Forthcoming: Oxford Bibliographies Online (OUP).
Entry ID: 9780195396577‐0219
http://www.oxfordbibliographies.com
SCIENTIFIC REPRESENTATION
Mauricio Suárez (Complutense University of Madrid)
Email: msuarez@filos.ucm.es
Contents:
Introduction
General Overviews
Anthologies and Edited Collections
Historical Background
Primary Sources
Secondary Sources
The Syntactic and Semantic Views
Modelling and Idealization
Analytical Inquiries into Scientific Representation
Practical Inquiries into Scientific Representation
Substantive Approaches
Isomorphism
Similarity
Critiques
Deflationary Approaches
Denotation / Stipulation
Inference
Mental Representation and Cognitive Science
Representation in Art and Science
INTRODUCTION
Scientific representation is a booming field nowadays within the philosophy
of science, with many papers published regularly on the topic every year, and
several yearly conferences and workshops on related topics. Historically the
topic originates in two different strands in 20th century philosophy of science.
One strand begins in the 1950s with philosophical interest upon the nature of
scientific theories. As the received or ‘syntactic’ view gave way to a
“semantic” or “structural” conception, representation progressively gained
the centre stage. Yet, there is another, older, strand that links representation
to fin de siècle modelling debates, particularly in the emerging ‘bildtheorie’ of
Boltzmann and Hertz, and to the ensuing discussion amongst philosophers
1
thereafter. Both strands feed into present day philosophical work on
scientific representation. There are a number of different orthogonal
questions that philosophers ask regarding representation. One may ask
about the nature of the representational relation between theories or models,
on the one hand, and the real‐world systems they purportedly represent.
Such questions lie at the more metaphysical and abstract end of the spectrum
– and are often addressed with the abstract tools of the analytical
metaphysician. They constitute what we may refer to as the “analytical
inquiry” into representation. On the other hand there are questions
regarding the use that scientists put some representations to in practice –
these are questions that are best addressed by means of some of the
philosopher of science’s favourite tools – descriptive analysis, illustration by
means of case studies, induction, exemplification, inference from practice, etc
– and are best referred to as the “practical inquiry” into representation. The
notion of representation invoked in such inquiries may be ‘deflationary’ or
‘substantive’ – depending on whether it construes representation as a
primitive notion, or as susceptible to further reduction or analysis in terms of
something else.
GENERAL OVERVIEWS
Discussion of representation amongst scientists – physicists in particular –
and philosophers alike goes back to the 19th century. Yet, explicit and
articulate reflections upon representation within philosophy of science are
much more recent, and arguably only emerge about 15 years ago. Already a
historical document, Hughes 1997 started the interest of many of us on the
topic. A number of recent book‐length treatments such as Pincock 2012 and
Winsberg 2011 provide general overviews from different angles and
philosophical persuasions – thus bearing witness to the extraordinary
fertility of the topic within recent years. There are as of today very few state
of the art papers such as Suárez 2010; but fortunately many of the recent
book length contributions start off by setting some of the required
background – see Boniolo 2007 and Van Fraassen 2008. The selection in this
section attends mainly to accessibility as an introduction and / or overview.
Boniolo, Giovanni. On Scientific Representations: From Kant to a New
Philosophy of Science. London and New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2007
A historical introduction to the topic emphasizing its sources in
semantics and epistemology from Kant onwards. It then discusses on
the nature of theories and models, thought experiments, and fictions
and possible world semantics. The historical ambition is awesome, but
the book is rather brief – so, inevitably, much detail is missing. Yet, the
tone is light, and the level is appropriate for the uninitiated.
2
Hughes, RIG. “Models and Representation.” Philosophy of Science, 64 (1997):
325‐36.
This paper inspired many subsequent contributions to the topic. A
major towering achievement by a contemporary philosopher, it not
only put scientific representation on the table, it also managed to
provide (within scarcely 10 pages) both the backbones of one of the
most fertile deflationary approaches, and the outlines of criticisms
against substantive notions of representation.
Pincock, Christopher. Mathematics and Scientific Representation, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2012.
A well argued and thought through and discussion of representation by
means of mathematical structures. It discusses some of the major
alternatives fairly and concisely, and provides a view of its own, which
tries out the unfashionable route to build a substantive theory of
representation as structural matching.
Van Fraassen, Bas. Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
By now already a classic oeuvre by one of the most accomplished
philosophers of science of our generation, and a pioneer on the topic.
Van Fraassen’s life work traces a significant route from a concern
chiefly with the structure of theories towards more pragmatic issues
regarding the use of models in scientific practice, which culminates in
this major work.
Suárez, Mauricio. “Scientific Representation.” Philosophy Compass, 5: 1
(2010): 91‐101.
One of the few state of the art papers available on the topic. It
introduces some of the distinctions employed in this bibliography –
such as analytical vs. practical inquiries, and substantive vs.
deflationary conceptions –, and can serve as a helpful complement to
the present document.
Winsberg, Eric. Science in the Age of Computer Simulation. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2011.
This is a concise and readable account of simulation, idealization and
fiction in scientific representation. It raises many significant issues in
3
the area and provides a roughly instrumentalist answer to several key
questions concerning the use of idealizations and fictions in
representation.
ANTHOLOGIES AND EDITED COLLECTIONS
As mentioned, representation is a growing and expanding field. The six
volumes listed here in one way or another resulted from some of the most
important events – conferences and workshops – that have taken place in
recent years, and display some of the intense levels of activity and excitement
that nowadays surrounds this topic. Díez and Frigg 2006 is a pioneering
collection edited by a team of two young European philosophers with
credentials on structuralism and models. Gelfert 2011 contains essays
devoted to a practical inquiry into representation. Humphreys and Imbert
2012, and Vorms and Pincock 2013, arise out of the series of conferences on
Models and Simulations that have been taking place annually over the last 6
or so years. Lynch and Woolgar 1990 is a sociological approach to the topic.
Morrison and Morgan 1999 is well‐known for launching the ‘mediating
models’ movement.
Díez, José, and Roman Frigg, eds. “Scientific Representation.” Theoria (special
issue), 21: 1 (2006): 5‐85.
It includes papers by Andreas Bartels (defending homomorphism as an
account of representation); Andoni Ibarra and Thomas Mormann
(defending an ‘interventionist’ approach to representation); Mauricio
Suárez and Albert Solé (defending the plurality of deflationary
approaches); Roman Frigg (criticizing the semantic conception); and
Craig Callender and Jonathan Cohen (defending a Gricean account of
representation as stipulation).
Gelfert, Axel, ed. “Model‐Based Representation in Scientific Practice.” Studies
in History and Philosophy of Science (special issue), 42, 2 (2011): 251‐398.
It includes essays by Tarja Knuuttila (discussing an artefactual
approach to model‐based representation); Axel Gelfert (on the
inferential uses of mathematical representation), Marion Vorms (on the
format of imaginary models in scientific practice), Demetris Portides
(on phenomenological model‐building) and Margaret Morrison (on the
underdetermination of models).
Humphreys, Paul, and Ciryl Imbert. Models, Simulations, and
Representations. London: Routledge, 2012.
4
It contains a range of different essays by senior and younger scholars
alike with a focus on the relation between simulation and
representation in general, and provides a good entry point into the
subject.
Lynch, Michael, and Steven Woolgar, eds. Representation in Scientific
Practice. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990.
This is a well‐known collection in the sociology of science edited by two
prominent scholars on techniques of representation across the
sciences. It contains some fine sociological discussions of
representational practices in diverse fields such as physics, the life
sciences, socio‐biology, physiology and cognitive science.
Morrison, Margaret, and Mary Morgan, eds. Models as Mediators:
Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1999.
This volume collects essays resulting from a pioneering research
project at the London School of Economics, Amsterdam’s Tinbergen
Institute, and Berlin’s Wissenschaftkolleg in the mid 1990s. The project,
and ensuing volume established the so‐called “mediating models”
movement, according to which models are autonomous and
independent of both theory and data.
Vorms, Marion, and Christopher Pincock, eds. “Models and Simulations 4”.
Synthese (special issue), 2013.
It contains essays engaged in a practical inquiry into representation and
simulation. Three essays in particular explicitly address scientific
representation, namely those by: Agnes Bolinska (a critique of the
inferential conception), Gordon Purves (a critique of Winsberg’s
account of fictional representation); and Peter Gildenhuys (on
representational practices in classical population genetics).
HISTORICAL BACKGROUND
One of the main strands of philosophical work that feeds into contemporary
discussions is the long modelling tradition in science – as well as
philosophical commentary and reflection upon this tradition. Three key
primary sources are Boltzmann 1902, Maxwell, 1990 (1856), and Hertz 1956
(1894). They are followed by a selection of a few amongst many
philosophical discussions and reactions that they have prompted.
5
Primary Sources
Ludwig Boltzmann, James Clerk Maxwell and Heinrich Hertz stand as some of
the towering thinkers that started a tradition of philosophically minded
physical science, where modelling and representation play a main role. More
specifically Maxwell initiated a novel way to carry out modelling as analogical
reasoning, Hertz gave a full development of the theory of representations
characteristic of the neo‐Kantian German speaking modelling tradition, and
Boltzmann attempted an imaginative rebranding of both in the form of a
radical Viennese tradition. Together they helped put modelling centre stage.
Boltzmann, Ludwig. “Models”. Encyclopedia Britannica 10th Edition (1902):
788 – 791.
This is a classic text on models as representations by one of the most
imaginative and reflective physicists of the late 19th century. It
discusses both the nature of models as images of the world, and the role
that models play in the development of mathematical physics.
Maxwell, James Clerk. “Analogies in Nature: Essay for the Apostles”.
Reprinted in Harman, Peter, ed. The Scientific Letters and Papers of James
Clerk Maxwell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1990): 376‐383.
Maxwellian electrodynamics is at the heart of the methodological
revolution in late 19th century physics that brought about the new
modelling tradition. This is Maxwell’s most philosophical essay where
he discusses some debts and implications of his modelling attitude.
Originally published in 1856.
Hertz, Hermann. The Principles of Mechanics Presented in a New Form. New
York: Dover Publications, 1956.
This is the translation into English of what is probably the most
important work in the development of the bildtheorie, or theory of
representations – the view that came to dominate the philosophical
language and landscape amongst German‐speaking scholars in the early
20th century. Originally published in 1894, it contains some perspicuous
discussions of the role and nature of scientific representation, and
remains unsurpassed in its clarity and depth.
Secondary Sources
6
Bailer‐Jones 2009 reviews the history of philosophical reflection upon
models; Hunt 1991 recounts the history of modelling in the 19th century; De
Regt 2005 links the 19th century Bildtheorie to current concerns regarding
explanation; and Nersessian 2008 is a study of the cognitive structures
underlying Maxwell’s work.
Bailer‐Jones, Daniela. Scientific Models in Philosophy of Science. Pittsburgh:
University of Pittsburgh Press, 2009.
This book is a comprehensive historical account of philosophical
interest on models and representation, and it will attract anyone with
an interest in the history of the philosophy of science. It discusses 19th
century science views on analogy, Pierre Duhem’s disparaging reaction,
the logical empiricist confinement of models to heuristics, and the
1960’s British reaction in favour of models, as well as more recent
debates.
De Regt, Henk. “Ludwig Boltzmann’s ‘Bildtheorie’ and Scientific
Understanding”. Synthese, 119 (2005): 113‐134.
This paper brings Boltzmann’s version of the bildtheorie to bear on
current debates regarding the nature of explanation and, in particular,
the explanatory force of representation. Highly recommended for those
looking for a historical introduction to the topic – and a good example
of contemporary iH&PS (integrated History and Philosophy of
Science)—style work at its best.
Hunt, Bruce J. The Maxwellians. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press,
1991.
A comprehensive account of the birth of the modelling attitude in
Victorian 19th century physics. It discusses the models and modelling
techniques of Maxwell, Thomson, Lodge, Heaviside and Fitzgerald in
detail, and provides invaluable historical background to the origin of
philosophical reflection upon the techniques of representation that
developed in the British Isles.
Nersessian, Nancy. Creating Scientific Concepts. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press,
2008.
A study of the cognitive practices underlying James Clerk Maxwell’s
development of his vortex models of the ether. It interprets Maxwell’s
modelling methodology in terms of model‐based reasoning, and
provides an elegant account of how representational practices may
serve to generate new concepts.
7
THE SYNTATIC AND SEMANTIC VIEWS
One of the main strands that feeds into contemporary debates on the nature
of representation concerns the nature of scientific theory, and is a direct
descendant of attempts – in the logical empiricist tradition of Hempel, Carnap
and others –, to develop an account of the confirmation and explanatory
power of scientific theories. Representation comes to the fore in the 1980’s
when a semantic conception of theories comes to replace the language‐based,
or syntactic, conception of the logical empiricists. Suppe 1977 recounts the
history of the received or syntactic view, and the reasons that led many to
abandon it; Giere 1988 defends a model‐based version of the semantic
conception; Suppes 2002 promotes a roughly structural version; and Van
Fraasseen 1980 outlines a phase space version.
Giere, Ronald N. Explaining Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1988.
A classic text introducing a cognitive science‐based version of the
semantic view. Chapter 3 in particular is the source of a widespread
division, within the semantic conception, between a theoretical
‘definition’ and a theoretical ‘hypothesis’. Note that Giere’s version of
the semantic view does not require a structural or model‐theoretic
understanding of models.
Suppes, Patrick. Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures. CSLI
Publications. Leland Stanford Junior University, 2002.
A classic and very influential text by one of the major figures in
analytical philosophy of science in the second half of the 20th century.
The original text goes back to the early 1970’s, and is reprinted here
virtually unchanged. It provides a thorough defence of the applicability
of mathematical methods to data and measurement structures, and
advances the structural version of the semantic conception of theories.
Suppe, Frederik. The Structure of Scientific Theories. Illinois and Chicago:
University of Illinois Press, 1977.
The is a celebrated collection containing several essays on the nature of
theory, at a time when the so‐called ‘received’ or syntactic view was
opening the way to the new semantic view. Philosophers who, in the
tradition of logical empiricism, pursue questions regarding the nature
8
of scientific theories are thus enabled to adopt representation as the
key notion in the relation of theories to the world.
Van Fraassen, Bas. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1980.
Another classic text in the epistemology of science, defending both a
semantic conception of theories – in Van Fraassen’s preferred phase
space version – and a form of anti‐realism regarding the hypothetical
unobservable entities postulated in such theories.
MODELLING AND IDEALIZATION
The other strand that feeds into contemporary debates on representation is
the large and very intense philosophical literature of the last 20 or so years
on modelling and idealization. The texts below constitute just a very small
selection within that large body of literature dealing with scientific
modelling. Cartwright 1983 and Galison 1997 are some key advanced
research references. Hartmann and Frigg 2006 is an accessible introduction.
Jones and Cartwright 2005 and Magnani et al. 1999 are collections of papers
on idealization and representation with varying degrees of difficulty.
Weisberg 2007 is an example of recent ground breaking research in the area.
Woods 2010 is unusual in its focus on fiction within science and literature,
and may provide a good point of entry for those in aesthetics, literary theory
and criticism, and other areas of philosophy outside the philosophy of
science.
Cartwright, Nancy. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1983.
Cartwright’s first book defends realism for phenomenological laws, and
antirealism regarding explanatory theory. Its simulacrum account of
explanation is particularly well known, as is the view that explanatory
or covering law power is often inversely related to descriptive accuracy.
Galison, Peter. Image and Logic. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1997.
It details the development of theoretical practices as major
representational tools in 20th century particle physics. Galison’s work
was key in setting the view that theory involves its own practice – thus
inviting the view that representation in general is also a practice.
9
Hartmann, Stephan, and Roman Frigg. “Models in Science”. Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2006.
A concise and clear introduction to the general topic of models and
representation, separating the main issues in 3 distinct areas
(semantics, ontology and epistemology), and reviewing some of the
most general philosophical implications.
Jones, Martin, and Nancy Cartwright, eds. Correcting the Model: Idealisation
and Abstraction in the Sciences. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the
Sciences and Humanities, 68. New York: Rodopi, 2005.
This collection of essays chiefly deals with the distinction between
abstraction and idealization, and other concomitant notions. The
distinction is key to the idea that representation in science involves
either fiction or misrepresentation of one or another sort.
Magnani, Lorenzo, et al. (eds.), Model‐Based Reasoning in Scientific
Discovery. Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1999.
This is one of the first volumes to have appeared in the series collecting
the proceedings of the conferences that Lorenzo Magnani and
collaborators have put together in Pavia, Italy, on topics closely related
to scientific representation. The book contains some key papers by
Giere, Hartmann, Bailer‐Jones, etc., on the ways in which models
represent their intended targets.
Weisberg, Michael. “Who is a Modeler?”. British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science, 58: 2 (2007): 207‐233.
A defence of a model‐based strategy in science as a form of indirect
representation of systems of interest, suitably emphasising both the
provisional and idealized character of models, and their capacity to
instruct and inform regarding observed phenomena.
Wood, John, ed. Fictions and Models: New Essays. Munich: Philosophia
Verlag, 2010.
A recent collection of essays on the topic of fictional representation in
science and elsewhere, which includes interesting analogies between
the modes of representation in science and those in mathematics, art
and literature. The emphasis is on the fictional character of many
scientific representations, and how this may or not be consistent with a
realist attitude to representation in general.
10
ANALYTICAL INQUIRIES INTO SCIENTIFIC REPRESENTATION
Inquiries into the nature of representation are not new, they have a long
history that takes them back at least to the 19th century. There is an
analytical type of inquiry that asks questions regarding the necessary and
sufficient conditions on the concept of representation. In other words it aims
to define the concept. Typically representation is here understood to be a
relation between what we may call sources and targets – where the sources
are the vehicles (i.e. models) and the targets are the intended objects of the
representation. More complex analytical inquiries do not suppose the
relations are necessarily dyadic, but they do assume representation can be
defined analytically. Peirce 1931 contains some pioneering reflections on
scientific representation, which opened up the field of semiotics. He founded
both the analytical and the practical inquiry into representation. Bolinska
2013 and Rusanen and Lappi 2012 exemplify recent attempts to provide
necessary and sufficient conditions on representation as the conveyor of
information – they will appeal to anyone with an interest on the role of
information. Frigg 2010 and Toon 2012 deal with fictional representation –
and will interest those with literary and artistic backgrounds. Swoyer 1991 is
a foundational text that should interest everyone, even though it is hardly
introductory.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. Collected Papers, Volume 2: Elements of Logic.
Edited by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard
University Press, 1931.
Peirce is the originator of the field of semiotics, or the science of signs.
He distinguished three kinds of signs and developed a complex and
influential view, according to which representation is not dyadic, but
triadic; it involves not only a source and a target, but also an
interpretation of the source that allows it to stand for the target.
Bolinska, Agnes. “Epistemic Representation, Informativeness and the Aim of
Faithful Representatioin”, Synthese 190: 2 (2013): 219‐234.
This paper by a young and promising scholar addresses directly the
notion of information that appears as part of the inferential conception
of representation (see below: *Deflationary approaches*). It argues for
a completion of the inferential conception in terms of necessary and
sufficient conditions deriving from information.
Rusanen, Anna‐Mari, and Otto Lappi. “An Information Semantic Account of
Scientific Models”. In De Regt, Henk, Stephan Hartmann and Samir Okasha,
11
eds. EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. Dordrecht: Springer
(2012): 315‐327.
It goes beyond extant accounts in providing a complementary
information‐based view. Again, very much in the spirit of the analytic
inquiry, searching for a complete set of conditions that define the
abstract concept of representation, yet sensitive to issues of practical
applications too.
Frigg, Roman. “Models and Fiction”, Synthese, 172, 2 (2010): 251‐268.
One of the earliest attempts to apply the full machinery of Walton’s
pretence theory of fictions to scientific modelling. It proposes a two‐
tiered account of representation by models.
Toon, Adam. Models as Made‐Believe: Imagination, Fiction and Scientific
Representation. Palgrave Macmillan, 2012.
Another impressive attempt by a young scholar to apply Walton’s
theory of fictions to scientific representation, thus providing a set of
supposedly necessarily and sufficient conditions on the representation
of systems by model sources.
Swoyer, Christopher. “Structural Representation and Surrogative Reasoning”.
Synthese, 87 (1991): 449 – 508.
One of the first papers to pay attention to the essential role of
representation in reasoning and inference in scientific contexts. The
paper attempts to ground such activities upon a roughly structural
account, although it presciently announces that no particular type of
morphism, or structural mapping, will do for representation.
PRACTICAL INQUIRIES INTO SCIENTIFIC REPRESENTATION
A practical inquiry into representation will raise questions regarding the
typical means that representations take in practice, without worrying too
much as to whether these typical means may be part of the definition of the
concept. Thus philosophers, historians and sociologists of science who are
involved in a practical inquiry will describe modelling practice and attempt
to understand the types of properties of representations that play an active
role in the way that scientists use them. Practical and analytical inquiries are
not always exclusive, but can be complimentary, and Peirce’s original theory
of signs also has an origin in his practical work as a scientist in charge of
geodetic surveys in the East coast during the 1870s and 1880s. Hughes 2010
is a book‐length treatment of modelling from the perspective of a practical
inquiry. Suárez 2009 is a selection of papers on fictional representation – all
12
oriented towards a practical inquiry. Graham Kennedy 2012, Knuuttila 2009,
Perini 2010, and Peschard 2011 are all very good examples of recent
practical inquiries – and, incidentally, all written by women.
Graham Kennedy, Ashley. “A Non‐Representationalist View of Model
Explanation”. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 43: 2 (2012): 233‐
240.
It describes some modelling practices in astrophysics, and aims to
establish on this ground that explanation does not require
representation. However, it defines representation narrowly in a
substantive sense, so a reinterpretation of the work is invited that
furnishes a description of some representational means in practice.
Hughes, RIG. The Theoretical Practices of Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2010.
A very thorough and charismatic treatment of representational
practices and means in a variety of historical episodes in theoretical
physics, from Galileo to the Ising model. The textual analysis approach
lends it a refreshingly novel outlook. Hughes was one of the key original
thinkers on this topic, and this book summarizes his work in this area
over the years.
Knuuttila, Tarja. “Some Consequences of the Pragmatist Approach to
Representation: Decoupling the Model‐Target Dyad and Indirect Reasoning.”
In M. Suárez, M. Dorato and M. Rédei, eds. EPSA Epistemology and
Methodology: Launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association.
Dordrecht: Springer, 2009: 139‐148.
An analysis of both recent pragmatist approaches to representation and
indirect reasoning accounts. It nicely signals a shift from the analytical
to the practical inquiry into representation, and argues for it on
philosophical as well as practical grounds.
Perini, Laura. “Scientific Representation and the Semiotics of Pictures”. In
Magnus, P.D. and Jacop Busch, eds. New Waves in Philosophy of Science.
London: Palgrave Macmillan (2010): 131‐154.
This paper argues by means of a number of detailed case studies that
some commonplace assumptions about visual representation in science
are mistaken. In particular it shows that visual representations may
convey truths; and that a visual representation need not hold any
relevant similarity or resemblance to its target. Perini argues
13
convincingly for a semiotic understanding of visual representations as
complex signs in symbol systems á la Goodman.
Peschard, Isabelle. “Making Sense of Modeling: Beyond Representation”.
European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1: 3 (2011): 335 ‐352.
A research paper that, on the basis of some interesting contemporary
models in fluid dynamics, urges philosophers to overcome the notion of
representation in philosophy of science. It does so by focusing on
representation as an activity and not as a relation (or at any rate not a
relation between our concepts and the external world).
Suárez, Mauricio, ed. Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling
and Idealization. London: Routledge, 2009.
It contains nine papers on the practical ways in which scientists employ
fictional and idealizing assumptions as part of their representations.
Arthur Fine’s seminal article “Fictionalism” (1993) is reprinted, and
appears alongside others that were first delivered at a conference in
Madrid in February 2006, and are now pioneering contributions to the
growing literature on fictional representation in the sciences (see Frigg
2010 and Toon 2012 cited under *Analytical Inquiries into
Representation* above).
SUBSTANTIVE APPROACHES
A substantive approach to representation will try to reduce it to some other
notion, or to otherwise define it away in terms of necessary and sufficient
conditions. Substantive accounts have tended to come in two varieties:
structural isomorphism, or similarity.
Isomorphism
Amongst the former: Bueno et al. 2002 and French 2003 defend partial
isomorphism; Mundy 1986 and Suppes 2002 (cited under *The Syntatic and
Semantic Views*) propose homomorphism; while Van Fraassen 1987
suggests embedding (i.e. isomorphism to a substructure).
Bueno, Otavio, Steven French and James Ladyman. “On Representing the
Relationship between the Mathematical and the Empirical”. Philosophy of
Science, 69: 3 (2002): 452 – 473.
14
It discusses some of the objections to the partial isomorphism approach
to representation, and argues for an extension to what the authors refer
to as “partial homomorphism”.
French, Steven. “A Model‐Theoretic Account of Representation (or, I Don’t
Know Much About Art … but I Know it Involves Isomorphism).” Philosophy of
Science, 70: 5 (2003): 1472‐1483.
It argues against Suárez 2003 (cited under *Critiques*) and Hughes
1997 (cited under *Denotation / Stipulation*) that isomorphism may be
both necessary and sufficient for representation. It also argues that this
may be the case throughout the board – i.e. both in science and in the
arts.
Mundy, Brent. “On the General Theory of Meaningful Representation”.
Synthese, 67 (1986): 391 ‐ 437.
An early attempt to understand representation as isomorphism in the
physical sciences, particularly in relation to spacetime theories. The
claim is often made in this context that diffeomorphism invariance is
akin to theoretical equivalence, which prima facie lends credence to the
representation‐as‐isomorphism view.
Van Fraassen, Bas. “The Semantic Approach to Scientific Theories.” In Nancy
Nersessian, ed. The Process of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer (1987): 105‐124.
Here Van Fraassen comes tantalizingly close to explicitly endorsing a
structural conception of representation, roughly as follows: a theory
represents a phenomenon if it contains structures with substructures
isomorphic to the phenomena. Van Fraassen has refined his views in
later works, explicitly embracing a deflationary notion instead.
Similarity
Amongst defenders of similarity, Aronson et al. 1995, and Giere 2004, are
early proponents; Godfrey‐Smith 2006, and Weisberg 2012 are more
sophisticated developments.
Aronson, Jerry, Eileen Way, and Rom Harré. Realism Rescued. London:
Duckworth, 1995.
Rom Harré is one of the pioneers of philosophical interest on modelling,
as a member of a prominent group of mainly British philosophers
working in the late 1960’s and early 1970s on the topic, which included
15
also Richard Braithwaite, Max Black, and Mary Hesse. The book
advances the view that targets and sources of representations are
similar, and builds an ontological hierarchy on these grounds.
Giere, Ronald. “How Models are Used to Represent Reality”, Philosophy of
Science 71: 5 (2004): 742‐752.
Ron Giere has long been a champion of similarity, and in this paper he
expands on his early views by turning representation into a 4‐place
relation, with perceived similarity playing a key role. He then explores
the ways in which representation is an effective modelling strategy.
Godfrey‐Smith, Peter. “The Strategy of Model‐Based Science.” Biology and
Philosophy, 21 (2006): 725‐740.
It brings together a number of relevant issues, such as fictions and
representation, and shows how they play a role in model‐based science.
It also offers a brief but clear defence of the role of similarity in
scientific representation, which takes from Giere’s earlier work and
leads to some subsequent work by some of Godfrey‐Smith’s students.
Weisberg, Michael. Getting Serious about Similarity. Philosophy of Science,
79: 5 (2012): 785‐794.
The basic problem with similarity as an account of representation is
that it just seems to have the wrong logical properties to analyse
representation. Similarity appears prima facie to be a symmetrical and
reflexive relation, while representation patently is neither. In this paper
Weisberg shows how to apply the insights into similarity judgements
developed by empirical psychologists.
Critiques
Defenders of similarity and isomorphism tend to argue for the universality
and necessity of either for representation. Critics (Frigg 2006; Suárez, 2003)
point out that the putatively reducing notions lack some fundamental logical
properties of representation, so they can hardly constitute the reductive
basis. Others (Downes 1992; Toon 2012) point to the manifest diversity of
representational means. Van Fraassen is a remarkable critique of
isomorphism as substantive account of representation on epistemic grounds.
Downes, Steven. “The Importance of Models in Scientific Theorizing: A
Deflationary Semantic Approach.” In D. Hull, M. Forbes and K. Okruhlik, eds.
Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1 (1992): 142‐153.
16
This is an early and pioneering defence of deflationism. Although it
frames the issue within the semantic conception, it presciently
anticipates some of the subsequent moves against substantive accounts
of representation.
Frigg, Roman. “Scientific Representation and the Semantic View of Theories.”
Theoria, 55 (2006): 49‐65.
Not all defenders of the semantic conception have considered the issue
of application, and not all have, in so doing, defended a structural
version of the view. However, this paper argues convincingly that the
semantic conception of the application of theories lends itself naturally
to a structural conception of representation as isomorphism – and
proceeds to criticize it for doing so.
Suárez, Mauricio. “Scientific Representation: Against Similarity and
Isomorphism.” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17: 3
(2003): 225‐244.
It proposes five different arguments against similarity and
isomorphism, and concludes that representation cannot be naturalised
by reducing it to any relational dyadic version of either. It ends by
suggesting non‐relational versions of these views, and indeed several
philosophers reacted by developing more sophisticated accounts of
their views in response.
Toon, Adam. “Similarity and Scientific Representation”. International Studies
in the Philosophy of Science, 26 (2012): 241‐257.
This is an example of a recent paper in the contemporary critical trend
against substantive theories. It takes extant criticisms of similarity
further, by arguing against some sophisticated developments of the
similarity view, such as Giere’s (2004).
Van Fraassen, Bas. “Representation: The Problem for Structuralism.”
Philosophy of Science, 73 (2006): 536 ‐547.
This is a curious paper in that it raises arguments against what appear
to many to be Van Fraassen’s earlier views – i.e. against a purely
structural conception of representation. The paper culminated with the
very explicit endorsement of an intentional and pragmatist conception
in Van Fraassen 2008 (*General Overviews*).
17
DEFLATIONARY APPROACHES
In contrast to substantive approaches, deflationary views typically assume
that representation lacks necessary and sufficient conditions. Deflationists
typically will defend that representation cannot be reduced to any property,
relation, or set of properties or relations, of the objects that play the role of
representational source and target. They propose instead to focus
philosophical attention upon the features of the use of representations by
agents in their particular contexts, attempting to generalize such uses
whenever possible. In the recent literature there have been roughly two
types of deflationary approaches.
Denotation / Stipulation
One set of views links representation to acts of stipulation by agents that fix
the denotation of the signs employed. Callender and Cohen (2006) emphasise
the role of the act of stipulation itself; while Goodman 1968, Hughes 1997,
and Elgin 2009 chose to emphasise the denotation relation – and the target of
the referential relation thus established. On chronological grounds Goodman
1968 is the obvious entry point, but nothing beats Hughes 1997 for clarity
and concision.
Callender, Craig, and Jonathan Cohen. “There is no Special Problem About
Scientific Representation”, Theoria, 21: 55 (2006): 67‐85.
Callender and Cohen argue that scientific representation is merely
another instance of (non‐natural, i.e. conventional) representation in
general, so there is no special problem concerning specifically scientific
representation. They show that a Gricean conception sheds light on a
number of conundrums raised by scientific representation.
Elgin, Catherine. “Exemplification, Idealization, and Understanding.” In M.
Suárez, ed. Fictions in Science: Essays on Modelling and Idealization, London:
Routledge (2009): 77‐90.
This paper provides an extension of Nelson Goodman’s account in
terms of denotative function. It confronts the issue of the
representation of fictive or non‐existent entities, such as unicorns. It
argues that denotative function is not a success term so a sign or source
with denotative function (a painting of a unicorn) need not denote
anything in the actual world.
18
Goodman, Nelson. Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols.
Indianapolis: The Bobbs‐Merrill Company, 1968.
This is the classic statement of the denotation theory. It first raises
some criticisms against resemblance or similarity theories, and then
goes on to articulate the view that representation is essentially the
denotation of an object by a symbol in a complex sign system.
Hughes, RIG. “Models and Representation.” Philosophy of Science, 64 (1997):
325‐36.
This paper has already been mentioned as a classic in this area. It
merits another mention specifically as a defence of a sophisticated
version of Goodman’s theory. More particularly, Hughes develops what
he calls the Denotation‐Demonstration‐Interpretation (DDI) account on
which representation is typically (although not necessarily)
characterised by these three separate components in a model.
Inference
The other set of deflationary views focus on the inferential uses of
representations. Suárez 2004 is an early statement of the inferential
conception, which led Contessa 2007 to develop his own ‘interpretational’
variant. Bueno and Colyvan 2011 and Newman 2012 are recent attempts to
further apply the inferential conception to specifically mathematical
representation and explanation, respectively. Zamora and De Donato 2012
attempt to provide the inferential conception with foundations in Robert
Brandom’s philosophy of language.
Bueno, Otavio, and Mark Colyvan. “An Inferential Conception of the
Application of Mathematics.” Nous, 45: 2 (2011): 345‐374.
The authors claim to be developing an inferential account of the sorts of
scientific representations afforded by mathematical structures.
Although they explicitly oppose a substantive conception of
representation – a view they refer to as “the matching account” –, they
also attempt to show that the inferential capacities of models ride upon
structural relations.
Contessa, Gabriele. “Scientific Representation. Interpretation and Surrogative
Reasoning.” Philosophy of Science 74 (2007): 48‐68.
The explicit aim of the paper is to further develop extant ‘distinctions
between denotation, epistemic representation and faithful epistemic
representation’. Using the inferential conception as foil, it develops out
19
of it a substantive account of representation as interpreted surrogative
reasoning.
Newman, Mark. “An Inferential Model of Scientific Understanding.”
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26: 1 (2012): 1‐26.
Another exponent of what we may call the San Diego representation
school (together with Callender and Cohen 2006, cited under
*Denotation / Stipulation*), this paper further applies insights from an
inferential view on representation – and convincingly argues for a
distinction between understanding and explanation on these inferential
grounds.
Suárez, Mauricio. “An Inferential Conception of Scientific Representation.”
Philosophy of Science, 71:5 (2004): 767‐779.
It provides a first outline of an inferential conception of representation
and it introduces a distinction between the force and the inferential
capacity of a representation, which, it argues, drives the dynamics of the
model building. Its main virtue, however, may have been to provide
critical foil for the development of other inferential views and
approaches, including those listed in this section.
Zamora‐Bonilla, Jesús, and Xavier De Donato. “Explanation and Modelization
in a Comprehensive Inferential Account.” In De Regt, Henk, Stephan
Hartmann, and Samir Okasha, eds. EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam
2009. Dordrecht: Springer (2012): 33‐42.
The paper claims that the inferential character of scientific
representations (models) may be captured in terms of Robert
Brandom’s semantic inferentialism. It then attempts to display the
analogues of Brandom’s entitlements and commitments at work in the
development of scientific models.
MENTAL REPRESENTATION AND COGNITIVE SCIENCE
There is a large and thriving literature on representation within the
philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Philosophers of science often
approach these views in order to find inspiration and help, even though the
commitment to representation as a mental state that is typical in the
philosophy of mind has, on the whole, being eschewed. Yet, some of the
debates in the philosophy of science replicate old debates in these areas. For
instance, Cummings 1997 develops the analogue for mental representation of
20
the substantive view of scientific representation as isomorphism. He
essentially claims that mental representation is structural. His views have
been criticised on grounds similar to those employed by critics of the
isomorphism view in the philosophy of science. In particular, Millikan 2000
develops a rather convincing response. A recent account that takes
inspiration from the structural isomorphism view, but stops short of
attempting a reduction is Shagrir 2012. Within philosophy of science proper,
Ronald Giere has long defended the application of cognitive science to
scientific representation: Chapter 5 in Giere 2006 is an accessible and up to
date introduction.
Cummings, Robert. Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, 1997.
The usual reference for structural conceptions of mental
representation, this is an advanced book in philosophy of mind by a
technically gifted and proficient scholar.
Millikan, Ruth. “Review of Cummings’ “Representations, Targets and
Attitudes.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60 (2000): 103‐113.
This essay review raises a number of objections to the structural
conception of mental representation defended by Cummings. Although
it provides an elegant summary of the object of its critique, and
constitutes a good entry point for the uninitiated, the interested reader
is advised to consult some of the larger and more complete works on
the topic, including the original source of the critique mentioned above.
Giere, Ronald. Scientific Perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2006.
This is the last published book by a very prominent philosopher of
science, which continues his defence of cognitive science as a tool for
understanding scientific modelling in general. Chapter 5, in particular,
develops a distributed cognition approach to modelling.
Shagrir, Oron. “Structural Representations and the Brain”. British Journal for
the Philosophy of Science. 63: 3 (2012): 519‐545.
An example of how the cognitive science literature is nowadays leaning
towards a consideration of neurobiology and neurology in an attempt
to better understand mental representation. It sensibly falls short of
reducing mental representation to any structural mappings.
21
REPRESENTATION IN ART AND SCIENCE
Philosophers of science have been learning a fair amount from their
colleagues over in aesthetics and the philosophy of art in recent years. Indeed
the analogies between scientific and artistic modes of representation have
regularly turned into fertile ground for understanding scientific modelling
better.
Representation in Aesthetics
One of the classic texts in the philosophy of art has already been mentioned
(Nelson Goodman’s 1968, cited under *Denotation / Stipulation*), and it has
been made clear that its defence of a theory of representation as denotation
has had a considerable impact upon present day discussions on scientific
representation. There are other texts in the philosophy of art that have
exerted influence, and several have become current objects of discussion
amongst philosophers of science concerned with representation. A brief
selection is listed in the first section including: Gombrich 1960, which first
proposes the substitution account and pretty much sets the field; Kulvicki
2006 which interestingly further develops the Goodman approach; Lopes
1996 which contains all the Goodman‐inspired criticisms of resemblance
theories; and Wollheim 1987 which is the most ambitious philosophical
attempt to date to grapple with the notion of representation in the arts.
Gombrich, Ernst. Art and Illusion. London: Phaidon Press Limited, 1960.
Enormously influential, it defends a ‘substitution’ account of
representation, best exemplified in the often cited and much discussed
example of a hobbyhorse. The substitution view fits in well with current
emphasis amongst philosophers of science on the autonomous nature
of models.
Kulvicki, John. “Pictorial Representation”, Philosophy Compass 1: 6 (2006):
535‐546. Blackwell Publishing.
A state of the art paper that moreover argues originally for a version of
Goodman’s symbolic system view of representation as denotation by a
complex sign. It offers a balanced review, providing an excellent entry
point into the field.
Lopes, Dominic. Understanding Pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1996.
22
An elegant and comprehensive review of the main positions regarding
representation in the philosophy of art. It develops a sustained criticism
of resemblance theories of artistic representation, which philosophers
of science have gone on to apply to scientific representation. It provides
an excellent follow up to Kulvicki 2006 as a thorough and complete
introduction.
Wollheim, Richard. Painting as an Art. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1987.
The book is a classic in the field, by one of its most eminent and
distinguished scholars. Wolheim criticises extant views with delicate
touch, and goes on to propose a notion of his own, namely “seeing‐in”,
which appeals to some fundamental and primitive psychological
dispositions. A challenging but enormously rewarding book.
Scientific and Artistic Representation
The last section lists some key works explicitly dealing with the analogy
between scientific and artistic representation: Suárez 1999 puts Wollheim’s
insights to work in an study of the analogy between artistic and scientific
representation; Downes 2009 applies critical lessons from Lopes against
isomorphism views; Debs and Redhead 2007 develop a conventionalist
account; Frigg and Hunter 2010 is a collection of essays that displays well the
considerable recent interest on the art – science analogy.
Debs, Talal A., and Michael Redhead. Objectivity, Invariance and Convention:
Symmetry in Physical Science. Chapter 1. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 2007.
Debs and Redhead develop a conventionalist account of representation
in science, and distinguish objectivity from structural invariance, or
symmetry, to which it often is linked. They instead emphasise the need
to select conventional features for any representation, which they very
originally illustrate by means of examples from the performance arts.
Downes, Steven. “Models, Pictures, and Unified Accounts of Representation:
Lessons from Aesthetics for Philosophy of Science.” Perspectives on Science,
17, 4 (2009): 417‐428.
Downes applies the lessons from aesthetics to scientific representation
in a straightforward and convincing manner. He shows that analogues
of Goodman’s and Lopes’ arguments against resemblance have bite
against substantive conceptions of representation too.
23
Frigg, Roman, and Matthew Hunter, eds. Beyond Mimesis and Convention:
Representation in Art and Science. Dordrecht: Springer, 2010.
This book collects some of the papers arising out of a conference on
representation in art and science that took place in London in 2006. It
contains some papers on fictional representation, models and parables,
illocutionary representational speech acts, functional versus
informative conceptions of representation, and other relevant topics at
the interface of the philosophies of science and art.
Suárez, Mauricio. “Theories, Models, and Representations.” In Magnani,
Lorenzo, et al., eds. Model‐Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery. Kluwer
Academic Publishers (1999): 75‐84.
An early attempt to suggest a fruitful analogy between scientific and
artistic representation. It introduces a distinction between
representational and non‐representational uses of theories, and
illustrates it by means of three paintings (by Velázquez, Picasso and
Mondrian) that have thereafter often been discussed in relation with
this analogy.
24