Academia.eduAcademia.edu

The Ethics of Intercultural Communication

2013, Educational Philosophy and Theory

University of Warwick institutional repository: http://go.warwick.ac.uk/wrap This paper is made available online in accordance with publisher policies. Please scroll down to view the document itself. Please refer to the repository record for this item and our policy information available from the repository home page for further information. To see the final version of this paper please visit the publisher’s website. Access to the published version may require a subscription. Author(s): Malcolm N MacDonald Article Title: The Ethics of Intercultural Communication Year of publication: 2012 Link to published article: http://www.wiley.com/bw/journal.asp?ref=0013-1857 Publisher statement: The definitive version is available at wileyonlinelibrary.com EPAT Workflow " rP Fo ! # $$ % # % & % %' ( w ie ev rR ee EPAT Workflow % ) Page 1 of 19 The Ethics of Intercultural Communication Introduction For some time, the role of culture in language education within schools, universities and professional communication has received increasing attention (Corbett, 2003). This area of pedagogic activity is referred to as ‘intercultural communication’; the attribute of being able to communicate with interlocutors from other cultures is termed ‘intercultural competence’ (Feng, Byram & Fleming, 2009); and a person who possesses this attribute has been dubbed the Fo ‘intercultural speaker’ (Kramsch, 1998; Byram, 2008, pp. 57-77). The aim of this paper is to disclose, critique and circumvent the implicit ethical imperative which underwrites this area of inquiry. Indeed, across many areas of contemporary discursive practice there appears to be an rP incitement to communicate with the other, the ethical grounds for which remain undisclosed and unproblematised. The central argument in the paper identifies two ‘aporias’, in the sense of ee untraversable boundaries, logical contradictions or antinomies (Derrida, 1993), which arise from the ontological and axiological assumptions of intercultural communication: first, they contain an rR unstated impetus towards a universal consciousness; second, the truth claims of much of intercultural communication (IC) discourse are grounded in an implicit appeal to a transcendental moral signified. Inter alia, we contend that these features constitute the study of intercultural ev communication as ‘totality’ (Levinas, 1969/2007, 1998/2009) or as a ‘metaphysics of presence’ (Derrida, 1976, 1978, 1981). We then propose more considered and radical ethical grounds for ie intercultural pedagogy and praxis. w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 EPAT Workflow Intercultural Consciousness Intercultural communication aims to encourage mutual understanding and dialogue across cultural divides in ways that not only consolidate the communities to which its members belong, but also win over the sceptical. In particular, it seeks to raise awareness of the role of language in constituting national and supra-national identities and cultures (Holliday, 2010). This includes not only subscribing to radical intercultural pedagogies (Shi-xu & Wilson, 2001), but also envisaging more cosmopolitan subjects who traverse the transnational terrain with openness towards, and tolerance of, the other (Starkey, 2007). These goals are often expressed as a desire 1 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow for the transformation of intercultural consciousness, and are realized pedagogically through bringing about a deep-seated change in the mind or consciousness of the intercultural speaker, e.g.: Through competence-based IC training, trainers can mindfully transform the mindsets, affective habits and behavioural routines of the trainees and help them to communicate adaptively across cultures (Ting-Toomey, 2010, p. 21). Furthermore, in the context of the expanding European Union (EU), Byram (2008) proposes that such a transformation embrace a measure of democratic participation – not just within the Fo political culture of the nation state, but also within that of pan-national political groupings. [E]ducation for intercultural citizenship expects to create change in the individual, to rP promote their learning. Becoming an intercultural citizen involves psychological and behavioural change including change in self-perception and understanding of one’s relationships to social groups (p. 187). ee Such pedagogic goals contain a weak and a strong claim with regard to the intercultural rR speaker’s sense of self. The weak claim suggests that the intercultural speaker is able to recognise difference in the beliefs, attitudes and values of the other, and tolerate this difference. This already entails a certain shift in the speaker’s self-consciousness. The strong claim is that ev the intercultural speaker recognises difference in the beliefs, attitudes and values of the other, embraces them and in so doing becomes ‘transcultured’. For example, some form of hybridized ie consciousness appears to be entailed in Kim’s (2005) socio-psychological account of cross- w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 2 of 19 cultural adaption, positioned within the mainstream, functionalist strand of US intercultural communication. [A]n increasingly intercultural identity and selfhood emerges from extensive experiences of stress and adaptation. In this process, we are likely to see a blurring of lines between ‘us’ and ‘them.’ Our old identity is never completely replaced by another. Instead, our identity is transformed into something that will always contain the old and the new side by side to form a perspective that allows more openness and acceptance of differences in people, an understanding of ‘both-and’, and a capacity to participate in the depth of aesthetic and emotional experience of others (pp. 395-6). 2 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 3 of 19 The strong claim is commonly implied by much of the literature in the field, as a construct which sits below the surface of the discourse and is not in plain view. Asante and Yoshitaka (2008), for example, in commenting on the IC field in a recent collection, indirectly draw our attention to it. Scholars writing in intercultural communication have seen the tremendous advance made by expanded consciousness […]. Implied in all of the selections in this collection is the idea that the people of the world can communicate. There is a sense that we are against conflict and in support of the harmonious coexistence of humans […]. It is actually the only reason why we communicate, that is, to make ourselves understood in ways that produce harmony (p. 6). Fo It is often in the dual notions of an expanded consciousness and the harmonious (co)existence of peoples that IC discourse frequently implies the strong claim, because both are dependent upon a rP conception of wholeness, or a movement towards wholeness as the basis of their comprehension. It follows then that if existing human consciousness is limited and needs to be expanded, then ee intercultural consciousness must be a more complete consciousness, or at least a consciousness that is moving towards an ideal of completeness. If we support the harmonious concord of rR humans as an end goal, then the parallel implication is that it requires an intercultural consciousness that is equal to the task. It seems to us, therefore, that there is an implicit endpoint to the strong claim of intercultural communication, which actually goes against the grain of the ev recognition of difference according to which the field of intercultural communication subsists. This is the development of a universal consciousness in which difference is effaced. That this ie projected endpoint – the desire for oneness – may be temporally beyond a statement’s immediate w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 intent, does not negate the fact that it is still present beneath the surface of the discourse. It is this desire for oneness which provides the strong claim’s ‘metaphysics of presence’. By this we refer to an implied desire for conceptual fulfilment and purity in the discourse, in the process of which the consciousness of the intercultural speaker is transformed and the difference between the self and the other erased. In this respect, IC discourse appears to echo the oneness of the Hegelian dialectic, according to which the history of humankind involves the transformational development of the collective human spirit towards full consciousness: 3 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow World history merely shows how the spirit gradually attains consciousness and the will to truth; it progresses from its early glimmerings to major discoveries and finally to a state of complete consciousness […]. The principles of the national spirits in their necessary progression are themselves only moments of the one universal spirit, which ascends through them in the course of history to its consummation in an all embracing totality (Hegel, 1822/1999, p. 404). Here, national identities appear as disparate ‘national spirits’ which are only elements in a wider global consciousness, that is, a ‘universal spirit’ (Geist) which is the totality of a collective consciousness. For Hegel, history marks the gradual transcendence of the circumscribed national Fo spirits towards a universal ‘Spirit’ or ‘Mind’ by which humankind attains full consciousness. This occurs as a staged awakening of Mind: an incremental transformation of consciousness rP through time, towards an absolute knowledge and understanding which marks the end of history. This drive towards universal consciousness appears to us to be a principal – although hitherto ee unacknowledged and untheorised – implication of IC discourse. The intercultural ideal is imbued with the Enlightenment principle of presence as the satisfactory repletion of ideas and outcomes, rR in which difference is resolved in favour of a rationally ordered ‘transcultural’ totality. This implicit momentum towards a universal consciousness constitutes our initial aporia in IC ev discourse; for the ontological impetus towards transculturalism in the form of an integrated human consciousness simultaneously implies closure, finitude and the resolution of difference ie within what is supposed to be an antinomic intercultural terrain. In other words, by presupposing ‘oneness’, IC discourse systematically effaces the premise of its own ontology – the irreducible w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 4 of 19 relation to the other. Thus, by means of the passage from the many to the one, intercultural communication brings about its own dissolution. Truth and Transcendentalism To achieve these transformations, interculturalists frequently adopt an interventionist stance which appeals to the transcendental. That is, they contribute rhetorically and materially to the transnational public sphere in order to promote co-operation, reduce conflict and improve human rights (Phipps, 2007a; de Souza, 2006), and they do so by appealing to an implied higher order of 4 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 5 of 19 morality by which the differences that exist may be adjudicated and in some manner resolved. For example, referring to ‘critical cultural awareness’, Guilherme writes: [C]ritical cultural awareness […] may be defined as a reflective, exploratory, dialogical and active stance […] that allows for dissonance, contradiction, and conflict as well as for consensus, concurrence, and transformation. It is a cognitive and emotional endeavour that aims at individual and collective emancipation, social justice, and political commitment (2002, p. 218; original emphasis). Here Guilherme appeals, amongst other things, to transcendental ideals of emancipation and Fo social justice as goals of critical cultural awareness. Taking a more explicitly interventionist and ethically motivated position, Salzman argues for a ‘just globalization’: rP What to do? We can work to build just world (sic) based on a ‘just globalization’ […]. We can, through education and enlightened representatives of our diverse humanity, ee make salient the affirmative, humane values existent in all religions and cultural traditions. We can work to make salient the ‘higher angels of our nature.’ The affirmative and high values of mercy, justice, love, and compassion exist and find rR correspondence across belief systems. It is these we must make salient from the pulpit to the school (2008, p. 326). ev Here Salzman makes explicit appeal to ‘high values’ in the transcendental plane as a means of solving the intercultural problems of the immanent plane – i.e. the plane of lived existence. The ie positions of Guilherme, Salzman and others can be regarded, then, as the ‘critical- w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 transformational’ ethical arm of IC discourse. Its spokespersons intend to increase people’s awareness of manipulation, exploitation, discrimination and abuse in the world against an (often) implied foundational ethical premise; and to move them to act upon it. This sense of transformational purpose sees the desedimentation of subjectivities as positive and productive, because it gives strength to the hope that, “things might be different some day” (Adorno, 1973, p. 323). For Giroux, this ethical interventionism is a principal role of the public intellectual: [W]e have obligations at least to inaugurate a discourse around the unrepresentable, that which cannot be spoken within social relations, particularly within groups that know that generally to speak is to be punished […]. [A]s a public intellectual I have the 5 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow obligation to rewrite the narratives of possibility for those who have occupied subject positions where that hasn’t been possible before (2005, p. 158). Why we have these obligations, and where they come from, is not made explicit by Giroux, or others, but is presupposed. That they exist however is not in doubt – the implication in IC discourse is that they are transcendentally given. It is the legitimacy of these critical-transformational claims to truth that leads to our second aporia. As with any claim to truth, these propositions can imply a right to determine for others what counts as truth. Moreover, it remains unclear what distinguishes these truths from other Fo ‘truths’ to which a critical-transformational discourse is often opposed, such as economic neoliberalism and religious fundamentalism; and specifically what makes critical interventionist rP truths ‘truer’ than these others. There is also the risk in what we are calling critical- transformational truths that they simply become elements in a wider intercultural ‘meta- ee narrative’ (Lyotard, 1984), an overarching template for explaining the intercultural whole. Problems arise when the meta-narrative encounters those whose own claims contradict its own. rR These might possibly include neo-conservatives, nationalist political parties and fundamentalist groups of any religious persuasion. If the discourse of these groups is at odds with criticaltransformational discourse, the following ‘aporetic’ questions arise: To what extent can a critical ev transformational discourse refuse to engage in a transformational dialogue with these others; and closely related to this, on what ethical grounds might it assert preference for its claims over the ie claims of these others? To address these questions it is necessary to explore a further set of w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 6 of 19 grounds on which IC discourse can construct propositions and positions regarding prejudice, equality and human rights; and how it is possible to assert that a particular ‘intercultural’ claim should prevail. It seems to us that current articulations of the critical-transformational discourse of intercultural communication, as evidenced by Guilherme and Salzman above, are grounded in an implicit appeal to a transcendental signified. That is, a noumenon or ‘moral theism’ existing outside human experience, against which intercultural claims can be measured and judgements made. In the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/2003), Kant saw the operation of the moral noumenon as a priori to the world, and distilled it in his work in terms of a faith that it was there. That is, he 6 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 7 of 19 believed that it existed, but also that it was impossible to step outside our world to see it, know it or experience it. This led Kant into moral contradiction, which despite the categorical imperative he was never satisfactorily able to overcome. With regard to intercultural communication this Kantian aporia is revisited primarily through the discourse of tolerance, e.g.: There is little question that in the post September 11 cultural landscape, the need for tolerance among peoples of different faiths has become more urgent, especially in the war-torn Middle East, where religion inspired violence often turns homicidal and catastrophic (Abramovich, 2005: 295). Fo Similarly, drawing on the work of Berlin (1990), Byram (2006) proposes adjudicating between, “[cultural] values which one can condone, and those which are ‘beyond the pale’ of human rP reason and value” by reference to the (transcendental) principles contained in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (p. 125). ee Due to its emphasis on the ‘need for tolerance’, IC discourse finds itself in a Kantian moral bind. By asserting the claim that tolerance is the preferred ethical option, but being unable to give rR grounds – other than transcendentally – for why this is so, the truth which such a claim presupposes becomes reduced to that of an opinion. If this truth is indeed an opinion, then not ev only is intercultural communication misleading itself about the implied universality of the ethic of tolerance, it also puts itself in the position of not having immanent – i.e. ‘here and now’ ie grounds for adjudicating between competing truth claims. In this paper we understand the immanent to consist of the world within our possible lived experience of it. Just as the immanent w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 critique of the Frankfurt School (e.g. Adorno, 1967, 1973) was concerned with critiquing the object on its own terms – i.e. from within – so an immanent critique of the ethics of cultural practice must navigate without the assured moral compass of tolerance to guide it. The implicit universal moral imperative of tolerance is a danger to interculturalists because it can lead in principle to ethical paralysis and inertia, particularly in the face of exorbitant acts of the other which on the aforesaid grounds they feel obliged against reason to condone. In our present times these include practices such as vaginal circumcision, wearing of the niqab, linguistic engineering (e.g. California’s Proposition 227), culture-based homophobia and the fetishism of the female form. Where the instinct is to react against such practices, interculturalists have relied too much 7 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow for their interventions on the transcendental idealism of Enlightenment thinking and the universalities of equality and human rights. If our responses to the cultural acts of the other are to become more ethically consistent, we need to devise explicit and persuasive immanent – as opposed to transcendental – grounds for the positions which we take so that we may not only adopt a more inwrought and intrinsic ethical stance, but still also move to ethical judgement as part of a necessary and ongoing reflexive intercultural praxis. Totality and Terror Fo This Enlightenment desire for plenitude and its appeal to transcendental idealism gives rise to similarly dramatic, yet philosophically distinct responses from Emmanuel Levinas and Jacques rP Derrida. Levinas sees it as ‘totality’ linked to violence and terror: “The visage of being that shows itself in war is fixed in the concept of totality” (1969/2007, p. 21). While Kant posited a ee priori transcendental concepts for the understanding of phenomena and the sensory intuition of space and time, for Levinas the processes of reason are executed through human consciousness, rR the cogito. Through the process of rationality, the other is constituted by perceptual noesis that obtains to the knowing subject. On this argument, in order to understand or to communicate purposefully with another person, we exercise our powers of reason upon them. However, ev through the very exercise of rational understanding we reduce the other to who we are, and the other becomes “part of the same” (1969/2007). The attempt to understand other people through ie categorizing, objectifying knowledge not only denies the immediacy and potential of the one-to- w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 8 of 19 one relationship with others – “beings in the openness of being” – but also serves to dominate and possess them. In so doing, we carry out a “partial negation” of the other which constitutes an “act of violence” (1997, p. 8). Derrida’s critique of totality arises from the violence of language and signification residing in the logocentric workings of the Saussurean sign (Derrida, 1976, 1978, 1981, 1988). In the first instance, the union of the signifier and the signified seems to satisfy a desire for a certain type of fulfilment, that of having a sound or mark which can be used to refer to a concept. But having seemingly named the concept, we find that the concept has no meaning except in its difference 8 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 9 of 19 from other signs, as there are no self-identical words or signs. Derrida names this différance; différance entails that there are no pure signs – “there is no experience consisting of pure presence” (1988, p. 10; original emphasis). For example, the ‘inside’ can never be a pure inside, because it is dependent on there being an ‘outside’. For this reason Derrida demonstrates how the essence of the signified must be formally prior to the sign, and that fulfilment, or ‘pure presence’, cannot be claimed except by making recourse “in favour of a meaning supposedly antecedent to différance, more original than it, exceeding and governing it in the last analysis. This is […] the presence of what we called […] the ‘transcendental signified’ (Derrida, 1981, p. 29). On these terms the transcendental signified is the signified to which all signifiers ultimately Fo refer; it is the place where meaning comes to rest in itself. If the transcendental signified is prior to the sign, it is, like Kant’s noumenon, a-discursive and a-historical, outside our experience, rP unknowable. The transcendental signified is the object of the human longing for fulfilment and plenitude – a craving for the unfulfilled unity of the sign itself. ee The longing for presence does violence to the sign by seeking to ‘fix’ its concepts against the transcendental signified. For Derrida, this is an impossibility. The transcendental signified is not rR present to us, it is outside the text, of which there is “no outside” (Derrida, 1976, p. 156). Meaning, therefore, cannot be ‘fixed’. In place of the absent signified, Derrida posits an endless ev chain of signifiers, one referring to the other ad infinitum: ie The meaning of meaning … is infinite implication, the indefinite referral of signifier to signifier … its force is a certain pure and infinite equivocality which w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 gives signified meaning no respite, no rest, but engages in its own economy so that it always signifies again and differs (1978, p. 29). This entails that no meaning can ever be fully grasped in its entirety, in its full presence, because signifiers only refer and time does stop for them. For critical-transformational interculturalists to make (implied) foundational claims about justice, tolerance and understanding is to do unintended violence to these concepts; for by unintentionally ‘fixing’ their meaning they potentially close them down. They also run into the danger of arrogating to themselves privileged access to the noumenal signified, the signified 9 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow outside. Asserting such entitlements is dangerous since the claims which ensue may then become organising principles, i.e. ‘truths’, against which the claims of others can then be judged. When a claim becomes an organising principle, it finds itself in conflict with other dissenting claims, and reacts with violence towards them. The western alliance’s ‘War on Terror’ and the Jihadism of Al-Qaeda are both examples of claims which are being used in this way. They each represent a will to truth which colonises the discursive terrain according to its own perceptions, based as they are on the presupposed obviousness of their own moral privilege. Alterity, Difference and Signification Fo The second part of this paper responds to the twin aporias identified above. To address the first, relating to the implications of a universal consciousness, we explore after Levinas (1969/2007, rP 1998/2009) the possibility of a non-totalising relationship between the self and the other. For Levinas, the source of the self is incontrovertibly located in its relation with the other. This ee subverts and supersedes the ontology of being as an autonomous ‘existent’ and challenges the orthodox ontology of presence that has underwritten western philosophy from Descartes to rR Heidegger, namely the self-consciousness of the self in its being in the world. For Levinas, the self is inextricably bound up with the other in as much as the same is unable to exist in its absence: “the self cannot survive by itself alone, cannot find meaning within its own being-in- ev the-world within the ontology of sameness” (Levinas in Kearney 2004, p. 75). Furthermore, while in Hegelian thought the historical apogee of the relation between self and other entails the ie erasure of difference and the reconciliation of the self and other in the attainment of universal w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 10 of 19 consciousness, for Levinas the maintenance of distance and separation through time is fundamental to existence: “a relation with a reality infinitely distant from my own reality, yet without this distance destroying this relation and without this relation destroying this distance” (1969/2007, p. 41). This irreducible space gives rise to the ‘infinitely distant’ nature of the relation between same and other; while the surplus of being which the other presents to the same gives rise to its property of ‘transascendence’. 10 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 11 of 19 The infinite and trans(a)scendent properties of this relation, then, do not entail the other being positioned in a negative, ‘antithetical’ relation to the self; but rather the self being aligned in a positive, constitutive relation with the other: [T]he separation of the same with regard to the other […] cannot rest on an opposition to the other which would be purely antithetical. Thesis and antithesis, in repelling one another, call for one another. They appear in opposition to a synoptic gaze that encompasses them; they already form a totality which, by integrating the metaphysical transcendence expressed by the idea of infinity, relativises it. An absolute transcendence has to be produced as non-integratable [...]. Correlation Fo does not suffice as a category for transcendence (1969/2007, p. 53; original emphasis). rP On this argument the ‘non-integratability’ of same and other becomes the originary condition for selfhood, and hence the milieu for the development of subjectivity. rR ee Like contemporary interculturalists, Levinas describes the relation between the self and the other as being ‘accomplished’ through language (1969/2007). For Phipps (2007b) intercultural ev pedagogy is more a process of becoming through ‘languaging’ with the other, rather than an edifice of knowledge and understanding about the other. However unlike many interculturalists, ie this relation is not a symmetrical one, but rather is “such that the other, despite the relation with the same, remains transcendent to the same” (Levinas, 1969/2007, p. 39). Furthermore, while the w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 idea of the ‘cultural’ emerged from language education as a necessary contextualization of a priori linguistic systems (Corbett, 2003), for Levinas the relationship between self and other is autochthonous. Language arises from this ‘pre-existing’ relation and realizes it through arguably its most immediate form, speech. For the relation between self and other is “primordially enacted as conversation, where the same, gathered up in its ipseity as an ‘I’, as a particular existent unique and autochthonous, leaves itself” (1969/2007, p. 39). These forms of relational selfhood are not suspended until some eschatological, Hegelian future; but are located in the immanence of interhuman relations lived out in the here and now. 11 EPAT Workflow Page 12 of 19 EPAT Workflow Truth and the Ethical Relation This section addresses our second aporia, the implicit transcendental appeal of a criticaltransformational discourse. On this argument, if judgemental truths are caught up in the metaphysical complicity of a signed universe which cannot be critiqued without recourse to the sign itself – that is from the inside (Derrida, 1978), the premise for judgemental critique must also be derived from within a system of knowledge in which ethical concepts are not outside dependent, i.e. based on transcendentals. In order to push ethical practice along this internal path Levinas distinguishes between two interdependent dimensions of the relation between self and other: the interhuman and the ethical. Fo The interhuman relationship emerges with our history, without being-in-the-world as intelligibility and presence. But it can also be considered from another perspective... – rP which transcends the Greek language of intelligibility – as a theme of justice and concern for the other as other, as a theme of love and desire which carries us beyond the finite ee Being of the world as presence. The interhuman is thus an interface: where what is ‘of the world’ qua phenomenological intelligibility is juxtaposed with what is ‘not of the world’ qua ethical responsibility (Levinas in Kearney, 2004, p. 74). rR The interhuman dimension is again familiar to us from those sciences in which humans are ev viewed “as citizens, as individuals, as a multiplicity in a genus”. From this perspective, the study of intercultural communication has veered towards a concern with knowledge and functionality, ie rather than with truth and justice. However, on Levinas’s account, ethics precedes ontology as ‘first philosophy’: w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Pre-existing the disclosure of being in general taken as the basis of knowledge and as meaning of being is the relation with the existent that expresses himself (sic); preexisting the place of ontology is the ethical plane (1969/2007, p. 201). The theme of “justice and concern for the other as other” disrupts the ontology of presence by always already preceding it and providing the grounds for ethical relations between human beings. 12 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 13 of 19 This ethical movement towards the human other is always preferable as difference than as unity: “sociality [...] is better than fusion”. It is this irreducible other that Levinas names ‘the face’ (1969/2007, pp. 194-201); and the approach of the self to the face is the location of the ethical core of this relationship, “the most basic mode of responsibility”. The face of the other summons the ‘I’ through language, and invokes the obligation of the self to the other. The ethical ‘I’ is subjectivity precisely insofar as it kneels before the other, sacrificing its own liberty to the more primordial call of the other...As soon as I acknowledge that it is ‘I’ who is responsible, I accept that my freedom is anteceded by an obligation to the other (Levinas in Kearney, 2004, p. 78). Fo In this way, Levinas’s conceptualization of ‘the face’ offers a critical-transformational rP interculturalism grounds for an ethics arising from the immanence of the relationship with the other rather than through a Kantian appeal to a transcendental moral signified. ee Levinas goes on to argue that the responsibility of the self for the other is accomplished by its rR capacity to substitute itself for the other. In an expiative description, the self is described as ‘accused’, as ‘persecuted’, as ‘a hostage’: “...under accusation by everyone, the responsibility for everyone goes to the point of substitution” (1998/2009, p. 112). On this argument, the principles ev for action in relation to the other do not proceed from an ontologically bounded self that projects itself towards the other through an appeal to a set of transcendental ideals; but rather emanate ie from an asymmetrical relationship in which the self is positioned in an ethical relation of w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 responsibility for the other. Responsibility for another...precedes essence in it...I have not done anything and have always been under accusation – persecution. The ipseity, in the passivity with arche characteristic of identity, is a hostage (1998/2009, pp. 114-115). Moreover, this ethical relation gives rise ‘primordially’ to the grounds of signification: “an exposure to the other, it is signification, is signification itself, the one-to-the-other to the point of substitution, but a substitution in separation, that is responsibility” (1998/2009, p. 54). These are 13 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow posited as fundamental to human existence in an ‘inversion’ of identity which ‘escapes’ conventional ‘relations’ in as much as these relations presume ontology. Towards a Discourse Ethics of Responsibility We have identified two aporias within IC discourse: one emerges from its implicit impetus towards a universal consciousness, which is in contradiction with its declared principles of openness, tolerance and difference; the other arises from its grounds for truth being implicitly based on an appeal to a transcendental moral theism. The second part of this paper has attempted to circumvent these aporias, first, by outlining a more immanent relation between self and other Fo in order to supersede the implication of universal consciousness; and second, by proposing that there is a way of reconstructing an intercultural praxis so that it is no longer dependent upon idealist claims to truth. rP This ethical relation of responsibility is adopted and extended in the later work of Derrida (1999, ee 2001; Derrida & Dufourmantelle, 2000); and from this it is possible to extrapolate further immanent grounds for a critical-transformational intercultural praxis. On Derrida’s account, rR without an infinite responsibility to the other, “you would not have moral and political problems, and everything that follows from this” (in Critchley, 1999, p. 108). In other words, it is through responsibility, rather than through the foundationalist presuppositions of presence, that the ev discursive terrain remains open and that a non-normative ethics becomes possible. Without responsibility, the hope which is carried in the possibility of the other that things might be ie different one day, as well as the praxis which such hope implies, would be denied. By drawing w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 14 of 19 on responsibility for the other, and therefore to a commitment to openness rather than closure, the point is not to determine whether different truth claims are good or bad, but whether putting a particular discourse or set of discourses into practice might lead to a silencing of open alternatives; and therefore also a turning away from the other. That these alternatives should be open makes it possible for IC discourse to locate itself in opposition to perspectives and practices which interculturalists would normally associate with closure and intolerance, while simultaneously seeking to exercise reflexive support for more open alternatives, not because they know it is right to do so but because they know that not to do so would be an act of irresponsibility. In this way, the praxis of intercultural communication is able to supersede a 14 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 15 of 19 universalist telos of tolerance, understanding and reconciliation by reaching a new (and everrenewable) accommodation with the other, one which moves the discussion with the other on without reaching a conclusion. This then provides the grounds for denying the alterity of the other, when that alterity presents itself as received and final – in extremis and exorbitant – as in the widespread cultural presentation of homosexuality as ‘sin’, the linguistic engineering of California’s Proposition 227, and the culturally-legitimated oppression of women by means of the niqab, vaginal circumcision and the fetishism of the female form. There have to be grounds for questioning the supposedly culturally unquestionable, and for not welcoming the evidently unwelcome. The grounds for this are immanent rather than transcendental, and are based upon Fo principles of openness and responsibility as ethical bulwarks against discursive closure and cultural introversion. rP We therefore propose (after Levinas and Derrida, op. cit.) a discourse ethics of responsibility ee whereby it becomes possible for an intercultural praxis to engage critically and transformatively with regard to the exorbitant cultural acts of the other. This does not entail that interculturalists rR must automatically forgive in the moment that they are summoned to forgiveness; but rather that they must consider whether their forgiveness might entail a sanctioning of the other’s practice, ev and a closure and acceptance of eschatological finitude. Nor does it entail that interculturalists should accept the unacceptable just as they accept other acts of the other. In intercultural ie responsibility ‘tolerance’ is rejected; for tolerance is a form of charity. As Derrida puts it: w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 If I think I am being hospitable because I am being tolerant, it is because I wish to limit my welcome, to retain power and maintain control over the limits of my ‘home’, my sovereignty, my ‘I can’ (my territory, my house, my language, my culture, my religion, and so on) (2003, p. 128). Tolerance declares to the other that their acts are being entertained under sufferance, and that these acts are at one and the same time subject to a privileged hegemonic order of the self. 15 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow The extremis and exorbitant acts of the other which are in conflict with an intercultural discourse that is obliged against reason to countenance them, are unacceptable because of the way in which truth is employed to justify their perpetration. The employment of truth as an organising principle leads to an iteration of certain types of practice which over time pass under the banner of ‘tradition’. Religion does this by claiming a moral foundation in tradition, science by claiming an unquestioned, self-legitimating universality. In both cases a privileged signified is employed as truth, and by this means each closes itself off from public interrogation. What this suggests is that tradition in intercultural communication should never be accepted as giving privileged warrant for any type of cultural practice, but should always be rigorously questioned, Fo problematised and deconstructed. rP In conclusion, while we may not be able to supersede the aporias in IC discourse which we have identified, there are alternative pathways through which it is perhaps possible to circumvent them. To avoid the Hegelian impetus towards universal consciousness implicit in IC discourse ee we posit an irreducible distance and separation between the self and other; in so doing not only are we able to bypass the field’s implicit appeal to the transcendental as the source of truth but rR also to counter the exorbitant claims and actions – out of ‘tradition’ – of the (intercultural) other. Thus, the ethical grounds for intercultural praxis derive from an immanent “non-reciprocal ev relation of responsibility” between the self and the other (Bettina, 2008). In “the human struggle to make meaning” (Phipps, 2007b, p.19), it is necessary to strive not to finish with just the one – ie but all the time to keep a reflexive eye on the many. This way, the radical otherness of the other is preserved; for a critical intercultural praxis keeps the space between same and the other open w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 16 of 19 in expectation and hope without ever needing arrival and acceptance. In intercultural communication we are obligated to sustain an incitement to responsibility and all that this entails, because, following Derrida, “pure unity or pure multiplicity […] is a synonym of death” (1997, p. 13). In our quest for the intercultural we therefore favour the multiple over the singular, the variable over the stable and the mess over the arranged. 16 EPAT Workflow Page 17 of 19 References Abramovich, D. (2005) Overcoming the Cultural Barriers of Conflict: Dialogue between Israelis and Palestinians, Jews and Muslims, Journal of Intercultural Studies, 26: 4. Adorno, T. W. (1967) Prisms (London, Neville Spearman). Adorno, T. W. (1973) Negative Dialectics (New York, Continuum). Asante, M. K. & M. Yoshitaka (eds.), (2008) The Global Intercultural Communication Reader (Oxford, Routledge). Bettina, B. (2008) Emmanuel Levinas, in: E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia Of Philosophy, available at <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/levinas/>. Fo Berlin, I. (1990) The Cracked Timber of Humanity (NJ: Princeton University Press). Byram, M. (2006) Developing a Concept of Intercultural Citizenship, in M. Byram & G. Alred rP (eds.), Education for Intercultural Citizenship (Clevedon, Multilingual Matters). Byram, M. (2008) From Foreign Language Education to Education for Intercultural Citizenship: Essays and Reflections (Clevedon, Multilingual Matters). ee Corbett, J. (2003) An Intercultural Approach to English Language Teaching (Clevedon, Multilingual Matters). rR Critchley, S. (1999) Ethics, Politics, Subjectivity: Essays on Derrida, Levinas and Contemporary French Thought (London, Verso). ev de Souza, L. M. T. M. (2006) Language, Culture, Multimodality and Dialogic Emergence, Language and Intercultural Communication, 6:2. ie Derrida, J. (1976) Of Grammatology (Baltimore, John Hopkins University Press). Derrida, J. (1978) Writing and Difference (London, Routledge). Derrida, J. (1981) Positions (London, The Athlone Press). w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 EPAT Workflow Derrida, J. (1988) Limited Inc. (Evanston, North Western University Press). Derrida, J. (1993) Aporias (Stanford, University of Stanford Press). Derrida, J. (1999) Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas (Stanford, Stanford University Press). Derrida, J. (2001) On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness (London, Routledge). Derrida, J. (2003) A Dialogue with Jacques Derrida, in: G. Borradori (ed.), Philosophy in a Time of Terror (Chicago, University Of Chicago Press). Derrida, J. & A. Dufourmantelle (2000) Of Hospitality (Cultural Memory in the Present) (Stanford, Stanford University Press). 17 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Feng, A., Byram, M. & M. P. Fleming. (2009) Becoming Interculturally Competent through Education and Training (Clevedon, Multilingual Matters). Guilherme, M. (2002) Critical Citizens for an Intercultural World (Clevedon, Multilingual Matters). Giroux, H. (2005) Critical Pedagogy and Cultural Power, in: Border Crossings: Cultural Workers and The Politics Of Education, (London, Routledge). Hegel, G. W. F. (1822/1999) The Philosophy Of History, in: S. Houlgate (ed.), The Hegel Reader (Oxford, Blackwell). Holliday, A. (2010) Complexity in Cultural Identity, Language and Intercultural Fo Communication, 10: 2. Kant, I. (Kant 1781/2003) Critique of Pure Reason (trans. N. K. Smith) (Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan). rP Kearney, R. (2004) Debates in Continental Philosophy: Conversations with Contemporary Thinkers (New York , Fordham University Press). ee Kim, Y.Y. (2005) Adapting to a New Culture: An Integrative Communication Theory, in W. B. Gudykunst (ed.), Theorizing about Intercultural Communication (Thousand Oaks CA, rR Sage). Kramsch, C. (1998). The Privilege of the Intercultural Speaker, in Byram, M. & Fleming, M. ev (eds.), Language Learning in Intercultural Perspective (Cambridge, CUP). Lévinas, E. (1997) Entre Nous: On Thinking-Of-The-Other (London, Athlone Press). ie Lévinas, E. (1969/2007) Totality and Infinity (Pittsburgh, Duquesne University Press). Lévinas, E. (1998/2009) Otherwise than Being (Pittsburgh, Duquesne University Press). w 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 Page 18 of 19 Lyotard, J. (1984) The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge (Manchester, Manchester University Press). Phipps, A. (2007a) Other Worlds Are Possible: An Interview with Boaventura de Sousa Santos, Language and Intercultural Communication, 7: 1. Phipps, A. (2007b) Learning The Arts Of Linguistic Survival: Languaging, Tourism, Life (Clevedon, Multilingual Matters). Salzman, M. B. (2008) Globalization, Religious Fundamentalism and the Need for Meaning, International Journal of Intercultural Relations, 32: 4. 18 EPAT Workflow EPAT Workflow Page 19 of 19 Shi-Xu, & Wilson, J. (2001) Will and Power: Towards Radical Intercultural Communication Research and Pedagogy, Language and Intercultural Communication, 1: 1. Starkey H. (2007) Language Education, Identities and Citizenship: Developing Cosmopolitan Perspectives, Language and Intercultural Communication, 7:1. Ting-Toomey, S. (2010) Intercultural Conflict Interaction Competence: From Theory to Practice, in: M. Guilherme, E. Glaser, & M. D. C. Mendez-Garcia (eds.), The Intercultural Dynamics of Multicultural Working (Clevedon, Multilingual Matters). w ie ev rR ee rP Fo 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 19 EPAT Workflow