Studia Theologica - Nordic Journal of Theology
ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/sthe20
Saints in public
Holy lives and the function of theological speech in the political theology of
Rowan Williams
Patrik Hagman
To cite this article: Patrik Hagman (2021): Saints in public, Studia Theologica - Nordic Journal of
Theology, DOI: 10.1080/0039338X.2021.1939153
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/0039338X.2021.1939153
© 2021 The Author(s). Published by Informa
UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
Published online: 10 Jun 2021.
Submit your article to this journal
View related articles
View Crossmark data
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=sthe20
Studia Theologica - Nordic Journal of Theology, 2021
https://doi.org/10.1080/0039338X.2021.1939153
Saints in public
Holy lives and the function of theological speech in the
political theology of Rowan Williams
Patrik Hagman
This article explores the way Rowan Williams understands saints as theo-politically
significant. By surveying a number of key texts by Williams in different genres, the
author argues that the saints for Williams are highly important for his political
theology. For him, the saints make a political theology possible, since they
witness to the world as rooted in Gods will. This, in turn, is significant for
understanding how theological language works, since it goes beyond the limits
of “realistic” discourse, bound by a certain secular understanding of the way the
world “is”. The significance of this feature of theological language is
demonstrated by discussing texts by Martin Hägglund and Theo Hobson.
That theological language is complex and has different functions in different contexts is an elementary insight, yet it is something that often causes
confusion. I give examples of this below, instances where criticism of theological statements for a lack of realism seems to fail to grasp the function of
these statements. In this article, I will try to clarify how theology in its
“proclamatory voice” relates to the “realistic voice” by exploring the political theology present in the writings of the former Archbishop of Canterbury, Rowan Williams. More specifically, I will show that the way
Williams understands the function of the saint as a locus of political significance is able to shed light on the workings of theo-political language.1 As I
will demonstrate below using a number of Williams’ writings in rather
diverse genres,2 Williams tends to end his arguments – regardless of
whether he is writing an academic study or lectures to the general
public – with rather overt political statements. I suggest that these
© 2021 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/bync-nd/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any
medium, provided the original work is properly cited, and is not altered, transformed,
or built upon in any way.
2
Saints in public
passages are more than mere applications of a particular theological or
spiritual thought complex; and are actually part of the very structure of
Williams’ theological thinking, with the ultimate purpose of saying something about how our common world is structured. I will demonstrate the
significance of this function using two cases: Theo Hobson’s criticism of
Williams’ ecclesiology as an example of a common critique of church-centered political theology; and Martin Hägglund’s critique of the notion of
eternity in his secular political theology. My aim in this article is thus to,
on the one hand, explore the shape of Williams’ theological argumentation, but also, more broadly, to explore what makes theo-political
language function.
Two cases of confusion regarding theological language: Hobson
and Hägglund
Williams’ political thinking has been widely praised. But – if we exclude
questions of church policy during his time as Archbishop of Canterbury
– it may also be the aspect of his theological output that has been most
heavily criticized.3 In part, this is to be expected, since political issues
are relevant to a wider audience. However, writers that do engage
with his theology in depth, such as Theo Hobson4 and Williams’ biographer Rupert Shortt,5 also focus their criticism on this area.
Hobson, in his critical study of Williams’ ecclesiology, pinpoints his
concerns at the tension between “two powerful theological impulses”:
The first is a postmodern (meaning above all “cultural-linguistic”)
Catholicism: the actual practices of the church are the outward
essence of this religion. The other, less officially acknowledged,
impulse is eschatological universalism: the truth of this tradition
lies in this heralding of a new unlimited human community.6
Hobson thus perceives a tension between a focus on the church as a tangible community upheld (or produced) by its practices, above all the
Eucharist, and the prophetic proclamation of the Kingdom of God in
its fullest sense. The tension consists in claiming that the latter is contained in the former, while common experience would tell us that this
rarely is the case.
This tension is not unique to Williams’ work of course, nor is Hobson
alone in pointing this out. That there is such a tension in the traditional
Christian understanding of the church is probably not in dispute – but
Patrik Hagman
3
opinions regarding how to handle it differ wildly. In a way, one could
claim that this criticism goes back at least as far as the Protestant Reformation, if not further. Certainly, this is when the distinction between the
Visible and the Invisible church enters the theological vocabulary7 and
becomes the standard (Protestant) way of dealing with the discrepancy
between the church as it actually is, and the church as it should be theologically. For the reformers, the notion of the invisible, or hidden, church
was a way to accommodate the need to criticize (or reject) the church
hierarchy without giving up the ideal of catholicity.8 However, as is
often the case, this approach over the centuries has had unforeseen consequences. Williams rejects this distinction; thus, his ecclesiology represents a reaction against this approach.9 He writes
I think that, ultimately, the separation of two elements here, an inner
relatedness to Christ and an outer flexibility about words and forms,
takes away something vital from the idea that God calls into being a
tangible human community, whose common language is the carrier
of its common relatedness to Christ’s invitation. Move away from
this, and the visible reality of the Church becomes something
almost optional, in a way that makes more abstract the interdependence of believers on one another – their interdependence precisely
as visible, material, historical and language-using subjects.10
Thus, over time the separation of the invisible and the visible church introduces a new fundamental logic in the Christian tradition: the idea that true
faith can exist apart from the concrete life of the Christian community. This
idea can take very different forms, ranging from conservative to liberal versions,11 but they often share the notion that this faith is somehow insulated
from the manifest problems of the practical life of the church.
It is this insistence on the “visible reality of the Church” that exposes
Williams to criticism such as Hobson’s.12 These differing positions on
ecclesiology highlight the underlying question of how such a disagreement arises. I refer to this ongoing debate, suggesting that there is a
real theological difficulty here which has to do with the way theological
language functions. Put very basically, it would seem that theology
needs to speak in two registers: a realistic voice that, for instance, talks
about how things “actually are” in the local parish, and a proclamatory
voice which could be taken to describe how things should be, i.e. what
the Kingdom of God should mean for life in this world. To put it this
way is, however, to concede the game to the position above represented
by Hobson. If the two registers relate to each other simply as “what is”
4
Saints in public
and “what ought to be”, then it would be a clear error to claim that things
are in a certain way when one’s intention is to talk about how they should
be. However, the way these two registers function is altogether more
complex; and it seems that the lack of clarity about this issue forms the
basis of a wide range of misunderstandings and debates.
To give another example: in Martin Hägglund’s recent provocative
book, This Life: Secular Faith and Spiritual Freedom, he maintains that a
belief in eternity necessarily makes life meaningless and eliminates all
value of life in this world.
What I do and what I love can matter to me only because I understand myself as mortal. … The question of what I ought to do
with my life – a question that is at issue in everything I do – presupposes that I understand my time to be finite. For the question of how
I should lead my life to be intelligible as a question, I have to believe
that I will die. If I believed that my life would last forever, I could
never take my life to be at stake and I would never be seized by
the need to do anything with my time.13
For Hägglund, belief in eternity thus undermines not only all
meaning, but also all political or social ambition. When religious
people thus profess that their faith inspires or even commands them
to care for the poor, the needy, or for the environment, they are deluding themselves. According to him, what they profess is a secular faith,
the belief that since our lives are finite, they have value and thus are
worth caring for.
In his 450-page work, Hägglund discusses writers such as Augustine,
C.S. Lewis, Kierkegaard, Martin Luther King as well as Marx and Hegel.
However, the basic understanding of time and eternity is not really
developed at all.14 In his argument, it acts as a silver bullet to all religious
thinking. While Hägglund’s argumentation can be criticized in many
ways,15 I want to focus on the way he assumes that he can exhaustively
define eternity negatively as “the absence of time”, and then logically
claim that human beings either live according to such a concept or
not. This does not merely display a lack of nuance (there could be
more alternatives and one’s belief in eternity could function in different
ways), but also a lack of understanding of how religious language
works. In a way similar to Hobson, Hägglund assumes that if the proclamatory voice of religion speaks of eternity in a way that in some sense
contradicts a realistic understanding of how the world is, what is
going on is either hypocrisy, lies or profound confusion.
Patrik Hagman
5
This becomes very clear in his discussion of grief. Here Hägglund discusses C.S. Lewis’ book A Grief Observed. In this frank recounting of his
grief over the death of his wife, Lewis describes how the belief in an
afterlife fails to console him, how he is unable to overcome the
longing of being together with her here on earth. Hägglund quotes
Lewis professing his irritation with believers who say, “there is no
death”, or claim that death does not matter. Hägglund comments:
In speaking out of his experience of mourning, Lewis here articulates
a profound faith: not faith in a transcendent God, or in a life exempt
from death, but faith in the irreplaceable value of life that is bound to
death. If what happens matters and our actions have consequences, it is
because they are irreversible and cannot be undone. … The sense that
something matters thus emerges from a secular faith, which sustains
the commitment to a finite and fragile form of life.16
Hägglund does not consider the possibility that belief in eternity could
have any other influence on our perception of finitude than the denial of
its meaning. What Lewis is doing in these pain-filled passages, however,
is trying to navigate between erroneous understandings of what belief in
eternity means for life within time. When describing the moment at his
wife’s deathbed and quoting Dante’s Poi si tornò all’ eterna fontana, it
clearly does not mean that “there is no Joy Davidman for C.S. Lewis
in heaven”,17 rather, it means that the language of eternity offers a
way of relating to mortality that neither denies the horror of death nor
reduces life to a vain, possibly heroic, struggle to avoid the inevitable.
It is not my purpose here to try to elucidate the Christian doctrine of
eternal life,18 but rather to point out that this failure to understand the
way theological talk functions is analogous to Hobson’s problem with
an ecclesiology that – in his view – overestimates the holiness of the
church. The common trait is that in both instances a certain sense of
what is realistic – Hobson’s awareness of the church’s failures and Hägglund’s analysis of how meaning arises from finitude – is used to judge
the proclamatory voice of theology. While it is usually a sound habit to
be realistic, I maintain that using this approach is to misunderstand how
the proclamatory voice of theology works.
Political theology – mapping the territory
This question is of central concern to political theology, which is also
how Hägglund frames his argument.19 Political theology is a term –
6
Saints in public
and a field of academia – that can be described in a wide variety of
ways.20 Luke Bretherton defines political theology as “an interpretive
art for discovering faithful, hopeful and loving judgements about how
to act together in response to shared problems”.21 He understands
that the politics that political theology studies has three dimensions:
(1) the nature and form of the polis, (2) that which shapes the common
life over time, and (3) the relational practices through which a
common world of meaning and action is created and cultivated.22 This
definition intentionally leaves out what he terms “non-confessional political theology”, i.e. political philosophers that “utilize the Christian
archive out of recognition that, at least in the West, much of the language
and conceptual grammar has roots in theological beliefs and practices”.23 While Hägglund’s argument for atheism is clearly at home in
the non-confessional type of political theology (though one could
perhaps argue that his is a very Lutheran kind of atheism), I hope to
show that Williams’ decidedly confessional political theology has relevance for Hägglund’s thesis as well.
In academia, it has become commonplace to distinguish between public
theology and political theology.24 This, of course, can be done in many
ways. I propose a distinction of these terms, one that may not fit historically, but one which, nevertheless, clarifies my purpose for this article. I
would suggest that whereas public theology is concerned with the role
of theology – or religion more broadly – in the public political discussion,25
political theology is more interested in Christianity and religion as a set of
political practices in itself, and thus not politically interesting for political
discourse alone.26 Thus political theology will be at least as interested in
who is saying something, and how, as in what is being said.
Rowan Williams is, of course, one of the fairly few present-day voices that
are clearly at home in both these traditions. Throughout his life he has
shown interest in political issues and his collections of essays and speeches,
Faith in the Public Square (2012), is one of the best examples of public theology in recent years.27 It is worth pointing out, however, that a huge aspect of
its “publicness” is due to the fact that it has been written by the (now
former) Archbishop of Canterbury. My point is that public theology is, in
a sense, dependent on a social reality, the existence of the Church, which
it tends to underemphasize and thus analyse insufficiently. This, in turn,
says something about the importance of political theology as the study of
the structures that make a Christian political discussion possible.
Therefore, I will not focus on Williams’ contributions to discussions
about secularism, religion and law, the environment, the economy or
religious diversity (all subheadings of the above-mentioned book),
Patrik Hagman
7
important and insightful as they are.28 Instead, I am more interested in
the politics involved when Williams is doing theology more generally
– a politics that also enables his “public theology”.29
This interest thus broadly fits within Bretherton’s third dimension of
politics. Jonathan Cole provides another useful definition of political
theology: “a mode of political analysis that proceeds from the conviction
that politics (however defined) is embedded within a Christian ontology
and shaped by a Christian historical teleology”.30 What I will try to do is
to unveil a central characteristic of how Williams’ politics connects to
and flows out of a Christian ontology.31
A politics of awe and amazement
This characteristic is on display in this quotation from the very different
book Tokens of Trust (2007):
I’ve often preached – like others, I’m sure – on how, when we come
back to our places after taking communion, we ought to look at our
next-door neighbours with awe and amazement. The person next to
me – whom I may love deeply, may not know at all, may dislike,
may even fear – is God’s special, honoured guest, praying Christ’s
prayer, living from Christ’s life. Just for this moment, they are
touched with the glory of the end of all things; and so are we.32
If there is politics in this – and I believe there is – it is of a very particular
kind: the politics that arises from our looking at our neighbours with
awe and amazement. I will postpone the question of in what sense
such a proposal is political, and instead first ponder on what we are
looking at, and what kind of looking we are talking about here.
Williams offers some elaboration on exactly what we might be looking
at when we look at our neighbour post-communion:
One of the simplest possible definitions of the Church is to say that
it is meant to be the place where Jesus is visibly active in the world.
And once we have said that, we can turn it around and say that
where Jesus is visibly active, something very like the Church
must be going on.33
This is a statement that invites the kind of criticism Hobson articulates.
Williams is, however, clear that such a declaration is never without complications. Without claiming that the church is more Christ-like than our
8
Saints in public
common experience tells us it is, Williams goes on to give some fairly
every-day, but nonetheless very “churchy” examples of holiness.
Examples of when the church – as he puts it – “works”: the culmination
of the Jubilee 2000 campaign; the work of a retired minister and his wife
in an area of South Wales with social problems; and an Anglican religious community in the Solomon Islands, whose peacekeeping work
involving martyrdom, exemplifies the church at its best. These,
especially the latter two, are given as examples of fairly ordinary,
every-day saintliness.
One could easily respond to this by saying “well, yes, but look at all
these other examples where the church fails to be anything like
Christ”. This, however, would be to misunderstand what Williams is
doing. Williams is not building a quantitative argument for Christianity.
Nonetheless, whenever the argument being put forward is pushed to the
point where the question “Yes, that sounds nice, but is any of this real?”
almost becomes audible, Williams points us towards the saints as
examples. How, then should we understand why Williams is making
this move?
Taking responsibility for God
Another, less ordinary, example is found in the previously mentioned
book, Faith in the Public Square, where the closing essay deals with Holocaust victim Etty Hillesum.34 While Williams’ book is a collection of
essays which originated over a long period, I think it is safe to assume
that it is significant that this particular text has been chosen to close the
book. On one level the essay, called “Religious lives”, deals with the
popular distinction between being spiritual (good) and being religious
(bad). The way Williams describes the extraordinary life of Hillesum indicates, however, that there is more at stake than yet another example of a
religious life under grave circumstances. Williams wants to demonstrate
how Hillesum exemplifies a particular way for God to be in the world.
Proceeding from Wittgenstein’s35 notion that life experiences may
“force” the concept of God upon a person, Williams explores how in
her letters from the concentration camp Hillesum understands her
purpose to be to “take responsibility for God”.36 Hillesum writes
You cannot help us, … we must help You help ourselves. And that is
all we can manage these days and also all that really matters: that
we safeguard that little piece of You, God, in ourselves.37
Patrik Hagman
9
There must be someone to live through it all and bear witness to the
fact that God lived, even in these times. And why should I not be
that witness?38
Williams argues that a religious life, such as Hillesum’s, but also more
generally, is a life where “certain realities become visible”; it “takes
responsibility for the appearing of God”.39 It is thus more than a life
marked by certain religious truth claims. Rather than pointing
towards a particular understanding of reality, it makes a claim to be
such a reality itself. This is an altogether more dynamic notion of how
the “eternal”, in Hägglund’s terminology, relates to present day life. It
is not motivated by a desire to fulfil a religious or moral duty. It is, in
a sense without motivation, beyond this responsibility in itself. Williams
writes:
Etty Hillesum does not decide that the world would be a better
place if belief in God persisted, and so decides to make her life a
locus for God. Something unarguable is happening to her apprehension of who she is, something exhibited in her material life;
and whatever happens becomes part of the uninterrupted conversation with God, that listening to a foreign voice in the heart of the
self, which becomes habitual.40
This, of course, is the essential difference between embodying an ideal
and embodying, well, God. God, in order to be God, must remain the
subject of any form of being in the world. Hillesum testifies to the
reality of God by providing God with a place to become visible in the
world. At the same time, this is not a case of a frail human being overtaken or “possessed” by a powerful being. It is actually the opposite:
in a situation of deepest darkness, like that of the concentration camp,
God’s presence is all but extinguished – unless Hillesum gives God a
shelter in her very self.
The Christological parallels – indeed Mariological – are clear here, and
Williams points to the very particular theological content of Hillesum’s
mode of witnessing.
[T]he idea that the paradigm religious life is one that “gives shelter”
to a vulnerable divine presence, a narrative that seeks to embody
God, to take responsibility for the appearing of God (and of suffering and love), has a particular resonance with the Christian and
10
Saints in public
Jewish tradition, and illuminates why a life like Etty Hillesum’s is
hard to read without that tradition in mind.41
As Jesus comes into the world as a defenceless child, God’s (knowable)
presence in the world is frail and relies on humans being responsive and
responsible enough to carry that presence.
Central to this notion of life as testimony, embodied in Hillesum, is
thus the notion of responsibility. This gives us an important clue into
what makes a saint; responsibility is – in one sense – the founding
virtue of saintliness. Hillesum thus provides another example that Hägglund’s thesis encounters problems with when facing empirical reality.
Hillesum’s diaries give ample examples of how an intense engagement
with the eternal feeds into a strong and radical involvement with the
temporal world and the people living – and suffering – in it.
Hillesum’s life takes place within an extreme political situation. But
this discussion sheds light on the political theology of Rowan Williams
because of how he positions her life in the current discussion. According
to Williams, Hillesum’s is a life which enables a culture to feel and show
grief and pity, and without which it would be difficult to understand
what God in the Christian sense means.
To give over a life, in any circumstances, not only the dramatic and
terrible context of Westerbork and Auschwitz, to making a habitation for grief and for God is the most effective resistance possible
both to a secular reduction of human meaning to the level of arbitrary choice and commodified feeling or imagination, and to a
pseudo-religiousness, a spirituality, in which religious symbolism
itself becomes a fashion accessory for the postmodern self.42
We see here how Williams turns once again to a clearly political
language at precisely the point where he wants to sum up the crucial significance of a life like Etty Hillesum’s, pointing to the way capitalism
configures meaning and religious symbolism. Ultimately, he seems to
suggest, a life lived open to the presence of God will act as a node in a
kind of politics different than the secular reductionisms of capitalist
societies.
Mystic embodiment
This function of the saints, both in the world and in Williams’ theology, is
clarified substantially in his 1991 study of one of the most iconic of
Patrik Hagman
11
Christian saints, Teresa of Avila. In the closing chapter of that book, Williams turns to the concept of mysticism, arguing against the then still
prevalent idea of mystical experience as a common core of different religious traditions. In its stead, Williams proposes a model of mysticism
based on function rather than content.
[The mystics’] lives become a classical exegesis of the tradition’s
basic texts and stories: something like what used to be called a
règle vivante in monastic communities – someone from whose
conduct you could reconstruct the text on which it was based.
But, more than this, such a life becomes a point of access to a truth
in danger of being overlaid by the passage of time.
The sort of people who tend to be called mystics must, in other
words, be understood as having a clear function within a specific
religious tradition; and if we want to generalize about mysticism,
we should concentrate more on this comparability of function than
on any supposed comparability of the content of experience.43
Again, this concept of becoming a “living rule” is much more nuanced
than merely trying to live up to the moral and ritual teachings of one’s
tradition – the measure of someone’s saintliness is not how close their
“is” is to the “ought”. As the example of Hillesum also indicates, the
mystic saint might very well end up in a very different place than the tradition one inhabits might have expected. The mystic nurtures an access
to the sacred that is not controllable and is, therefore, unpredictable.
“For a religious tradition to foster and sustain the forms of non-ritual
access to the sacred is for it to take a necessary and calculated but still
quite genuine risk”.44
What is exceptional with the truly great saints, in Williams’ analysis, is
that someone like Teresa of Avila witnesses not only to one particular
strand of the Christian tradition. In contrast with the older religious
studies model of mysticism, where one universal mystical experience
gives rise to different traditions, Teresa is able to see a deeper unity
behind different religious experiences.
Perhaps, though, what gives particular greatness to those figures
whose work and life have been seen as classical and authoritative
in Catholic tradition is their capacity to see the unity of all these
different aspects of spirituality, because they see the unity of the
divine act underlying them. Any one such figure may in practice
12
Saints in public
concentrate on or have an attrait towards a particular style, but will
be able to set it in the context of a coherent theology – and sometimes at least to acknowledge also the proper and legitimate diversity of spiritual paths.45
These figures, Williams argues, can function as guides for the Christian
community precisely because their witness is broad and nuanced
enough for a whole community of believers to identify with. So, while
there is no denying the strong personality of most such saints, it is not
their individual experience of God that enables them to embody a tradition, but precisely their ability to transcend that individual experience.
While Williams is clear that Teresa is no social reformer,46 when he
goes on to describe the actual content and significance of Teresa’s
witness, we again see him turn to a more political language.
The paradox of Christian mysticism – at least on Teresa’s account –
is that there is no detached divine absolute with which to take
refuge. We may and must detach ourselves from all that keeps us
from God: our Sin, our fearfulness and false humility, our pride of
race or family; but the God with whom we are finally united is
the God whose being is directed in love towards the world, which
we must then re-enter, equipped to engage with other human
beings with something of God’s own wholeheartedness because
we have been stripped of certain modes of self-protectiveness: of
an understanding of our worth or loveableness as resting on prestige, achievement or uniformity.47
There is, thus, no opposition between the contemplative and active life
(if we broaden these terms somewhat beyond their traditional monastic
meanings). For Teresa, the contemplative enables a true engagement
with the world; and such contemplation without such worldly concern
would be deeply un-Christian. Unlike Hägglund’s argument,48 contemplation is not true contemplation if it undermines interest in the temporal world.
We can thus summarize that – for Williams – a true engagement with
God will result in life choices that can well be described (or perhaps are
best described) as political. Moreover, in the case of Teresa, too, we get
some political content – a strong criticism of the culture of honour,
that Williams deems more generally relevant than her particular situation (even though he maintains that it is a result of that particular
situation).
Patrik Hagman
13
To criticize the conventions of honour was implicitly to challenge
the secular basis of social unity. Unity, for Teresa, is not innate by
virtue of birth; it can be discarded without damage to the person.
Communities can exist with other bonds – that is, friendship with
each other and with God; for the Christian the existence of such
communities is an essential witness to God’s own saving disregard
for honour, human and divine.49
Note that Williams is insistent on keeping the very particular Christian
theological “content” that the saints exhibit in their lives together with
the political implications of it, as if he wants to bypass the conventional
“therefore we ought to” commonly used to link Christian beliefs
together with moral exhortations. It is not by living up to a standard
set by theological ideals that the saints become saints, it is by living a
life made possible by those ideals. What the saints do show, he seems
to say, is that when trust in God is taken absolutely earnestly, a certain
kind of community is inevitable. Furthermore, it will be a community
that displays characteristics that differ from the present society, differences that are best described in political language.
Living icons
My final example is again taken from a very different kind of book by
Williams, his 2008 study Dostoevsky: Language, Faith and Fiction. As a
whole, with its careful reading of Dostoevsky’s novels, the book explores
the analogy of God as author. Saints – albeit fictive one’s – play a significant role here too, and Williams develops his view of their function by
exploring the holiness of characters such as Zosima, Aljosja, Sonya
and Myshkin. Since by now we know where we are going with this, I
will start by displaying where Williams – at least on my reading –
ends up on his journey through Dostoevsky’s work.
Here is the heart of Dostoevsky’s concern, and it is something
unquestionably urgent in a cultural setting where depthlessness
looks like becoming normal. … For Dostoevsky one of the characteristic motives in planned violence, individual or political, is the
determination to extinguish dimensions in the other that exceed
what is chosen and granted. And the contemporary cultural scene
is one which strongly suggests that there is more than one style of
violence directed against these rebel dimensions in humanity: to
take the most obvious example, the global economy works on the
14
Saints in public
assumption that local solidarities and patterns of shared meaning
are all accidental to the fundamental practice of human beings in
the world, which is the unrestricted exchange of commodity and
currency. All particulars are levelled or assimilated to each other
on the principle that everything has an exchange value that can
be clearly determined. And the principle is applied equally to
objects and to practices or skills: hence it becomes possible to quantify quite strictly the value of activities that were formerly regarded
as given meaning by their intrinsic human worthwhileness, and
surrounded accordingly by informal cultures and disciplines. The
point at which the activity of nursing the sick can be expressed in
terms of a producer supplying a customer is the point at which
the culture of nursing the sick begins to disappear.50
Here too the political language surfaces in the last few pages of the
book (though political issues are discussed here and there throughout
the study, in connection with the political themes of Dostoevsky’s
novels). My interest here, once again, is not primarily in the
content of Williams’ politics, but rather in its form and, specifically,
the function of the saint.51 He develops this theme at some length
in the book.
Of the various saintly figures created by Dostoevsky, the Elder
Zosima stands out, not least because he gets to tell his whole life
story himself (sort of)52 in book six of The Brothers Karamazov. Williams
identifies “responsibility for all” as the central theme of the notion of
holiness explored by Dostoevsky, and here we are reminded of the
point made above about the unity between contemplative and active
life.53 In his reflections on his life, Zosima himself seems to make
the connection between clearly religious themes such as sin and forgiveness, the notion of responsibility (echoing Hillesum’s thoughts
cited above), and clearly political questions such as the discrepancy
between universal human rights and the glaring inequality in the
means to fulfil the most basic human needs.54 In what way is such a
politics actually enacted (rather than merely formulated) by Dostoevsky’s saints?
Williams brings attention to the recurring theme of desecrated icons in
Dostoevsky in the last full chapter of his work (before the “Conclusions”). From this he develops a concept of “iconic presence”
which, it seems to me, could function as a general concept for the
theo-political function of the saint that I have tried to tease out of Williams’ texts.
Patrik Hagman
15
Williams suggests Dostoevsky tells his stories of desecrated icons in
order to tell us something of the “visible or recognizable forms of the
holy”.
Holy images contain without simplifying the tensions of the actual
world, and they offer a context of narrative and self-identification
within which human agents may find a shape and a communicative
significance for their activities. … Holy images inform us that our
lives are serious – that is, that they may succeed or fail in fulfilling
a calling given by the creator, and failure in this is a hideous and
painful loss. And they are also a representation that neither distorts
nor substitutes for an underlying reality, but is transparent to its
workings – “true” images not because they reproduce something
absent but because they express, and give a specific vehicle for,
something present.55
Icons depict, not so much a thing in the world, such as a holy person, but
a world in which holy persons are possible – made possible by something beyond that world, its Creator. It is this which makes any desecration of them so potent. Rather than indicating the falseness of that vision
and that world, the very possibility of desecration tells us something
about that presence, something about who God is and consequently
about the world created by that God. The presence of holiness in the
icon has the same form as the presence of Christ in the world – i.e. it
is vulnerable, dependent on the care and love of human beings. In
that sense, a broken icon is even more of an icon than a “perfect” one.
It displays God’s way of being in a particular world. We can here
sense, too, (in part) how Williams would answer a critic such as
Hobson: The weakness of the church – and its failures to live up to the
standards set by its theological ideals – is part of its witness to the world.
Subsequently, moving from icons painted on wood to human lives
displaying this iconic presence necessarily involves a focus on the
process by which that iconic character is achieved, a process that will
have the same vulnerable character. Thus, the life story of a Zosima
included not only youthful sins and frailties, but also a certain lack of
self-awareness about certain details about those lives – e.g. the slightly
morbid concept of the younger brother being responsible for living the
life the older dying brother will not be able to live.
The icon thus testifies to the “dialogic nature of our reality”.56 The
presence of the other makes my identity possible in a constant and
never-ending exchange, a call-and-response that makes up our lives.
16
Saints in public
And the “iconic” other, the holy image either in the literal form of
the icon or in the translation of the icon into narrative in the holy
person, is likewise not a kind of impenetrable surface repelling
my identity, nor a solid presence invading my weak and under
defended territory, but a presence that offers to nourish and
augment what I am. In the world of human relations, what
expresses this is precisely the mutual answerability and taking
responsibility we have examined at length.57
We are now at the point, I think, where we can attempt to formulate the
precise significance of the saint in the political theology present in Williams’ thinking.58 The examples of political language that I have given
from Williams’ writings all rely on something to uphold it. Williams’
political criticism is not merely anti-capitalist rhetoric floating in the
air. Neither are the saints’ lives and teachings probed for “resources”
for such rhetoric. Rather than grounding such utterings in some kind
of philosophical system, metaphysical theory, or indeed, political ideology, Williams points us towards the saints, be it in the form of the great
Teresa of Avila, the fictional Zosima or the captivating yet paradoxical
figure of Etty Hillesum. This, it seems, is because they possess the
iconic presence that grounds political discourse, not in an ideology or
in a tradition, but rather in a quite specific world. The saint’s life indicates
a world with particular features which can only be described in words in
a limited way. In order to ground a different kind of politics, however,
that world has to be lived, mere description will not suffice. The saint
plays this function.59
Conclusion
Let us then return to the moment after taking communion, when Williams wants us to look at our neighbours with awe and amazement.
This is a moment when the “is” and the “ought” overlap completely,
and where it is possible to catch a glimpse of the world as Christianity
claims God sees it. Only based on this reality, where the eternal breaks
into the temporal, is a Christian politics possible.
This indicates a different relationship between the two registers of
theological talk. The saints are not to be understood as rare examples
of human beings who are able to live up to the standard set by theological norms; nor are they primarily rare instances when even the “realistic” voice has to agree with the “proclamatory” voice. Rather, the
saints challenge the presuppositions of the “realistic” voice. They
Patrik Hagman
17
witness to a world that is willed by God, and it is thus a world that
differs in purpose, meaning, structure et cetera from what the “realistic”
voice would believe. From that world a certain politics follows, one
which will have points of contact with the kinds of politics that are possible in a world unaware of its divine origins, but which will also show
important differences.
Thus, when theologians such as Williams formulate their “precariously high” ecclesiology (to use Hobson’s phrase),60 it is not because
they are not being realistic. It is, on the contrary, an attempt to formulate
what the church is like; because it exists in a God-willed world. Of
course, it can do this in a way that obscures the frailty of the church’s
witness, which would be a theological failure – though it seems to me
that William’s seldom succumbs to this. To fail to speak of the church
in a way that shows how it can be a means for God to exist in the
world, however, would be an even worse theological failure. It would
be to allow a world that is unaware of its God-willed-ness to dictate
how God can be present in his world. Without such proclamative talk,
the church is realistically impossible.
The same is true for the Christian talk of eternity. The saints are
examples of human lives that indicate that the world cannot be
described accurately using merely a realistic voice. While Hägglund is
right that meaning arises from finitude, that finitude appears in a markedly different light if it is viewed as a God-willed exception to eternity,
than if it is seen as a closed-off finite universe.61 The saints’ lives witness
to this difference. Rather than being rendered meaningless by their rootedness in eternity, those roots deepen the meaning that arises from their
finite existence, and enable them to exhibit meaningfulness even in the
face of the utter meaninglessness of human evil, as e.g. Hillesum’s life
exemplifies.
Williams, on my reading, suggests that the saint is someone who
embodies a tradition in a way that goes beyond divisions of time and
eternity, practicality and proclamation, because it presupposes a different world from the one where various secular ideologies are the dominating options. When we are looking at the saints – with awe and
amazement – our world begins to change, and thus a different kind of
politics becomes visible and possible.
Patrik Hagman
Faculty of Arts, Psychology and Theology
Åbo Akademi University
Biskopsgatan 19
18
Saints in public
Turku 20500
Finland
patrik.hagman@abo.fi
Disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).
Notes
1. Ben Myers has previously discussed “Williams’ Theology of Saints”. Myers, Christ the
Stranger, 73–81. He suggests that the Saints are a central feature of Williams’ ecclesiology that is ultimately apologetic in nature. “The saint is an argument for the existence of
God” (81). Oliver O’Donovan has also described Williams as “a very unconventional
apologist”. Quoted in Shortt, Rowan’s Rule, 13. As I hope to show in this article, this
is not wrong, but it is too narrow a way to formulate the role the saints play in Williams’ thinking.
2. A few words on method: Williams is a theologian who seems unwilling to present a
theology of “his own” in a way that is easily discerned. One looks in vain for the
one “big book” or chapters in his books where he lays out his own view. He seems
to prefer to let the various subjects of his studies do the talking, or else, refers to the
church’s tradition. This makes it complicated to say something very particular about
his theology. In the following, I have tried to attend especially to those short instances
where he seems to want to make points, by referring to our present world or in other
ways going beyond the particular material under study. However, I do want to
acknowledge that this introduces quite a bit of subjective choice, since it is not
always clear if such passages do indeed reflect Williams’ own thought, or the subject
under study (or both!).
3. I am thinking in particular about the “Sharia-controversy”. Shortt, Rowan’s Rule, 390–
402.
4. Hobson, Anarchy, Church and Utopia; Hobson, “Rowan Williams as Anglican”.
5. Shortt approvingly quotes the priest and author Angela Tilby saying: “[William’s] politics had always come out of a different and less sophisticated part of him” (Rowan’s
Rule, 175).
6. Hobson, Anarchy, Church and Utopia, 99.
7. The distinction is used by Wycliffe (De ecclesia) and Calvin (Institutes IV, 1,7). Luther
seldom calls the church invisible, but uses “hidden” or “spiritual” in much the same
sense. The reformers believed that they were following Augustine in this, though
that would be a very narrow reading of Augustine. See Lee, Augustine and the Mystery.
8. For Calvin, the invisible church is distinct from the visible, because the latter includes
“ambitious, greedy, envious persons, evil speakers and some of quite unclean life”. The
reason why this is “tolerated for a time” is practical – either a competent tribunal is not
available, or the discipline is not vigorous enough. Institutes IV, 1,7. It is thus not
because the true church is fundamentally unknowable that it is invisible, but
because the “visible church” is imperfect. So, while Calvin clearly moves in a more
individualistic direction in his ecclesiology (compared to e.g., Augustine), for him
the talk of the invisible church is not a way to devalue the need for a visible church
Patrik Hagman
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
19
displaying the characteristics of a “new unlimited human community”. On Calvin’s
ecclesiology, see Locher, Sign of the Advent.
See Hobson, Anarchy, Church and Utopia, 45–7; Shortt, Rowan’s Rule, 23–64. Williams
mostly seems to avoid this language altogether, but it is interesting to note that in
his dissertation on one of the most famous modern critics of the notion of an invisible
church in Protestant theology, Vladimir Lossky, Williams merely relates Lossky’s
(fairly over-the-top) criticism on this matter without any comment on his own, and
then proceeds to Lossky’s similar issues with St. John of the Cross and Thomas
Aquinas, with extensive discussion. One gets the impression that Williams finds
Lossky’s judgment on the Protestant ecclesiology mildly amusing but not wrong. Williams, “The Theology of Vladimir”.
Williams, Why Study the Past?, 109. For a discussion of Williams’s rejection of the
visible/invisible church-distinction, see Cary, “Authority, Unity and Truthfulness”.
Hobson’s critique is liberal in character. An example of a more conservative version
would be Radner, A Brutal Unity.
As mentioned, neither Williams’ position nor Hobson’s criticism is very original; rather
it is a very common critique of what is arguably a mainstream position today. For a
well-argued response to this type of criticism, see Cavanaugh, Migrations of the Holy,
141–69.
Hägglund, This Life, 5. Emphasis in the original.
This is not to imply that Hägglund’s understanding of time is unsophisticated; all his
earlier books deal with time in various senses.
For instance, his lack of interest in acknowledging that different religious traditions
understand eternity and related concepts in very different ways undermines much
of his argument. E.g., for Christianity, eternity is first and foremost God’s way of existing, and to define it negatively as timelessness is thus deeply insufficient. This is a very
different concept of eternity than e.g., Buddhism’s Nirvana. On a more philosophical
level, the fact that Hägglund ignores that all of the texts he studies – seriously and competently – deny that time and eternity relate to each other the way he claims they do,
raises questions about his philosophical method. Thirdly, his lack of interest in understanding the writers he studies in their historical context weakens his argument,
especially regarding Augustine, but to a lesser degree also regarding Kierkegaard.
Hägglund, This Life, 68. Emphasis in the original.
Hägglund, This Life, 65.
I have done this elsewhere: Hagman, Om tron, 227–39.
Hägglund describes his book as an attempt to combat all forms of political theology
which anchor moral or spiritual life in “a religious sense of ‘fullness’” (This Life, 27).
Hägglund refers to Peter E. Gordon’s definition of political theology. “In Gordon’s
account, political theology is defined by two theses. The first thesis postulates a normative deficit: secular life suffers from a lack of moral substance and cannot establish a
viable ground for political life together. The second thesis postulates a religious plenitude: to compensate for its normative deficit, secular life must turn to religion as the
unique and privileged resource of moral-political instruction” (“Critical Theory
between the Sacred and the Profane”).
See e.g., Phillips, Political Theology, 42–4; Cavanaugh, Field Hospital, 99–120; Rasmusson,
The Church as Polis.
Bretherton, Christ and the Common Life, 6. For a discussion of the complexities of defining “Political Theology”, see Cole, Christian Political Theology, 11–9.
Bretherton, Christ and the Common Life, 32–4.
20
Saints in public
23. Ibid., 23–4. Bretherton alludes to Carl Schmitt’s famous phrase: “All significant concepts of the modern theory of the state are secularized theological concepts”
(Schmitt, Political Theology, 36).
24. This practice is complicated by the fact that we often distinguish two waves of political
theology, the first wave including names such as Moltmann and Sölle, who today are
appreciated more by self-designated public theologians than by political theologians
of the second wave. Current political theologians such as Stanley Hauerwas and
William T. Cavanaugh also tend to react more against an earlier generation of public
theologians, such as Reinhold Niebuhr and John Courtney Murray, than the first generation of political theologians. Bretherton is very critical of the term (and perhaps the
field?) “public theology”, calling it “a category mistake” since it “assumes that it is
necessary to translate theological concepts into the idioms and frameworks of liberalism” (Bretherton, Christ and the Common Life, 33). While that certainly is a common
practice within the field of public theology, I am not convinced that that practice is
intrinsic to public theology – Williams would be a counterexample; nor am I sure
that everything that public theology does could be contained in Bretherton’s definition
of political theology.
25. See Graham, Between a Rock; Breitenberg, “To Tell the Truth,” 55–96.
26. It is clear that this distinction will not fit everything that is called political theology or
public theology, but nevertheless I maintain that this distinction has some heuristic
use.
27. For an earlier example of Williams’ work as a public theologian, see Williams, The Truce
of God. It was originally published in 1983 and has since been revised.
28. For an overview of Williams’ political thinking (his public theology in my terminology), see Higton, Difficult Gospel, 112–34. See also Frame, “Rowan Williams on War”.
29. I agree with Luke Fodor who argues concerning Williams’ spirituality that always “(1)
it is embodied or incarnational; (2) it is public and political in nature; (3) it is purgative
and progressive” (Fodor, “The Occasional Theology,” 270).
30. Cole, Christian Political Theology, xxvi. Emphasis in original.
31. The political theology of Rowan Williams has previously been studied mostly based on
his engagement with Hegel, via Gillian Rose. See Russell, “Dispossession and Negotiation”. See also (the rather problematic) article Moseley, “Rowan Williams as Hegelian”. Williams wrote three articles on Hegel between 1992 and 1998: “Hegel and the
Gods of Postmodernity”, “Between Politics and Metaphysics: Reflections in the
Wake of Gillian Rose” and “Logic and Spirit in Hegel”. All three are now republished
in Williams, Wrestling with Angels. While it is fair to say that the Hegelian perspectives
explored in these articles can be seen in some of Williams’ other writings on political
issues, it is less clear what relation they have to his more theological or indeed pastoral
writings and the political language found there.
32. Williams, Tokens of Trust, 120. There is a very similar passage in Williams, Being
Christian.
33. Ibid., 128.
34. Hillesum grew up in a non-practicing Jewish family, and seems to have had little
contact with any form of organized religion. Her saintly status is thus not officially
accepted by any Christian church, but it is clear that Williams – in the article discussed
– is treating her in a way that is at least comparable to how saints are treated by
theologians.
35. On the significance of Wittgenstein for Williams’ thinking, see McKinlay, “Ludwig
Wittgenstein”.
Patrik Hagman
36.
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
42.
43.
44.
45.
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
51.
52.
53.
54.
55.
56.
57.
58.
59.
60.
61.
21
Rowan Williams, Faith, 318.
Hillesum, Etty, 488.
Ibid., 506.
Williams, Faith, 319.
Ibid., 322.
Ibid., 323.
Ibid., 324.
Williams, Teresa of Avila, 197.
Ibid., 198.
Ibid., 202.
Ibid., 214.
Ibid., 206. Emphasis in the original.
Hägglund, This Life, 76–90. “To be saved in the religious sense is to no longer care” (77).
Williams, Teresa of Avila, 216.
Williams, Dostoevsky, 229–30.
It is worth pointing out that Williams’ criticism here indicates what is also problematic
with Hägglund’s Marxist view of value in life. Hägglund too, criticizes the way capitalism orders our life so that the only value that is comprehensible is the kind that
creates profits (Hägglund, This Life, 212–69). However, his own proposal stays
within a strict economic framework where all value is related to time in one sense
or another. While probably preferable to the present order, it would still have the
effect that “all particulars are levelled”.
As always with Dostoevsky, it is more complicated. What we have in book 6 of The
Brothers Karamazov is Aljosja’s notes from a conversation with Zosima, thus there is,
as Williams notes, room for “critical suspicion and at least a degree of alienation” (Williams, Dostoevsky, 159).
Ibid., 164–80.
Ibid., 166.
Ibid., 200.
Ibid., 208.
Ibid., 208.
Williams makes a similar use of the saints in other works too: Williams, Lost Icons, 184;
Williams, On Christian Theology, 219. It is interesting that Williams does something very
similar in The Tragic Imagination. Even though it deals with a very different subject, Williams evokes the Russian poet Anna Akhmatova on the very last page as an embodiment of the understanding of tragic drama explored in the essay (Williams, The Tragic
Imagination, 158). While this might be more of a rhetorical move, it is a very plausible
one for Williams to make if the thesis explored above is correct.
It is thus insufficient to describe Williams’ understanding of the saints as apologetical
in nature, as Myers holds. While the saints clearly can be evoked for apologetical
reasons – as in a sense I do in relation to Hägglund in this article – their function in
Williams’ thinking has a more fundamental role, as they enable theological talk to challenge conventional notions of what is realistic. The saints thus play a constitutive role
in Williams’ thinking, establishing the conditions for “reality”.
Hobson, Anarchy, Church and Utopia, 54.
It is ironic that Hägglund’s own secular political vision, which he calls democratic socialism, has features he ascribes to religious notions of eternity. While he wants to show
how it derives from his notion of spiritual freedom, based on his notion of secular
faith, it is so far removed from present political reality that the way it is supposed to
22
Saints in public
function seems to be as a kind of transcendent ideal, inspiring political activism in a
certain direction. Hägglund gives no indications as to what kind of practices and institutions could be created in the present society that would take us towards his ideal
system. This leads one to wonder whether the faith he wants to recommend is actually
secular in the sense he claims.
Bibliography
Breitenberg, E. H. “To Tell the Truth: Will the Real Public Theology Please Stand
Up?” Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 23, no. 2 (2003): 55–96.
Bretherton, L. Christ and the Common Life: Political Theology and the Case for
Democracy. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2019.
Cary, J. W. “Authority, Unity and Truthfulness: The Body of Christ in the
Theologies of Robert Jenson and Rowan Williams with a View toward
Implications for Free Church Ecclesiology.” 2010. https://baylor-ir.tdl.org/
handle/2104/8022.
Cavanaugh, W. T. Field Hospital: The Church’s Engagement with a Wounded World.
Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2016.
Cavanaugh, W. T. Migrations of the Holy: God, State, and the Political Meaning of the
Church. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2011.
Cole, J. Christian Political Theology in and Age of Discontent: Mediating Scripture,
Doctrine, and Political Reality. Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock, 2019.
Fodor, L. F. “The Occasional Theology and Constant Spirituality of Rowan
Williams.” Anglican Theological Review 94, no. 2 (2012): 263–279.
Frame, T. “Rowan Williams on War and Peace.” In On Rowan Williams: Critical
Essays, edited by Matheson Russell, 163–185. Eugene, OR: Cascade, 2009.
Gordon, P. E. “Critical Theory Between the Sacred and the Profane.”
Constellations 23, no. 4 (2016): 466–481.
Graham, Elaine. Between a Rock and a Hard Place: Public Theology in a Post-Secular
Age. London: SCM, 2013.
Hägglund, M. This Life: Secular Faith and Spiritual Freedom. 1st ed. New York:
Pantheon, 2019.
Hagman, P. Om tron: Att söka den djupa verkligheten. Skellefteå: Artos, 2018.
Higton, Mike. Difficult Gospel: The Theology of Rowan Williams. New York: Church,
2004.
Hillesum, Etty. Etty: The Letters and Diaries of Etty Hillesum 1941–1943. Edited by
Klaas A. D. Smelik and Arnold J. Pomerans. Complete and Unabridged.
Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2002.
Hobson, T. Anarchy, Church and Utopia: Rowan Williams on Church. London:
Darton Longman & Todd, 2005.
Hobson, T. “Rowan Williams as Anglican Hegelian.” Reviews in Religion &
Theology 12, no. 2 (2005): 290–297.
Lee, J. K. Augustine and the Mystery of the Church. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress,
2017.
Locher, Gottfried Wilhelm. Sign of the Advent: A Study in Protestant Ecclesiology.
Fribourg: Academic Press, 2004.
McKinlay, B. “Ludwig Wittgenstein in Rowan Williams’s Theological Account of
Language.” New Blackfriars 98, no. 1075 (2017): 327–341.
Patrik Hagman
23
Moseley, C. “Rowan Williams as Hegelian Political Theologian: Resacralising
Secular Politics.” The Heythrop Journal 53, no. 3 (2012): 362–381.
Myers, B. Christ the Stranger: The Theology of Rowan Williams, a Critical
Introduction. London: T & T Clark, 2012.
Phillips, E. Political Theology: A Guide for the Perplexed. London: T & T Clark, 2012.
Radner, E. A Brutal Unity: The Spiritual Politics of the Christian Church. Waco, TX:
Baylor University Press, 2012.
Rasmusson, A. The Church as Polis: From Political Theology to Theological Politics as
Exemplified by Jürgen Moltmann and Stanley Hauerwas. Rev. ed. Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1995.
Russell, M. “Dispossession and Negotiation: Rowan Williams on Hegel and
Political Theology.” In On Rowan Williams: Critical Essays, edited by
Matheson Russell, 85–114. Eugene, OR: Cascade, 2009.
Schmitt, C. Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2005.
Shortt, R. Rowan’s Rule: The Biography of the Archbishop. London: Hodder &
Stoughton, 2014.
Williams, Rowan. Being Christian: Baptism, Bible, Eucharist, Prayer. London: SPCK,
2014.
Williams, R. “Between Politics and Metaphysics: Reflections in the Wake of
Gillian Rose.” Modern Theology 11, no. 1 (1995): 3–22.
Williams, Rowan. Dostoevsky: Language, Faith, and Fiction. London: A&C Black,
2008.
Williams, R. Faith in the Public Square. London: Bloomsbury, 2015.
Williams, Rowan. “Hegel and the Gods of Postmodernity.” In Shadow of Spirit:
Postmodernism and Religion, edited by Philippa Berry and Andrew Wernick,
72–80. Abingdon: Routledge, 1992.
Williams, R. “Logic and Spirit in Hegel.” In Post-Secular Philosophy: Between
Philosophy and Theology, edited by Phillip Blond, 116–130. Abingdon:
Routledge, 1998.
Williams, R. Lost Icons: Reflections on Cultural Bereavement. Harrisburg, PA:
Morehouse, 2000.
Williams, Rowan. On Christian Theology. Challenges in Contemporary Theology.
Oxford: Blackwell, 2000.
Williams, R. Teresa of Avila. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2004.
Williams, R. “The Theology of Vladimir Nikolaievich Lossky: An Exposition and
Critique.” PhD diss. Oxford University, 1975. https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/
uuid:15b86a5d-21f4-44a3-95bb-b8543d326658.
Williams, R. Tokens of Trust: An Introduction to Christian Belief. London: Hymns
Ancient & Modern, 2007.
Williams, Rowan. The Tragic Imagination. The Literary Agenda (Litag). New York:
Oxford University Press, 2016.
Williams, Rowan. The Truce of God: Peacemaking in Troubled Times. Norwich:
Canterbury, 2005.
Williams, R. Why Study the Past?: The Quest for the Historical Church. Grand
Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2005.
Williams, R. Wrestling with Angels: Conversations in Modern Theology. Grand
Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2007.