367
Justifying the Right of Return
David Miller*
With the Israeli-Palestinian conflict in mind, this Article asks whether
there is a human right to return to one’s country, and if so what
justifies it. Although such a right is widely recognized in international
law, who can claim it and on what basis remains ambiguous; the
ambiguity is revealed by asking what “country” means in “return to
one’s country.” I argue that to treat the right simply as an adjunct of
citizenship is too narrow an approach, even though the right has a
role to play in managing inter-state relations. As with other human
rights, personal autonomy might be proposed as a justification for
the right of return. But although the autonomy interest in developing
long-term life-plans may explain the right not to be forcibly displaced
from the place where you live, it cannot explain why there is a right
to return once displaced, particularly in the case of people who enjoy
an adequate set of options elsewhere. Instead we need to invoke the
need to belong to a homeland, access to which the right of return
protects. The Article explores a homeland’s different dimensions
and considers various respects in which the need to belong might be
thought too indeterminate to ground a right. Finally it distinguishes
and evaluates the return claims of Jews and Palestinians to Israel/
Palestine; only Palestinians whose homeland this remains can claim
a human right of return as analyzed and defended here.
*
Senior Research Fellow and Professor of Political Theory, Nuffield College,
University of Oxford. Earlier drafts of this Article were presented to the Workshop
in Practical Philosophy, University of Bergen, 9–10 May 2019, the Conference
on Historical Justice in the Context of the Israeli-Palestinian Conflict, Faculty of
Law, Tel Aviv University, 28–30 May 2019, and the Oxford/Queen’s workshop
in Legal and Political Philosophy, 10 June 2019. I am very grateful for comments
received on all these occasions, and especially to Professor Ruth Gavison who
acted as my respondent in Tel Aviv. Cite as: David Miller, Justifying the Right
of Return, 21 Theoretical Inquiries L. # (2020).
368
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
IntroductIon
According to Article 13 (2) of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights:1
Everyone has the right to leave any country, including his own, and
to return to his country.
This is a right we take for granted every time we travel abroad on business or
on holiday. It seems at first sight uncontroversial: we would be scandalized
if each time we returned to our country we had to do more than establish our
legal identity by producing a passport or other such document in order to be
admitted. We justifiably value the right to leave, but how much would that
right be worth if by leaving our country we ran the risk of never being allowed
back in? But matters are not so simple when we pass from individual cases
of return to collective cases. Now the right of return is likely to prove highly
contentious: think of displaced populations eager to return to their homelands,
and citing the right of return as their justification for being allowed to do so.
Perhaps the most prominent case is that of the exiled Palestinians, for whom
their right of return to historic Palestine has become an article of faith and
a major source of political contention. Equally, Jewish immigration to the
land of Israel is often justified as an exercise of Jews’ right to return to their
original homeland. Since it may not be possible jointly to satisfy both of these
claims to return, some would question whether the right of return applies in
these cases of mass movement. At the very least, we are in urgent need of
some clarity on whether return can be claimed as a human right, whether it
can be claimed by people moving en masse as well as singly, and if the right
does indeed exist, how it could be justified.
At this point I need to explain briefly how I understand human rights.2
They are moral rights that ought to be given legal recognition in both the
domestic law of states and international law. They serve to specify a global
minimum that people everywhere, regardless of societal membership or
cultural affiliation, are owed as a matter of justice. They are owed this in the
first place by those who wield power in the places where they are living—by
their governments, in the normal case. But if for some reason the local powerholders are unable or unwilling to deliver this minimum set of entitlements,
1
2
G.A. Res. 217 (III) A, Universal Declaration of Human Rights [hereinafter
UDHR] (Dec. 10, 1948).
I draw on my fuller treatment of this question in David Miller, Grounding Human
Rights, 15 CritiCal rev. int’l SoC. Pol. Phil., 407 (2012); David Miller, Border
Regimes and Human Rights, 7 l. ethiCS hum. rtS., 1 (2013); David Miller,
Personhood versus Human Needs as Grounds for Human Rights, in Griffin on
human riGhtS (Roger Crisp ed., 2014) [hereinafter Personhood].
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
369
then the responsibility falls on people and governments in other countries
to overcome the deficiency. To establish that a candidate right qualifies as a
human right, one must show that it forms an essential part of a set of rights
that together provide the right-holders with the opportunity to lead a minimally
decent human life. On my account, we begin with the core idea of a human
life itself as made up of a number of activities which are reiterated across the
many more specific forms of human life that have arisen at different times
and places. We can then identify a set of basic needs that must be fulfilled if a
decent human life is to be possible—material needs such as food and shelter,
but also needs to engage in communal life, to form intimate relationships,
to express one’s beliefs and cultural identity, and so forth. Human rights
secure the conditions under which these needs can be met. They do so either
by protecting people from threats that would prevent them from satisfying
their needs—such as being coerced not to engage in activities such as playing
music or engaging in a religious ritual—or by imposing obligations to provide
resources that fulfil needs, such as food or basic healthcare.
The present Article applies this general understanding of human rights
to the specific case of the right of return, which as we shall see often finds a
place in the major human rights documents that inform international law. I
will show, however, that we cannot achieve clarity on the nature and extent of
the right simply by examining the relevant sources from the UDHR onwards;
instead what we find is considerable ambiguity over what the right of return
actually means in practice (Part I). We therefore need to explore the right’s
moral foundations in an effort to resolve the ambiguity. I consider first whether
the right of return might be treated merely as an incident of citizenship, and
argue that at best this provides an incomplete justification (Part II). Next I
examine the currently most popular way of grounding the right, namely by
appeal to the value of individual autonomy, and argue that this, too, does not
succeed (Part III). Instead we need to appeal to a particular human need, the
need to belong to a homeland, in order to explain why return, specifically,
is a human right, while there is no equivalent right to enter countries other
than one’s own (Part IV).
Having defended such a need-based justification for the right of return, I
argue in the final Part of the Article that this provides us with a perspective
from which to evaluate specific return claims, such as the claims of Jews and
Palestinians to return to Israel/Palestine. It allows us to ask whether either
or both of these groups can justify return by appeal to human rights. It is
important to remind ourselves, however, that return claims can have a wider
significance than this. Both the right of return asserted by Palestinians and
370
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
Israel’s Law of Return (for Jews)3 have become laden with political meaning
over and above the assertion of a human right on the part of the groups in
question. They have become, in effect, ideological doctrines. Because the
phrase ‘the right of return’ has for both sides come to encapsulate claims
about historical responsibility, reparations, national identity and so forth,
taken as a whole these two doctrines are almost certainly incompatible.4 In
this context, it is very much worth asking what form of return either party to
the conflict can claim as a matter of human rights – which may well turn out
to be much less than they are currently claiming politically.
Note also that in focusing on return as a human right, I am setting aside
the wider issue of “justice in return,” which would involve enquiring into the
conditions under which return to one’s country would meet higher standards of
distributive and reparative justice.5 Questions such as the right to re-appropriate
abandoned property would be included under this heading. It would also
involve investigating the criteria according to which repatriation to one’s
homeland would qualify as fully voluntary.6 These are important questions,
but human rights ought not to be stretched to cover all aspects of justice. As
indicated above, they are best understood as devices to fulfil basic human
needs and to protect people from forms of political domination that would
prevent them from leading decent lives.7 So full justice certainly demands of
states that they should protect human rights, but it asks considerably more
than this. Here again, I am only dealing in this Article with questions that
arise directly from the idea of a human right of return.
3
4
5
6
7
Law of Return, 5710–1950, SH No. 51 p. 159, as amended (Isr.).
For supporting evidence, see for example Adina Friedman, Unraveling the
Right of Return, 21 RefuGe: Canada’S J. refuGeeS, 62 (2003); Nadim Rouhana,
Truth and Reconciliation: The Right of Return in the Context of Past Injustice,
in exile and return: PrediCamentS of PaleStinianS and JewS (Ann Lesch &
Ian Lustick eds., 2005).
See meGan Bradley, refuGee rePatriation: JuStiCe, reSPonSiBility and redreSS
44–64 (2013) [hereinafter refuGee rePatriation]; Megan Bradley, Is Return the
Preferred Solution to Refugee Crises? Exploring the moral value of the right
of return, in the PolitiCal PhiloSoPhy of refuGe (David Miller & Christine
Straehle eds., 2020).
See, e.g., Mollie Gerver, Refugee Repatriation and the Problem of Consent, 48
Brit. J. Pol. SCi., 855 (2016).
Supra note 2.
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
371
I. InterpretIng the rIght of return In
InternatIonal law
As indicated above, we cannot understand the right of return merely by
consulting the relevant international law documents. Nonetheless we need
to begin with these, not least because the existing philosophical literature
that addresses the topic is quite sparse.8 The UN Declaration is by no means
the only human rights document in which the right of return is listed. In
slightly different versions, it appears in the International Covenant on Civil
and Political Rights (ICCPR),9 the European Convention on Human Rights,10
the American Convention on Human Rights,11 the African Charter on Human
and Peoples’ Rights,12 and so forth. There are also more detailed statements,
such as the UN’s Draft Principles on Freedom and Non-Discrimination in
respect of the Right of Everyone to Leave Any Country, including His Own,
and to Return to His Country, and the Strasbourg Declaration on the Right
to Leave and Return.13 One might conclude from this that the right of return
is at the least clearly established and well defined as a human right under
international law. But that would be a mistake. As I shall explain shortly,
international lawyers themselves are quite conflicted about the meaning and
status of the alleged right. What might initially appear to be small differences
of wording between the various documents may conceal quite different ways
of understanding the right of return. In any case, we need to look beyond the
documents themselves, on the one hand to the actual practice of states, and
on the other to the moral grounding of the right, in order to grasp it properly.
I am going to start, however, by exploring the meaning of the right of return
as set out in the international charters and conventions, because the ambiguities
8
This may be because philosophers have frequently set themselves the more
ambitious task of justifying international freedom of movement. Clearly if that
could be defended, movement in the form of returning to one’s own country would
fall out as an easy case. Note, however, the philosophically informed work on
refugee repatriation, specifically, found in Bradley, refuGee rePatriationsupra
note 5; Katy lonG, the Point of no return: refuGeeS, riGhtS, and rePatriation
(2013) and mollie Gerver, the ethiCS and PraCtiCe of refuGee rePatriation
(2018).
9 G.A Res. 2200A (XXI) (Dec. 16, 1966).
10 Eur. Consult. Ass., Convention for the Protection of Human Rights (1950).
11 Organization of American States [OAS], American Convention on Human
Rights, (Nov. 22, 1969).
12 African Union, African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights, (June 21, 1981).
13 These are both conveniently reproduced as appendices to hurSt hannum, the
riGht to leave and return in international law and PraCtiCe (1987).
372
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
found there turn out to be revealing. The two most important ambiguities, for
present purposes, are these: what “country” means in phrases such as “return
to his country,” and whether the right of return is understood to be a right
exercisable only singly by individuals, or also includes the right exercised
collectively by large groups when they seek to return to their homelands. I
will discuss each of these ambiguities in turn.
In some formulations of the right we are discussing, the reference to
“country” is replaced by a reference to the claimant’s status as a national. For
example, The European Convention on Human Rights, Protocol 4, Article
3 (2) states:
No one shall be deprived of the right to enter the territory of the State
of which he is a national.14
If we compare the wording of this Article with the wording of the UDHR
Article with which I began, we see that in one respect it is more generous,
since it protects the right of entry of nationals who are not returning (i.e., those
who have never lived in the state but who qualify as its nationals), while in
another respect it is considerably less generous, since it excludes people who
may have lived in the state and regard it as their home, but are not nationals.
It also excludes those who have been deprived of their citizenship by the state
to whose territory they wish to return. (For present purposes, the distinction
between nationality in the legal sense and citizenship is unimportant, and I
will treat “national” and “citizen” as equivalent statuses in what follows.)
It is not clear whether the various international law documents recognize
the full significance of the distinction between “country” and “nationality”
in their formulations. Consider for example the wording of the UN Draft
Principles, section II:
(a) Everyone is entitled, without distinction of any kind, such as race,
colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or
social origin, property, birth, marriage or other status, to return to his
country.
(b) No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his nationality or forced to
renounce his nationality as a means of divesting him of the right to
return to his country.
(c) No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of the right to enter his own
country.15
14 Supra note 10, at Protocol No. 4, art. 3 (2).
15 Cited in hannum, supra note 13, at 147–48.
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
373
Clauses (a) and (c) interpret the right of return in such a way as to apply to
anyone returning to the place which they can justifiably claim to be their
own country regardless of whether they have the legal status of citizen there.
Clause (b), on the other hand, defends the right of return for nationals against
states who are tempted to undermine it by arbitrarily denationalizing those
of their citizens who they do not want to readmit. There is nothing strictly
incoherent in defending both versions of the right together—i.e., interpreting
it broadly so that it includes both everyone who can claim to be a genuine
returnee and everyone who qualifies as a national of the state in question—but
it is somewhat curious to see the latter sandwiched between two assertions of
the former as though the drafters did not recognize the ambiguity, or perhaps
consciously chose to blur it.16
To achieve greater clarity here, I propose to distinguish four possible
ways of specifying who can claim the right of return. The main distinction
is between residence-based (R) and citizenship-based (C) conceptions, but
each of these can be given a narrower or a wider interpretation.
The right of return to state S might be held by:
R1: Everyone who has lived in S for substantial periods of time and has
the right to reside permanently, whether or not they are also citizens.
R2: Everyone who has lived in S for substantial periods of time, whether
or not they have a formal legal entitlement to do so.
C1: Everyone who is legally a citizen of S, whether or not they have
resided in S.
C2: Everyone who is sufficiently connected to S by ties of inheritance,
culture, etc. so as to be “effectively” a national of S, whether or not
they are legally citizens or have resided in S.
International lawyers are divided on which of these gives the correct specification
of the right of return.17 Some argue that the right of return is tied directly to
nationality, and by way of justification point to the accompanying obligation
on the part of states not to undermine the right by arbitrarily depriving citizens
16 Further ambiguity is introduced by the fact that the relevant section is headed “The
Right of a National to Return to his Country,” which suggests that the drafters
all along intended these principles to apply only to nationals, the narrower view.
For evidence that the meaning of “country” was deliberately left imprecise by
those responsible for drafting the ICCPR, see Kathleen Lawand, The Right to
Return of Palestinians in International Law, 8 int’l J. refuGee l., 532, 549–50
(1996).
17 See also Jeremie Bracka, Past the Point of No Return? The Palestinian Right
of Return in International Human Rights Law, 6 melBourne J. int’l l., 272,
298–302 (2005).
374
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
of their nationality (C1).18 Others argue that the right applies to all those who
are lawfully present in a country, regardless of citizenship status: having
granted someone permanent residence, a state cannot then (unless there are
exceptional circumstances) refuse that person reentry if she leaves (R1).19
Support for interpretation R2 can be drawn from various documents connected
to the peace settlement in Bosnia/Herzegovina, including, for example,
Security Council Resolution 947, which “[a]ffirms the right of all displaced
persons to return voluntarily to their homes of origin in safety and dignity
with the assistance of the international community.”20 The phrase “homes of
origin” intuitively conveys the idea that someone who has once been settled
in a place has a right to return there, and this applies regardless of changes in
citizenship or other legal status such as came about through the breakup of
the Yugoslavian state. Finally, some commentators defend the rather broad
interpretation C2 by appeal to the Nottebohm decision of the International
Court of Justice,21 which used various criteria to determine which of two
countries an individual was “substantively” linked to, and in which therefore
he enjoyed “effective” (i.e., non-legal) nationality. The underlying rationale
for this way of understanding the right of return was spelt out by a contributor
to the 1972 Uppsala Colloquium, a meeting of legal and human rights experts
from 25 countries convened to examine the meaning of UDHR Article 13 (2):22
A person’s “country” is that to which he is connected by a reasonable
combination of such relevant criteria as race, religion, language, ancestry,
birth and prolonged domicile. Governments come and go, and their
political fluctuations and vagaries should not affect the fundamental
18 See, for example Paul SieGhart, the international law of human riGhtS 179
(1983); Ruth Lapidoth, The Right of Return in International Law, with Special
Reference to the Palestinian Refugees, in 16 iSrael yearBooK on human riGhtS
103 (Yoram Dinstein ed.,1986).
19 See, for example Stig Jagerskiold, The Freedom of Movement, in the international
Bill of riGhtS: the Covenant on Civil and PolitiCal riGhtS 180–81 (Louis
Henkin ed. 1981); hannum, supra note 13, at 56–60.
20 Cited in Alfred-Maurice de Zayas, The Right to One’s Homeland, Ethnic Cleansing,
and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia, 6 Crim. l.
f., 257, 311 (1995). For discussion of how the right of return was implemented in
this case, see Megan Bradley, Liberal Democracies’ Divergent Interpretations of
the Right of Return: Implications for Free Movement, in demoCratiC CitizenShiP
and the free movement of PeoPle (Willem Maas ed., 2013).
21 Nottebohm (Liech. v. Guat.), Judgment, 1955 I.C.J 1 (Apr. 6).
22 Supra, note 1, at Art. 13 (2).
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
375
right of human beings, such as the right to return to one’s own country
and to have a homeland. 23
I do not intend to try to establish which reading of the right of return in
international law is “correct,” even supposing that question has a definite answer
(perhaps different bodies of international law point in different directions).24
The implication we should draw is that different extensions of the right
correspond to different ways of justifying it, as I shall argue below. Before
moving beyond international law, however, I need to address its second
ambiguity, over whether the right of return can be asserted by individuals
when they are acting as part of larger groups, such that it can be appealed to
in cases like those that arise in the aftermath of ethnic cleansing, or the mass
exodus of refugees. Again, international lawyers give different answers to
this question.25 For some it seems obvious that if the individual members of
a group have the right of return, this must apply regardless of whether they
acting singly or as part of a larger movement of people. As Lawand puts it,
[t]he fact that an individual left his or her country as part of a mass
movement does not prejudice his or her rights as an individual. To
subsume an individual’s rights into those of the displaced group is
contrary to the objects and purposes of human rights instruments
generally and would render illusory most of the rights which they are
intended to protect.26
Against that, others argue that the relevant human rights documents were not
meant to apply to circumstances of mass movement. Jagerskiold, for example,
argues that the right of return contained in the ICCPR
is intended to apply to individuals asserting an individual right. There
was no intention here to address the claims of masses of people who
have been displaced as a by-product of war or by political transfers of
territory or population, such as the relocation of ethnic Germans from
23 the riGht to leave and to return: PaPerS and reCommendationS of the
international Colloquium held in uPPSala, Sweden, 19–21 June 1972 343 (Karel
Vasak & Sidney Liskofsky eds., 1976). “Prolonged domicile” is mentioned here,
but only as one of a number of factors that might be used to establish sufficient
connection, not as a necessary condition.
24 For cases yielding different interpretations of ICCPR Article 12(4), which
proclaims a person’s right to enter his own country, see Sarah JoSePh & meliSSa
CaStan, the international Covenant on Civil and PolitiCal riGhtS: CaSeS,
materialS and Commentary 408–17 (2013).
25 Bracka, supra note 18, at 302–03.
26 Lawand, supra note 17, at 543.
376
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
Eastern Europe during and after the Second World War, the flight of
the Palestinians from what became Israel, or the movement of Jews
from the Arab countries.27
There is no simple way to resolve this disagreement. On one side, we might
think that circumstances of mass expulsion or flight are precisely those in which
the right of return has its greatest importance, given the vulnerability of those
who are displaced. On the other side, the return of large numbers of people
to the territory of a state can raise questions about social order, democracy,
cultural identity, and so forth which seemingly cannot be dismissed simply
by proclaiming an individual right of return. To make further progress, we
need to explore some alternative ways of grounding the right, which will
prove to have implications for its content.
II. the rIght of return as a cItIzenshIp rIght
Consider first a way of grounding the right that is suggested by position
C1 above, which assigns the right of return only to nationals of the state in
question. This view implies that the right of return is one of the incidents of
citizenship. Just as the state cannot deprive one of its citizens of the right to
vote or the right to a fair trial, so it cannot deprive her of the freedom to reside
on the territory of the state, and must therefore allow her to reenter should
she decide at any time to leave. Having this right protects her access to the
other rights of citizenship. The state cannot relieve itself of its obligation
to her by forcing or inducing her to leave and then refusing to let her back
in. At the same time, it protects other states from having to incur unwanted
responsibilities. If a UK citizen emigrates to Canada, though without acquiring
citizenship there, and proves to be a burden on the Canadian state, Canada
can ask him to leave on the basis that the country he came from cannot refuse
to take him back. Obviously this will only work so long as the right of return
is accompanied by stringent constraints on the state’s right to denationalize
its citizens. But if such constraints are in place, then it seems we have found
a (statist) way of justifying the right of return.
The justification appeals both to the individual’s interest in not becoming
stateless (since with the right of return in place he can always reactivate his
citizenship rights in the country that first awarded them) and to the state’s
interest in being protected against unwelcome responsibilities; other states
27 Jagerskiold, supra note 20, at 180.
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
377
cannot simply expel their unwanted citizens and refuse to take them back.28 It
may be questioned whether this provides a suitable justification for the right
of return as a human right. This will depend on how far we are prepared to
allow human rights to be shaped not merely by the interests of their bearers
but also by the interests of the states that have to implement them.
Whatever view one takes on the last question, however, a right of return
tied in this way to citizenship as its justificatory ground will be subject to
some obvious limitations. First, it will not apply to people who leave a country
where they have no rights of citizenship, even if they have become dependent
on that country for their survival, or have close personal connections there.
A recent example was provided by the so-called “Windrush scandal” in the
UK, where people of Caribbean origin who had been living in the country
for 50 years or more, but had never formalized their status, suddenly found
themselves at risk of deportation and/or being refused reentry to the UK.29
Moreover, the right could be interpreted so as to exclude citizens living
abroad who have either already acquired a second citizenship in their new
country of residence or would be able to do so if they applied for one. For
these people, removing their right of return would not render them stateless,
since they have access to an alternative form of citizenship.
What seems to be missing, when the right of return is justified solely as a
way of protecting a person’s other rights as a citizen and avoiding statelessness,
is an appreciation of the fact that people have a separate strong interest in
being able physically to return to the place that they regard as their homeland,
which at this point could be understood either as a return to a physical location,
a return to a social network, or a return to a cultural community. In Part IV I
will look more closely at the idea of a homeland, and at how its component
parts are interrelated. For people with this interest, being offered citizenship
somewhere else, even if the basket of rights that comes with it is quite plentiful,
cannot substitute for being allowed to live in that special place. If this thought
is correct, then although states may have an interest in construing the right of
return narrowly so that it is held only by nationals in the formal sense (i.e.,
their own citizens), we need to look for a way of grounding the right that
28 Nevertheless, states may be tempted to place a more restrictive interpretation
of the right of return in the case of their own citizens, and a more expansive
interpretation in the case of citizens of other states who they are currently
sheltering (and want rid of), such as refugees. See the discussion in Bradley,
supra note 21.
29 The Empire Windrush was the ship that had brought around a thousand West
Indians to Britain in 1948 after an appeal posted in Jamaica for immigrants to
come and work in the UK. Their arrival was recorded via landing cards, but in
other respects their status in the UK was never clarified.
378
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
gives it a wider scope. That doesn’t mean that the justification explored in
this Part of the Article is irrelevant. Human rights frequently have multiple
groundings. In particular, a right can be grounded both in the direct interest
the bearer has in exercising the right, and in the supporting role it can play
vis-à-vis other rights. For example the right to freedom of speech is grounded
both in the speaker’s need for self-expression, and in the importance of free
speech for the effective exercise of democratic rights, by others as well as the
speaker. So it may be important to underline the way in which a right of return
protects a person’s status as citizen. But if we believe it should do more than
that—that it should apply also to some noncitizens, like the Windrush families,
and to people who have emigrated and secured citizenship abroad—we need
to look for a different kind of justification.
III. IndIvIdual autonomy as a ground for
the rIght of return
The most obvious way to justify the right of return as a human right is to show
that it is necessary to protect a basic human interest. Several authors have
proposed that the interest in question is the interest in individual autonomy.30
Grounding human rights in autonomy is a familiar strategy: it plays a central
role in James Griffin’s well-known “personhood” account of the basis of
human rights, for example.31 As my comments in the Introduction imply, I
do not accept this justificatory strategy. A major concern is that autonomy is
too culturally specific as a ground for human rights, since while it is a core
value in contemporary Western societies, it does not appear to have this status
elsewhere, where less emphasis is placed on a person’s capacity to choose
their own plan of life, and more on their ability to live a good life.32 But since
many authors believe that it is possible to justify human rights by showing
that they protect the conditions for living an autonomous life, I will set that
general concern aside for now. The specific issue to be addressed is whether
an appeal to the value of autonomy can provide sufficient justification for
30 For an extended argument to this effect, see Christine Straehle, Refugees and
the Right to Return, in the PolitiCal PhiloSoPhy of refuGe (David Miller &
Christine Straehle eds., 2020). Note that Straehle’s argument is developed so
as to apply to the specific case of refugees, allowing her to bring in autonomyrelevant factors that may not be present in other cases in which return is sought.
31 JameS Griffin, on human riGhtS (2008).
32 I have expressed this worry, among others, about Griffin’s theory in Personhood,
supra note 2.
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
379
asserting a strong right of return on the part of those who have been voluntarily
or involuntarily displaced from their homelands.
The argument that it does this begins with the assertion that to be autonomous
one must have the ability to form and carry out plans and projects, and these
are typically spatially located. So being removed from the place in relation
to which my plan of life has been formed, and then barred from re-occupying
it, would be a severe setback to my autonomy. As Stilz puts it,
Occupancy of territory is connected to autonomy because it plays
an important role in almost all of our plans. We build our lives on
the assumption that our goals, relationships, and pursuits will not be
unexpectedly destroyed through forced displacement. If I structure my
goals and choices against the background of continuing legal residence
in a particular territory, and if I am there through no fault of my own,
then respect for my autonomy tells in favor of allowing me to remain
there since it would be impossible to move me without damage to
nearly all my life plans.33
Lefkowitz argues that even this does not go far enough, since it still treats
secure residence as merely a means to the pursuit of whatever goals a person
might have:
For many people, however, particular territories are not merely means
to the pursuit of a good life, but integral to the very way of life they
pursue. Respect for a person’s autonomy requires not only respect for
his or her ability to use objects or physical spaces as means to their ends,
but also respect for his or her ability to set ends. Here, the relevant end
is the pursuit of a territorially grounded conception of the good; that
is, the pursuit of a way of life located in a particular place.34
33 Anna Stilz, Nations, States, and Territory, 121 ethiCS 572, 583–84 (2011)
[hereinafter Nations]. In her later work, Stilz continues to defend the importance
of located life-plans, but without making it a condition that these should be
autonomously formed. As she puts it, “my account of territorial occupancy is
not grounded in the interest in autonomy, but in a broader interest in carrying out
the located projects that we happen to have, whether or not these projects were
acquired through a process of evaluation and choice” (Anna Stilz, Occupancy
Rights and the Wrong of Removal, 41 Phil. & PuB. aff. 324, 337 (2013) [hereinafter
Occupancy]). This shift reflects a concern that an autonomy-based account may
not correctly capture the interest that indigenous groups in particular may have
in occupancy rights.
34 David Lefkowitz, Autonomy, Residence, and Return, 18 CritiCal rev. int’l
SoC. & Pol. Phil. 529, 533 (2015).
380
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
These arguments undoubtedly provide a strong case for protecting people
from forcibly being removed from the places where they live.35 Compelled
removal prevents autonomously chosen plans and projects from being brought
to completion insofar as they are place-specific. Indeed even the threat of
removal interferes with autonomy, since it deters people from developing plans
that depend upon their ability to stay living where they are, thus restricting
the range of options available to them. Although autonomy doesn’t require
a person to have unlimited options, it’s plausible that for most people, their
most important projects do depend on having a secure place in which to live
(“place” here meaning locality or neighborhood rather than individual dwelling).
The right to return, however, only comes into play in the case of people
who have already left that place, and it is therefore not a direct corollary
of the right not to be removed. There are different cases to consider: first,
whether the removal is voluntary or involuntary, and second, whether it
involves individual displacement or collective displacement. We might think
that an autonomy-based right of return would only apply to those who have
been involuntarily displaced, since these are the people whose plans of life
have been disrupted against their will, and remain disrupted so long as they
are excluded from the place where those plans were formed. But before
reaching that conclusion, we should consider why the right might still be
important to those who have chosen to leave. One reason is that a voluntary
emigrant might later come to regret her decision. She might realize that her
most important projects were located in the place she has left and cannot be
reproduced in the locality or the country where she has now chosen to live.
So perhaps there is a universal, autonomy-based right of return that anyone
can claim, regardless of the cause of their present displacement.
To assess this argument, we need to consider what autonomy prescribes
in general when people voluntarily make life-changing decisions. As they
open new doors for themselves, is it essential that the old doors should also
remain open in case they change their minds and come to regret their previous
decision? Here we can learn something by reflecting on a wider range of
cases in which we do not think that the possibility of later regret requires
that the rejected options should be kept open. When people sell their houses,
they are not awarded the right to buy them back if they later come to rue
their decision. Equally, people who quit their jobs don’t have the right to be
reemployed if they come to realize that they have made a serious mistake.
35 Without defining “forcible removal” precisely, I intend it to cover both the case
where a political authority deliberately compels people to move, and the case
where living conditions in the relevant place become so degraded that there is
no reasonable choice but to move; civil war exemplifies the latter.
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
381
The reason might seem obvious: granting such return rights would interfere
too much with security of tenure. Barry, who has bought Jim’s house, would
live in constant worry that Jim might reappear to claim his property back;
ditto Sarah, who has been given the job that Elizabeth left. However, it is
revealing that we do not seem to respond to the possibility of regret in such
cases even in the much weaker form of giving the displaced person first refusal
if the abandoned option should become available again. If Barry later decides
to sell, he is neither legally nor morally required to offer Jim the chance to
buy his house back at current market value, nor do we require Elizabeth’s
previous employer to give her back her job if Sarah leaves. In both these
cases, we understand that an autonomous choice will typically mean opening
up a new set of possibilities while decisively abandoning some of those that
currently exist, so there is a sense in which we would not be respecting a
person’s capacity to choose if we insisted on giving them an unlimited right
to go back on what they had already decided.36
So why would the same reasoning not apply to a person who decides
freely to emigrate? Why, on autonomy grounds, should they be allowed to
have second thoughts and decide that after all their life projects would be best
carried out in the country where they had been living? Of course, a decision
to leave a country is not exactly analogous to a decision to leave a house or
a job. For one thing, the former decision involves a more comprehensive
renunciation of rights, as the discussion in Part II made clear.37 In case the
emigrant comes to realize that they have made a serious mistake, perhaps there
should be a period of time within which they are granted a right of return. But
why should the right persist for more than a couple of years or so after they
have made the move and are settled in the new country, if it is grounded in
personal autonomy—which as we have seen is normally understood to require
renouncing old options when new ones are chosen? It therefore seems that
individual people who choose to leave cannot demand an unlimited right of
return on autonomy grounds alone.
The same reasoning would apply, perhaps even more strongly, to a group
that leaves in order to pursue a project that they believe cannot be carried out
36 The furthest we appear to be willing to go in protecting people against regret is
to insist in certain cases on a short cooling-off period within which a person is
entitled to cancel a contract they have made, such as a hire-purchase agreement
to buy some expensive household item.
37 Moreover, it is typically less costly to grant emigrants a right of return than it
would be to offer house sellers and job-quitters the right to change their minds,
since when a person returns to her country, she does not by that act itself displace
any other right-holder.
382
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
while living where they now are—for example, a religious community whose
members think that only by emigrating can they find the isolation they need
to live a spiritual life. In this case, a person who leaves takes within him the
social milieu within which his later projects are to be carried out, so again
on autonomy grounds it is hard to see how he could have a strong claim to
return to enjoy the options he has freely abandoned.
At first sight, things look very different in the case of individuals or
groups who are compelled to leave their places of residence, and especially
their countries. As suggested above, all of their located life plans, to use
Stilz’s phrase, are disrupted, and not of their own volition. So they suffer an
immediately loss of autonomy, since previously chosen life-plans cannot be
carried out. But we must also ask about what happens to the displaced people,
and about the range of options that are available to them in the place they
move to. These options will not be identical to the ones they have lost, but
they might be roughly comparable. This will depend on the perspective from
which they are valued, and initially we should expect people who already
had territorially based life plans to find the set of options they now face less
valuable, since the specific components of their original plans are unlikely
to be available. But this might change with the passage of time; it clearly
cannot be the case that people can only find valuable the options they are
currently pursuing, otherwise we would never witness the phenomenon of
people emigrating voluntarily to make new lives for themselves. So why not
expect those who are involuntarily displaced to revalue options and make
autonomous choices among the set that they now face? Why should the loss
of autonomy be more than temporary?
Again it may be illuminating to consider the position of people who are
forced to leave their homes or their jobs. To some extent we protect people
legally against these losses. They cannot be evicted or sacked arbitrarily.
Reasons and notice must both be given. Nevertheless, landlords can evict
tenants when their tenancies expire, people who default on their mortgages
can lose their homes, and local authorities can purchase houses compulsorily
for public projects; likewise employers can declare workers redundant or
dismiss them for unsatisfactory performance. Some may want to argue that
current law and policy gives people too little protection against these forced
displacements.38 Nevertheless, the fact that we permit them to happen suggests
that in these fairly important domains we do not recognize an autonomybased human right against removal. We allow the interests of landlords and
38 In the case of housing, see Katy Wells, The Right to Housing, 67 Pol. Stud. 406
(2019).
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
383
employers to prevail, presumably on the assumption that the people displaced
will find other homes and other jobs and adjust their life-plans accordingly.
To return to the case of involuntary displacement between countries, it looks
as though an appeal to autonomy will only generate a right of return in the case
of those who are displaced to locations where the set of available options is
poor. This is of course important: many refugees find themselves in precisely
this situation. Forced to leave their own countries, they very often end up in
camps that may provide the basics but few other opportunities. Note, however,
that even here autonomy considerations do not strictly require a return to the
country of origin. Indeed, given the choice, many refugees would prefer to
be resettled in rich countries that provide them with a wider range of options
than would have been available at home. The general point is that if we ask
what the conditions are under which a person can live an autonomous life, then
on the one hand we can say that they must have access to a sufficiently good
set of life-options to choose from, while on the other that the environment in
which they live should be sufficiently stable that they can form and carry out
longer-term plans. This is why it’s at least plausible to think that an appeal
to autonomy can be used to justify many of the human rights that we would
expect to find on the standard list—food, shelter, healthcare, employment,
education, etc.—and also a right against involuntary displacement. What
invoking autonomy cannot justify, however, is a right to return to the specific
place in which a person’s life-plans were originally formed.39
However we must also consider collective displacement. Intuitively we
have a strong sense that when communities are forced to move against their
will, they have a strong claim to return. Moore gives the example of the Inuit
from Labrador who were moved away from their traditional hunting grounds:
Adaptation was difficult, not because the policy involved the rupture
of personal relationships, but because it was closely bound up with the
way of life of the people in the community, and it was very difficult,
culturally and personally, to adapt to a context in which caribou hunting
was not possible; the migratory patterns which the people had been
39 What if these plans are such that they can only be carried out in that original
place, and the person in question is unwilling to change them? Human rights
do not shield individual life-plans. Consider a skilled craftsman who identifies
closely with his work. He might be a cabinet-maker working at a time when
the demand for handmade furniture is declining. If the firm he works for goes
bust, he cannot call on a human right to be provided with employment of that
specific kind. The personal loss in such a case is real, but not one that human
rights can protect against.
384
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
taught were no longer relevant; and people were left without their past
cultural resources, unable to adapt to this new, quite different context.40
Stilz offers a similar example involving the removal of the Navajos from Arizona
in the 19th century to launch her argument about the wrong of removal.41 In
both cases, the fate that befell these peoples seems to provide good grounds
for asserting their human right to return to the places from which they had
been evicted.
What is noticeable about these examples, however, is that neither author
explains their wrongness by appealing to individual autonomy. Moore explicitly
rejects autonomy as providing the appropriate way to think about removal and
return,42 and Stilz, having initially favored autonomy as a grounding43 clarifies
that her argument about the Navajos requires only that individual Navajos
should endorse their traditional herding practices, not that they should choose
them autonomously.44 It is no accident that the most compelling collective return
cases concern indigenous groups whose identity is formed by longstanding
practices such as hunting and herding that can only be carried out in the group’s
ancestral home. What is being denied by removal is not individual autonomy
but the continuation of a way of life that defines the group.
Whatever merit there is in using autonomy as the basis for human rights
in general, it does not succeed in grounding a robust right of return. It cannot
explain why it should matter so much to people that they be able specifically
to return to their homelands.45 This emerges most clearly in the case of people
who exercise their autonomy by choosing to emigrate. If we believe that such
40
41
42
43
44
45
marGaret moore, a PolitiCal theory of territory 41 (2015).
Occupancy, supra note 34, at 324.
moore, supra note 41, at 142–46
Nations, supra note 34, at 583–84.
Occupancy, supra note 34, at 337.
Autonomy is sometimes appealed to in order to justify a human right to freedom
of movement internationally: see, for example Kieran Oberman, Immigration
as a Human Right, in miGration in PolitiCal theory: the ethiCS of movement
and memBerShiP (Sarah Fine & Lea Ypi eds., 2016). However even if it is true
that increasing the number of options open to a person increases their autonomy
(something there is reason to doubt), when autonomy is used to ground human
rights, it must be interpreted as a threshold concept: human rights provide their
bearers with sufficient, not unlimited, autonomy. For the argument that there
is no human right to international freedom of movement, see David Miller, Is
There a Human Right to Immigrate?, in miGration in PolitiCal theory: the
ethiCS of movement and memBerShiP (Sarah Fine & Lea Ypi eds., 2016). For
present purposes, however, the main point is that an autonomy approach can
count the number of options open to a person, and the subjective value they
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
385
people nonetheless possess a human right to return to their countries of origin—a
right that could only be forfeited under the most extreme circumstances—we
need to justify this in another way. But even for those who are forced to leave,
individually or collectively, appealing to autonomy can at best explain the
immediate wrong of removal, but cannot show why a right of return should
persist even after those displaced have had the opportunity to develop new
life-plans. So to show that both those who choose to leave and those who are
involuntarily displaced, but to option-rich places, nonetheless retain a right
to return to their own countries, we need to seek a different justification.46
Iv. the need to Belong to a homeland as grounds
for the rIght of return
To find a better foundation for a robust right of return, we need to adopt a
communitarian perspective, one that acknowledges the special nature of the
ties that exist between a person and the country she recognizes as “home” and
therefore the importance of having secure and ongoing access to that place.
We need, in other words, to appeal to the human need to belong. But belong
to what? Here I need to introduce and explain the idea of a homeland, an
idea that is suggested by the indigenous examples discussed in the previous
Part, and also by the last of the four specifications of the holders of the right
of return listed in Part I (C2), which referred to people who are bonded to a
country by ties of culture and ancestry. So what is meant by a “homeland”—a
concept that appears in many different European languages: “patrie” in
French, “patria” in Italian, “Heimat” in German, “fosterland” or “hemland”
in Swedish, etc.? In order for the concept to make sense, we must first begin
with the people whose homeland it is. This might be a nation in the modern
sense, but there are also pre-modern and present-day indigenous groups whose
identity connects them to a physical place in a similar way. The homeland is
regarded as the collective possession of the people in question, and in normal
cases they will also be its current occupants—though as we have seen people
who have been forcibly expelled from their homeland are likely still to regard
attach to them, but it gives no special weight to options that are only available
in someone’s original homeland.
46 At this point it may be worth reminding the reader that we are searching for a
way to justify a general right of return on the part of those who have left or been
displaced from their home countries, no matter how the uprooting has come
about. Among these there will be some whose claim to return is strengthened
by additional reasons, for example those who can demand it as reparation for
the injustice of involuntary exile.
386
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
it as rightfully theirs. There is an internal connection between the physical
area of land that constitutes the homeland and the cultural life of the group,
though the exact form that this connection takes will vary somewhat from
case to case. So in describing the characteristic features of a homeland, I do
not mean to lay down necessary and sufficient features for one to exist.
The homeland is the area that the group has inhabited over time, and with
the passage of time it will typically have imprinted the land with its own
distinctive culture.47 It will have cultivated parts of the terrain to meet its
material needs, while at the same time endowing specific places within it with
symbolic significance—there will be sacred sites, a distinctive architecture,
memorials to various historic events, and so forth. But the physical properties
of the land will also have shaped the group’s culture, again both in a material
sense, as the group adapts its way of life to the physical possibilities and
constraints of its habitat, and in a cultural sense, as both natural and manmade
features of the land are celebrated in art, literature, folksong, etc. (this is the
lesson we learn from the cases of the Labrador Inuit and the Arizona Navajo).48
The homeland is also often understood to be the place where the people’s
forebears were born, lived, and died: in the most extreme case, as with the
ancient Greek idea of autochthony, they are understood to have sprung from
the soil in a literal sense.49 However, group members’ relationship to the
homeland is not simply one of (real or imagined) historical memory; there
is also an element of immediate experience. The person who returns to the
homeland after travelling abroad will at once have a direct sense of being “at
home” as she looks at and listens to the goings-on around her. This doublesided quality of attachment to the homeland is well brought out by Tuan in
the following passage:
A homeland has its landmarks, which may be features of high visibility
and public significance, such as monuments, shrines, a hallowed battlefield
47 Note that the concept of “homeland” used in this article differs from Chaim
Gans’ idea of a “formative territory,” understood as the territory that is of
primary importance in forming the historical identity of the group in question.
See Chaim GanS, the limitS of nationaliSm Ch. 4 (2003). A homeland must be
a place that the group either occupies now or has occupied in the recent past,
whereas a formative territory may simply be a place that ancestors of the group
are believed to have lived in millennia ago. Of course, a homeland may also be
a formative territory, and vice versa.
48 For a wide-ranging survey of representations of the homeland in art, see Simon
Schama, Homelands, 58 SoC. ReS. 11 (1991).
49 The same idea (though in a less literal form) can be seen at work when the
homeland is referred to as the “fatherland” or “motherland” of the people.
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
387
or cemetery. These visible signs serve to enhance a people’s sense of
identity; they encourage awareness of and loyalty to place. But a strong
attachment to the homeland can emerge quite apart from any explicit
concept of sacredness; it can form without the memory of heroic battles
won and lost, and without the bond of fear or of superiority vis-à-vis
other people. Attachment of a deep though subconscious sort may
come simply with familiarity and ease, with the assurance of nurture
and security, with the memory of sounds and smells, of communal
activities and homely pleasures accumulated over time.50
It is important to add here that, with the exception perhaps of very small
indigenous groups, different group members will have attachments to particular
places within the homeland. So the general link between the group and the
homeland is supported by numerous more specific links between individual
members and places or areas within it. It is also worth adding that there will
often be a region that the group recognizes as its heartland, and other areas
that, though still seen as belonging to the homeland, are nevertheless regarded
as more peripheral—for example, those that have remained uninhabited and
have no special features that are celebrated in the group’s culture.51 Finally,
note that the group’s homeland may or may not coincide with the territory over
which it currently exercises political jurisdiction. The group will of course
aspire to have a sufficient degree of control over its homeland to enable it
to preserve its valued connection to that place, and to continue to shape it
for the future. If the group is a modern nation, it will probably aim to have a
state whose boundaries coincide with the periphery of the homeland. But for
various reasons, including in some cases the parallel claims of rival groups, it
may have to compromise on that aspiration. In exceptional cases, it may not
even be able to govern the area that it regards as the most iconic.52
Having now outlined the part that the homeland plays in the collective
identity of the group whose homeland it is, we are now in a position to see
how it can be invoked to support a right of return. The argument proceeds
in three steps.
First, it is a widespread if not universal feature of human beings that they
have a need to belong: they experience their own identity as bound up with
50 Yi-Fu tuan, SPaCe and PlaCe: the PerSPeCtive of exPerienCe 159 (1977).
51 This distinction between heartlands and outlying areas is explored at greater
length in Moore, supra note 41, at 118–22.
52 For an example, consider the prominent role given to the Lithuanian forest in
the national imagination of the Polish people, even though for long stretches
of time that area was not under Polish political jurisdiction: see Simon SChama,
landSCaPe and memory Ch. 1 (2004).
388
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
the identity of social groups. These can be of many different kinds, but they
certainly include the physically located groups, such as nations, that were
introduced to explain the idea of homeland. So the need to belong includes
not just the need to belong to the group, but also to the place in which it is
rooted. To satisfy this need, one must either be physically present in the
homeland, or have the opportunity to return there when one wishes to. Having
a homeland is in this respect analogous to having an individual home; as the
saying goes, home is the place where they have to take you in. In one sense,
therefore, you don’t possess a home, or a homeland, if you are debarred from
going and staying there.
Second, although people can over the course of time come voluntarily to
acquire new identities, including new national identities, it is important that this
should be their own decision and not one forced upon them by circumstances.
Even those who choose to emigrate with the intention of becoming nationals
of the society to which they are moving usually keep a strong emotional
connection to their original homeland. A French person living abroad may
be as distressed as a Parisian when he hears that the cathedral of Notre Dame
has been engulfed by flames. They become in effect binational, and would
resent being forced to renounce their original identity.
Third, the need to belong is a deep human need, a need of sufficient weight
to support human rights. Since in order to satisfy it one must have access to
the homeland of the group one identifies with, and since that homeland is
likely to correspond more or less closely to the territory in which one was
born and/or raised and/or had dwelt in for most of one’s life, to protect it one
must have a right of return to that place in particular.
To clarify this further, consider three possible objections to the claim that
a right of return can be grounded on the need to belong. The first would say
that although the need to belong to a group of some kind may be universal,
the need to belong to a place-related group, such as a nation, is not. In the
world today, there are many who identify themselves as cosmopolitans,
and whose more specific ties of identity may be formed with like-minded
people—fellow-enthusiasts for some cause or cultural practice—no matter
where they live. Apparently they have no need to belong to a homeland. Yet
without entering the debate about whether there is something impoverished
about the life of a person who has no roots that fasten him to a particular
place, it is enough to observe that when rights are grounded on basic human
needs, the needs that count are ones that are widely shared as part of the
human form of life, without necessarily being experienced by everyone. There
are people who feel no need to have sexual relationships, or to experience
art or music. Yet we continue to assert human rights to sexual freedom and
freedom of artistic expression because we know that for the great majority
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
389
of people everywhere life would be miserable if they had no opportunity
to fulfil these needs. Likewise, the right not to be forcibly displaced from
one’s homeland, and the corresponding right to return to it from abroad, are
justified by observing that belonging to the place they identify as home is a
basic need whose fulfilment matters greatly to most people. They would find
the prospect of being permanently exiled from that place acutely distressing.
A second objection is that, inasmuch as the right of return is claimed by
virtue of identification with the homeland, it seems to depend on subjective
facts about the claimant, and these cannot adequately ground such a right. But
this is to misunderstand the justificatory argument at work here. Starting from
the claim that the need to belong is a human need, it defends a human right
that everyone has to return to the country that qualifies as their homeland.
There is then, for each person, a further question as to how that country is to
be identified—a question that is normally straightforward to answer, but that
can become practically pressing in legal cases; for example, cases in which
someone was born in country A but has subsequently spent much of her life
living in country B, and the issue is whether A can still count as her homeland
for purposes of exercising the right of return. When trying to establish whether
the person is “effectively” a national of A, the court is likely to take account
of a mix of objective and more subjective factors, including time spent in A,
personal or business connections with people living there, etc.53 Someone’s
mere assertion that they “feel” that they belong to country A would never be
enough. But this has nothing to do with the right of return as such, only with
whether the right can be claimed in relation to a specific country. Like other
needs, the need to belong is not itself subjective.
A third objection focuses on the concept of “homeland” and claims that it
is amorphous in a way that makes it an unsuitable basis on which to claim a
right. When introducing the concept, I noted that it combines several different
elements, and no doubt if we were to ask people what they regard as “their
home” or “where they come from,” we would get different answers that reflect
this complexity. Some might identify the place quite narrowly as a village or
a valley. Others might specify a cultural milieu, such as the region where a
language or a dialect is spoken—say the Ladin-speaking area of South Tyrol.
Yet others would think of their homeland in much larger terms, such as a
culturally variegated nation (within which, however, they would also have
lesser loyalties to particular places). For the purpose of justifying a right of
return, however, these differences will rarely matter.54 The right of return is
53 For some relevant cases, see JoSePh & CaStan, supra note 25, at 408–17.
54 At least for return at the individual level. When we consider cases of collective
return, in contrast, the way that “homeland” is specified may be important,
390
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
a right to enter the state where your homeland is located. So long as there is
internal freedom of movement, therefore, the right gives a person access to
that special place no matter how widely or narrowly it is defined. So long as
an out-of-territory Ladin-speaker has the right to enter Italy (and has freedom
of movement within the country), he can make his way to the valleys where
Ladin is mainly spoken.
It is, of course, a contingent question whether the sought-after homeland
will continue to exist in a recognizable form with the passage of time. It may
be destroyed by physical changes, such as the desertification of a once-fertile
valley or the drowning of an island home by rising sea levels; it may also be
eroded by cultural change, either because of inward or outward movements of
population55 or because the people who remain no longer speak the language
or practice the religion that they once did. This has two consequences. First,
it explains why when the right of return is formalized in law, it is usually
time-restricted, applying only to the displaced person and her immediate
descendants.56 It will generally be implausible to claim that one has a need to
belong to the place where one’s remoter ancestors lived, not least because the
claim will almost certainly rely on the place in question having physical and/
or cultural features that it no longer possesses; in other words, the claim is a
claim to return to a largely fictitious “home.”57 Second, it shows that the need
to belong is a need that cannot always be satisfied for a particular person. The
place that would otherwise count as his homeland may no longer exist, taking
account of its different dimensions. But this does not undermine the case for
a human right of return. Although on the view I am defending, human rights
because of the possibility that the designated place has meanwhile been occupied
by another group.
55 Here I am considering population changes that occur by legitimate means. Clearly
the intentional destruction of a homeland, whereby the current occupants are
forced out and replaced by others, as in ethnic cleansing or certain forms of
colonialism, raises much large issues that cannot be dealt with here.
56 Such a restriction is often justified by referring to the legitimate claims of later
occupants, who might have to be displaced if a time-unlimited right of return
were granted: see, for example the argument put forward in Jeremy Waldron,
Superseding Historic Injustice, 103 ethiCS 4 (1992); Jeremy Waldron, Settlement,
Return, and the Supersession Thesis, 5 theoretiCal inquirieS l. 237 (2004).
Waldron also, however, points out that it becomes less plausible for a person
to claim a deep need to be in a place after they have been removed from it for
a long time.
57 On this point, see especially Alon Harel, Whose Home Is It? Reflections on the
Palestinians’ Interest in Return, 5 theoretiCal inquirieS l. 333 (2004); Waldron,
supra note 57.
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
391
are to be explained by reference to the basic needs whose fulfilment they
protect, they cannot always guarantee that every such need will be satisfied.
The right to marry protects the need to form stable, loving relationships, but
some people who would like to marry never find the right partner; similarly
for the right of return, and the homeland that (on the view I am defending)
provides its underlying rationale.
So far I have investigated how the need to belong can justify a right of
return on the part of individuals who have been displaced either involuntarily
or as a result of choice. But now we must consider the case in which a
whole community is expelled from (or chooses to leave) its homeland. Here
the very idea of an individual right of return may seem problematic, for
what would the individual be returning to? As I have analyzed the idea of
homeland, it depends upon the symbiotic relationship between land, people,
and culture, and when the people are expelled, this relationship unravels. So
an individual’s claim to return only makes sense in this case in the context
of a collective right of return, whereby a sufficiently large number of people
go back to recreate the located community that has been destroyed.58 The
exercise of any individual’s right of return will depend on the willingness of
the other members of the relevant group to seize the opportunity to repatriate
and reconstitute the homeland.59 This might at first glance seem bizarre.
How can an individual’s right depend on what other putative bearers of that
right are willing to do? But there are other cases that appear to involve this
kind of dependence. Consider the right of self-determination. If we treat this
as an individual right as well as a collective right, then whether any given
person is able to exercise that right depends on whether other members of the
relevant “self” are prepared to do what it takes—set up political institutions,
participate in them, accept their decisions, etc.—to make the collective right
58 To clarify, an individual person in this situation might still be able to claim a
right of property in some part of the territory that the group has left, and argue
that she should be allowed to go back to occupy the house or land that she owns.
But this is obviously different from asserting a right to return as such, which I
am arguing derives from the need to belong to a homeland.
59 This point is also made in Victor Tadros, The Persistence of the Right of Return,
16 Pol. Phil. & eCon. 375, 379–80 (2017). More generally, as discussed above,
establishing a right of return cannot always guarantee that an individual’s need
to belong will be fulfilled. The right must be understood as a right not to be
prevented by states or other bodies from returning individually to an existing
homeland or returning collectively to reconstitute the homeland in the case of
a group that has been displaced. But where a person’s homeland vanishes and
cannot be recreated, their right becomes empty, and their need cannot be satisfied
unless they are able to identify and move to a new homeland.
392
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
effective. So either we have to concede that there is no individual right here,
or we must say that the individual right is only exercisable on condition that
enough others in the relevant group also exercise theirs. In the same way,
in cases where the whole group has either voluntarily abandoned or been
forced out of their homeland, the right of return must, in the first instance,
be exercised at the collective level.
v. the return claIms of Jews and palestInIans
To end the Article, I will briefly examine how the analysis of the right of
return I have provided can be applied to the claims of Jews and Palestinians
wishing to return either to the State of Israel or to the Occupied Territories it
controls. I need to reemphasize that my focus is on return as a human right,
and not on the expressive or reparative purposes that return, or the claiming
of it, may serve. Let me start by setting aside the case of those who already
enjoy Israeli citizenship. I take it for granted that any Israeli national who
wishes to return should be allowed to do so, unless there are exceptional
reasons, such as a serious security threat, for barring him. To explain this,
we need not look beyond the narrow justification of the right of return as an
indispensable adjunct to citizenship analyzed in Part II above. The contestable
(and contested) cases involve noncitizens wishing to enter—Jews living abroad,
or Palestinians displaced to neighboring countries who lack Israeli citizenship.
Under the much-trumpeted Law of Return, Israel has granted anyone with
Jewish ancestry the positive right to come to Israel and acquire citizenship.
To treat this legal right as justified by the human right of return, however,
would be to stretch the meaning of “return” beyond the bounds recognized
by international lawyers, even those who would support the most inclusive
interpretation listed in Part I above, C2. Although a Jewish person living
in New York, say, may identify culturally with Jews in Israel, he cannot in
advance of returning claim any ancestral, familial or material connection
with that territory. In other words, it is not his homeland, as understood here.
Better justifications for the positive right are available: it can be seen either
as a way of safeguarding Jews from the oppression they have experienced
historically, by providing a guarantee that they can exercise their human
right of exit from the state they currently occupy, or as an instrument of
national self-determination. In the latter case, the argument is that political
self-determination for Jews must involve gathering in a place where they can
exercise control over territory, and the right of entry to that place follows
2020]
Justifying the Right of Return
393
immediately.60 I do not wish to evaluate these justifications (which strike me
as plausible), but only to emphasize, as others have, that whereas the case for
return made by Palestinians is indeed about the return of people who have
actually been displaced, voluntarily or involuntarily, the Jewish case is not.61
Palestinians, therefore, have at least prima facie a human right to return to
the places in Israel or the Occupied Territories from which they were displaced.
Those who have the clearest claim are those who were recently displaced
and have been denied the opportunity to become citizens of the states where
they reside. If my analysis of the right of return, grounding it in the need to
belong, is correct, their only homeland remains historic Palestine, because they
have been denied the chance to sink roots in the places to which they have
moved. It is irrelevant that the denial of rights to Palestinians may have been
a deliberate strategy on the part of receiving states to keep up the pressure for
return. The morality of such policies can be questioned, but the Palestinians
themselves cannot be held responsible for them. So it is not the mere fact of
having Palestinian ancestry or identifying as Palestinian that triggers the right
of return: it is the fact that many Palestinians have unwillingly been placed
in situations where they have no opportunity to adopt a new homeland, so
their need to belong can only be met by returning to Palestine itself. This
also means that the right cannot be claimed (as a human right) by people of
Palestinian descent who have become assimilated citizens of other countries, at
least if their connection to Israel/Palestine dates back half a century or more.62
Since, however, this still leaves some millions of Palestinian who can
claim a right of return, the pressing question becomes “return to where?”. As
my analysis indicated, the ideal return scenario is one where a person returns
at the same time to a physical location, a network of people, a cultural way
of life, and a political community. This can readily be achieved only for
those able to return to places where Palestinians have continued to live and
60 So far as self-determination goes, the place need not have been the land of
Israel: the cultural argument for choosing Israel as the place for Jews to gather
is a supplementary one.
61 Or to put the point more carefully, the Palestinian case is at least centrally about
the return of people who have been displaced within one or two generations—
people who had been living in Israel-Palestine or whose parents were. As time
moves on, the emphasis may shift towards the idea of reoccupying an ancestral
homeland, which would bring the Palestinian argument more closely into
alignment with the Jewish argument.
62 To clarify, I have conceded that people who are displaced from country A to
country B may for a time have two homelands and be able to claim the right to
return to A as well as to B; but that claim must be time-limited, for the reasons
set out in Part IV.
394
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
[Vol. 21.2:367
to sustain their economic and cultural practices, and even here the issue of
citizenship looms large (return to a Palestinian state or to Israel itself?). For
most, return would have to be collective, and would involve the recreation
of communities in places that can support Palestinian culture, not necessarily
the precise locations from which they or their parents were displaced. So
we find ourselves very much in the realm of the second best: the Palestinian
right of return has to be tailored to take account of other rights, including the
collective self-determination rights of Israeli citizens. Those who are skeptical
of the idea that the right of return can apply to cases of mass displacement
may find their skepticism confirmed by looking at the logistics of Palestinian
repatriation.
conclusIon
In the face of such skepticism, I have argued that the right of return qualifies
as a human right, one that is normally exercisable on an individual basis,
but that may under some circumstances need to be realized collectively, by
a community of people returning together. Alongside its important role in
securing citizenship and preventing statelessness, it is justified by reference
to the human need to belong, to have a homeland one can always return to.
The normative force of human rights is not diminished by recognizing that
there will be unhappy circumstances in which they cannot all be fulfilled.
I have argued elsewhere that the mass movement of refugees, now and in
the future, is likely to create tragic situations in which the unwillingness of
states, and their populations, to admit the refugees will lead to human rights
violations on a large scale.63 It is more honest to recognize such situations
as tragic than to trim down the list of human rights so that the appearance of
moral conflict is avoided. At least by so doing the pressure to help as many
as possible is sustained, and those whose rights are infringed may later
qualify for compensation. This, I believe, is the right way to think about the
Palestinians who qualify for the right of return to historic Palestine: as caught
up in a tragic situation where it is for the moment impossible for all their
human rights to be fulfilled.
63 david miller, StranGerS in our midSt: the PolitiCal PhiloSoPhy of immiGration
162–64 (2016). To clarify, speaking of tragedy here presupposes that states have
strong moral reasons for not taking in the refugees, as well as strong moral
reasons to accept them.