India combat Covid-19. It enabled the central government on 13 March 2020 to
declare masks and hand sanitizers as essential commodities until 30 June. This law’s vast potential to control
production, supply, distribution and to secure their equitable distribution and availability at fair prices, is once
again writ large on the economy and the nation. So remains its potential for use in life after Covid-19.
Third, whatever one may say about its design and detail, the principle of federalism as an essential aspect of the
basic structure of the Constitution remains necessary to sustain social diversity and human dignity. Asymmetric
federalism is not always irredentist or secessionist; it also promotes “the conditions of an enlarged democratic
setting’… by leveraging group ‘equality, inclusive participation and justice’ which ‘deepen the legitimacy and
strengthen the functionality of multinational states” (Hausig 2011, 89). Unsurprising is the fact that “extensive
empirical case studies […] conclusively show that all durable multinational states also happen to be federal
democratic states” (Ibid).
5.
An endemic feature of Indian politics, and probably all party-political systems everywhere is the processes of
politicisation of catastrophe. The term ‘catastrophizing’ has been long used by social psychologists to
characterise a social disposition, but Adi Ophir (an Israeli political philosopher, whose work should be better
known in India), explicitly links it with the distribution of evils, including (if I may use my words) radical suffering
of the constitutional have nots. Ophir describes this political process of “the sudden or gradual rise in evils”, its
“quantity, quality, frequency, span of distribution, and durability” – in short, a rise in “the volume of evils” and
the “accompanying decline in the availability and effectiveness of means of protection, healing, and restoration”.
Indeed, such internal processes where natural and man-made disasters often work conjointly to “create
devastating effects on a large population” and represent the “very avalanche of evils that injure entire
populations” (Ophir 2010). Cognate insights are offered by the Nigerian thinker Clade Ake (1994) in speaking
about the “democratization of disempowerment” and the Cameroonian philosopher Achilles Mbembe (2019)
who has accentuated the “necrophiliac” nature of power.
If the spread of a global pandemic was an act of misfortune, its
catastrophization has to be located in the injustices of social
structure and policy.
This combination of multiple disasters and mass catastrophe is on abundant display in the migrant crises. First,
the policy inadvertence which lasted till 29 April, and second the difficulties since then in making transport and
related facilities available to migrants on the move. We all know of the costs to be borne by the originary states
of migrant workers, the so-called ‘bus politics’ or ‘train politics’, and the repatriation of some migrant workers to
the host states. If the spread of a global pandemic was an act of misfortune, its catastrophization has to be
located in the injustices of social structure and policy. On the other side, the spectacular emergence of new
Page 5
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
communities of belonging (social groups trying to meet the many needs of migrants on the move), which
counter the politics of creating communities of danger, hopefully will become a post-Covid-19 future, ending
forever the production of social indifference.
6.
The Covid-19 styles of law and administration all over the globe enhance the powers of the administrative
biopolitical state. But from its inception, India’s apex court has acquiesced in the constitutional fact of vast
powers to make law and policy. The presumption of the constitutionality of state laws and policies still stands.
The judicial doctrine of harmonious construction in the sphere of conflicting rights in Parts III and IV of the
Constitution still prevails. Administrative mala fides remain difficult to prove; and the courts in interpreting the
constitution still hold that the mere possibility of abuse of power is not a ground for not conferring it. Further,
several draconian security and anti-terror and related economic offences have been held constitutionally valid.
And let us recall that as late as in the Kesavananda Bharati case (1973), six Supreme Court justices ruled in favour
of Parliament’s absolute power to change the basic structural constitutional identity and many justices even
today believe in judicial self-restraint.
[I]t must be reiterated that the conflict between the
legislative/executive combine and adjudicative constitutional
interpretation stands ingrained in the Constitution itself as a vital
aspect of republican democracy.
Yet the indictment of judicial overreach survives and grows, as an example of successful political (and even
academic) propaganda since the dawn of the Constitution! But (without exploring here my writings), it must be
reiterated that the conflict between the legislative/executive combine and adjudicative constitutional
interpretation stands ingrained in the Constitution itself as a vital aspect of republican democracy. We may learn
from it but cannot eliminate it.
And the differences between competitive power politics and the constitutional politics of courts needs to be
always re-explored. The latter may be occasionally jurispathic (rulings that are coercive) but is never selfinterested. Justices do not decide disputes or contentions on considerations of personal benefit, even when the
quality of justice they produce may be contested.
The heightened use of suo motu proceedings by the Supreme Court and the high courts has been quite
remarkable in times of Covid-19. Aggressive monitoring by as many as 19 high courts of administrative schemes
and local institutional management procedures is an aid, rather than an obstacle, to more effective anti-Covid-19
action (as, for example, in situations of domestic violence, inadequate nutrition, and release of undertrial
prisoners on bail).
How to make the invisible socially visible is another name for social action litigation (SAL), still conflated with the
so-called public interest litigation (PIL). Even if considered identical twins, each has a different constitutional
visage. SAL is dialogical, not adversarial. The protracted ‘hope and trust’ jurisdiction is inherent to SAL and not an
aberration, even though in PIL we may prefer certain instantly desired outcomes.
The vast executive and administrative structures claim, and rightly
so, to be sensitive to people’s misery in a global pandemic. But does
that necessarily mean that courts and justices may not speak at all?
Page 6
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
Still the SAL power and process may be criticised when dismissal of well-reasoned petitions amounts to judicial
abdication. Whether such abdication occurred or not in relation to the migrant labour exodus is a hotly
contested issue, both inside and outside the Court. A Supreme Court bench has referred to the central
government the detailed SWAN report on stranded migrant workers, and articulated the ‘hope and trust’ SAL
jurisdiction to trigger appropriate policy and on-the-ground action.4 Sometime later, a different bench took
urgent suo motu action and issued some interim directions.5 Welcome though this step is, on a better-late-than
never principle, it is too soon to make even informed guesses on how these directions will work in the daily life
of those on the move. We may also ask whether the adversarial litigation is more to be preferred compared with
suo motu action.6
The vast executive and administrative structures claim, and rightly so, to be sensitive to people’s misery in a
global pandemic. But does that necessarily mean that courts and justices may not speak at all? Is not there a
difference between a rights-based solicitude and the more routine policymaking tasks? Judicializing the issue of
mass public health, monitoring of the supply of essential medicines and testing, conditions in public hospitals
and costs in private ones, for example, mark judicial itineraries of normative cooperative action to sensitise and
redirect the local executive regarding specific issues otherwise solely left to health and other experts.7
There is lots to be learnt on all sides from those who decided to walk across the length and breadth of India that
is Bharat; this mass civil disobedience met with some law and order type preventive or punitive response.But
undeterred, they marched on very long distances on foot, gambling with exhaustion, hunger, disease, fatigue
and even death. Neither policy, nor political, actors thought that such “mass illegalities” (to use a striking phrase
of Michel Foucault) were ever possible and therefore did not anticipate legal ways to solicit compliance. We
should also accept that the migrant labourers acted as individual moral actors, rather than as an inert mass of
moral patients.
7.
While not offering any fully-fledged theory of this form here, I suggest in that our constitutionalism may truly be
called exodus constitutionalism, acting as the other of ordinary democratic constitutionalism. In a sense, border
control is the insignia of the sovereignty of a modern state and marks the beginning of geopolitics. The good
side of this is what Hannah Arendt was to call natality: a political community to which one may belong. The flip
side is the terrible reality of statelessness: a being without any national identity and having the status of a global
pariah as a refugee or asylum-seeker, a quintessentially a rightless human being.
Exodus constitutionalism is born and thus always at work with ordinary constitutionalism but it also stands often
at the crossroads of political and judicial power. One may here usefully borrow from life sciences the imagery of
the host and parasite, to learn how the latter begins the dance of its own destruction while populating the host. I
know that the analogy is stressful in Covid-19 days, but as the great French philosopher Jacques Derrida once
described it, this relation constitutes a viral trajectory: “an inert code that replicates itself by using a host,” by
making “an unsuspecting host ingest it; to force the host’s internal machinery to make new copies of the virus;
and to spread as many of these copies as possible, in order to maximize the possibility of infecting new hosts”.
The virus “requires a more complex host to invade and destroy but cannot live by itself.” The “virus being many
things […] in part a parasite that destroys, that introduces disorder into communication […] it derails a
mechanism of the communicational type, its coding and decoding [... it] is neither alive nor dead.” (quoted in
Barnett and Wills 1994, Salingaros 2015).
Extended to the constitutional text, Covid-19 and the epic tragedy of mass migration, we find the same disease
of a “combinational type” that introduces “disorder” and death “in communication”.
The Constitution of India may well be said to provide a leading contemporary text of exodus constitutionalism.
Composed in the poignant times of the Partition of India, the Constitution itself was written with blood. It bears
Page 7
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
many birthmarks of its foundational violence — 20 million people — Hindus, Sikhs, and Muslims constituted the
largest mass migration in human history. Since then many exoduses have happened, marked with considerable
violence. The Planning Commission of India in 2012 stated that since Independence in 1947, about 60 million
people had been displaced by development projects. And the 2017 India Migration Report acknowledges that
apart “from conflicts and disasters, over the years, development projects, including urban redevelopment and
beautification, have displaced large numbers of people from different parts of the country”.
The Constitution of India may well be said to provide a leading
contemporary text of exodus constitutionalism – composed in the
poignant times of the Partition of India, the Constitution itself was
written with blood.
The constitutional development has been thus haunted by many an involuntary mass migration, from the mass
exodus of the Kashmiri Pandits to now Covid-19 threatened mass migrants often walking to their distant homes
from many populous Indian states they had once made their own. It is estimated that in the first phase of the
lockdown about 5 million (see the complex analysis by Nomaan Majid 2020), although the statistical scenarios
fluctuate widely and are as diasporic as the migrants on the move (Seema Chishti 2020).
Exodus constitutionalism crystallises the dilemma of dates. Our citizenship provisions stipulated in Articles 3–5
of the Constitution expose this. So do the recent memories of the conjoint working of the Citizenship Act of
1955 and its amendments, the 1946 Foreigners Act, the 1964 Foreigners (Tribunal) Order, and the adjudicatory
leadership of the Supreme Court resulting in some forcible detentions and migrations in Assam.
8
What may one say are the main characteristics of an exodus constitutionalism? First, at the heart of every
constitution there pulsates a distinction between ‘us’ and ‘them’, the constitutional self and the constitutional
others. In this sense, even when the other may not always be regarded as an enemy, constitutional identity
depends a great deal on the distinction (rendered famous by Carl Schmitt) between the ‘friend’ and the ‘enemy’.
The USA is often cited as an example of restricted citizenship because no foreign born naturalized citizen can run
for the office of president, but restrictions based on citizenship for contesting or voting at elections and
occupying public offices are common to most societies.
Second, the status of citizenship is available through Articles 5–9 of Part II of the Constitution, and Parliament
may make further law (which it has through the Citizenship Act or Foreigners Act). But citizenship is a sovereign
decision of the state and not a fundamental right. Parliament by simple majority may decide who may count as
citizen and the supreme judiciary seems in no constitutional hurry to decide thorny constitutional issues thus
arising and now raised by a few states and social action petitioners.
Third, exodus constitutionalism enhances the vulnerabilities of the populations affected. Even the term
‘Covid-19 migrant workers’ does not fully disclose various vulnerabilities specific to the very young as well as
very old, women at work (notably sex-work and domestic labour), and married women. According to the 2011
Census, about 205.8 million women in India migrated for marriage; an extraordinary fact illustrating how
marriage is related to migration. The demography of migration also varies strikingly, as we all know.
Fourth, a devaluation of citizenship is typical of exodus constitutionalism. IDPs (whether victims of natural
disasters or of conflict and violence, or certain practices of development as governance) are often treated as
objects rather than subjects of governance. This distinction has been affirmed by the UN Declaration on the Right
to Development (Baxi 2007). IDPs signify kaleidoscopically changing situations in which constitutional othering
always takes place, often making the culmination of the process of ‘thingification’.
Page 8
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
Many other variations exist. But it is high time that we recognize ways in which we continue to repudiate the
foundational postulate of the Declaration of Philadelphia in 1919 that birthed the International Labour
Organization. It enunciated a century ago that “labour is not a commodity” and that “all human beings,
irrespective of race, creed or sex, have a right to pursue both their material well-being and their spiritual
development in conditions of freedom and dignity, of economic security and equal opportunity.” These are also
the solemn pledges of the Constitution of India. Shall we allow forms of exodus constitutionalism to further
override it?9
The India Forum welcomes your comments on this article for the Forum/Letters section.
Write to editor@theindiaforum.in.
References:
Ake, Clade. 1994. Democratization of Disempowerment in Africa. Lagos: Malthouse Press.
Baxi, Upendra. 2007. Human Rights in a Posthuman World: Critical Essays. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Birmingham, Peg. 2006. Hannah Arendt and Human Rights: The Predicament of Common
Responsibility. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Burnett, Peter and David Wills. 1994. Deconstruction and the Visual Arts: Art, Media, Architecture. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Chisti, Seema (2020) 'Explained: How many migrant workers displaced?: A range of estimates'. Indian Express, 8
June 2020.
Gostin, Lawrence O, John T Monahan, Jenny Kaldor, et al. 2020. 'The legal determinants of health: harnessing
the power of law for global health and sustainable development'. Lancet 393 (10183):1857‐1910.
Hausing, Kham Khan Suan. 2014. 'Asymmetric Federalism and the Question of Democratic Justice in Northeast
India'. India Review 13 (2): 87-111.
Jayal, Niraja Gopal. 2013. Citizenship and its Discontents: An Indian History. Cambridge,MA: Harvard University
Press.
Kannabiran, Kalpana. 2020. 'Justice and Rights in a Viral Contexts in India'. The India Forum. 2 May 2020.
Majid, Nomaan. 2020. 'How many casual workers in the cities have sought to go home?' The India Forum. 5 June
2020.
Mander, Harsh. 2020. 'Migrant Workers, the Lockdown, and the Judiciary'. The India Forum. 11 May 2020.
Mbembe, Achilles. 2019. Necropolitics (Durham: Duke University Press).
Michelman, Frank. 1996. 'Parsing 'A Right to Have Rights'. Constellations 3 (2): 200-209.
Ophir, Adi. 2010. 'The Politics of Catastrophization'. In Contemporary States of Emergency: The Politics of Military
and Humanitarian Interventions, edited by Didier Fassin and Mariella Pandolfi, 40-61. New York: Zone Books.
Parekh, Serena. 2004. 'A Meaningful Place in the World: Hannah Arendt on the Nature of Human Rights'. Journal
of Human Rights 3 (1): 41-53.
Salingaros, Nikos. 2003. 'The Derrida Virus.' Telos 126: 66-82
Page 9
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
Singh, Chander Uday. 2020. 'The Supreme Court is in Thrall of Government'. The Wire. 28 May 2020.
Tags:
Constitutionalism
Exodus
Exodus Constitutionalism
Constitution
Rights
Judiciary
COVID-19
Migrants
Mass Migration
Epistemic Humility
pandemic
Right to Health
Footnotes:
1.
2.
See Justice B Pardiwala and Justice Ilesh J Vohra in the Gujarat High Court decision 22 May 2020 who
summoned “resilient” and “dynamic” leadership and the role of “emotional intelligence” in these “testing
times” for the ruled and rulers alike.
It is surprising that the constitutional protection accorded to IDPs by Justice Gita Mittal in P.K. Koul v Estate
Officer is insufficiently put to use now. That landmark 2010 decision of Delhi High Court not merely
reiterated the right to housing as a core human right but reiterated (paragraph 34 onwards) the famous
principles enunciating the human rights of IDPs. She also bemoaned the “hyper-technical” approach adopted
by the union government in relation to the housing of the violently displaced Kashmiri Pandits.
3.
4.
5.
As late as 27 May 2020, Chief Justice S A Bobde and Justices A S Bopanna and Hrishikesh Roy took serious
notice of a Jamait Ulama-i-Hind averment that “communal colour being given to the outbreak of the Covid-19
pandemic by certain sections of print, electronic and social media posing a threat to the life and liberty of
Muslims infringing their fundamental rights under Article 21 of the Constitution. The demonization is also an
infringement of the right to live with dignity which is also covered under Article 21 of the Constitution." The
News Broadcasters Association (NBA) as well as Additional Solicitor General K M Natraj were directed to file a
reply explaining inaction by the government under sections 19 and 20 of the Cable Televisions Networks
(Regulation) Act, 1995.
Per Justices N R Ramana, Sanjay Kishan Kaul, and B R Gavai on 24 April 2020. The situation of the stranded
migrant workers was highlighted in public discourse by three petitions, respectively, by: (1) Mahua Moitra and
Swami Agnivesh, on behalf of migrant workers seeking various other reliefs; (2) Aruna Roy and Nikhil Dey,
seeking payment of wages to registered MGNREGA households by the government, in consonance with the
Ministry of Labour’s direction of 20 March 2020 to chief secretaries of all states directing that during the
coronavirus pandemic, all workers be paid “full wages without any deductions”; and (3) Harsh Mander and
Anjali Bharadwaj. See Singh (2020) and Mander (2020).
See an altogether different suo motu order by Ashok Bhushan, Sanjay Kishen Kaul, and M R Shah JJ on 26
May 2020, concerning “the problems and miseries of migrant workers.”
Page 10
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020
6. We would never know whether the late-night letter by some superannuated justices of the Supreme Court
and high courts and by some eminent senior counsel addressed to the Supreme Court made a vital difference
to the judicial attitudes the next morning.
7.
8.
9.
Yet, the judiciary may not always speak with one voice; the US Supreme Court on 29 May 2020, for example,
denied relief to the church that had asked for the Pentecost Sunday celebrations. Chief Justice John Roberts
held that “when restrictions on particular social activities should be lifted during the pandemic, … is a
dynamic and fact-intensive matter subject to reasonable disagreement” and the courts should not “secondguess the choices ….” made by “politicians”. But dissenting justices Clarence Thomas, Neil Gorsuch, and
Brett Kavanaugh maintained that the restrictions were not justified when others are permitted; “malls, pet
groomers, hair salons and marijuana dispensaries – are comparable to gatherings at houses of worship, and
California has not shown a good reason for treating houses of worship differently” and notably that religious
organizations are “comparable secular businesses.”
See the magisterial study by Niraja Gopal Jayal (2013). There, she speaks, among other valuable things, of
how cherished and at the same time contested the concept of citizenship has become and of ‘legal’ and
‘aspirational’ citizenship and the conflicts between the individual and collective dimensions of citizenship and
identity.
Kalpana Kannabiran (2020) suggestively evokes the concept of “constitutional commons”, appealing to “a
robust memory of the Constitution, of the directive principles”, and counsels that we “ act on that basis
alone”, subjecting all forms of state action to “empathy and a deep ethical commitment to constitutional
morality.” Constitutional commons are not achieved or preserved by action that escalates “the assertion of
prerogative and the distribution of largess”. We return to Mbembe’s quest, then, of “a politics that no longer
necessarily rests upon diffference or alterity but instead on a certain idea of the kindred and the incommon.” (2019, 40.
The idea of constitutional commons is one way to roll back ‘exodus constitutionalism’ but perhaps we need
to ask: (1) how the ‘in-common’ deals with the politics of identity and difference; and (2) how the practices of
subaltern nonviolent normative insurgency may begin to reshape politics and bring democracy near to
people’s constitutionalism. This set of themes form many a challenge for the post Covid-19 world.
Page 11
www.TheIndiaForum.in July 3, 2020