PROD #: 01019
Psychoanalytic Psychology
2002, Vol. 19, No. 3, 501–524
Copyright 2002 by the Educational Publishing Foundation
0736-9735/02/$5.00 DOI: 10.1037//0736-9735.19.3.501
Jung, Jungians, and Psychoanalysis
Kenneth Eisold, PhD
William Alanson White Institute
The break between Freud and Jung—and the subsequent division between their followers—has had profound and continuing consequences for both parties. The Jungians have continued an ambivalent relationship to psychoanalysis, with the
effects of internal conflicts and institutional schisms. Mainstream psychoanalysis, for its part, has used Jung, the primary
and still most prominent “deviant,” to inhibit developments in
areas associated with his work. This article explores how the
pressure to maintain solidarity and conformity in psychoanalysis has curtailed, in particular, thinking in 3 areas: symbolism,
lifelong development, and paranormal experience. It concludes
with observations about the opportunities and dangers associated with the move toward pluralism being considered in
both camps.
Ownership
Who owns psychoanalysis? The question may seem absurd to us now, and
yet the issue of proprietorship and control of the copyright has been an
intricate and pervasive part of our history. In his “On the History of the
Psychoanalytic Movement,” Freud (1914/1957a) asserted bluntly,
psycho-analysis is my creation. . . . I consider myself justified in maintaining
that even today no one can know better than I do what psycho-analysis is, how
it differs from other ways of investigating the life of the mind, and precisely
Kenneth Eisold, PhD, William Alanson White Institute, New York, New York.
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Kenneth Eisold,
PhD, 353 Central Park West, New York, New York 10025. E-mail: Keneisold@
aol.com
501
502
EISOLD
what should be called psycho-analysis and what would be better described by
some other name. (p. 7)
He emphatically made the point that Adler and Jung should stop using the
term. And, indeed, they did.
The myth that grew up around Freud as the isolated and courageous
hero (Sulloway, 1979) legitimized his ownership: He was the conquistador
who first set foot on the territory of psychoanalysis, the Copernicus who
first observed its distant movements, the Newton who first elucidated its
laws. He encouraged that myth by repeatedly stressing the courage required to hold firm to the stark truths of psychoanalysis in the face of the
resistances and opposition of society. In his “An Autobiographical Study”
(Freud, 1925/1961), he restated his conviction that Adler and Jung’s defections were motivated by the “temptation . . . of being freed from . . . the
repellent findings of psycho-analysis” (p. 52).
The myth of the hero became the myth of the movement. Freud
wrote Ferenzci, “Of course, everything that strives to get away from our
truths has public approval in its favor. . . . We are in possession of the
truth” (Freud & Ferenczi, 1993, pp. 482–483). To Abraham, he wrote,
“recognition will come only for the next generation. But we have the
incomparable satisfaction of having made the first discoveries” (Freud &
Abraham, 1966, p. 111).
The claim required an institutional basis. “There should be some
headquarters whose business it would be to declare: ‘All this nonsense is
nothing to do with analysis; this is not psycho-analysis’ ” (Freud, 1914/
1957a, p. 43). So wrote Freud in 1914, explaining his motive in forming
the International Psychoanalytic Association (IPA). Earlier, before the
threat of Adler and Jung’s “defections,” he had similarly claimed that the
IPA was founded “to repudiate responsibility for what is done by those
who do not belong to us and yet call their medical procedure ‘psychoanalysis”’ (Freud, 1910/1957b, p. 227).
By the public, Freud may have been seen as autocratic or authoritarian, but there was no doubt that he was and remained the dominant
figure—victor, leader, and proprietor. Adler and Jung continued to be
defined by their relationship to the central, heroic enterprise from which
they “defected.” Paradoxically, they were cast out of the psychoanalytic
band and yet perpetually linked to it as “deviants,” “former disciples,”
derivative figures. Protesting this continuing linkage, Ellenberger (1970)
stressed the point that both Adler and Jung had developed some of their
key ideas before being swept up in the psychoanalytic movement and that
they evolved quite differently from Freud and each other: “Contrary to
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
503
popular assumption, neither Adler nor Jung is a ‘psychoanalytic deviant,’
and their systems are not mere distortions of psychoanalysis” (p. 571). But
this remains a lonely point of view.
Indeed, Adler himself responded to his “expulsion” by naming the
alternate society he founded The Society for Free Psychoanalytic Research. He was stunned and deeply hurt by Freud’s ad hominem attacks on
his “petty outbursts of malice” and “uncontrolled craving for priority”
(Freud, 1914/1957a, p. 51). But, in his injured pride, he stressed the point
that this was an institutional issue, not a personal one.
If Adler’s response to Freud’s declaration of ownership was defiant,
he nevertheless agreed to give up the term psychoanalysis. Jung, by contrast, at first entirely withdrew from organizational life. He resigned all
institutional positions after resigning as president of the IPA, including his
university professorship. He also abandoned the Zurich Psychoanalytic
Society and only gradually found a way back into organizational life as an
“analytical psychologist.”
Wrote Jung’s most recent biographer, “By common consent, Jung
never got over the trauma of his break with Freud” (McLynn, 1996, p.
420). He himself suggested, in Memories, Dreams, Reflections (Jung,
1961), that he underwent a profound disorientation, “menaced by a psychosis” (p. 176). I think we can understand this disorientation as representing a cleavage in Jung’s identity. No doubt there was a confusing and
troubled working out of his relationship to Freud as a father, but also there
was conflict among the identities he had attempted to weld together as a
psychoanalyst. As Ellenberger (1970) pointed out—and as Taylor (1996,
1998) and Shamdasani (1998) more recently elaborated—Jung brought to
psychoanalysis not only considerable standing as a psychiatrist, a standing
that so impressed Freud, but also significantly developed interests and
orientations that linked him with others outside psychoanalysis. To put it
perhaps overly simply, there was the identity of a psychiatrist and psychologist, linked to Freud, committed to working professionally with patients, and there was the identity of a spiritual seeker, drawn to the study
of religious myth and linked to the long line of Protestant ministers from
which he had descended.
But the important point here is that his experience with Freud and the
IPA inevitably had profound organizational consequences as well. After
reorienting himself and his thoughts, following the break with Freud, Jung
also had to develop the organizational structures and policies that would
carry his work forward. Those structures had to be responsive to the
particular needs and qualities of his ideas and his identity. As would be
504
EISOLD
inevitable, they reflected his traumatic experiences with the organizations
of psychoanalysis he left behind. And as they developed, they continued
to bear the imprint of that traumatic break and to exhibit a complex,
conflicted, and ambiguous relationship with psychoanalysis. In a parallel
article, I focus on the impact of that split on the institutional development
of analytical psychology (Eisold, 2001), the effects of which are still
powerfully felt today.
Here I want to focus on the effects of that split on psychoanalysis.
Freud’s determination to exclude Jung and his followers did not abate, and
many of his loyal followers enthusiastically kept up the struggle. The IPA,
formed to defend against “deviants,” is still not open to Jung’s followers.
Indeed, I think, many in the psychoanalytic mainstream do not even recognize it as an issue to be concerned with; they “own” the copyright to the
term psychoanalysis that Jung gave up the right to use. In a sense, they
would agree with Ellenberger that Jung is not a psychoanalytic “deviant,”
though he may once have been. They see him as a somewhat mystical,
somewhat eccentric—if popular—writer on myths and dreams. They may
be well aware that there are Jungian institutes and Jungian practitioners,
but, in general, that is viewed has having no relevance.
In effect, the struggle against Jung initiated by Freud has become
more subtle, more embedded in everyday assumptions. Like Foucault, we
could view this as a struggle to dominate and control the discourse: Language now, itself, keeps analytical psychology outside. But I will argue
that the open war has been succeeded by the entrenched, invisible warfare
of social defenses aimed at maintaining vestigial boundaries around psychoanalysis, of containing threats to its integrity and core assumptions.
Many “deviants” followed Jung. Indeed, a central portion of the history of
psychoanalysis can be read as the story of such “defectors” as Horney,
Sullivan, Thompson, Fromm, Lacan, and others, key figures suffering
fates narrowly avoided by others such as Ferenzci, Klein, and Kohut. None
of them were forced to abandon the term psychoanalysis, no doubt emboldened and warned by the examples of Adler and Jung, though many of
them were subject to the same charge of watering down psychoanalysis to
make it more acceptable to the public. It has been said of most of them, at
one point or another, “This is not psychoanalysis.” But their use of the
term was never successfully proscribed. Jung remains the warning figure
who went too far, the one who defines the dangerous boundary of what is
acceptable.
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
505
“A Silent Experiment”
In 1916, when Jung emerged from his period of “disorientation” and
“confusion,” the organization he founded to support and advance his work
was a “Psychological Club.” Retrospectively, he called it “a silent experiment in group psychology” (Jung, 1959/1970, p. 469). In a paper he
presented to the Club in 1916, he wrote,
It is an attempt to work together as analyzed men. . . . We are acquainted in
analysis up till now only with the function of the personal-collective (analyst
and patient), just as we have learnt much about the individual function. But we
know nothing about the collective function of individuals and its conditions.
(quoted in Shamdasani, 1998, p. 24)
As Fordham (1979) put it much later, “it was to have no professional
status, and membership was not a qualification to practice psychotherapy”
(p. 279). It was a group gathered together to support members in their own
spiritual and psychological development. In doing so, they would also
support Jung and provide a forum for him to present his thoughts.
This Club has been called a “cult” (Noll, 1995, 1997), and, indeed,
in its blending of mystical and German “volkisch” elements together with
the reverence for Jung’s idealized position in it, the Club bears some
resemblance to a cult. But it seems more likely that the Club actually
suffered from a lack of clear focus, permitting it to resemble, as one
member wrote at the time, sometimes a “madhouse” and sometimes something “occult-sectarian” (Shamdasani, 1998, p. 78). It was convivial and
social. A library was organized. There were lectures and discussions;
every two weeks or so, Jung met there with a group of senior analysts.
Responding to his recent experience of the professional structures of
psychoanalysis, structures dominated by a strong leader, Jung was determinedly informal and nonprofessional. As Fordham (1979) put it,
Jung did not want to form a school of Jungian analysts, and, indeed, no formal
training was ever instituted by him. He had witnessed that particular development in psychoanalysis; he did not like it and he did not want to repeat it. (p.
280)
Indeed, not only had he witnessed psychoanalytic politics firsthand
as the first president of the IPA, he had also been the object of an organizational plot to displace and discredit him. The summer before his
personal break with Freud, Jones had proposed a secret committee that
would operate outside of the formal structures of the IPA (Grosskurth,
506
EISOLD
1991). In his letter proposing the “unofficial inner circle,” Jones expressed
his “pessimism” about the “men who must lead for the next thirty years,”
noting “Jung abdicates his throne” (Freud & Jones, 1993, p. 146). The
reference was to the fact that Jung had suddenly gone to America to
deliver lectures and see patients, postponing the 1912 Congress as a result.
Jones pointedly lamented, in that same letter to Freud, “so many put their
own private personality first, in the foreground of importance, and relegate
the cause to a subordinate position” (p. 145).
As Grosskurth (1998) put it, the secret committee’s “implicit raison
d’être was to expel Jung, the Outsider, from the psychoanalytic movement” (p. 91). Immersed in their own suspicions and plots, they became
riddled with paranoid fears about Jung’s plans to take over the psychoanalytic movement.
For his part, Jung seems to have had little idea of the campaign being
mounted against him. He did not know that he had been supplanted by the
secret committee, that his authority had been undermined. When Freud
and his close followers abstained from voting for him in his second term
as president, he appeared to be genuinely surprised and hurt (Jones, 1953–
1957). He was obviously deeply offended the following month when he
heard that Freud doubted his good faith in his conduct as editor of the
Jahrbuch, and he precipitously resigned (Paskauskas, 1988, p. 28). As it
turned out, Jung not only had no interest in a fight but also, as ever, little
interest in running an organization. In April 1914, he resigned as president.
The issue was loyalty, the willingness of Freud’s followers to defer
to his leadership, to confirm his ownership of psychoanalysis. But although it was undoubtedly the case that Freud wanted to maintain his
ownership of psychoanalysis (see Roustang, 1982), it is important to bear
in mind that it was Freud himself who put forth both Adler and Jung as his
successors. Their ability to succeed depended on the willingness of others
to follow them. In the case of Adler, I believe, his erstwhile followers
brought him down, exploiting the issue of theoretical differences, in order
to induce Freud to take charge (Eisold, 1997). In the case of Jung, the
loved and chosen “Crown Prince,” it was a group of Freud’s closest
followers who banded together and—with Jung’s own active cooperation—deposed him.
This was the experience that lay behind Jung’s decision to set up his
Club. In his new organization, by avoiding a professional focus and placing the emphasis entirely on mutual support and spiritual development, he
hoped, consciously at least, to avoid recreating the organizational dangers
he had come to know first hand. He also created for himself an institu-
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
507
tional refuge. No other formal organization existed, associated with Jung,
until the founding of The Jung Institute in 1948.
How anyone became an analytic therapist in those days is vague and must be
regarded largely as a matter of vocation, though there was an unwritten law that
any person who wanted to be called a Jungian analyst was expected to go out
to Zurich, make a relation with Jung himself, and undergo analysis with either
himself or one or more of his close colleagues. (Fordham, 1979, p. 280)
At some point, Jung would indicate that he felt the person was ready to
practice and wrote a letter to that effect. Samuels (1994) pointed out, this
“cozy club setting” was “undoubtedly riddled by unresolved transferences
and countertransferences. . . . One gets the impression from accounts of
people who were there of a sort of therapeutic community” (p. 139).
Thus, setting out deliberately to avoid the kind of professional competition and rivalries that had characterized psychoanalytic politics, Jung
ended up in the “silent experiment” of the Club creating an almost hermetically secure environment for himself. By rejecting formal training, he
avoided the possibility of creating rivals. And by not exploring transference, he ensured his preeminent, idealized status.
In part, I believe, this reflected the need of a fragile ego in a period
of recovery, when he was “menaced by a psychosis.” But it also represented a choice about the nature of the movement he wished to establish.
The stress was on exploration of myths and religions, on education in
occult traditions of symbolism, and on articulating the notion of spiritual
development. Only secondarily was there a focus on the preparation of
careers in psychotherapy.
Jungian Training
When formal professional training in analytical psychology began, following World War II, it emerged with Jung’s reluctant agreement. Aging
and ill, he was persuaded to give his consent. Moreover, professional
training had to establish itself in the institutional space that had been
created in the intervening years, the space between Jung’s psychological
clubs and the highly professionalized world of psychoanalysis. Inevitably,
it was forced to be in competition with both.
The development that Jung resisted, thus, took two opposing
courses, represented by the two training institutions that were the first to
be established: The Zurich Institute, founded in 1947, in the city where
Jung continued to live, stayed close to his informal methods and to the
508
EISOLD
ethos of the Clubs, stressing education in myth and symbols. The other,
The Society for Analytical Psychology (SAP), sited in London, founded in
1946, looked to psychoanalysis for models of training and professional
links.
According to Fordham (1979), the chairman of the SAP,
In many ways the London analysts were doing just what Jung had sought to
avoid. . . . His agreement to what was being done was, however, gained and he
became the first president, protesting, however, that he would not be able to take
an active part in the proceedings of the Society. No doubt he was ambivalent,
and when he was written to about the starting of a clinic, he registered a
vigorous protest, but here again was persuaded to let his name be used. . . . The
C. G. Jung Clinic was thus started with the master’s approval. (p. 283)
As Samuels (1994) noted, “the Society of Analytical Psychology of
London followed the British Psychoanalytical Society when it drew up its
constitution in 1946 and the nomenclature is, in many respects identical”
(p. 146). In addition, the SAP made several key controversial decisions
that were based on the practices of the British Psychoanalytical Society
and which, as a result, increased tensions between not only the SAP and
the Club but also within the SAP between older Zurich-trained analysts
and the new group under Fordham’s leadership: a focus on transference,
regression, and infantile material; an increase in the number of analytic
sessions per week; evaluation of candidates by the training analyst; and a
minimizing of “education” by the analyst. All of these represented significant departures from Jungian traditions.
The Jungians in England also actively explored parallels between
their theories and methods and those of Klein (Astor, 1995; Fordham,
1993) as well as Winnicott and Bion (Samuels, 1985). The institutional
connections between the Jungian analysts and the members of the British
Psycho-Analytical Society through the British Medical Society, as well as
the links through the Tavistock Institute, made additional connections and
collaboration possible. Fordham (1979) noted,
it began to appear that the old divisions between the two disciplines were in the
process of dissolving because of the new thinking that was going on on both
sides. Thus though the divisions are maintained formally their scientific basis is
less meaningful. (p. 293)
In his obituary of Jung, Fordham (1961) declared forcefully that he
believed the notion of Jung’s personal and scientific incompatibility with
Freud “was a disaster, and in part an illusion, from which we suffer and
will continue to do so until we have repaired the damage” (p. 4). It could
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
509
be said that in the manner in which Fordham took up the job of establishing training for analytical psychologists he aimed precisely to repair
the damage.
The Zurich Institute, on the other hand, established in 1947, became
the repository of Jungian tradition, the Mecca attracting international students. According to Kirsch (1996), “The Zurich Institute was the place to
train; here one could have analysis with a direct pupil of Jung, perhaps also
see Jung himself, and the Institute in Zurich was certainly oriented towards
international students” (p. 573). There was little if any influence from
psychoanalytic practice. Indeed, it “was set up on the model of a European
university with lectures, seminars, and finally exams” (Kirsch, 1995, p.
237). Multiple overlapping analyses were conducted, and a primary stress
of dreams and myth was maintained.
The founding of these two centers of training inaugurated the complex and strife-torn institutional history of analytical psychology in the
post-war era. In America, the battles of Jungian orthodoxy versus psychoanalytic influence have tended to be fought within institutes. As in England, many mental health professionals have sought training, many of
them influenced by the theories and practices of mainstream psychoanalysis. Moreover, in recent years, a number of American Jungians have
moved toward reclaiming the term psychoanalysis. Currently, the C. G.
Jung Institutes of New York, Chicago, and Los Angeles are component
societies of the National Association for the Advancement of Psychoanalysis—as is the Alfred Adler Institute in New York—which means that
they sought and received accreditation as psychoanalytic institutes. I do
not believe this implies that the identities of these institutes as organizational parts of analytical psychology no longer matter, but there is a
larger—and older—identity they are reclaiming.
Furthermore, the American Jungians, under the auspices of the Journal of Analytical Psychology, organized a series of conferences to explore
areas of common or overlapping interest with mainstream Freudians. Conferences were held at Sebasco, Maine, in 1996 and 1997; a third was held
in Mérida, Mexico. A similar event was held in England to explore differences between contemporary Jungians and psychoanalysts (Astor,
1998).
As Kirsch noted in his address to a 1996 conference in Sebasco,
As psychoanalysts in general have so little knowledge of Jung and the Jungian
literature, there is the potential danger that our uniqueness could get lost. On the
other hand, most of us have some working knowledge of psychoanalysis in its
510
EISOLD
various forms and are only too happy to embrace large parts of it. Will it go the
other way around? (Kirsch, 1997, p. 24)
Silent Censorship
Symington (1986) has declared emphatically, “We of the Freudian school
who have rejected Jung have been impoverished thereby” (p. 226). But
what, in fact, has psychoanalysis lost by this continuing proprietary exclusion of the Jungians?
The question can be viewed in two ways. What are the potential
links that are not being explored? Samuels (1996) has attempted a list of
such topics, and the recent conferences in London, Sebasco, and Mérida
sought to identify such common ground. Earlier Scott (1978) attempted a
sketch of this terrain, but, significantly, in a talk to a Jungian group
published in a Jungian journal. More recently, Psychoanalytic Dialogues
has published an issue on the post-Jungians, and this journal has published
a lengthy article by three prominent American Jungians titled “What
Freudians Can Learn From Jung” (Beebe, Cambray, & Kirsch, 2001).
But exploring potential links is an enormous and complex task, one
requiring considerable depth of knowledge in two different traditions and
two realms of clinical practice. It also requires a desire on both sides to
bridge the gap, a desire that clearly many Jungians have evidenced over
the years but one that has been notably lacking among mainstream psychoanalysts. I believe that this lack of desire reflects not simply ignorance
of Jungian thought and what it might have to offer mainstream psychoanalysis but also considerable resistance. Despite the current ecumenical
climate and interest in pluralism, analytical psychology by and large continues to be the object of a pervasive disparagement and neglect, amounting to a “social defense” (Menzies, 1967), a collectively elaborated set of
assumptions and behaviors that subtly but firmly protects mainstream
psychoanalysis from the anxiety of questioning some of its deepest and
most pervasive affiliations. This “social defense,” I believe, is what lay
behind Wallerstein’s (1988) remarkable statement excluding the Jungians
from the contemporary effort to define a psychoanalytic “common
ground” (pp. 11–12). As a number of Jungians have pointed out (Kirsch,
2000; Samuels, 1996), Wallerstein ostensibly based his statement on the
flimsy evidence of a doctoral dissertation. Firsthand knowledge seemed
irrelevant.
This brings us to the second way the question about the loss to
psychoanalysis of this continuing exclusion can be raised: What has psy-
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
511
choanalysis used the figure of Jung to avoid? The wall of neglect and
denial that has surrounded the contributions of Jung and the Jungians to
the psychoanalytic discourse has been used to warn potential other deviants, to confine and proscribe exploration within psychoanalysis itself.
Significantly, of course, it has often been those treading on or near the
ground Jung had trod who experience the danger that they, like him, might
be seen as going “too far.” They too could be proscribed.
There have been a number of significant personal relationships that
have allowed communication and influence to occur across this barrier,
but even those are poorly known and have led to very little public acknowledgement. This is the hallmark of a social defense. It is not actually
about the encounter with the proscribed matter. It is about the maintenance
of the solidarity of the group and the preservation of one’s relationship to
it. It is a powerful collusion constituted of small acts of avoidance, distraction, and rationalization.
Acknowledging this, Winnicott (1964) exclaimed forcefully in his
review of Memories, Dreams, Reflection, “If we fail to come to terms with
Jung we are self proclaimed partisans, partisans in a false cause” (p. 450).
And, indeed, his own coming to terms with Jung in that review aroused a
disturbing identification, expressed in a remarkable dream of his own,
which he came to feel he had dreamt “for Jung and for some of my
patients, as well as for myself” (Winnicott, 1963/1989a, p. 229). His
account of the dream is abstract, lacking the details that could suggest
specific associations, but he leaves no doubt about its impact:
1. There was absolute destruction, and I was part of the world and of all people,
and therefore I was being destroyed. . . . 2. Then there was absolute destruction,
and I was the destructive agent. . . . 3. . . . in the dream I awakened. As I awakened I knew that I had dreamed both (1) and (2). (p. 228)
Winnicott linked this dream to the genesis of his late seminal paper, “The
Use of an Object and Relating Through Identifications” (Winnicott, 1969/
1971), in which he described the vital significance of the child’s acting on
and living through its destructive impulses, learning that both the object
survives as well as himself or herself.
We cannot know for sure what Winnicott meant in claiming that he
dreamt this dream “for Jung.” But it is worth noting that the act of writing
the review aroused in him such powerful aggressive feelings and fear that
it led to a burst of creative insight as well as a strongly worded challenge
to his colleagues not to remain “partisans in a false cause.” It speaks, I
believe, to the power that lies in social defenses and the terror aroused in
confronting them.
512
EISOLD
I identify three areas of exploration in psychoanalysis, where the
threat of Jung’s example discouraged and intimidated new developments:
Work on symbols, most usually manifest in dreams; work on identity and
lifelong development; and, finally, “synchronicity,” uncanny correspondences in human experience. In what follows, what I say can only be
suggestive and incomplete—and easily challenged. As we know from our
own clinical experience, it is difficult to identify definitively areas that
have been avoided, split off, or denied. Nor am I arguing that these are the
only areas where the social defense mobilized around the figure of Jung
has discouraged exploration. But these are areas where the evidence is
strong.
Symbols and Dreams
This is the topic Jung pursued during the period of his growing alienation
from Freud in the book that has since become known as Symbols of
Transformation (Jung, 1911–1912/1967). For his part, during this period,
Freud (1913/1955) was spurred on to write Totem and Taboo, his own
version of the origins of religious practices. The competition was friendly,
at this point, if fierce, but it brought them together in acknowledging the
kind of phenomena which Jung, later, referred to as “archetypes.” That is,
Freud (1913/1955) depended on the argument of a phylogenetic inheritance to account for “the assumption of a collective mind” (p. 158). Jung’s
argument was different, but they both were interested in the phenomenon
of symbols that had the quality of universals, that did not arise directly
from individual experience.
In his Interpretation of Dreams (Freud, 1900/1953)—but in a passage added in 1911, during the period of this competition—Freud first
elaborated the point that dream symbolism pre-existed individual experience: “how irresistibly one is driven to accept it in many cases” (p. 359).
Jung explorations were indeed far-reaching, examining myths and
religious rituals in order to develop and elaborate a thorough-going grammar of symbols. Jones (1916/1948), at a strategic moment following the
break between Freud and Jung, attacked him for abandoning “the methods
and canons of science,” to wander “in a perfect maze of mysticism, occultism, and theosophy” (p. 136). He warned psychoanalysts, in effect, to
stick to the narrow range—and, indeed, it became a realm of inquiry that
mainstream psychoanalysis has tended to avoid. Thus, as Fromm (1951)
pointed out, dream interpretation has tended to go in two opposing and
mutually exclusive directions: Jung developed the notion of an autonomous realm of archetypes reflecting transcendent aspirations in the
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
513
psyche, and Freud adhered to the notion that the symbolism of dreams
reflected infantile, sexual urges. As Laplanche and Pontalis (1973) pointed
out, “Whereas the symbols discovered by psychoanalysis are very numerous, the range of things they symbolize is very narrow” (p. 444).
For the English “developmental” Jungians, Klein’s interest in phantasy, symbolization, and inner objects provided renewed opportunities to
explore links with Jung’s ideas about myths, symbols, and archetypes.
Fordham (1993), for example, wrote, “I discovered analogies between
what Jung found in myths and what Klein found in small children’s
fantasies about their mother’s bodies” (p. 66). As we have seen, the
postwar years in London, when training in analytical psychology first got
underway, were years of ferment and interaction. Mainstream psychoanalysts participated in some beginning dialogues with their Jungian colleagues (Scott, 1978), and many Jungians opened themselves up to learning from psychoanalysis about child development and transference, topics
neglected if not avoided by Jung.
It was in this context that Glover (1950/1991) wrote and published
his polemical Freud or Jung. Clearly, he felt the danger that in this climate
Jung was at risk of being more accepted than at any previous time in
England. In a prominent footnote, he observed, “In the writer’s view this
Kleinian system constitutes a deviation from Freudian principles and practice, combining it is interesting to note, some of the errors of both Rank
and Jung” (p. 21).
The potential of such criticism, I believe, inhibited psychoanalytic
developments in dream interpretation. Friedman and Goldstein (1964), in
their critical review of Jung’s psychology, noted this area of “definite
interest” in Jung’s work: “the study of comparative mythology and of
the parallels between mythological and individual dreams and fantasies. . . . material which is rarely referred to in psychoanalytic writings”
(p. 196). Meltzer (1984) noted, in his groundbreaking Dream-Life, that
there has been a corresponding paucity of significant work on dreams in
the psychoanalytic literature: “It is an enigma of psycho-analytical history
that the theory of dreams . . . should have been preserved throughout the
years in word while dishonoured in deed in every session where a dream
plays a part” (p. 14). In attempting to develop a more adequate theory
based on the centrality of emotional experience and symbol formation,
influenced by Bion’s work on thinking, Meltzer once again aroused the
interest of Jungians who saw an approach that linked up with their clinical
and theoretical work (Fordham, 1995). But Meltzer himself did not credit
Jung, nor did he seem in any way to come to his theory by way of Jungian
514
EISOLD
connections. Indeed, his few references to Jung seem designed to establish
the point of their differences.
The point I am making is precisely about the absence of such references. Psychoanalysts, going out on a limb to develop new approaches
in such controversial areas, have felt hardly able to afford associating
themselves with the original apostate. Indeed, to assert a critical difference
with Jung can been seen to affirm that they are still loyal to the mainstream. Casement suggested such a point at the London meeting organized
by the SAP: he wondered “whether every Freud in history needs a Jung ‘to
represent the thinking that goes beyond one person”’ (Astor, 1998, p. 709).
It is perhaps worth adding that, among Jungians, work on archetypes
and symbols has not remained static or without controversy. Contemporary Jungians are increasingly less likely to see symbols as direct reflections of transcendent reality. Polly Young-Eisendrath (1995), writing from
a post-modern perspective, has commented,
Constructivism does not reject universals such as archetypes or universal emotions, but it assumes that both the concepts and the experiences to which they
refer come directly from human interpretation. That is, archetypes do not move
and shape human consciousness; not are we caught in morphogenic structures.
(p. 5)
Acknowledging these developments in the Jungian community more
recently, Modell (1997) noted in a paper originally presented at the first
Sebasco Conference, “This interaction of private metaphor and cultural
symbols may prove to be an area of fruitful collaboration between Freudian and Jungian psychoanalysts” (p. 116). But it still remains to be seen if
such collaboration is possible.
Identity and Lifelong Development
Jung’s notion of lifelong “individuation,” together with his notions of
typologies of the self, provided a framework for his beginning speculations on adult development (Jung, 1933/1972a). Winnicott (1970/1989b)
pointed out that “Jung usefully drew our attention to the fact that human
beings . . . do go on growing in all respects, right up to the moment of
death” (p. 284). As Staude (1981) suggested, these speculations probably
had their beginnings in Jung’s own need to understand the extraordinary
transformations of his own midlife crisis, the developments that led to his
break with Freud and the need to set out on his own adult pathway.
Erikson (1968), probably the psychoanalytic mainstream’s best
known student of the life cycle, noted the clinical discoveries of Jung in
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
515
this area but in a curiously indirect manner: “in the inventory of our
patients’ ideal and evil prototypes we probably also meet face to face the
clinical facts on which Jung based his theory of inherited prototypes
(‘archetypes’)” (p. 58). He added, “As though in fear of endangering a
common group identity based on an identification with Freud’s personal
greatness, psychoanalytic observers chose to ignore not only Jung’s
excesses but also the kind of universal fact he had, indeed, observed”
(pp. 58–59).
Erikson’s recent biographer has called attention to the fact that “it
took years before Erikson could speak publicly about an . . . important
(and perhaps more ‘heretical’) influence on his life, the Jungian analyst
Joseph Wheelright” (Friedman, 1999, p. 163). It was only at the point
where his own reputation was securely established that he ventured some
tentative acknowledgment of the important role in the development of his
own thinking played by Jungian ideas (Erikson, 1982/1987).
Levinson, in his ground-breaking work on the male midlife crisis,
was able to go further, calling Jung “the father of the modern study of
adult development” (Levinson, Darrow, Klein, Levinson, and McKee,
1978, p. 4). But, no doubt, Levinson was helped by the fact that he had no
“common group identity” as a psychoanalyst to preserve, though he places
his own work squarely in “the intellectual tradition formed by Freud, Jung
and Erikson” (p. 5).
This is an area that has been explored in our literature by a number
writers and researchers, reflecting its clinical importance. But it has also
aroused significant wariness on the part of psychoanalytic commentators.
Valliant’s (1977) book, Adaptation to Life, based on a longitudinal study
at Harvard, places itself in the Ericksonian tradition and cites Jung’s
contributions. Colarusso and Nemiroff (1981), similarly, place their
work in the tradition of Freud, Jung, and Erikson, adding to their list of
progenitors the anthropologist Van Gennep. Emde (1985), too, notes the
core contribution of Jung’s work on individuation, Erikson’s work on
stages, adding Kohut’s work on the self. But he also notes that in this
area “findings . . . may be difficult for the psychoanalyst to assimilate”
(p. 109).
The difficulty is that the concept of developmental stages throughout
life does not easily fit the more traditional notion of intrapsychic conflict
working itself out in individual and, often, highly idiosyncratic ways
throughout adulthood. Indeed, as Abrams (1990) has suggested in his
thoughtful review of the subject, any elaborated notion of development
poses a threat to mainstream assumptions:
516
EISOLD
In such an approach, the therapist’s stance may have to be different from what
is customary in analysis, the unfolding treatment process would have to be
different, and in all likelihood the mode of therapeutic action would also be
different. It would be unwise to call such an approach “psychoanalysis.” (p. 673)
Others have expressed similar reservations. In a review of Colarusso and
Nemiroff’s book, Solomon (1982) noted, “psychoanalysts . . . will find the
book of limited value because of the insufficient elaboration of the intrapsychic ramifications of the developmental issues being considered,” adding that it was “more appropriate to psychotherapy than to psychoanalysis” (p. 662).
No doubt, those engaged in substantial research projects in this
realm worry less about their fidelity to privileged mainstream concepts,
just as they worry less about acknowledging their indebtedness to Jung.
Those who derive their primary identities from the world of psychoanalysis, however, walk a tighter line. Pollock and Greenspan’s (1988–1993)
multivolume compilation of articles on the stages of life, The Course of
Life, avoids a theoretical frame and, except for the final volume on old age,
does not reference Jung. Settlage et al. (1988), in their comprehensive
review article on the subject, entirely omit any reference to Jung.
Synchronicity
This is, perhaps, the most difficult topic to discuss because it so readily
brings to mind the occult. And yet there is, in fact, so much “uncanny”
material that many of us encounter in the course of our clinical work that
we are at a loss to explain. “Synchronicity”—in Jung’s (1935/1972b)
terms a “connecting principle” that is neither causal nor merely chance—is
hardly an explanatory concept. Still it creates space in clinical dialogue to
acknowledge the presence of correspondences and seeming linkages that
appear to have meaning, that are charged with significance, though we
have no current way of explaining how or why that could be so.
The notion of “unconscious communication” occupies a somewhat
analogous position in classical theory. Freud (1912/1958) used the analogy of the telephone: the analyst “must turn his own unconscious like a
receptive organ towards the transmitting unconscious of the patient” (p.
115). Mechanisms such as projective identification, postural mimesis, and
role responsiveness have been put forward to explain such processes, but
the fact of the matter is that we seldom understand how we intuit what we
know. Abend (1989) comments, “Surely, every practicing analyst has had
many experiences that remind him of Freud’s telephone analogy, but we
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
517
are not very comfortable with mystical explanations of unconscious communication” (p. 388.). Freud himself, however, was not averse to the
notion of thought transfer, and Deutsch (1926/1970), elaborating on his
comments and her own experiences of telepathy, wrote, “analytic experiences confirm that ‘occult’ powers are to be sought in the depth of psychic
life” (p. 146).
Deutsch’s quotation marks around “occult,” however, speak to a
certain reticence in embracing such phenomena, a reticence that continues
to inform psychoanalytic writings. Nelson (1969) noted the “ostracism of
colleagues who take parapsychology seriously” (p. 4). Farrell (1983) commented that telepathy is “treated like a skeleton in our closet” (p. 79).
More recently, Mayer (1996a) has described a study group of the American Psychoanalytic Association formed to discuss personal experiences of
uncanny knowledge not accounted for by our
public theories. . . . Some of those [more personal] schemata have been frankly
disturbing to the analysts describing them and are based on experiences they
have found exceedingly unsettling to disclose among colleagues. When spelled
out, they suggest possible implication for psychoanalytic knowledge which
are . . . potentially radical. (p. 191)
She has gone on to describe convincing research suggesting that not
only is thought transfer common and demonstrable but also that thoughts
have external effects on inanimate matter. “Psychoanalysts belong in the
dialogues these investigators are undertaking, and we belong as well in the
effort to render comprehensible and non-anomalous what currently appears anomalous in the effects they are examining” (Mayer, 1996b, p.
723). At the same time, again, she acknowledges how difficult it is to
engage such material: “I think we may need to re-cast certain of our
conventions regarding what we find believable” (p. 724).
The history of applied psychoanalysis provides additional examples
of uncanny phenomena. In “Group Relations Conferences,” for example,
designed to study the behavior of large systems (Miller, 1989), one repeatedly sees striking parallels in the behavior of different parts of the
system. Common themes emerge in seemingly unrelated groups; individuals are put forth to enact behaviors on behalf of others without any conscious knowledge of what they are doing; member groups will mirror the
staff without either group being aware of what is happening.
The point I am making is that those who have studied such processes
must pay attention to what actually occurs without worrying about how it
could be explained. To those unfamiliar with the methodology or experi-
518
EISOLD
ence of such conferences, such correspondences will appear uncanny or
simply accidental. We may resort to such explanatory concepts as “parallel
process” or “mirroring” or “projective identification”—but the fact of the
matter is that we do not know how such connections occur. With inadequate experience, they could be overlooked or dismissed.
A second example comes from the work of Gordon Lawrence (1998)
on social dreaming. Lawrence has devised a methodology in which a
“matrix” of individuals reports out its dreams and, then, associates to the
dreams presented. The point is not to interpret the dreams but to allow, so
to speak, dreams to speak to dreams. What he has found is that uncanny
parallels and correspondences in the dreams begin to emerge. One becomes aware of a level on which, it could be said, our individual dreams
are linked collectively.
Again, we may resort to some such idea as “unconscious communication” to explain such uncanny “synchronicities.” Bion’s (1970) introduction of the concept of O, “the unknown and the unknowable,” has been
frequently invoked to justify such an expanded version of the unconscious.
But the point is that we profit in learning about our collective behavior
by keeping our minds open to the meaningfulness of events we cannot
explain.
Jung’s concept of synchronicity is by no means an exactly parallel
notion. Nor, I think, would it be accurate to attribute the reticence of
psychoanalysts to openly embrace uncanny or anomalous phenomena exclusively to their association to Jung. And yet, I believe, there is no doubt
that those psychoanalysts who are interested in exploring these ideas and
experiences know about the work of Jung and avoid referencing it. The
effort to gain a respectful hearing from one’s colleagues for such unconventional thoughts could only be compromised by association to Jung and
Jungians. And yet, as a result, the community of inquiry into such phenomena is unquestionably narrowed and constrained.
Pluralism
I believe there is less interest now in attempting to define psychoanalysis
(Cooper, 1997). The ground has shifted to reconceptualizing psychoanalysis as a pluralistic endeavor. Following Wallerstein’s (1988) classic question “One psychoanalysis or many?”—a question that seemed inevitable to
pose but increasingly impossible to answer—the question we might now
ask is this: In what sense is it “one” and in what sense is it “many”?
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
519
In some measure, this is a matter of political expediency. If there is
no longer the possibility of integrating or synthesizing the divergent
schools of psychoanalysis, to find “the common ground,” it becomes
increasingly necessary to find a political solution, a form of co-existence.
The model of competing interest groups within a democratic state, under
these circumstances, becomes attractive. Berlin (1988/1990) has argued
compellingly for such a form of politics: “an uneasy equilibrium, which is
constantly threatened and in constant need of repair” (p. 19).
And, yet, there are dangers in such a solution for psychoanalysis: it
can become eclectic, abandoning the effort to reconcile competing theories, or it can become relativistic, abandoning theory altogether. Perhaps
an even greater danger is that the professional identity of a psychoanalyst
under such circumstances becomes virtually impossible to sustain. What
forms of practice or set of skills can one hold on to as essential to one’s
professional identity?
But there are signs that pluralism might be more integrated into the
fabric of psychoanalytic thought and clinical experience. Two proposals
have recently been put forth—interestingly, one from the mainstream and
one from the Jungians.
In her researches into the actual beliefs and practices held by analysts of different analytic communities, Hamilton (1996) has demonstrated
not only the variety of forms the actual practice of psychoanalysis takes,
even within the mainstream, but also the role of the local community in
shaping and sustaining that variety: “analysts think and practice much
more loosely than they publicly claim. They are guided preconsciously by
many dimensions” (pp. 3–4).
For Hamilton (1996), the key concept is the preconscious, analogous
to Winnicott’s “transitional space,” the third area of the mind in which
creative ambiguity and play are sustained. Her argument is that this is the
area of the mind in which analysts do much of their thinking, a realm of
“muddled overlaps and uncomfortable, precarious coexistence of parts of
belief systems” (p. 3). But, far from being a liability or simple embarrassment, such pluralistic complexity and potential confusion in the mind of
the analyst is an asset because it matches the ambiguity of mental experience. The greater danger is that of a precise theoretical map that misleads
with too much definition and clarity about a territory that does not lend
itself to map-making in any traditional sense.
Where Hamilton agues for taking up an analytic stance in the preconscious, where creative ambiguity and conflict can be sustained,
Samuels (1989) argues that the pluralism of theories matches the pluralism
520
EISOLD
of the psyche. That is, the mind requires different and conflicting theories
because it is itself composed of different and competing selves. The clinician approaching this complex and seemingly contradictory set of clinical phenomena is helped by having a diversity of theories to guide him.
For Samuels (1995), the danger is not only a hierarchical view of the
mind, matched by efforts to establish a theoretical hierarchy, but any view
of consensus that minimizes conflict and contradiction. “The more integrated and professional the training programme, the greater the denial of
pluralism” (Samuels, 1995, p. 41).
The proposals of Samuels and Hamilton overlap in key respects and,
yet, emphasize different phenomena. Both suggest ways in which pluralism can become a more viable option for psychoanalysis—and, I believe,
they open the way for additional speculation and theorizing so that pluralism does not remain simply a politically expedient solution.
Shamdasani (1994), introducing a collection of papers originally
commissioned for a conference at the Freud Museum, commented,
“psychoanalysis is not One, cannot be owned, or adequately appropriated. . . . its heterogeneity renders impossible any pluralist, allencompassing programme, or attempt at unification” (p. xv). But this
heterogeneity is difficult to live with, confusing to keep in mind, impossible to enjoy.
In its beginning years, psychoanalysis could not sustain such diversity. Adler, Jung, and their followers were victims of that failure. Now,
however, it might be possible to conceive of it as one potentially encompassing if, at times, contentious, even acrimonious, conversation—that is
if psychoanalysts of different schools were able to enter into it.
References
Abend, S. (1989). Countertransference and analytic technique. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 58, 374–395.
Abrams, S. (1990). The psychoanalytic process: The developmental and the integrative. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 59, 650–677.
Astor, J. (1995). Michael Fordham: Innovations in analytical psychology. London:
Routledge.
Astor, J. (1998). Some Jungian and Freudian perspectives on the Oedipus myth and
beyond. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 79, 697–712.
Beebe, J., Cambray, J., & Kirsch, T. B. (2001). What Freudians can learn from Jung.
Psychoanalytic Psychology, 18, 213–242.
Berlin, I. (1990). The pursuit of the ideal. In H. Hardy (Ed.), The crooked timber of
humanity (pp. 1–19). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work
published 1988)
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
521
Bion, W. R. (1970). Attention and interpretation. London: Tavistock.
Colarusso, C. A., & Nemiroff, R. A. (1981). Adult development: A new dimension of
psychodynamic theory and practice. New York: Plenum Press.
Cooper, A. M. (1997, November). Psychoanalytic education: Past, present and future.
Address to the Association for Psychoanalytic Medicine, New York, NY.
Deutsch, H. (1970). Occult processes occurring during psychoanalysis. In G. Devereau
(Ed.), Psychoanalysis and the occult (pp. 133–146). New York: International Universities Press. (Original work published 1926)
Eisold, K. (1997). Freud as leader: The early years of the Viennese Society. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 78, 87–104.
Eisold, K. (2001). Institutional conflicts in Jungian analysis. Journal of Analytical
Psychology, 46, 335–353.
Ellenberger, H. (1970). The discovery of the unconscious. New York: Basic Books.
Emde, R. N. (1985). From adolescence to midlife: Remodeling the structure of adult
development. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 33(Suppl.),
59–112.
Erikson, E. H. (1968). Identity: Youth and crisis. New York: Norton.
Erikson, E. H. (1987). For Joseph Wheelwright, my Jungian friend. In S. Schlein (Ed.),
A way of looking at things: Selected papers from 1930 to 1980 (pp. 713–715). New
York: Norton. (Original work published 1982)
Farrell, D. (1983). Freud’s “thought transference,” repression, and the future of psychoanalysis. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 64, 71–81.
Fordham, M. (1961). Obituary: C. G. Jung. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 34,
3–4.
Fordham, M. (1979). Analytical psychology in England. Journal of Analytical Psychology, 24, 279–297.
Fordham, M. (1993). The making of an analyst: A memoir. London: Free Association
Books.
Fordham, M. (1995). Freud, Jung, Klein—The fenceless field: Essays on psychoanalysis and analytical psychology (R. Hobdell, Ed.). London: Routledge.
Freud, S. (1953). The interpretation of dreams. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The
standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vols. 4 &
5, pp. 1–630). London: Hogarth Press. (Original work published 1900)
Freud, S. (1955). Totem and taboo. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard edition
of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 13, pp. 1–162).
London: Hogarth Press. (Original work published 1913)
Freud, S. (1957a). On the history of the psychoanalytic movement. In J. Strachey (Ed.
& Trans.), The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund
Freud (Vol. 14, pp. 3–66). London: Hogarth Press. (Original work published 1914)
Freud, S. (1957b). “Wild” psycho-analysis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard
edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 11, pp.
221–227). London: Hogarth Press. (Original work published 1910)
Freud, S. (1958). Recommendations to physicians practicing psychoanalysis. In J.
Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard edition of the complete psychological works
of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 12, pp. 109–120). London: Hogarth Press. (Original work
published 1912)
Freud, S. (1961). An autobiographical study. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The
522
EISOLD
standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 20,
pp. 3–74). London: Hogarth Press. (Original work published 1925)
Freud, S., & Abraham, K. (1966). A psychoanalytic dialogue: The letters of Sigmund
Freud and Karl Abraham, 1907–1926 (H. C. Abraham & E. L. Freud, Eds.). New
York: Basic Books.
Freud, S., & Ferenczi, S. (1993). The correspondence of Sigmund Freud and Sándor
Ferenczi, Vol. 1: 1908–1914 (E. Brabant, E. Falzeder, & P. Giampieri-Deutsch,
Eds.; P. Hoffer, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Freud, S., & Jones, E. (1993). The complete correspondence of Sigmund Freud and
Ernest Jones, 1908–1939 (R. A. Paskauskas, Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Friedman, L. J. (1999). Identity’s architect: A biography of Erik H. Erikson. New
York: Scribner.
Friedman, P., & Goldstein, J. (1964). Some comments on the psychology of C. G.
Jung. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 33, 194–225.
Fromm, E. (1951). The forgotten language. New York: Reinhart.
Glover, E. (1991). Freud or Jung. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
(Original work published 1950)
Grosskurth, P. (1991). The secret ring. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Grosskurth, P. (1998). Psychoanalysis: A dysfunctional family. Journal of Analytical
Psychology, 43, 87–95.
Hamilton, V. (1996). The analyst’s preconscious. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.
Jones, E. (1948). The theory of symbolism. In Papers on psycho-analysis (pp.
87–144). London: Baillière, Tindall & Cox. (Original work published 1916)
Jones, E. (1953–1957). The life and work of Sigmund Freud (Vols. 1–3). New York:
Basic Books.
Jung, C. G. (1961). Memories, dreams, reflections (A. Jaffé, Ed.; R. Winston & C.
Winston, Trans.). New York: Random House.
Jung, C. G. (1967). Symbols of transformation. In H. Read, M. Fordham, & G. Adler
(Eds.) & R. F. C. Hull (Trans.), The collected works of C. G. Jung (Vol. 5, pp.
1–462). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published
1911–1912)
Jung, C. G. (1970). Introduction to Toni Wolff’s “Studies in Jungian Psychology.” In
H. Read, M. Fordham, & G. Adler (Eds.) & R. F. C. Hull (Trans.), The collected
works of C. G. Jung (Vol. 10, pp. 469–476). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press. (Original work published 1959)
Jung, C. G. (1972a). The stages of life. In H. Read, M. Fordham, & G. Adler (Eds.)
& R. F. C. Hull (Trans.), The collected works of C. G. Jung (Vol. 8, pp. 387–403).
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1933)
Jung, C. G. (1972b). Synchronicity: An acausal connecting principle. In H. Read, M.
Fordham, & G. Adler (Eds.) & R. F. C. Hull (Trans.), The collected works of C. G.
Jung (Vol. 8, pp. 417–519). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original
work published 1935)
Kirsch, T. B. (1995). IAAP and Jungian identity: A president’s reflections. Journal of
Analytical Psychology, 40, 235–248.
Kirsch, T. B. (1996). A brief history of analytical psychology. The Psychoanalytic
Review, 83, 569–577.
JUNG, JUNGIANS, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS
523
Kirsch, T. B. (1997). Response to John Beebe. Journal of Analytic Psychology, 42,
21–24.
Kirsch, T. B. (2000). The Jungians: A comparative and historical perspective. London:
Routledge.
Laplanche, J., & Pontalis, J. B. (1973). The language of psycho-analysis (D. Nicholson-Smith, Trans.). New York: Norton.
Lawrence, W. G. (Ed.). (1998). Social dreaming @work. London: Karnac Books.
Levinson, D. J., Darrow, C. N., Klein, E. B., Levinson, M. H., & McKee, B. (1978).
The seasons of a man’s life. New York: Knopf.
Mayer, E. L. (1996a). Changes in science and changing ideas about knowledge and
authority in psychoanalysis. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 65, 158–200.
Mayer, E. L. (1996b). Subjectivity and intersubjectivity of clinical facts. International
Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 77, 709–737.
McLynn, F. (1996). Carl Gustav Jung. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Meltzer, D. (1984). Dream-life: A re-examination of psycho-analytical theory and
technique. Perthshire, Scotland: Clunie Press.
Menzies, E. (1967). The functioning of social systems as defense against anxiety.
London: Tavistock.
Miller, E. (1989). The “Leicester” model: Experiential study of group and organisational processes (Occasional Paper No. 10). London: Tavistock.
Modell, A. H. (1997). The synergy of memory, affects, and metaphor. Journal of
Analytic Psychology, 42, 105–117.
Nelson, M. C. (1969). Contribution on parapsychology: Introduction. The Psychoanalytic Review, 56, 3–8.
Noll, R. (1995). The Jung cult: Origins of a charismatic movement. New York: Free
Press.
Noll, R. (1997). The Aryan Christ: The secret life of Carl Jung. New York: Random
House.
Paskauskas, A. A. (1988). Freud’s break with Jung. Free Associations, 11, 7–34.
Pollock, G. H., & Greenspan, S. I. (1988–1993). The course of life (Vols. 1–7).
Madison, CT: International Universities Press.
Roustang, F. (1982). Dire mastery: Discipleship from Freud to Lacan. Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Samuels, A. (1985). Jung and the post-Jungians. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Samuels, A. (1989). Fred Plaut in conversation with Andrew Samuels. Journal of
Analytical Psychology, 34, 159–183.
Samuels, A. (1994). The professionalization of Carl G. Jung’s analytical psychology
clubs. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 30, 138–147.
Samuels, A. (1995). Pluralism and psychotherapy. Australian Journal of Psychotherapy, 14, 31–44.
Samuels, A. (1996). Jung’s return from banishment. The Psychoanalytic Review, 83,
469–489.
Scott, W. C. M. (1978). Common problems concerning the views of Freud and Jung.
Journal of Analytical Psychology, 23, 303–314.
Settlage, C. F., Curtis, J., Lozoff, M., Lozoff, M., Silbertshatz, G., & Simburg, E. J.
(1988). Conceptualizing adult development. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 36, 347–369.
524
EISOLD
Shamdasani, S. (1994). Introduction: The censure of the speculative. In S. Shamdasani
& M. Munchow (Eds.), Speculations after Freud: Psychoanalysis, philosophy and
culture (pp. xi–xvii). London: Routledge.
Shamdasani, S. (1998). Cult fictions: C. G. Jung and the founding of analytical
psychology. London: Routledge.
Solomon, R. Z. (1982). [Review of the book Adult development: A new dimension of
psychoanalytic theory and practice]. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 51, 660–662.
Staude, J.-R. (1981). The adult development of C. G. Jung. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Sulloway, F. J. (1979). Freud, biologist of the mind: Beyond the psychoanalytic legend. New York: Basic Books.
Symington, N. (1986). The analytic experience: Lectures from the Tavistock. London:
Free Association Books.
Taylor, E. (1996). The new Jung scholarship. The Psychoanalytic Review, 83,
547–568.
Taylor, E. (1998). Jung before Freud, not Freud before Jung: The reception of Jung’s
work in American psychoanalytic circles between 1904 and 1909. Journal of Analytical Psychology, 43, 97–114.
Valliant, G. E. (1977). Adaptation to life. Boston: Little, Brown.
Wallerstein, R. S. (1988). One psychoanalysis or many? International Journal of
Psycho-Analysis, 69, 5–21.
Winnicott, D. W. (1964). [Review of the book Memories, dreams, reflections]. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 45, 450–455.
Winnicott, D. W. (1971). The use of an object and relating through identifications. In
Playing and reality (pp. 86–94). London: Tavistock. (Original work published
1969)
Winnicott, D. W. (1989a). D. W. W. ’s dream related to reviewing Jung. In C.
Winnicott, R. Shepard, & M. Davis (Eds.), Psycho-analytic explorations (pp.
228–230). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Original work published
1963)
Winnicott, D. W. (1989b). Individuation. In C. Winnicott, R. Shepard, & M. Davis
(Eds.), Psycho-analytic explorations (pp. 284–288). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Original work published 1970)
Young-Eisendrath, P. (1995, March/April). Struggling with Jung. Round Table Review, 4(2), 4–7.