Consciousness: A Bio-philosophical
Investigation
A philosophical and neurophysiological investigation.
Being a study of the neurophysiology and evolution of consciousness
through the Animal Kingdom, with special consideration applied to human
consciousness.
John Dale
Consciousness: A Bio-philosophical Investigation
© Copyright 2012 John Dale
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval
system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical,
photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the written prior permission of the author.
All images have come from the public domain.
ISBN -13: 978-1470124540
BY THE SAME AUTHOR
Snowshoes & Stethoscopes 1995
Notes from a Sidecar 2005
CONTENTS
Introduction
iv
Chapter I
The Beginnings
1
Chapter II
From primitive creatures to creatures with neural systems
8
Chapter III
The Development of Intelligence in Animals: initial examination
20
Chapter IV
Language in Animals
29
Chapter V
Emotions in Animals
35
Chapter VI
Pain in Animals
43
Chapter VII
Some embryology and the development of the human brain
48
i
Chapter VIII
Division and Function of the parts of the Brain
58
Chapter IX
Definitions of Levels of Consciousness and a discussion on Locked-in
Syndrome and preliminary philosophical discussion
70
Chapter X
Varieties of consciousness, neurological disorders that shed light on a
theory of consciousness
80
Chapter XI
Mind-v-Consciousness and the "Hard problem"
107
Chapter XII
The history of Language and the role of Language in Consciousness
117
Chapter XIII
Conclusions and comments on Neurophenomenology, and the
"Evolution" of Consciousness
123
Index
130
ii
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank all of the following who have given advice and
encouraged me to go ahead and finish the unformed thoughts which I had
been mulling over for many years:
Professor John Hayes, of Limerick, Eire for giving this amateur, confidence
to go ahead and collect these ideas and ignoring the non-academic level of
writing.
Dr. M O’C Drury (deceased) for assisting me on the path of staying a
practicing Family Doctor but not ignoring the desire to do philosophy.
Diana, who has patiently permitted me to write three books now.
iii
Introduction
(Diagram)The general areas of the human brain.
Defining the problems.
Here we have this wondrous and mysterious brain. But what is the exact
relationship of consciousness to the brain? Furthermore what do we really
know about consciousness and the role it has played in the evolution of
humans? Did consciousness suddenly appear in humans with no evidence of
its appearance in animals other than humans? Or did a God suddenly decide
to create one species as conscious over all others?
What we commonly call consciousness is a complex word and we
sometimes use it in ways (usually religious or philosophical) that contain a
theory and exclude any further scientific or philosophical examination. If we
are restricted to humans from the outset then this book is probably
superfluous. If we allow that it may mean a gradation of consciousness, or
even self-awareness, that may be present in the “lower” animals, then we
can begin to look for something. In philosophy it is sometimes considered
that there is a “Hard” problem of the ultimate subjectivity of self-awareness.
iv
The "Easy Problem" would be the more superficial aspects of the day-to-day
functioning of an alert human being. These involve dealing with sensory
input, interpretation of basic information and certain other primary roles of
consciousness. However, as we will see later, this may be an artificial
distinction.
This thing called “Consciousness”! What does it have to do with the
brain? How did it evolve? Has it evolved?
I do not want to imply in any way that this book is anything but an
attempt to bring philosophy a little closer to scientific neurophysiology and
that philosophy has a role to play in developing knowledge of
consciousness. "Consciousness" should be primarily a neurophysiological
concept, not only a philosophical concept. By making it magically complex,
from the time of Descartes on, we have hampered research into this subject.
I would add that this same consciousness changes throughout the day, in
sickness and in health, in response to moods or concentration and is most
certainly not fixed. It may be altered in meditation. Now it is, of course,
quite possible that the very notion is a pure linguistic delusion and that we
are not experiencing anything different from an animal looking at the sunset,
but we seem to have more. This “more” seems to be what makes us
essentially human. But is it? Perhaps we need a little more humility in our
approach to the subject and a different scientific or philosophical approach
to work around the dilemma presented by objective-v-subjective. This inner
experience is undoubtedly important.
Some philosophers start off with the distinction between our “higher”
consciousness, ability to imagine, ability to discriminate past from future,
etc, as leading to a sine qua non that we possess this distinct consciousness.
Again some humility might be in order here following an investigation into
the whole animal kingdom.
I believe it is adding an extra linguistic layer to say we know that
anything is a conscious experience, as the simple matter is that we
experience it. I see something "red". Then I can answer a question from
v
someone else "What do you see"? "I am looking at something "red". Am I
"conscious" of that? Why would I even need to ask that question? I "feel
pain", I don't have to be conscious of "feeling pain". However there are
situations where it appears as though someone is in pain but is unable to
verify/prove it in any way that we know of, except a certain physical
behaviour. And this is enough! Animals surely do the same, not all animals
but those of a certain level of organization.
It has been stated by philosophical mysterians that we will have to
evolve more, to comprehend this mystery; our brains are too limited at
present. Perhaps! We are going to examine the possibility that this
awareness is an emergent property of the brain. There may be a need to
apply laws to the complete concept that may not apply to individual
components. This may happen in the same way that a crowd is not
completely reduced, in its behaviour, to that of an individual, or that a soccer
match is a composite of players and rules and follows different behaviour
and rules than those of an individual. We may have an entity whose laws are
determined by complex adaptive behavioural laws. The notion of an
Emergent Property does not entail that a new entity arises out of the neurons
in the brain. Only that at a certain level of organization it gives rise to
behaviour which may now follow different laws. We will return to this
theme later, but in the meantime we need to examine the animal kingdom
and look at the evolution of brain and intelligence and indeed the evolution
of consciousness itself.
We will see if we are yet able to outline a cogent and unified theory of
consciousness based on evolution, embryology, other animals, neurology of
humans, and, to a lesser extent, philosophy. Abstract concepts by their very
nature, may have different ways of behaving than the usual laws of physics.
Yet if we make scientific predictions from them then we need to return to
some sense of empirical verification. This is not denying the need to
appreciate that the laws of physics apply throughout, at a reductionist level,
but laws applying to an individual may not apply to a set. The behaviour of a
herd of elephants is quite different and studied differently than the behaviour
vi
of one elephant. Different laws may apply but the laws of physics stand
unchallenged.
I will try to paint, illustrate, prove in a certain way, that consciousness
is an emergent physical property. It is associated with a certain level of
complexity of the brain as a whole. It is also dependent on a pretty normal
functioning of a myriad of component parts and mechanisms, many of which
I will illustrate. We will be doing anthropological philosophy and
neurophilosophy in order to get at our subject. Furthermore we will be
painting a picture, illustrating, not attempting to prove outright, any thesis.
We are perhaps bypassing the problem, rather than solving a problem which
we might feel is overrated. Rather we will hope to offer a working
supposition on the nature of consciousness with the basic assumption that it
is a naturally occurring phenomenon, which has given Homo Sapiens some
advantages. However it may be that in the long run, our development of
consciousness contains our downfall. We may be guilty of dissociating
ourselves too far from our organic origins and by our very attempts to
control our whole environment, we may destroy our species.
I prefer to "paint a picture", using words, of consciousness and any
theory, because language and science are both deficient in assisting me in
saying what I truly might think. That is not meant to be mystical. If the
limits of my world are the limits of my language then I am sure language is
at fault and needs to be changed to represent more closely the limits of my
world, as I see it. I reject the prison imposed on us by the earlier
Wittgenstein but even wish to expand on the limits implicit in the later
Wittgenstein.
The issue of self-referential statements may arise as we talk about
self-awareness, and I do not wish to be sidetracked too much by those. The
famous paradoxes of logic in the 20th century were viewed as critical, and
Frege was totally dismayed by Russell's pointing out the "fatal" flaw in his
logical system. But there were ways around the set theory paradox, which
Russell and Zermelo had discovered in 1900 and 1901. It is complex, when
stated in set theory but basically comes down to the notion of the famous
vii
"Socrates says all men are liars, is he telling the truth?" The set of all sets
which are not members of themselves is harder to fathom but at the basis are
self-referential statements or formulae. Russell attempted a solution with his
"Theory of Types" but it was weak. However although the discovery lead on
to other things it was not anything like as serious as Frege seemed to think,
in terms of the massive accomplishment that he and Russell achieved. The
point being twofold:-Sometimes there is a methodological solution, and
sometimes you can just ignore paradoxes and move on bypassing them.
Wittgenstein in the later thirties seemed to downplay paradoxes. Now
although we are not dealing with a paradox, more of a dilemma, we are still
looking for ways around it, rather than a formal proof/disproof.
Our attempt is to take some of the mystery out of "mind",
"consciousness" and "self-awareness" and tackle the subject from an
empirical viewpoint. There will be some philosophical considerations, but
on this subject, I believe, philosophy defers to science. I have used the
internet freely, especially Wikipedia but tried not to plagiarize without
source recognition. I apologize to the reader, in advance, where he might
feel this has already been written and discussed too much already in recent
years, but I am writing to try and clarify my own comprehension. If any of it
registers with anyone else, then that's nice. If a reference, quote, or diagram,
appears to have no source quoted, it will have been used from the internet,
with no copyright mentioned.
I must apologize to those hoping for more academic references, but
this whole book has been written in the relative isolation of Nelson, BC,
where the only philosophical library is my own. I am very dependent on the
internet for factual research and have found it to be extremely helpful.
I also want to avoid the linguistic trap that we have probably inherited
from the early onomatopoeic principle that words should sound like the
object they represent, or the sound should suggest the meaning. This has
survived through to the modern day. I support the ideas of Aristotle that
"language is by convention, since no names arise naturally" (De
interpretatione 16a 27 ). He went on to say "speech is the representation of
viii
the experiences of the mind". So we will try to avoid some of the linguistic
traps. By avoiding categorical mistakes we hope to avoid ontological
mistakes also. So I am in fact saying that the so-called "Hard Problem" may
be the wrong question to pose in whatever insoluble form is gets asked. It is
possibly similar to asking "what then, created the 'Big Bang?", or "What
created Singularity?", and other questions which, stated simply, should not
be asked. They are language gone wrong, and thinking gone wrong. Modern
philosophy has not necessarily removed itself from science and, like
Bertrand Russell, I would like to keep the two subjects very close, but with
better appreciation of the notions of certainty and causality and proof, and
this is where philosophy is still needed. There are modern thinkers, usually
scientists who think that, after Kant, no philosophers have enabled science to
proceed forwards. I cannot disagree more with this position and hope to shed
light on that as we proceed.
So I present a Unified Theory of Consciousness (UTC) and also
contend that the "Hard Problem" of consciousness need not be hard.
Furthermore I want, again to completely remove any traces of dualism from
our thinking. I want to say that the "Hard Problem" simply introduces a form
of linguistically induced dualism, with which we can dispense. I would be
also saying that there are quite feasible ways to have an idea what it is like to
be a bat, if indeed I can have any idea what it is like to feel the "same" as
another human being. Consciousness is not localized in any one place and
although I point out critical anatomical levels in the brain that are necessary
functional levels for consciousness to be in place, it is my opinion that
consciousness is a function of the living animal and not to be localized, even
specifically in the brain. Most of the critical components are, indeed, in the
brain but that is a different matter. For eons we have been trying to localize
minds and souls in pineal glands, or wherever, but with a UTC we dispense
with that and hope to progress to further research on particular substrates of
consciousness.
I cannot apologize for the mixture of English and American spelling
as I use both all the time.
ix
To begin our story, we really need to look at the very origins of life on
this planet and indeed the origin of the universe. We may as well start at the
beginning.
John Dale, Nelson, British Columbia, April 2012
x
Chapter I
The Beginnings.
So here we are at one of the greatest mysteries of science, the "Big
Bang" itself and Singularity. Matter suddenly formed from pure energy. We
really cannot ask the question as to any origin of the energy itself. We can
leave atheists and theists to argue over that one indefinitely. If the Big Bang
was just over 14 billion years ago, the universe took a while to form
elements and compounds and our own planet. Life began with chemotrophs
at some time after 4.6 billion years ago (BYA). These organic compounds,
some of which remain near hydrothermal vents on the ocean floors, used
inorganic material such as hydrogen sulphide to create organic molecules.
1
What happened next remains hypothetical, but it would appear that
collections of RNA (ribonucleic acid) became organized through
temperature and chemical changes, into prebionts. This may have taken 500
million years. These were non-living substances, almost creatures, and
gradually the prebionts organized into organic molecules capable of
absorbing materials from the surrounding water into their structure. These
macromolecules are known now as coacervates and they in turn evolved into
structures with double membranes, which could now grow and form buds.
They could perhaps form nucleic acids and such polypeptides as ATP
(adenosine tri-phosphate,) which is still critical in our own structure, as
illustrated by the famous Krebs cycle we had to learn in organic chemistry.
Our murky ancestors were anaerobes and liked high temperatures
(very high) and lots of sulphur, so maybe that’s why we still love those
stinky hot springs. Over a great length of time came the prokaryotes, such as
primitive bacteria. They have no nucleus and very little internal structure.
Eventually these specialized into eukaryotes. These highly advanced beings
had cells and a certain amount of internal (membrane-adherent) structure.
The first fossils were probably prokaryotes and were bacterial fossils,
somewhat similar to the modern cyanobacteria. This genus resulted in
stromatolites. These appear to be a colonizing version of the cyanobacteria.
They formed primitive coral reefs and dominated the earth (insofar as life
dominated anything at that time) for 2 billion years.
We don’t know much about what happened for a billion years or so
but some worm-like animal fossils have been found dating back about 1
billion years ago. So multi-cellular life-forms, began at least that far back.
But we need to take a look at the protists to consider before advancing to
multi-cellular organisms. Protists are predominantly unicellular, i.e. consist
of one cell, and have characteristics of both plants and animals. They live by
photosynthesis and can move around under their own power. Familiar
modern versions include seaweed, amoebae and slime molds. It is thought
2
that this line of development gave rise to the three main divisions of life i.e.
plants, animals and fungi, about 600 MYA. Most protists have one nucleus
but some have up to 10,000 nuclei in one cell. In size these creatures vary
from 0.01 mm, a green alga, to 65 metres in such forms as a giant kelp.
Are we reaching any form of intelligence yet? Slow down! Some
protists are capable of moving but they did not seem smart enough to invent
sexual recombination and mostly (with some exceptions, it is thought)
simply reproduced asexually, i.e. without DNA (deoxyribonucleic acid)
merging. But we do have to introduce the notion of purposeful behavior at
some early point in the life forms and make some distinctions between
intentional behavior and thoughtful behavior, so that we do not need to think
of heliotropes (i.e. sun-seeking plants) as intelligent.
The protists evolved in several pathways. Protozoans, sponges,
coelenterates, and protophytes, all evolved from protists. On the plant side
protophytes branched off to form all plant life, including seaweed. Protists
also gave rise to all invertebrates and vertebrates.
3
I am, of course, taking Darwin’s Theory of Evolution as the most
sensible explanation for the current species known in the world. All current
life involves combinations of 20 amino acids and utilizes DNA and RNA.
RNA, in all probability was the precursor of DNA and gave rise to protein
synthesis. We take natural selection to be involved and will not enter into
whether this is only at the gene level or whether at the species level, or
perhaps a mixture of both. Neither will we deny that natural selection is the
only force in nature which produced evolution of species. For instance,
natural disasters do not necessarily favour the “strongest” but may be
completely bad or good luck to a species. When it comes to human
consciousness I will propose a more complex form of evolution, involving
bio-social and historical forms. For example, my being influenced by
Aristotle some 2300 years later.
According to Stephen Jay Gould life does not evolve in any straight
sensible pattern but rather in episodes of success and failure. The early
species, Ediacaran, were multi-cellular and appeared 600 MYA and died out.
Gould has always emphasized that life is not necessarily progressive from
early multi-cellular organisms to invertebrates (animals without backbones)
through to vertebrates and humans. Vertebrates came through the line of
marine vertebrates and then reptiles and mammals followed with the
evolution of the neural structure, and onto humans. Yet we are by no means
even close to a comparison of success when compared to bacteria, so if we
could imagine these highly intelligent bacteria designing all future complex
life forms, simply to provide a means to propagate bacteria around the
world, we can see how a different look at life might lead us. Our assumption
of superiority may be based on transitory success.
We want to explore the development of neural systems and intelligent
response to the environment. We will also be looking at the development of
emotions and the whole notion of consciousness. Of course we are not
simply talking about conscious-v-unconscious in the primitive sense but the
so-called “hard problem” of consciousness, in terms of self-awareness,
which we appear to possess. This is not only a function of language
4
presumably, unless we see it as simply a delusion formed as a byproduct of
language. We will certainly return to the philosophical issues of
consciousness later. We will also need, perhaps, to distinguish
“phenomenal” consciousness (pain and recognition of sensory input) from
“access” consciousness (information processing with decision making).
To return to our evolution examination, according to Gould: “Only
one member of our chordate phylum, the genus Pikaia, has been found
among these earliest fossils. This small and simple swimming creature,
showing its allegiance to us by possessing a notochord, or dorsal stiffening
rod, is among the rarest fossils of the Burgess Shale, our best preserved
Cambrian fauna”. (Found not too far from where I live at present).
(Diagram: Pikaia)
So we had a slim chance of survival but, for probably precarious and
serendipitous reasons, vertebrate mammals did evolve and survive. The
impact of a cosmic body that effectively put an end to dinosaurs, 65 MYA,
further increased our chances of survival. As Gould goes on to say, the
actual evolution of a certain upright primate in a dry African savanna,
between 2-4 MYA was tenuous and we ourselves could have ended up as a
gorilla-like being with no further major advance.
5
This of course assumes that you see humans as an advance. There is
the possibility that our form of intelligence and specifically the development
of language, emotion and consciousness may in fact be our downfall as a
species. Let us not forget how successful the lowly bacteria are. But we will
return to that happy thought later. Gould himself has pointed out our bias in
assuming some superiority and taking our complexity as necessarily
“better”.
Now let us return to the examination of the progression of early
fauna. We will briefly examine the timelines of evolution and then go back
to primitive creatures to look at the evolution of “intelligence” and neural
systems and see if we can determine the origins of consciousness and which
animals we take to be called conscious.
Initially we stayed with unicellular creatures for a long time, in the
billions of years. Then around 600 MYA the multi-cellular creatures
evolved. Then, in the course of less than 200 million years most of the
significant changes in organization of multi-cellular primitives took place,
i.e. the significant multi-cellular patterns. In the aforementioned Burgess
Shale collection, containing specimens found in the Canadian Rockies, we
find around the Cambrian geological period that many new species evolved
seemingly over 5 million years, or longer according to some sources. The
so-called Cambrian explosion, during which the majority of all future
species evolved in one form or another, represents rather a similar pattern to
the explosion of culture seen in the phenomenally short period of the Athens
heyday. We do not yet understand fully the reasons for either. In the last 400
million years we have just further developed those patterns established
during that relatively short explosion of species.
Mass extinctions, such as that of the dinosaurs, which probably relates
to the asteroid, 7-10 Kms in diameter, which impacted at the Yucatan
peninsula in Mexico, about 65 MYA, may have played more of a role than
we probably know. This one impact led to the Cretaceous-Tertiary period of
evolution, possibly through a massive dust cloud, which may have blocked
light for several months and led to millions of deaths, including whole
6
species. Dinosaurs were but one. Birds seemingly only evolved after this,
possibly from certain dinosaurs. Sinosauropteryx prima appeared maybe
around 130 million years ago. The Velociraptor is more recent, dating
perhaps around 80 million years ago. It was primarily a ground-dwelling
dinosaur. These two were perhaps precursors of birds. Recent studies
indicate the connection to the modern wild turkey, mainly in terms of bone
structure.
By 500 MYA the first reptiles had evolved. They were eel-like
animals with no eyes. By about 450 MYA the first insects on land had
evolved to join some rooted plants. Life had crawled out of the ocean. A
mere 50 million years later, reptiles emerged with skulls. The brain began to
be protected. At 220 MYA mammals came into being, mostly smaller ones
looking like rats. These animals, being warm-blooded, needed to eat more
but still laid eggs like reptiles. Primates probably pre-dated the “non-nuclear
winter” of the Yucatan asteroid 65 MYA but humanoid creatures began
walking upright about 6 MYA. This would have been at the time of the
divergence between early hominids and proto-chimpanzees. Modern humans
have a heritage of a mere 200,000 years. Around 10,000 years ago we see
the first villages, or cities in the fertile valleys of the old Middle-East.
But we have jumped ahead, once again and need to return to earlier
animals. We have briefly discussed evolution but we need to look at
primitive animals in terms of their development of complex behaviour.
7
Chapter II
From primitive creatures to creatures with neural systems.
We have to start an investigation somewhere and we want to keep in
mind that we are trying to see where consciousness came into evolution and
even more complex how self-awareness may have arisen. But we need to
start at humble beginnings.
So let us go to some more primitive creatures. We have mentioned
bacteria as the most successful historical evolutionary creatures. They are
ubiquitous in soil and water. They are generally very small, but can be found
up to 0.5 mms in size. They have no cell nucleus, nor mitochondria (kind of
power centres), nor chloroplasts (another energy converter). The renowned
amoeba is also unicellular. These are protozoa’s with movement caused by
internal cytoplasmic flow. Slime moulds fall into this category, and the
amoebas have a pseudopod and can vary in size up to a few millimetres. The
amoeba is divided into an endoplasm and ectoplasm, the outer clear layer
being the ectoplasm. It eats by phagocytosis, i.e. by surrounding food
particles and sealing them into vacuoles and digesting at leisure. They don’t
seem to have to work too hard to earn a living. They are more comparable to
the civil servants in this respect. Do they have intelligence yet? Hard to say!
I refer of course to the amoeba. Maze solving for food is within the
capability of the amoeba.
8
(Diagram: single-celled amoeba)
Following Protozoa’s we move to worms, insects, fish, amphibia,
birds and mammals. The new name for the last four is chordata due to some
kind of backbone but for our purposes the earlier classification is better.
What we want to do is look at some more primitive forms individually,
rather than discuss the apparent reasons for evolutionary success. Such
things as colonial organization, sexual reproduction, exo- and endo-skeletal
development we will pass by at this time.
We will look at worms. There are four main groups of worms:
Flatworms or Platyhelminthes, Ribbon worms or Nemertea, Roundworms or
Nematoda and segmented worms, or Annelida. Platyhelminthes are the
simplest animals that are bilaterally symmetrical. They are triploblastic i.e.
composed of three fundamental cell layers. Flatworms have no body cavity
except a gut (and some may even lack that) and have no anus. The same
9
pharyngeal opening both takes in food and expels waste. Due to a lack of
any other body cavity, in larger flatworms the gut is often very highly
convoluted so as to transport food to all parts of the body. They must respire
by diffusion, thus cells cannot be far from the outside, which is why they are
flat.
(Diagram: Flatworm)
One of the flatworms, Notoplana Acticola has been well studied, and
its brain examined, as it does have one. There is a diversity of cell types and
some spines almost resembling the dendrites (“legs”) that we have on our
neurons. It may have 2000 neurons and can orient, move, locate food and
avoid predators. We can perhaps call this an early form of intelligence.
Some flatworms are free living, like planaria, and others are parasites, like
the human lung fluke. This one causes a most annoying disease in its host.
10
(Diagram: Lung Fluke)
The next category is Ribbon Worms and they would be interesting to
those that like to study them. I don’t, so we will pass them by and look at
Nematodes. These are actually the most numerous multi-cellular animals on
earth. They have perhaps 20,000 species and are divided into parasitic freeliving. Nematodes have neural systems; very primitive but they do have
something like a brain! Now many humans assume that only humans can be
conscious, or rather possess consciousness in the superior awareness context.
I am not at all sure about this. It is most presumptuous. I once asked my dog
“Lady” if she was conscious but being fast asleep she could not answer me.
She was also stone-deaf by this time, and so did not hear the question. But I
am sure she would answer in the affirmative.
Wittgenstein said that if a lion could speak, we wouldn't know what it
was talking about anyway, but I am sure if Lady could speak she would
make herself totally intelligible to me. I am also quite sure that if a lion
could speak, Wittgenstein would have been listening very carefully, had he
been close enough to hear the lion. Back to the nematodes; they do have
about 1000 somatic cells and over a hundred reproductive cells. They are
unsegmented and lack appendages but are useful as biological insecticides.
To say the roundworms have brains is perhaps misleading. They are low on
11
the bureaucratic order of intelligence but do possess a ventral and dorsal
nerve and primitive sense organs. They are starting to interpret and react to
their environment. It becomes a fine line as to when reaction becomes
"thoughtful" but we will look at that later.
(Diagram: The Nematode)
They do have an anus, such a big advance! The nematodes are plant
killers, in addition to their insecticide utility. Damage from worms may cost
$100 Billion US per year worldwide, it is thought. The last species of
worms, segmented worms, like the ubiquitous earthworm do not represent a
significant intelligence leap and we will crawl on by them.
12
Subdivisions of animal brains:The organization of brains in the animal kingdom can best be looked at by
the following levels:
• Molecular Level – basic avoidance or chemical response.
• Cellular level – Neurons, which are the basic signaling cells and most
basic elements of the nervous system
• Network Level – Neurons now organize into networks and process
singly or in parallel.
• Behavioural level – Neural information processing now results in a
certain behaviour of the whole animal
The insect brain seemed to evolve directly from the earthworm brain
design. In the annelid worms or segmented worms, each segment had its
own little brain or ganglia. These were interconnected, segment by segment.
The insect’s head is actually segmented but now has fused these segments
into a brain with optic lobes, ocelli (which are accessory eyes capable of
perceiving the intensity of light), olfactory lobes or antennal lobes. In
addition they have mushroom bodies which are the closest equivalent of a
higher “problem solving” centre. There are neurosecretory cells which
equate to a primitive hypothalamus in humans and corpora cardiaca and
allata, which produce a hormone. The last bit of the structure is a
subesophageal ganglion which coordinates the mouthparts while feeding.
13
(Diagram: The Insect Brain)
The insect brain appears limited to fairly rapid adaptive use but with
some Pavlovian learning by experience. It does not appear able, as we shall
see mammals are, to create and imagine virtual realities and thus to
anticipate new dangers. We assume some kind of memory. Interestingly the
"Mushroom Bodies" may be the closest counterpart in an invertebrate to the
cerebral cortex.
The insect brain is generally divided into four sections, optical lobes,
protocerebrum, deutocerebrum and the tritocerebrum. The mushroom bodies
are in the protocerebrum but although given the title, implying higher centre,
they are more to do with smell than anything else. However we should be
warned not to underestimate the immense importance of smell in conveying
information to animals. The protocerebrum is also secondary to the antennal
or olfactory lobes, in the deuterocerebrum, which in addition analyses touch.
We are not by any means implying consciousness at this level in the animal
kingdom, but we are perhaps starting to see the underlying structure
necessary for it to develop.
14
We now need to take a look at fish. Fish and certain early
vertebrates appeared in the Cambrian Period (510 MYA) and gave rise to
modern species only about 400 MYA. Interestingly the early forms, from
fossil knowledge, appeared to be in fresh water and the earliest modern
fossil forms of bony fish appeared about 250 MYA. Fish have developed
brains and have leapt well beyond a few basic nerve cells and can sense
toxic substances for navigation adaptation. The development of three areas
of the fish brain, appear to relate to the ability to navigate in complex
environments. The telencephalon, cerebellum and optic tectum are three
areas more highly developed to enhance spatial orientation in a visual
environment, i.e. light area of the ocean. The significant findings in this
more complex brain are the ability to interpret multiple and parallel inputs,
integrate the information and act on the resulting conglomerate of
information. Research on fish with brain lesions in specific areas, has
assisted these conclusions.
It has been concluded that the fish brain is not developed enough to
feel pain though animal rights activists question this. This is based on the
fact that the fish brain is primarily brain stem development, and not cerebral
hemispheres as is the human brain. So there may be a reaction that looks like
pain but with no cerebration sufficient to "feel" pain. A difficult concept, we
shall return at some point to that notion. A fish caught on a hook certainly
looks as though it is not very happy! There is an argument that lobsters and
crabs cannot feel pain when being boiled, because they have only about
100,000 neurons and we have over 100 billion. I find the argument
somewhat lacking and perhaps those who argue it should have all but
100,000 neurons removed, and then undergo boiling in the name of science!
15
(Diagram: Fish Brain)
Fish have a large olfactory bulb that is directly connected to the
cerebral hemisphere. This means that their higher thinking will be mostly
smell driven. They have no hippocampus, so that would lead us to expect
that they will not produce feelings of love, compassion, or rage. Fish do
however, have a modest cerebral cortex that is close to the occipital cortex,
which means that the fish will react to visual cues and create memories from
the visual cues. The "cerebral cortex", or telencephalon, of the fish is more
concerned with olfactory information than anything else. Fish may well have
a long term memory. It is well known in medicine that when a patient is
reduced to brain stem level of unconsciousness, the patient does not feel
pain. There may be a primitive level of stimulus avoidance but that is
different than pain as a remembered entity. Fish may fall into the category of
sensing pain but not knowing they are in pain. This is somewhat similar to
the situation of certain anaesthetics we use on humans. The patients appear
to react to painful stimulus but there will be no memory of any pain when
the patient "wakes up".
There are philosophical overtones, as mentioned previously, and we
may return to this subject as part of consciousness later. It has been said that
because fish lack a neocortex they could not possibly be conscious in any
similar manner to humans and therefore would not feel pain. An eminent
animal expert, Temple Grandin, stated that she believes fish could have
16
consciousness without a neocortex because "different species can use
different brain structures and systems to handle the same functions."
Grandin, Temple; Johnson, Catherine (2005). Animals in Translation. New
York, New York: Scribner. pp. 183–184.
There are many claims that fish can distinguish colours and be taught
to feed out of their owners hands, when pets. However we shall take fish in
general to be lacking somewhat in abstract thought and symbolic powers.
Fish, reptiles and amphibians have a six-layered allocortex, which is the
outer layer of their brain.
More complex brains are seen in all of the following groups:
arthropods (insects and crustaceans), cephalopods (octopi, squids and certain
mollusks), and vertebrates. Vertebrates or craniates began to have the brain
protected inside a skull and then increased the surface layer of the brain by
convolutions. The folds of the brain are called gyri. I show that below but
we are not ready to analyze it yet. This just illustrates nature's ingenuity in
increasing cortex but not overall size.
(Diagram) The Human Brain showing Sulci and Gyri
We mentioned that a flatworm might have 2000 neurons. In the
human being, during early development, the brain increases by 250,000
neurons per minute. The majority of the brain cells are in place by birth but
the brain increases in size for several years and increases the glial cells,
17
which are an evolutionary advance seen earlier in the phylogenetic tree. The
brain also adds many more connections after birth. The glial cells assist in
insulating neurons with myelin. The myelin sheath enables conductivity at
up to 100 times faster than a non-myelinized sheath. This was a dramatic
evolutionary leap.
(Diagram: The neuron showing the myelin sheath)
In humans we are familiar with the demyelination diseases and how
this affects us cognitively. The human brain ends up with between 10 billion
and 100 billion neurons with each one being linked to perhaps 10,000
neurons. This is a large computer!
18
Just as in certain worms, which develop ventral and dorsal neural
tubes the human brain develops from a neural tube. The front part becomes
the brain proper and the rest becomes the spinal chord. In the front part of
the human embryo develops the forebrain, midbrain and hindbrain. We are
not quite ready yet, in this investigation, to dive into a more detailed look at
the human brain, as we want to examine further the development of
intelligence in other animals.
19
Chapter III
The Development of Intelligence in Animals: initial examination.
Before we look at the complexities of humans and the human brain
function, let us focus on animals in general, and introduce birds. How can
we judge intelligence and emotions in animals? I take it for granted that the
development of emotions is every bit as important as "intelligence", and is in
fact a form of intelligence anyway. There are many recent books on
“Emotional Intelligence” and the phrase has become acceptable as a more
extended way of looking at intelligence in general.
We can break down the behaviour according to a system modified from
Wikipedia online:
• Attention: Picking out one useful item amongst the sensory fields.
Pigeons can find grain in the middle of substrate.
• Categorisation: Discrimination e.g. birds can discriminate between
differing human speech sounds
• Memory: Certain animals exhibit similar short-term memory to
humans e.g. monkeys and spatial memory is very well developed in
e.g. squirrels, who need to remember where all their hoards of nuts are
stored. Perhaps the Arctic Tern and navigation memory would be
applicable here also. The tern can navigate from polar areas to the
opposite polar region. I remember seeing them in spring in Cambridge
Bay, NWT (as it was then) and marveling at the distance they had
come.
• Tool use: Although finches have been observed to use tools, it does
not compare to the use of tools by baboons, observed by Jane Goodall.
Sea Otters are known to use tools also. They have been noted to tuck
tools under their armpits to use when diving for food.
• Reasoning and problem solving: Chimpanzees appear to have fairly
good reasoning in problem solving. My dog “Sadie” has excellent
reasoning in this faculty having successively weakened our resistance
20
to end up sleeping in the bed with us. This was her plan all along, only
it was not evident to us at the beginning.
• Language: This has often been researched by spurious methods of
trying to teach animals to speak, instead of studying advanced
communications in a non-verbal sense. The dance of the bees is one
example of complex language.
• Consciousness: This would include the ability to self-refer. Perhaps a
delusion of humans also. Maybe some aliens would find our belief that
we possess self-awareness very strange and would want proof. But if
we mark an animal’s skin, while asleep or sedated, and then let it see
itself in a mirror we can see a response from some animals. If they try
to remove the mark after seeing it in the mirror then that might be
interpreted as a form of self-awareness. Chimps who first look into a
mirror, act as though they were encountering another chimp, but they
soon begin to perform simple repetitive movements like swaying from
side to side while watching their images. Perhaps they are learning that
they can control the movement of the `other' chimp. They then appear
to grasp the equivalence between the mirror image and themselves and
start to explore body parts such as the genitalia, which they can't
ordinarily see. If a spot of dye that can't be smelled or felt is placed on
a chimp's eyebrow ridge during anesthesia, it will be noticed when the
animal first encounters a mirror after waking. More telling, the chimp
will touch the dyed area and then smell and look at the fingers that
have contacted the mark, suggesting self recognition - a sense of self.
We can probably assume they do not have a theory of other minds, yet
some humility may be in order here.
Of some cats we have had, Shoebrain did not like his own
mirror image but Wagstaff, seems quite enamoured of herself in the
mirror. Snowflake ignores mirrors with disdain. Animals that have
been known to recognize "self" in mirrors include great apes, pigeons,
elephants, and certain dolphins.
• Empathy and emotions: This will require a whole chapter, for
instance the behaviour of killer whales, if one of their own is
21
slaughtered, can hardly be called a lower animal instinct. So grief for
separation or death is a relevant topic here. See later for an account of
crows paying tribute to the death of one of their own.
• Playing: This is an often overlooked area but one which displays a
certain relation to our consciousness and needs examining. We shall
examine it later.
We should not really look at animal intelligence from an
anthropocentric viewpoint. We may be able to answer certain questions as to
“how” and “why” and even “when” a little better than the standard “who”,
“where” and “what” which other animals can do, but we just have a
specialized system of communication unused by other animals, i.e. symbolic
expression; specifically verbal. Later on, I will introduce the notion of
"emic" and "etic" studies in biology. That is to say, studying from "inside"
versus "outside" your subject domain.
Windsor Chorlton, in an online article from the United Kingdom,
documents some wonderful examples of animal intelligence. Hob, a falcon
used by police, is able to recognize his owner’s Lada car. Once when lost the
bird spotted the car on the A 303 amidst traffic and followed it to his turnoff
point. On another occasion when chasing a pheasant the falcon emerged
from the hedge sounding frustrated and continued to bug the owner until he
followed it into the hedgerow, where after some distance he again found the
bird standing over a rabbit hole where the pheasant was hiding. This would
appear to be innovative problem solving. “Among birds, crows have
especially large forebrains and display impressive resourcefulness Faced
with the problem of how to transport scattered biscuits, ravens, unlike other
birds, don't carry them off one-by- one. They stack them into one neat pile,
and then carry them all off. The woodpecker finch of the Galapagos Islands
uses a cactus spine to prise insects out of crevices, while the Egyptian
vulture smashes open ostrich eggs with stone.” (Windsor Chorlton)
With further regard to tool use Chorlton records the following: “In
what is now Ghana, colonial forestry official W B Collins witnessed the
extraordinary way in which driver ants harnessed a simple tool to break
22
through the defenses of a horde of snails. Driver ants can reduce a python to
bones in an hour, but these snails initially repelled the ant army by secreting
a foam-like mucus into the entrances of their shells for protection.
The ants deposited crumbs of dry soil in the mucus. As the liquid was
absorbed, the snails responded by secreting yet more mucus, and in turn, the
ants deposited more soil around the snails. This relentless attack technique
was repeated until the snails had exhausted their mucus reserves and lay
defenseless.” The more we look at animal intelligence the more we can
probably conclude that we differ in degree not kind.
Thomas Grandin (Department of Animal Science, Colorado State
University) in his online essay “Consciousness in Animals and People with
Autism” October 1998, discusses the adaptive intelligence of mice:
“In a classic experiment, blind mice were trained to run a maze almost
without error. This required that the mice make correct turns at about twenty
junctions in the maze. The maze was cleaned after each trial to remove
olfactory cues and the orientation of the maze was rotated to prevent sound
orientation from the laboratory. Temporary regressions were produced after
new orientations of the maze, however the mice soon overcame this and
were performing with hardly any mistakes at all. After three months, the
mice were successfully trained to the maze and four different variations of
the maze were introduced. In the first, the size of the maze was enlarged, in
the second the angles of the turns were skewed from 90 degree turns to 45
and 135 degree turns, the third was a reverse of the second and the mouse
had to turn through 134 and 45 degree turns and the fourth was a mirror
image of the original maze. Before long, the mice had successfully mastered
all the different mazes. The success of the experiment proved that the mice
had transformed the information learned from the first maze which the mice
then used to solve the problems of the novel mazes.”
There is then the question of need in various animals. We may have
developed the cortex because our environment required more adaptive and
abstract thinking to problem solve food supply etc. Another species may
have developed a visual brain and do its thinking primarily visually, just as
23
we will see Thomas Grandin states that that is the way he thinks, due to his
autism. Another animal may have primarily an auditory brain and think in
sounds or, again, yet another may have simply a massive olfactory brain and
think in smells. So we should have some humility in thinking we are
necessarily more intelligent than certain animals, just different. Our own
intelligence manifests itself in different ways.
Grandin describes the levels of consciousness as being four in total:
1. Consciousness within one sense
2. Consciousness where all the sensory systems are integrated.
3. Consciousness where all the sensory systems are integrated with
emotions.
4. Consciousness where sensory systems and emotions are integrated
and thoughts are in symbolic language.
He goes on to add that he is at level two because he does not connect
thoughts with emotions. Grandin has difficulty with abstract ideas and has to
imagine them as concrete examples, for example he defines "belief" as
"things where there is a high probability that something may be true, but I
am not 100% sure".
Michael Gazzaniga, in an online article written 25 years after his main
work on Split Brain Theory, notes the intriguing finding that mice can do
better than humans on some tests:
“Illusory contours reveal that the human right brain can process some
things the left cannot. Both hemispheres can "see" whether the illusory
rectangles of this experiment are fat or thin. But when outlines are added,
only the right brain can still tell the difference. In mice, however, both
hemispheres can consistently perceive these differences. For a rodent to
perform better than we do suggests that some capabilities were lost from one
hemisphere or the other, as the human brain evolved. New capabilities may
have squeezed out old ones in a race for space.” As humans developed
speech primarily in the left hemisphere, which is why speech is generally
24
lost more when the right side of the body is affected by a stroke, it may have
been at the expense of another important function or perceptual skill.
On the Television program “Daily Planet” there was, recently, an item
about rats being used in Africa to detect land mines. After suitable training
they could sniff out the TNT used and return for a banana, while the land
mine was destroyed, or deactivated. They say that rats are easier to train and
work with than dogs. Apparently they have not heard of lawyers, who for
three reasons make far better research animals:
1: There is no shortage of lawyers and PETA has betrayed no interest in
defending them yet.
2: There is only a remote chance of their trainer becoming emotionally
attached.
3: There is nothing they will refuse to do for a suitable reward.
On the same program, sheep given food laced with antibiotics when
sick preferred that to food without the antibiotic, seemingly a double-blinded
type of experiment. Would it be intuition or conscious knowledge of feeling
better after a certain food?
Of interest here is the comparison between a rat brain and a human brain.
25
(Diagram: Human Brain-v- Rat Brain)
Also of interest here, we note the main size difference in cerebral cortex and
in sulci and gyri. However the limbic system is well developed. We might
comment at this time that a mouse or rat has about 85% similarity in genes
to humans, a chimpanzee 98%, the famous fruit fly or Drosophila
Melanogaster actually shares about 60% of its genes with humans and with
the Roundworm 21%.
Play in animals as evidence of higher consciousness.
Playing in animals almost falls under the same chapter and logic as
emotions but let us examine it separately. The pleasure of a cat snuggled up
to you is two way and known to release dopamine and opiates. In rats,
permitting them to "play" has been shown to extend a healthy life. A Rhesus
monkey has been observed in the wild, doing a reverse flip. Rhinos play,
26
even badgers play. More surprising, is that some parrots and other birds have
been observed distinctly playing. Generally it is confined to mammals and
the longer the maturation to adult, the more playfulness observed. Animal
play has been categorized into locomotor play, predatory play, object play,
and social play. Locomotor play appears to be simply random exercise of
muscle groups, running, jumping etc. Predator play, often seen in our kitties
is very common, birds also indulge in this. Object play, whilst related to
predator play has a slightly more creative aspect, illustrated by "playing
house" in children.
Monkeys and Chimpanzees indulge in stick practice and practise
fishing termites out of holes to increase manual dexterity. Finally social play
involves other animals with games such as tag, or wrestling or even
play fighting. There are usually certain gestures performed by animals to
indicate that the following is within a play area of rules. Females are more
likely to perform grooming or looking after "baby brother". Whilst it is true
that human playfulness contains more symbolism and perhaps more
imagination, than other mammals, it is surely presumptuous of ourselves,
once again, not to appreciate the higher consciousness involved in all play.
Donald Griffin in a book entitled "Animal Thinking", Harvard
University Press 1984, uses an example I remember well as a child. When
milk bottles with aluminum foil caps were delivered daily and left outside
houses (as they were in the fifties and sixties anyway) the great tits and some
other small birds discovered a good source of rich cream on the top of the
milk, by pecking through the cap. We also had a race inside the house to see
who could get the most cream on their cereal and then shake the bottle and
pretend we had not been greedy. The birds exhibited great adaptive
intelligence. Griffin talks of "versatile adaptability of behavior to changing
circumstances and challenges", and wants to use that as a criterion of
conscious awareness in animals. It might be a good starting point but to
encompass the full range of human consciousness we may need more. He
goes on to discuss the notion of intentionality in animals and intention
movement as itself an indicator of consciousness. The fashionable
behaviouristic thinking of that era made it less likely that ethologists would
27
think along those lines. Griffin further points out the use of symbolism in
animals as an indicator of higher intelligence/consciousness. The famous
dance of the bees is symbolic for information as to whereabouts of food.
That these are in some meaningful sense conscious and intentional seems to
be a feasible interpretation. Thus philosophers who assume that man's use of
symbols is parallel to the higher levels of consciousness and even to the
notion of self-awareness, may need to rethink their conclusions. We shall
have recourse elsewhere to look at the origins of language and its
relationship to consciousness and the development of thought.
We need now to examine with what degree of sophistication animals can
communicate.
28
Chapter IV
Language/Communication in Animals.
There will be two parts to the discussion of language, firstly the advanced
state of animal "language" and secondly the evolution of language in
humans. The latter will be discussed in Chapter XI. Steven Roger Fischer in
"A History of Language" Reaktion Books Ltd 1999, discusses the
development and evolution of speech and communications in both animals
and humans. We shall borrow freely from his very readable book and focus
on aspects that illustrate the advanced consciousness of animals. Language
will be taken to include discursive (verbal speech) and symbolic. Symbolic
can be gestures, transmission of information by use of chemicals
(pheromones), or dancing, or pictures. In other words we are looking at all
ways in which information can be transmitted.
Fischer mentions the importance of the limitation of human audible
frequencies. At our best we hear between 30 and 18,000 cycles per second.
Many animals can communicate both above and below these levels. I will
just mention here that the remainder of this chapter paraphrases from
Fischer's informative book. The fact that we cannot understand, yet, the
language of fish or frogs does not mean that they do not have one, but the
focus is on ants, bees, and "higher" species. Ants use a combination of
pheromones and also stridulation, in an ultrasound range. Thus an individual
ant can communicate critical (food source) information through certain
movements and the above two methods. The honey-bee, made famous by
von Frisch, actually uses a combination of the complex dance, a variation of
a figure 8 for distance and direction, plus some vibration of the wings and
vibration of the thorax. So the other ants use observation, touch and hearing
to gain their information.
The research on the African Grey parrot has revealed an advanced
level of speech. A famous parrot, named Alex, was taught for about 12 years
and could name up to 100 objects, could count to six, could name colours.
Not only could he name these objects but he could perform various
29
conceptual exercises with them such as request, refuse and quantify the
objects. We do not yet know the full extent of complex bird songs but they
do operate out of our frequency range in some of their communication.
When we move on to mammals we have tended to concentrate on acoustic
means, such as used by bats in echo location. This is not necessarily
communication. Both bats and mice seem to use other frequencies for actual
communication, but we have much research to do still to understand it. It is
also known that bats can navigate by reference to magnetic fields and certain
experiments have been done to throw off their navigation by use of false
magnetic fields.
Much research has been undertaken with horses, elephants, whales
and dolphins on their communication methods. Both horses and deer use a
combination of gesture, orientation, eye contact, and avoidance, in order to
communicate and horse trainers have learned this to their advantage. It
reminds me of my early communication with Inuit, who do rely less on
normal speech (that is not to say the language is not functional and rich).
Elephants use rumbles, roars, growls, snorts, trumpets, and barks, some out
of the human range. The infrasound rumble between males and females may
carry 4 kilometres. Panic calls can carry miles as well.
Whales have even more subtle methods of communicating. The
frequency they use can be as high as 256,000 Hz, way above humans range.
The information transmitted, over long range, can be for sexual attraction,
information as to where the pod is and tracking members out of sight.
Individual pods have discrete calls and can "talk" eight kilometres away.
They use clicks, whistles, and short piercing screams which as pulsed. The
pods have unique dialects in their calls and can be identified by their
individual nature. The most complex sounds may be from the Blue Whale.
The "song" is at 188 decibels and might be detectable hundreds of
kilometres away. Even more interesting is the repetition at 128 seconds
intervals. This might be for communication but could be just echo location.
Humpbacks find a partner across hundreds of kilometres of ocean. The
songs appear to evolve over time.
30
Dolphins have been studied intensively. They do appear to be able to
transmit emotion more obviously than other mammals. There appears to be a
"help" signal. Overall their language may still consist more of groans,
giggles, and sighs, than information transmission. But we are only beginning
to understand how to study some of these animals and it cannot be from such
an anthropocentric viewpoint as we have generally taken.
Diagram illustrating size and shape of a dolphin's brain.
Of relevance are some points raised in an online paper by David Kaiser 1990
(Internet)
"Dolphins demonstrate many behaviors that show signs of conscious
awareness. For instance, behaviors which are illicit and punishable are often
performed only when a dolphin believes no one is around (e.g., SavageRumbaugh and Hopkins, 1986). When a dolphin squirts water at a human (to
show annoyance), he will often raise his head out of the water to curiously
31
observe the effect his behavior had on the unsuspecting victim (personal
observation). Both examples show an awareness of effects one's behavior
has on others."
(Diagram: comparison of Dolphin and Human Brain)
Although our own brain size is about three times that of the great apes, the
apes do have considerable language skills. Gorillas, such as Koko learned
Ameslan, a kind of sign language used by deaf people. Koko can use over
500 signs and transmit an appreciation of pain or discomfort in other
animals, illustrated by Fischer in the example given when Koko saw a horse
with a bit in its mouth. Koko signed "Horse sad" and was asked why and
responded "teeth". She has made attempts to talk and tried to use a phone
once and actually got through to a horrified listener who traced the call
thinking the caller was dying. Koko and her buddy, Michael, use a computer
keyboard with special keys and then the word is spoken with a speaker.
Koko was seen to be able to describe past incidents. She could tell lies,
illustrated by the time she was caught chewing a red crayon. Asked what if
she was eating the crayon, she replied "Lip" and started applying it as
lipstick. This might actually be more of an example of advanced emotion
and embarrassment.
Some doubt was thrown on some earlier experimentation and it was
thought that, as with the donkey that was thought able to count, some subtle
hints were given to influence answers and that we might be reading too
32
much into responses. However research on the miniature chimp, the bonobo
Kanzi indicated a far higher level of linguistic ability than previously
thought.
Kanzi used a "lexigram" a keyboard of symbols representing set
words. The response could activate a voice. Kanzi communicates to an
amazing level using this device. Once when the experimenter had her keys
stolen she asked Kanzi to find them. Kanzi went to the culprit and murmured
something in his ear, upon which the stolen keys were returned. Kanzi in
recent years was able to use 256 geometric symbols and score at least as
high as a 2 1/2 year old human. In other words Kanzi appears to be able to
speak to us at that age (human) level. However we really do not know much
about Kanzi's own language but the chimp had learned ours quite well. The
researchers are better these days at appreciating the mixture of devices used
by such animals as Kanzi. These include glances, gestures, postures, and
orientation.
About 5-7 million years ago when hominids split from the other great
apes, the real origins of human speech began to develop, pari-passu with the
enlargement of the brain and development of certain parts. But before we
look at humans, in a later chapter, we need to see how animals have evolved
their emotions. The relationship to developing consciousness is taken for
granted.
33
(Diagram: Bonobo brain above and Human brain below.
remarkably similar)
Getting
It is of course necessary to distinguish animal communication in general,
from language, in the human sense, but because we are more concerned with
the overall demonstration of intelligence, the distinction is of less
importance for our purposes. We are perhaps more interested in what has
been called Biosemiotics. This is the study of sign systems and
communications systems in all living creatures. I have focused on the more
"intelligent" animals and thus do not consider quite the same broad range
that biosemiotics appears to include.
So, for our purposes, our biological investigations, so far, reveal an
amazing degree of sophistication amongst many animals. The point to take
away from this is that once again our notions of intelligence, and even of
consciousness, require careful description and definition and we must avoid
the anthropocentric trap. In humans we learned to our chagrin, some years
ago, that our IQ testing was incredibly biased. I contend that it is even more
in need of a widening of scope so that we can see the incredible intelligence
of animals. This would include the notion of emotional intelligence in
animals. We will take a look at this in the next chapter.
34
Chapter V
Emotions in Animals.
As many deny the occurrence of higher emotions in animals, it
behooves us to look at what we can conclude about their emotions. Susan
B.Eirich, Ph.D. in an online essay “Do Animals have emotions” quotes an
incident with a pet hyena who had been raised at home initially and then
released into a pack. She tells the story of what happened when she went to
visit him. He had been attacked by females in the pack. She notes:
“He had been attacked by the females in the female-dominated hyena
society. The words "How is he" barely escaped my lips when there was an
outpouring of pitiful whining. He met me at the fence, falling to his carpals
and continuing his cacophony as though recounting the morning's ordeal.
His body posture epitomized hyena submissiveness, - bared teeth in an openmouthed appeasement grin, ears plastered to his head, the look of defeat in
his stance. As I entered his pen he glued himself to me. His hindquarters
turned to jelly. He sank to the floor, and like any frightened creature, he
relieved himself all over my boots. With Phoenix entwined in my legs I
stumbled to a pile of straw and sat down. Before I was even fully seated he
crawled into my lap (which he had long since outgrown), turned over on his
back, stared up at me with bewildered eyes, and whined a little longer. As I
consoled him and checked for cuts, he lowered his head, closed his eyes, and
fell sound asleep."
She continues:- "Granted Phoenix had taken an emotional beating, but
there was hardly a physical bruise on him. A little disinfectant here, a little
patting there, and he was good to go. In scientific terms he was a lowranking hyena who had suffered the stress and acute changes in circulating
cortisol levels brought on by social interactions with higher- ranking
animals. In layman's terms he was a frightened hyena who needed
comforting.”
35
Whilst it is possible that Ms Eirich may be biased, in that she works as
a biologist and psychologist at a home for native wildlife in Idaho, her
thoughts are nevertheless intriguing and contain much that should humble
humans. The notion of a triune brain i.e. a division into three parts: reptilian,
paleo-mammalian and neo-mammalian is based on the division of autonomic
nervous system, limbic system and true cortical system. The division again
would locate breathing, circulation control, reproduction and social
dominance, primarily in the autonomic areas.
The limbic system is thought to be a central element of controlling our
basic emotions in humans, not necessarily refined emotions but basic love,
joy, anger etc. The neo-mammalian area is the later more abstract thinking
area, advanced problem solving and creation of virtual realities. Eirich
points out that she and Jane Goodall, believe that animals can suffer posttraumatic stress and depression. Prozac has been used in animals with
beneficial effects and Zoloft and Paxil, used in humans for ObsessiveCompulsive disorder has also been seen in animals with fur-biting or feather
pulling, often symptoms of distress in animals.
Eirich states :
“The chemical neurotransmitters of animals are the same as humans dopamine, serotonin, opioids. The hormones are similar - those used for
hormone replacement therapy in women are made from the urine of pregnant
mares. The same hormones perform the same functions - oxytocin, for
example, initiates maternal bonding, care, tenderness, protection across all
the females of all the mammalian species including humans. We can
interpret this to mean we are all just bags of chemicals that react- or we can
interpret it to mean that tenderness is tenderness; that overwhelming grief at
the loss of a young one is overwhelming grief, and is real whether is it "just
chemical" or not. It certainly is real to human mothers. And brain scans of
animals exhibiting the behavioral patterns of depression, for example, show
the animal brain lighting up in the same places they do for depressed
humans.”
36
Conscious awareness of emotions may only be a factor of some
refinement in evolution, in fact a mere matter of an improved connection
between the limbic system and the frontal lobes. As we are aware, in levels
of consciousness in patients following head injuries, the levels descend to
the brain stem as the injury is more serious. Consciousness similarly
descends in complexity and here I am not referring to gross conscious-vunconscious in the absolute awake sense but cognition in general, finetuning and awareness of the environment around. So my doggie “Sadie”, in
her awareness of her emotion, is only lacking a certain ability to express
emotions in a way more akin to mine. This is not to say that she is not as
capable as me of experiencing emotions. Ours are more complex, involving
more far-reaching social contact, and capability of abstraction of ideas which
may give rise to emotions. We will have cause to return to the levels of brain
damage and consciousness in a look at Locked-in-Syndrome, later. We will
also have reason to examine various neurological pathologies in humans as
contributory towards a theory of consciousness.
Grief is really well known in animals. There is the story of one little
dog in Scotland who sat every day by his late master’s grave for 14 years.
An online article by Sarah Hartwell, entitled “Do Cats Have Emotions?
contained the following personal anecdote: “I have personal experience of a
pair of cats whose owner had died. The cats refused to eat while in the
shelter. To reduce stress, they were fostered in a household and the vet
prescribed appetite stimulants. One cat recovered but remained withdrawn
for a long period of time. The other continued to pine and became critically
ill until it had to be euthanized (prolonged fasting results in hepatic lipidosis
or fatty liver disease). Its behaviour was so severely affected that the foster
carer considered force-feeding unsuitable; the cat had no interest in life. Post
mortem showed no sign of disease, except for that caused by failure to eat.”
We do have examples of jealousy and embarrassment from cats and dogs. I
had a dog once called Heidi, and when she was getting older and a little
blind, she failed to recognize me walking down the road one day. She barked
and made to attack, then, on realizing who it was, she suddenly turned
towards a bush at the side of the road and pretended to attack it. It was as if
she was saying “oh sorry I didn’t realize it was you”.
37
Jeffrey Masson, a psychoanalyst turned animal lover and student says
online:
“Elephants, for example, feel grief for the death of other elephants as
deep as our own, and mourn them in particularly poignant ways. There have
been reports of elephants refusing to leave the body of a dead relative, with
some elephants removing the tusks, and hiding them in the jungle, as if they
somehow knew that humans were hunting elephants for their ivory. Young
elephants who had seen their mothers killed in front of them, would often
wake up in the night screaming, evidently from nightmares in which they
relived the trauma they had been through as witnesses of mass murder.”
Masson comments in an online interview about inter-species
friendship, in a story from a mid-west U.S. farmer. She had owned a sheep
which became blind and was helped by a cow:
“The cow had become extremely close to this blind sheep and would
spend all day in her company and would guide the sheep wherever she had
to go. They were inseparable. When the blind sheep finally died the cow
became so distressed that she absolutely refused to move from the spot and
stopped eating. Eventually she too died.”
Marc Bekoff, who has written in detail on animal emotions, illustrates
beautifully how complex animal emotions can be. This is an excerpt from
his book "The Emotional Lives of Animals"
"A few years ago my friend Rod and I were riding our bicycles
around Boulder, Colorado, when we witnessed a very interesting encounter
among five magpies. Magpies are corvids, a very intelligent family of birds.
One magpie had obviously been hit by a car and was laying dead on the side
of the road. The four other magpies were standing around him. One
approached the corpse, gently pecked at it-just as an elephant noses the
carcass of another elephant- (sic) and stepped back. Another magpie did the
same thing. Next, one of the magpies flew off, brought back some grass, and
laid it by the corpse. Another magpie did the same. Then, all four magpies
stood vigil for a few seconds and one by one flew off."(Pg. 1)Bekoff, Marc.
38
The Emotional Lives of Animals. Novato, California: New World Library,
2007.
The famous gorilla Koko was seen to exhibit great grief at the loss
of her pet cat. Humans philosophically make the great leap to other humans,
partly backed up by philosophical arguments such as the attack on private
language by Wittgenstein. We assume what looks like us must think and feel
like us but if it does not look like us then it must be very different. In our
arrogance and stupidity this also lies at the basis of racial discrimination, but
we also use it to rule out "minds" in animals. Of course the old religious
influences raise their heads here as many believers cannot let go of the
concept of human souls and human uniqueness.
Of course we could consider what a Gorilla would be like with a human
brain:-
It is a well accepted notion that dogs are thought to suffer from depressions
and neurosis. Such human emotions as shyness are thought to apply to dogs.
Charles Darwin appeared to have no qualms at dealing openly with
this subject and his book "The Expression of the Emotions in Man and
39
Animals" remains a classic. Whilst he is more concerned to show human
expressions he does refer to how they have evolved from animals and
opened the door to more modern works.
By restricting ourselves to a totally behaviouristic interpretation of
animal expressions we again run the danger of never breaching the gap
between animals and humans. "He looks sad", "he seems to be sad", "He is
sad" is a leap made in humans but rarely in animals, by most of us. We
cannot judge the expression of an emotion on a verbal statement only such
as "I feel sad" because I might be lying. We judge it on a total appraisal of
subjective statements and a coherence of observations. Personally I see no
difficulty in applying the same criteria to animals.
Wittgenstein says :
"In what sense are my sensations private?-- Well, only I can know
whether I am really in pain; another person can only surmise it. --In one way
this is wrong, and in another, nonsense. If we are using the word "to know"
as it is normally used (and how else are we to use it?), then other people very
often know when I am in pain.-- Yes, but all the same not with the certainty
with which I know it myself! --It can't be said of me at all (except perhaps as
a joke) that I know I am in pain. What is it supposed to mean - except
perhaps that I am in pain? ... The truth is: it makes sense to say about other
people that they doubt whether I am in pain; but not to say it about myself."
(Section 246) "Philosophical Investigations."
Ludwig Wittgenstein,
Philosophical Investigations. Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. 3rd ed. Malden,
MA: Blackwell, 2001.
In other words the statement or internal thought "I am in pain" adds
nothing but some further "pain behaviour". (See next chapter also). This
does not mean we have become total behaviourists denying internal life; we
just want to look at it in more subtle ways. Extending this reasoning to
animals is really no problem. It is possible to question Wittgenstein on this
one, from evolution (also see next chapter) where a nervous system may be
developed to react to pain, but the animal may not, in any cogent sense,
"know" that it is in pain. He may choose to argue that his philosophical quest
40
does not extend to animals, but I see no reason that animals cannot study
philosophy! For us to conclude that because we are not bats we cannot
know what is going on inside a bat's mind seems rather naive. I also have no
idea what is going on in any other person's mind, by the same reasoning. The
argument from homology is thin. So although we may not have "private
language" and do communicate quite well, the argument from analogy, or
homology, applies to human-animal interactions as well surely. We
approach that theme several times throughout this book.
Data from the blind-sight experiments in humans, indicates that
patients react in every way as if they know but do not consciously "know".
Once again science and biology may provide food for philosophers. We
went through an era of rigid behaviourism and at about the same time we
were exposed to Logical Positivism, both dead ends. At this time I do not
feel we need to justify the importance of recognizing animals as far closer to
us than we have generally thought. We do need to skip the unconscious
biases and do some creative science.
The argument that if it looks human then it must have selfawareness like me, but the animal is different, is difficult to maintain when
we conjure up some different scenarios. What it you imagine looking at a
person from a very primitive tribe and you are thinking "I wonder if she
thinks at all?" Or if you wandered back through time to a Neanderthal man
and might then wonder if they shared your consciousness or any similar
thought processes. Or again, if you are looking at a seriously autistic child
and have passing thoughts like "I wonder if anyone is home at all?" or a
brain damaged person or someone with advance Alzheimer's where there
often appears to be nobody home. Do we judge them all by this same
standard we apply to animals? But they are human you say! Then what
defines being human?
A true behaviourist would actually be a solipsist, as he would have
to deny thought processes and consciousness in other humans, as beyond
justifiability. Similarly we have seen from the above that even within
humans the differences are of degree of consciousness and it becomes less of
41
a stretch to extend the possibility of conscious thinking, to animals of a
certain complexity. We will not get carried away to the point of embracing
Alfred North Whitehead's notion that plants are capable of feelings and
conscious thought, so the only remaining issue is where to draw the line.
By studying emotions in animals we can close the gap somewhat with regard
to thinking and consciousness also. However pain represents a significant
evolutionary step and the refinement of pain, leading even to emotional pain,
forces us to study pain in animals, to see similarities to our own expressions
of pain. We will examine this area in the following chapter.
42
Chapter VI
Pain in Animals.
Pain can be considered a universal attribute of any animal with a
nervous system of any complexity. But we humans focus so much on pain
that we do need to look at how much other animals experience it, or seem to.
We have mentioned in earlier that fish may not “feel” pain as we do because
they lack the brain structure to “know” that they are in pain. They seemingly
only react with avoidance to noxious substances. It is true that we see in
head injured patients levels of consciousness where only some primitive
avoidance reaction is taking place, and there is a probably valid assumption
that no pain is being felt. We do need to examine this notion a little further
however. The whole philosophical issue of pain may arise again later with
regard to humans. Very simply I can be fairly sure I am in pain but quite
unsure that anyone else at all is in pain. A lot has to be taken for granted. But
it does seem that pain has a primitive basic level and interpretive centre, and,
in addition, a more refined cortical analysis. So pain behaviour may differ
for several different reasons.
There is also a physical and emotional aspect. Generally "emotional
pain" is denied to animals, but that is anthropocentric thinking of the highest
degree. Our mistaken notions of who can feel pain have even been applied to
young humans. Years ago we routinely performed circumcisions on infant
males with no anaesthesia, based on the same mistaken notion that they were
not developed enough to really "feel" pain. I must own up to have performed
my share of those also. We are moving closer to "if it looks like it is
suffering, then it is probably in pain" which is a more humane conclusion in
a world where we are hoping to move closer to our animal relatives and not
see them as objects evolved for our pleasure. Boiling lobsters whilst they are
still alive, strikes me as incredibly cruel, though I am not a vegan (see other
discussion on pain and brain anatomy). I am not sure how I would go about
killing a lobster anyway. My time with the Inuit in the High Arctic taught
me that you can hunt a caribou and still keep respect for it, with certain
rituals to demonstrate that respect. Not that I haven't watched indiscriminate
43
cruelty to wild animals, whilst I lived and worked there. There are no idyllic
races of man.
Pain is primarily detected by nociceptive receptors, even invertebrates
possess these. However their level of response may be only at a stimulusresponse level. They completely lack the higher brain anatomy to process
pain. Vertebrates however process the nociceptive input and can send signals
the other way as well. The medulla, the thalamus and the limbic system are
all involved in assessing pain, in addition to the cortex. Fish only possess a
rudimentary cortex. Thus we assume that fish, at least, are incapable of
emotional pain, grief, sadness etc. Primates, mammals, birds and perhaps
reptiles and amphibians, have a sufficiently developed cortex to warrant the
possibility of emotional pain. It remains for science to find evidence. Some
scientists argue that only primates have the ability to really "feel" pain, as
opposed to simply avoiding a noxious stimulus, and therefore only primates
could be considered conscious.
In humans we may have two levels of response-: an initial withdrawal
from the source of pain, followed by higher level responses, even cortical,
44
such as analysis or conjuring up legal settlements, which immediately make
the pain worse.
(Diagram): illustrates a more complex analysis of pain, whereas in
more primitive nervous systems the animal will only have sub-cortical
stimulus avoidance pathways. Here we see how the brain registers and
feels pain.
One comment on this diagram:- it contains a philosophical error in
that it documents “Pain Sensation IN”. However the sensation of pain is a
cortical judgment, and we do not have pain sensations or an appreciation of
“pain” peripherally. As we have seen above in the discussion on emotions in
animals, there is good evidence, albeit difficult to obtain scientific
verification, that monkeys, cats, dogs and birds can show emotional pain,
grief, etc. They can show depression in its vegetative symptoms of lethargy,
45
lack of motivation, anorexia, depressed sexual drive etc, the same as we
experience in depression in humans and probably due to the same lack of
circulating brain chemicals. As to the argument that we could never really
know that an animal is in pain because they are not like us, once again, it is
necessary to note that I really cannot be sure another human is in pain either.
We are back to the arguments in philosophy as to whether any mind other
than my own exists. If we are that sceptical we are probably misusing
language and the powers of questioning and thought.
An over-emphasis on completely objective scientific and empirical
verification has dominated us for a little too long. We need to pay heed to
qualitative science as well as quantitative. We do not throw out rational
thought with this paradigm change. Even fish, who we would assume are not
“conscious” in our sense of possessing “consciousness”, can remember
approximately 40 individuals and measure size of opponents before deciding
to fight with them. They appear to have a certain sense of their own size.
Limited self-awareness no doubt, but something is there.
What we are trying to emphasize is again differences in degree, not
kind, overall. In terms of pain we tend not to make distinctions amongst
humans but surely science would indicate that we perhaps should. We know
for a fact that certain diseases, such as leprosy, alter the perception of pain,
as do certain drugs. We do not believe lesser intelligence implies less pain
response, but it is commonly thought, and commented on by
anthropologists, that more primitive peoples deal with pain more easily.
After all it was not too long ago that most dental work was done with no
local freezing, now I cannot imagine having that done.
Richard Sarjeant, The Spectrum of Pain. (London: Hart Davis, 1969),
p. 72, says:
"Every particle of factual evidence supports the contention that the
higher mammalian vertebrates experience pain sensations at least as acute as
our own. To say that they feel less because they are lower animals is an
absurdity; it can easily be shown that many of their senses are far more acute
that ours--visual acuity in certain birds, hearing in most wild animals, and
46
touch in others; these animals depend more than we do today on the sharpest
possible awareness of a hostile environment. Apart from the complexity of
the cerebral cortex (which does not directly perceive pain) their nervous
systems are almost identical to ours and their reactions to pain remarkably
similar, though lacking (so far as we know) the philosophical and moral
overtones. The emotional element is all too evident, mainly in the form of
fear and anger."
We have not yet covered the complexity of the embryological
development of the brain. The relevance of this and its connection to notions
of “intelligence” and “consciousness” will be examined in the following
chapter.
47
Chapter VII
Some embryology and the development of the human brain.
For the following embryological and very brief summary, I am
grateful to
Arnold B. Scheibel, MD, professor of Neurobiology and
Psychiatry and former Director of the Brain Research Institute, UCLA
Medical Center, Los Angeles, CA. His online article provided the basis for
my summary.
Ernst Haeckel, a biologist in the 19 th century, came up with the theory
that “Ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny” i.e. that the embryonic phases will
show the evolutionary pattern. Whilst his idea is only accepted with
considerable modifications, it has been a richly creative concept. We will
look at the embryonic brain and its development.
48
The first element of brain to form, embryologically, in humans, is the
notochord, which is thought to recapitulate the transition from invertebrates
to vertebrates. It goes on to form the segmented spinal column, made up of
32 segments or vertebrae. Ectoderm overlying the chord then forms a neural
plate, which develops a fold. As this fold completes its shape it forms a tube,
which will go on to become the nervous system. This lengthens but might
not completely close. There is left an anterior and posterior opening, these
are called neuropores. If the anterior neuropore fails to close, serious
consequences follow, as this portion of the tube forms the cerebral
hemispheres. Thus this defect leads to the awful situation of an anencephalic
baby. The infant is born with no brain above the brain stem. There is
basically no skull above the eyes. It may live up to a week, but usually dies
within hours of birth. Those of us who have delivered such babies will never
forget such an event.
At the distal end, failure to close, leads to the more familiar spina
bifida. The well-known pilonidal cysts, generally form in the tiny residual
tract of a very minor spina bifida (often known as occulta).
After the tube closes successfully, the anterior portion divides into
five vesicles, which become the cerebral hemispheres, diencephalon,
midbrain, pons and cerebellum. Then the walls of the tube form the rest of
the nervous system; ganglia, peripheral nerves etc. The way the cerebral
cortex itself develops is quite fascinating. Layers, i.e. six in total, form with
successive migrations from the outside in. They use radial glial guide cells to
migrate. If the layers do not free themselves from the guide cells, a pile up
and the formation of abnormal neurons results. When mutant mice were
studied with this developmental abnormality, bizarre motor behaviour was
noted. The parallel in human disease is not yet known but it is likely present.
49
The other part of this phase is the formation of temporary connections,
later to be abandoned in favour of more appropriate connections. How this is
decided is unknown, but the abnormal cortical connections made when the
process malfunctions, may result in certain cognitive and emotional
disorders. After the nerve cells reach their destination, they will develop
dendrites and the lengthier axons. Then we see the formation of the
interesting corpus callosum, the only real connection between hemispheres.
As Scheibel says:
“The two hemispheres have differing, though complementary, roles
and it has been speculated that the corpus callosum facilitates the interaction
of these effects. For example, for most of us, specific portions of the left
hemisphere (Broca's and Wernicke's areas) are primarily responsible for the
semantic and computational aspects of language. Corresponding areas of the
right hemisphere are involved in the emotional and prosodic activities and
the interweaving of these two facets of language behavior make for
interesting and comprehensible narration. If activity of the right hemisphere
and its interaction with the left is compromised, either by cortical damage
(e.g. a stroke) or by surgical interruption of the corpus callosal fibers, this
relationship breaks down. Speech then sounds mechanical and flat, without
personal warmth and emotion.”
Work done on so-called split brain has left us with the implication that
if you cut the corpus callosum you may actually form two individual
consciousnesses. This does not explain multiple personalities, which is a
different phenomenon altogether, but does have tremendous philosophical
implications. Are there two "persons"? Is behaviour originating in one side
responsible for the total behaviour of the "person"? (see slightly further on).
The subsequent formation of myelin sheaths has been mentioned
already and speeds up conduction many fold. We have mentioned already
the enormous number of brain cells in the human brain, up to 100,000
million, and each neuron may have 10,000 synaptic connections and across
each connection there may be up to 100 neurotransmitters. Add to that the
parallel processing capabilities of the human brain and you begin to see the
enormous size and functional capability of this biocomputer.
50
However it is worthwhile pointing out the amazing achievements in
intelligent activity of animals with between 10,000 and 100,000 neurons.
This leads us to conclude that as humans, we are only using a very small
percentage of our total horsepower.
(Diagram: general anatomy of human brain.)
Synaptic connections continue to be made throughout the first 6-8 years of a
child’s life and then plateau and decay. There is a numerical decrease after
puberty. This makes you wonder, is that it? Are we just in decline after that?
Well it seems that this decline is a pruning process of unwanted connections.
Remember the discussion of REM sleep and the possible process of weaning
out of connections that it may be used for. This may be a similar process.
Luria, the great Russian neurophysiologist, said that it was forgetting that
was the more important human process in memory, not remembering. He
had a case of a patient who could forget nothing. The patient suffered
intensely and could not function in daily life. All was equally important.
51
Split Brain Theory:
Embryologically humans appear to develop two almost identical
halves of the brain. Then we develop the Corpus Callosum, a bridge between
the two hemispheres. When they are not joined, as they should be, certain
things occur. Over the years we have become familiar with the epoch
making work of Dr. Michael S. Gazzaniga and the split brain. Certain visual
information would no longer pass between brains split at the corpus
callosum. Actually there are several commissures connecting left and right
lobes but the corpus callosum is the main one. Gazzaniga says in the online
publication, 25 years after his initial work:
“If we projected an image to the right visual field - that is, to the left
hemisphere, which is where information from the right field is processed the patients could describe what they saw. But when the same image was
displayed to the left visual field, the patients drew a blank: they said they
didn’t see anything. Yet if we asked them to point to an object similar to the
one being projected, they could do so with ease. The right brain saw the
image and could mobilize a nonverbal response. It simply couldn’t talk
about what it saw.”
He goes on to comment on the main differences between the left and right
hemispheres:
“Ultimately, we discovered that the two hemispheres control vastly different
aspects of thought and action. Each half has its own specialization and thus
its own limitations and advantages. The left brain is dominant for language
and speech. The right excels at visual-motor tasks. The language of these
findings has become part of our culture: writers refer to themselves as leftbrained, visual artists as right-brained.”
Gazzaniga surmises at the end of his summary:
52
“Realizing the strengths and weaknesses of each hemisphere prompted us to
think about the basis of mind, about this overarching organization. After
many years of fascinating research on the split brain, it appears that the
inventive and interpreting left hemisphere has a conscious experience very
different from that of the truthful, literal right brain. Although both
hemispheres can be viewed as conscious, the left brain’s consciousness far
surpasses that of the right. Which raises another set of questions that should
keep us busy for the next 30 years or so.” (sic)
The Split Brain theory does raise the amusing possibility that although
most of the time we seem to function as one person, with one consciousness
we are only a razor blade away from being two people with two
consciousnesses. This lends new meaning to the old saying “I can’t make up
my mind” or “I’m in two minds about ….”
On the issue of split brain and double personalities, we do need to cover
briefly the differences between the two sides of the brain. These are, in
general, well known and we do not need to labour them, but a brief summary
may be helpful in further painting the whole subject of consciousness. The
awareness of this difference came historically from speech losses in stroke
patients.
To quote an online article from an interesting website : "thebigview.com"
edited by Thomas Knierim.
" Clinical evidence suggests that the two sides of the cerebrum serve
different functions. Injuries to the left side usually impair reading, writing,
speaking, calculation, and understanding. Injuries to the right side have less
dramatic effects, but tend to affect spatial perception and movement. More
extensive research has shown that the left and right hemisphere’s
involvement in certain functions is disproportionate.
Left Side Dominance General Function Right Side Dominance
Words
Letters
Vision
Geometric Patterns
Faces
53
Emotional Expression
Language Sounds
Audition
Non-language Sounds
Music
Touch
Tactual Patterns (Braille)
Complex Movement
Movement
Spatial Movement Patterns
Verbal Memory
Memory
Nonverbal Memory
Speech
Reading
Writing
Arithmetic
Language
Emotional Content
Spatial Ability
Geometry
Direction
Distance
Mental Rotation of Shapes
Yet, it would be wrong to speak of compartmentalisation. The hemispheres
of the brain work in tandem as a complex whole. In a famous experiment in
the 1950s, the American neuropsychologist Roger Sperry was involved with
separating the corpus callosum, to treat epileptics. The corpus callosum is a
strand of approx. 200 million nerve fibres connecting the left and right
hemispheres, which the brain uses to transfer signals between the
hemispheres. The patients remained largely normal, but each hemisphere
worked independently. Human split brain patients seemed to have two
independent brains, each with its own abilities, memories, and emotions.
Notably, the left hemisphere of split brain patients was capable of speech,
whereas the right hemisphere was not."
It actually makes sense when one thinks about the reasons for having
“two brains”. Many internal organs are duplicated for safety. If you lose one
kidney it is really not that serious. The two do the same thing. But it would
be a waste if both sides of the brain could not be of use. And they do need to
communicate so we have the corpus callosum. Yet the degree of integration
54
is such that splitting this connection does tend to create two virtual new
identities.
We may have reason to return to some embryological principles in
discussing psychological and neurological diseases later. For now we need
to move on to a discussion of what “consciousness” might mean and to what
animals we might apply the term.
Does brain size relate to consciousness or even intelligence?
Seemingly from brain size alone, the whales would win. However given
ratios of body size to brain humans are at 2.1% whereas a Sperm Male is
0.02% but a dolphin is 0.94%. An interesting example, of the brain size to
body size ratio, is the spiny anteater (an egg laying mammal, related to the
duck-billed platypus), which has a neocortex (the so-called 'modern' part of
the brain, which is greatly developed in primates and humans) relatively
larger than that of a human. Yet nobody has so far put forward any claims
for superior
"intelligence" in spiny anteaters. In an article “Brains,
Behaviour and Intelligence in Cetaceans (Whales, Dolphins and
Porpoises)” published by High North in 1994, Margaret Klinowska at
Cambridge University notes that even the cortical folding does not equate to
“brain power” or intelligence. Bottlenose dolphins, horses and chimpanzees
all have more convolutions than we do. As cetacean ancestors returned to the
oceans some 70 MYA and the new mammalian brain of land mammals
seems to have evolved 50 MYA the poor dolphin missed out on certain
55
developments. One particular layer in the neocortex is missing, according to
Klinowska, yet its function remains uncertain.
(Diagram: comparative brain sizes-- not allowing for animal size)
One most intriguing theory, quoted by the same author, is from some studies
indicating that REM or rapid-eye-movement sleep may serve an important
function called “reverse-learning” in which the brain during sleep removes
certain annoying neuronal connections. Dolphins and Spiny Anteaters have
large brains but perhaps need larger brains because the cerebral parking
space is overloaded with stuff they cannot remove as they apparently do not
dream! Now I understand my professor at medical school who advised me to
56
be cognizant of limited cerebral parking space. He must have been warning
me to quit partying and get some REM sleep.
We have examined some embryology and relative brain to body size
ratios and now we need to move on to looking at the actual substrata of
consciousness, the actual structure of the brain.
This part is quite technical and is included for those interested in
seeing in more detail the substrate of consciousness, but the single lesson for
those wishing to skim the chapter is to note how complex consciousness
really is and how dependent on many areas in the brain working together as
an integrated whole system.
57
Chapter VIII
Division and Function of the parts of the Brain.
We need to look closer at the anatomy and function of the human brain
because an understanding of the complexity is crucial to the total
physiological theory of consciousness being proposed.
Hindbrain
Myencephalon:
1.
Medualla
Metencephalon:
1. Pons
2. Cerebellum
The hind brain is mainly a
continuation of the spinal cord
and contains all the ascending
and descending fibres
connecting the brain and spinal
cord. We will see in the next
chapter how this level becomes, as it were, the gateway of consciousness.
Damage at the hindbrain level can paralyze the body but leaves
consciousness intact. Damage above this level erodes consciousness.
Mesencephalon or Midbrain
Small but crucial area of the brain with two subdivisions:
1.
2.
Tectum (dorsal; marks the top of the mesencephalon)
Tegmentum (ventral; marks the bottom of the mesencephalon)
Two main areas in the Tectum are the Inferior (auditory) and Superior
Colliculi (visual). Now, interestingly enough, in humans these are gates and
controllers to visual cortical areas, yet in earlier species they represented the
58
only “visual cortex”.
Tegmentum is the area below the tectum. This area is concerned with reflex
pathways and perhaps whether someone remains unconscious or conscious
and it also controls certain homeostatic pathways i.e. biochemical balance.
Primary structures in the midbrain:
1.
Substantia Nigra
a. Key source of dopameric neurones. The connection to DOPA
has led many to speculate that not only Parkinson’s Disease
comes from degeneration in this area, but also Schizophrenia.
The substantia nigra is plays a critical role in controlling eye
movement, motor planning, reward seeking, learning, and
addiction.
b. PAG (Periaqueductal Grey):- an area of growing interest as
lesions here have a serious effect on consciousness. It refers to
an area surrounding the aqueduct in the midbrain. It is a key
source of opiate receptors/ binding.
59
2.
Red nucleus
The Red nucleus is almost considered to be vestigial. Critically
important in other mammals, it now, in humans, seems to be
more of an informant, between the motor cortex and the
cerebellum
Diencephalon- part of the forebrain
Primary Structures:
1.
2.
Thalamus
Hypothalamus
(1) Thalamus
• Large group of nuclei
located anterior and
dorsal to the
midbrain
• Relay station for the
majority of the sensory
information that
projects to the cerebral
cortex. Thus it can
control arousal, sleep,
visual information,
auditory data.
60
(2) Hypothalamus
The hypothalamus regulates many ‘primitive functions’ including the
response to stress. It also has a key role in motivational behaviour (making
us find food, water), including sexual behaviour. In addition it houses at
least some ‘body clocks’. Although the hypothalamus is a small area it is
extremely important behaviourally. It regulates the activity of the pituitary
gland
Mammillary bodies: These represent specific hypothalamic nuclei. These are
two fascinating little bodies that are attached to the underside of the brain.
What they control is very important as they process memory, specifically
recognition memory (mine must be failing!) and are thought possibly to add
some degree of smell to memories. This is really interesting as there are
people whose memory is essentially linked to smell and who see names as a
smell or taste.
The Telencephalon:- the forebrain
This area is the most recent in the phylogenetic sense.
Primary Structures:
1.
2.
The limbic system and basal ganglia
The cerebral cortex including the hippocampus
(1) The Limbic system
(From limbus, meaning ring)
The limbic system seems to be involved in the fours Fs: Feeding, fighting,
fleeing and sexual behaviour. It is thought to be the centre of our emotional
make up. The Limbic and Basal Ganglia are primary for: emotion,
aggressive behaviour, fear, pleasure and several key aspects of personality.
Some components of the limbic system are:
61
• Hippocampus--converts short term memory into long term memory
• amygdala-- this plays a response role, centre for rage and anger,
damage here may cause indifference to fear, anger and sexual
pleasure.
• The thalamus itself is a regulator of sleep and wakefulness, levels of
awareness and thus consciousness levels.
Basal Ganglia
Main Structures
•
•
•
•
•
•
Caudate nucleus
Putamen
Globus Pallidus
Subthalamus
Amygdala
(substantia Nigra)--plays a role in reward, addiction and also
movement function (Parkinson's).
62
Broadly speaking, these areas deal with information from the cerebral
cortex, analyse it and return it to the cortex, through the thalamus. They also,
in conjunction with the cerebellum, coordinate voluntary movement.
Damage to the Basal Ganglia is associated with Huntington’s and
Parkinson’s disease.
“The basal ganglia are regarded as sub-cortical nuclear complexes that play
a critical role in the integration of motor activity” (Noback, 1996).
“Overall, there is growing evidence that alterations in basal ganglia circuits
with non-motor areas of cortex occur in a wide variety of neuropsychiatric
disorders, including not only schizophrenia and obsessive-compulsive
disorder, but also depression, Tourette’s syndrome, autism, and attention
deficit disorder..” Middleton and Strick (2000)
63
To describe the function of the Basal Ganglia as a whole, would take a
textbook, and that is only what we know about it at present. It does however
appear to play a critical role as an arbiter, a decision maker, about which
potential actions, that the cortex is planning, should be executed. The role of
Dopamine as a reward system in training the basal ganglia, as to which
actions should be rewarded, is yet to be analysed. Also the BG play a
specific role in planning and coordination of specific movement sequences
as well as temporal sequencing.
The role in fine movement has been studied by Hikosaka, Takikawa,
and Kawagoe in "Role of the Basal Ganglia in the Control of Purposive
Saccadic Eye Movements" Physiological Reviews Vol. 80, No3 July 2000
pp. 953-978. The authors conclude that the BG control eye movement with
two kinds of output-:
(1) control over the thalamo-cortical networks
(2) control over the brain stem motor networks.
The Saccade movement is a purposive rapid eye movement, damage
to this mechanism results in the fixed stare of the Parkinsonian patient. The
BG appear to select the appropriate drive by control of tonic inhibition.
To further illustrate the immense complexity and subtlety of our notion of
consciousness we can look at the connecting pathways involved in the
Substantia Nigra. Taken from Wikipedia, article on Substantia Nigra.
64
froM COftf'XI
OhiiiiiiUde'llt
(tlll:lllb)
....
....
Diagram: Circuits of the basal ganglia.
65
The diagram shows 2 coronal slices that have been superimposed to
include the involved basal ganglia structures. + and - signs at the point of the
arrows indicate respectively whether the pathway is excitatory or inhibitory
in effect. Green arrows refer to excitatory glutamatergic pathways, red
arrows refer to inhibitory GABAergic pathways and turquoise arrows refer
to dopaminergic pathways that are excitatory on the direct pathway and
inhibitory on the indirect pathway. Note that dis-inhibitory pathways in
effect are excitatory on the feedback to the cortex, while dis-dis-inhibitory
pathways in effect are inhibitory.
Note the incredible complexity of pathways, and that this part of the
brain controls some fine movement yet malfunction leads to Parkinson's
tremor and even on to a psychosis! The point once again is to illustrate how
delicate the balance of a normal consciousness is. Furthermore the point is to
show that functionally we are more and more able to break down the
complexity of personality, human consciousness and the total mystery of the
human being into comprehensible portions. I am not saying there will be no
mystery left but we are making progress. By bringing together all the
subjects studied in this book I am hoping to make the subject of
consciousness far more of a comprehensible object of study. What we are
looking at directly in this somewhat technical chapter is the functioning of
consciousness in action, bit by bit.
66
(2) The Cerebral Cortex.
The cerebral cortex in the human.
(Diagram of Cerebral Cortex.)
Functional breakdown:
Parietal Lobe - involved in the reception and processing of sensory
information from the body.
Frontal Lobe - involved with decision-making, problem solving, and
planning.
67
Function:
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Motor Functions
Higher Order Functions
Planning
Reasoning
Judgement
Impulse Control
Memory
Occipital Lobe - involved with interpreting visual data.
Temporal Lobe - involved with memory, emotion, hearing, and language.
We have seen throughout this chapter a lot of detail. This is to
illustrate the complexity of the concept of "consciousness" and show part of
the enormous necessary substrate. Much of this detail could be passed over,
if it seems confusing, yet it is showing again and again the necessary links to
the notion of consciousness.
The development of the cortex itself seems to be the critical element
which raises our level of consciousness and self-awareness to a higher
degree than the more "advanced primates". Yet we are still looking at
differences of degrees. It is also critical to point out that we are attempting
to show a picture of a complex mechanism that functions holistically. We
cannot break the brain into little centres as we have tended to do in the past.
We can begin to localize functions, but that by no means entails that a
certain area is the centre for that whole function. The plasticity and multifunctionality of the brain is critical. As Luria, the Russian neurophysiologist
indicated, the brain cells are pluripotential. Furthermore, to reiterate a
point made earlier, we have to examine the c o m p l e t e functioning
68
animal to examine consciousness, we cannot even localise it into the brain,
although we are seeing specific levels where it can be altered. That is an
anatomical breakdown. When it comes to the physiological animal, we still
need to think of chemical alterations in the body as affecting consciousness.
For instance, alterations in blood sugar levels, fever and its effect on
the brain function, mind-altering drugs, even such things as fatigue-induced
hallucinations.
So it is time to examine some further issues with levels of
consciousness and begin to open up the examination to philosophical
overtones. Are there absolutely critical anatomical levels where
consciousness is determined?
69
Chapter IX
Definitions of Levels of Consciousness and a discussion on Locked-in
Syndrome and preliminary philosophical discussion.
It is considered obvious, but it is still interesting to contemplate the
role of sleep in the development of consciousness and also to examine the
evolution of sleep through the animal kingdom. Sleep is primarily controlled
in the hypothalamus, i.e. in the limbic system and does appear to have an
important role in synaptic health. Again we have the notion of REM sleep
and its function in maintaining synaptic health. Learning appears to continue
during sleep, possibly by cleaning our cerebral parking space. REM sleep
may have a role in "reverse-learning" by eliminating certain neuronal
connections made during waking hours. We refer to this later. Luria refers to
the critical importance of forgetting. Warm-blooded animals sleep, most
cold-blooded vertebrates just rest. The cold-blooded ones that do sleep, have
no REM sleep. Sleep is also known to enhance the immune system and
several experiments have shown this. All in all, sleep is a development in
warm-blooded creatures with more developed frontal lobes and cortices in
general.
As far as consciousness is concerned we need some starting definitions:What practical definitions can we work with? The sense of responding to
one’s environment and being aware of the environment, approaches the
sense we generally mean by consciousness. Making decisions based on input
is obvious. But simply “being aware” of one’s environment and reacting to it
over and above simple reflexes does not quite reach the sense of selfawareness we want to deal with. Then there is being aware of a sensation,
say a red patch, or a sound. Almost all animals possess this to varying
degrees. Finally there is thinking about thinking or self-awareness. This may
turn out to be a delusion. It could either be a self-referential dead end, or
simply an unanswerable question. What preceded the Big Bang or
Singularity, or what happens after infinity, are all examples of questions that
we just don’t need to ask really. If consciousness in general is simply an
70
emergent property of brain development, the notion of self-awareness may
be either a meditational delusion or a linguistic creation. Or, perhaps, going
back to the sensory blocking theory, it is a method of heightening sensory
awareness by removing blocking distractions. By emergent we would mean
that the properties of the whole are now predicated by prior knowledge of
the structure and properties of the parts. Now this does not mean that
different laws of physics apply, just different laws of behaviour for the
whole over its parts. We will have cause in the final chapter to refer to a
detailed biological theory of consciousness.
In his famous paper of 1974, Thomas Nagel wrote about “What it is
like to be a Bat?” and concluded that we will never, nor can ever know.
However there is “batness” albeit only known to a bat. This subject has
come up before but is of critical importance, as it has traditionally offered
such a stumbling block.
(Diagram: what it is like to be a bat?)
71
As previously mentioned, I am not sure that the same argument does not
apply to other humans, i.e. other than me. There is a similarity of appearance
and so by analogy I assume I know what it is like to be a human being, but I
am not sure that I could ever say that I know what it is like to be another
human being. So in fact by analogy I may know a little bit about what it is
like to be a bat. If indeed “consciousness”, in the advanced self-aware state,
is an emergent property of neural structure, then we would expect animals to
possess something similar to what we have. Language may be the most
significant factor in confusing the whole issue. Again we must bear in mind
that it may introduce confusing aspects. Words, which may possess meaning
in a certain context, may become meaningless when strung together in
another way i.e. another sentence. An invisible pink hippopotamus sounds
like a normal existent grammatically, but would really to all intents and
purposes appear totally meaningless. A large part of philosophy is most
likely similar to this and I should not do it anymore but I enjoy it.
It may in fact be some time before we can come up with a workable
definition of consciousness and we may have to form some ground-based
theories of qualitative scientific research and go on to explore those before
we can say much more. We have commented before on the mirror-image
recognition of certain chimpanzees and it is also apparent that bottlenose
dolphins have a fairly evident self-awareness from mirror images. Even if
we add emotions to the basic concept we know that we have seen
considerable emotional response in many animals. We will leave all
discussion of souls to theologians as this is strictly an attempt at rational
enquiry. If we are worried about animals and free will, then one only has to
come and watch “Wagstaff” my cat, as she hovers on the front doorstep, in
the morning, trying to make the awfully difficult decision as to whether she
should go out for a little fresh air. She sits there and says “I know I can
either stay in or go out, I know he wants me out of his way for a while so he
can write his stupid philosophy, but I will exercise my free will and then
make a choice. I know I require 12 degrees centigrade and I am not quite
sure if the sun is warm enough yet – oh what the hell I may as well go out
for a while anyway”. There is as much free will as I have in deciding
72
whether to have another pint of beer before leaving the squash club- in fact
that is probably pre-determined.
Firstly we must of course distinguish awake from asleep, or coma.
Some of my lecturers in medical school evidenced extreme difficulty in this
distinction, amongst their students. I am paraphrasing from an article by
James L Bernat "Chronic Consciousness Disorders" Ann Rev Med 2009
60:381-92. One major advance to the biological study of consciousness has
been fMRI (Functional MRI) and PET (Positron Emission Tomography)
scans. In unresponsive patients fMRI has shown evidence of conscious
awareness when neurological exam was unable to do so. Consciousness
consists of wakefulness and awareness. For wakefulness we require a
functioning brain stem reticular system and certain connections. Awareness
of self is at a slightly higher level in the thalamic nuclei and cortical and
subcortical connections. Obviously a lower lesion destroying wakefulness
will remove awareness also.
Coma is a state with neither awareness nor wakefulness. Temporary
response to stimuli is called stupor with resumption of coma when the
stimulus is removed. Patients can recover from coma after hours, or weeks,
but if they do not they either die or enter a Vegetative State (VS). In this
state there is usually wakefulness but no awareness of self. In VS the
damage is at the level of the thalamus but not the reticular activating system.
Minimal Conscious State (MCS) patients exhibit impaired
responsiveness but some awareness of self, they may gaze at moving targets
and even say a few words, plus some response to questions. The damage
level is the same as for VS but less severe. These are both potential recovery
states.
In a later chapter we will have to become very detailed and illustrate a
variety of neurological disorders. The purpose of that is to add to the
physiological normal mechanisms of consciousness, which we have already
covered, and then to show the enormous variations of consciousness that
arise from disease. We are still examining different levels of consciousness,
73
to illustrate the incredible complexity of the concept. With knowledge of the
vast number of syndromes where the functioning of consciousness goes
wrong, we gain insight into what consciousness actually is. We may still not
reach a definition, but we will have an understanding. Locked-in-Syndrome
provides one of the most intriguing glimpses into what level of brain injury
actually is a kind of gateway to the whole concept of consciousness.
Locked-in Syndrome
This is one of the most fascinating and sad conditions known to us.
LIS shows us where the very gateway of consciousness is located. It is not
actually a disorder of consciousness at all. That is what makes it interesting.
Awareness and wakefulness are intact, although the patient may have
tremendous difficulties communicating. PET scans and fMRI (functional
MRI) do show some diagnostic signs although they are essentially normal,
showing considerable activity. There is total paralysis except for upper eyelid
and vertical eye movement. fMRI has begun to be predictive in VS
(Vegetative State), a most encouraging discovery. Bernat concludes his
article by positing that we may move away from more clinical diagnoses of
consciousness disorders to a pathophysiological model.
In LIS we have a very distinct level of damage, although some
patients even lose the minimal movement available to other patients, which
must be even more torture. It is caused by a brain stem lesion, often due to
infarction (arterial damage) in the area of the Pons in the brain stem.
Traumatic Brain Injury, various medication overdoses, stroke involving the
basilar artery, even a pontine myelinolysis (breakdown of the myelin sheath,
due to sudden over correction of sodium deficiency), may all cause this
condition.
The olfactory nerve is not a true cranial nerve but part of the brain
technically. The optic nerve also does not join the brainstem and is therefore
somewhat spared in this damage. A small part of the oculomotor, or 3rd
cranial nerve, is most often spared also. This innervates the Levator
74
Palpebrae, the muscle which raises the eyelid. This is really quite interesting
from an evolutionary and embryological sense, and shows the extreme
importance of vision. The anatomy here explains the lesion and the
consequences and also has tremendous implications for “consciousness”. So
we do have to go into a little anatomical detail.
The above diagram illustrates how the level of the lesion may spare the first
three "cranial" nerves (olfactory, optic and oculomotor). The optic nerve
actually arises from an outpouching of the diencephalon and is covered in
myelin rather than the Schwann cells of more peripheral nerves. It is thus
part of the brain truly. The Oculomotor nerve (Cr. N. III) arises from the
midbrain and is also spared in this condition. It has two nuclei.
• The oculomotor nucleus originates at the level of the superior
colliculus. The muscles it controls are the striated muscle in
levator palpebrae superioris and all extraocular muscles
except for the superior oblique muscle and the lateral rectus
75
muscle.
• The Edinger-Westphal nucleus supplies parasympathetic fibres to the
eye via the ciliary ganglion, and thus controls the sphincter pupillae
muscle (affecting pupil constriction) and the ciliary muscle (affecting
accommodation). These are generally intact in LIS.
The oculomotor nerve has two divisions:
In L.I.S. the Levator palpebrae works and also the rectus superior, so the
patient can look up and move the eyelid. The lower root of the nerve
(Inferior division) is usually damaged.
76
Detailed diagram of rectal muscles, illustrating where the paralysis in
L.I.S. occurs:- only 2 and 9 is spared.
Rectus muscles:
2 = superior, 3 = inferior, 4 = medial, 5 = lateral
Oblique muscles: 6 = superior, 8 = inferior
Other muscle: 9 = levator palpebrae superioris
Other structures: 1 = Annulus of Zinn, 7 = Trochlea, 10 = Superior tarsus,
11 = Sclera, 12 = Optic nerve
2 and 9 will remain working but little else. Yet this patient remains fully
conscious and fully self aware though with total paralysis essentially.
Everything below this is paralysed, thus effectively cutting these poor
patients off almost totally from all sensory and motor interaction with the
"outside" world. This does indicate pretty well exactly where consciousness
arises in the brain, in the sense of levels only, and does enable us to start a
pretty good working definition of consciousness.
To discuss normal consciousness we require a functioning brain above the
pons, a balanced chemical environment in the body as a whole, especially in
the brain. We also need a thousand small pathways and centres of function
to be working fairly normally. The list of neurological disorders shown in
Chapter X illustrates just how critical small areas of function are. So we
cannot call consciousness any one thing and we will only now move ahead
77
in physiology as we tease out more and more functional aspects of
consciousness.
There arises a need to distinguish consciousness as a biological entity from
self-awareness in the sense used by philosophers. Self-awareness, putting it
simply, gives rise to the "Hard Problem" referred to by Chalmers, i.e. the
self-awareness issue. Now it is incredibly complex and there are some
thought experiments we could carry out of an anthropological philosophical
nature. Imagine a very primitive species of man for a moment. Not that long
out of the trees, as we say, and involved in very basic survival, but with
some primitive language developments. Probably he does not have words as
we know them, and certainly not more than pictographs. But this urge to
communicate is there, along with the desire to communicate more than the
pictograph. Presumably then there is now an evolutionary advantage (i.e.
natural selection) in a better expression of the dangers or the food supply or
expressing an emotion for a partner, but to imagine thinking as we know it
or even self-awareness, as we describe it, is difficult.
Fast-forward to early civilization, perhaps 10,000 to 15,000 BCE and
we can know about, and imagine, more thinking ability, development of
some primitive languages, and we can start imagining where the evolution of
consciousness has got us. So where the biological entity of consciousness
evolves, the issue of when self-awareness can be said to have evolved, may
never be answered, but again, at a certain level of consciousness, selfawareness may also evolve and still be biological. But to have a concept of
self-awareness need not lead to dualism by the back door. It may be totally
created by the misuse of language. If we believe that, then we are partly
avoiding the philosophical dilemma by saying the "I-Thou" dichotomy
is perhaps invented, delusionary, a linguistic invention and in fact, a
categorical error if we imply it means anything meaningful.
Let us leave for now the preliminary discussion on consciousness, and
pass on to pathology, and see if we cannot gain some contribution from
disorders of brain/mind. I want to show that “consciousness” as I understand
78
it is a phenomenon derived from the evolving brain and depending on the
normal function of a great many parts of the brain. So, diminished cortical
function, a damaged hypothalamus or amygdaloid nucleus will actually alter
the consciousness of the affected person. It may well alter during the diurnal
cycle, or under drugs, or with depression also.
79
Chapter X
Varieties of consciousness, neurological disorders that shed light on a
theory of consciousness.
Just as William James considered varieties of religious experience, we
want to consider varieties of consciousness. We are often debating whether
we think primarily in words or pictures and the answers vary a great deal.
Thomas Grandin, of Colorado State University, in an online article (1998)
(Ibid), discusses his primary method of thinking being pictorial. He quickly
adds that this is because he is autistic. He gives the example of how he was
able to think his way out of a car accident by his pictorial analysis:
“The near-accident occurred in fairly light traffic on a sunny day
while I was driving to the airport on Interstate highway 25. Cruising along at
70 miles per hour in the southbound lane, I suddenly saw a huge bull elk
running full speed across the northbound lanes. I knew I had to react quickly
to avoid hitting him. Instantly, three pictures appeared in my mind. Each
picture represented the end result of an option available to me. The first
picture was of a car rear-ending my car. I knew from experience that
slamming on the brakes could cause this. The next picture was the elk
smashing through my windshield. From my understanding of animal
behavior, I knew that swerving or any sudden movement of my car might
cause the elk to stop or slow down. The third picture was of the elk passing
harmlessly in front of my car. In this picture I saw what would happen if I
gently applied the brakes to slow down. These pictures were like the picture
menus one can click on an Internet web page. They appeared in my mind
one at a time, but all within one second. This was enough time for me to
selectively compare the options and choose the slow down gradually picture.
I immediately calculated the elk's trajectory and speed coming across the
highway, and my speed and position in the southbound lane, and began to
slowly apply the brakes. This choice prevented me from being rear ended, or
having the elk crash through my windshield. The conscious choice was a
visual process without the use of internal verbal dialog. At the moment I
became aware of the elk crossing the northbound lane, I resisted the urge to
80
make a panic response and slam on the brakes. In just seconds, I evaluated
the three pictures in my mind. To use computer jargon, I conducted a basic
cost-benefit analysis of the options. After running a quick video like
simulation of the elk passing harmlessly in front of my car, I simply clicked
a mental mouse on the "slowing down gradually" picture. I made a
conscious choice from visual simulations played in my mind”.
Grandin goes on to say that it might take 0.5 secs to process a
conscious reaction over an unconscious instinctive response. He also talks
about the increasing complexity of consciousness notions from insects
onwards:
“Moving up the evolutionary ladder from insects, many biological
scientists agree that mammals and birds have primary consciousness because
they can process simultaneous stimuli and they have an internal
representation of their experiences. Svene Sjolander states that a snake may
not be conscious because it does not have a centralized representation of its
prey. It seems to live in a world where a mouse is many different things.
Sjolander explains that striking the mouse is controlled by vision; following
the mouse after striking is controlled by smell; and swallowing the mouse is
controlled strictly by touch. There is no integration of information from all
the senses. Each sensory channel operates independently of the others. When
a snake has a mouse held in its coils, it may still search for the mouse as if
"the information from its body which is holding the prey did not exist." It
appears that the snake has no ability to transfer information between sensory
channels. Sjolander further explains that a snake has no ability to anticipate
that a mouse running behind a rock will reappear. Cats and other predatory
mammals are able to anticipate that the prey will reappear. According to
Sjolander, snakes are therefore not conscious.”
81
(Diagram: conscious snake?)
Now I am not sure his conclusion is justified, as a certain vagueness creeps
in. Where can consciousness be said to begin if we agree that animals differ
in degree but not kind? I do not have much difficulty in saying a stone is not
conscious, although it may be hard to explain exactly why to a philosopher,
but not to anyone of normal intelligence. A virus or bacteria also lack all
neural structures, but once there is an actual brain we may be only dealing
with degrees of consciousness from there on. So even the snake may possess
consciousness, just at a degree we have not yet been able to define.
Grandin states that because he himself lacks verbal abstraction he
actually possesses a lower form of consciousness than people with language.
Brutally honest he may be, but even within the realms of linguistically
enabled people there are such vast differences that he does not need to be
humble about it at all. The higher consciousness of an Aristotle, Newton,
Einstein, Russell, to name but a few, puts all of our higher brain functions to
shame by comparison. In 1000 years time we may see significant evolution
of consciousness. We shall perhaps come back to the idea of how our own
culture i.e. humankind may have evolved over the 10,000 years we have
been socialized, and whether there is a sense of an advancing consciousness.
82
Now we need to dive into some technicality and take a preliminary
look at a number of neurological disorders which detract from consciousness
in some way. Then we can gradually see “consciousness” as requiring all
these functional substrata. We will start with the most recent part of the
cortex, the frontal lobes.
Frontal Lobe Syndrome is damage to the frontal lobes through
tumour or more commonly head injury. Again this becomes part of the
theory that consciousness is a functioning whole human being, with parts of
the brain as sine quibus non for that functioning. Emotions, ability to
perceive, reflect and act accordingly, ability to abstract, will all be part of the
advanced consciousness. Add to that the ability to play, to imagine future
and past experiences and recreate “in the mind’s eye” as well as to
coordinate all of these functions together and we have human beings, but
should we necessarily exclude animals from having these functions? I do not
think so and we may not find any one animal with all, but we also find a
large number of human beings with one or more aspect missing. So we have
a hierarchy of consciousness. I am quite comfortable with that. We are not
able to say any one disorder necessarily has a significant effect on altering
consciousness or personhood but it may.
83
The frontal lobes are divided into Precentral cortex, prefrontal cortex
and orbito-frontal cortex. These areas communicate with the thalamus,
caudate nucleus, putamen, hypothalamus, amygdala, hippocampus and
septal areas. So the frontal lobes definitely have a pre-eminent
communication with the limbic system. The rest of the complete cortex also
has a two-way communication with the frontal lobes. Some have said this is
the orchestra conductor. Luria, the great Russian physiologist, said that the
frontal lobes “regulated” mental or cortical activities. The dorsolateral
frontal cortex controls response inhibition, and patients with lesions in this
area have disinhibition, emotional lability, in addition to memory problems.
Frontal lobe lesions lead to personal neglect, sociopathy, emotional
neutrality, lack of ambition, lack of attentiveness and lack of creativity. The
most famous of these cases was over 100 years ago. Phineas Gage, a railway
worker, sustained an iron rod though his frontal lobe and was not even
unconscious with the injury. His personality was profoundly changed
84
however. Psychosurgery was popular in the last century but fell into
disrepute after too many lobotomies were performed, many with quite
disastrous results. However many patients with advanced paranoid
schizophrenia were helped. Psychosurgery will almost certainly creep back
in, with better ethical standards one hopes and less primitive methodology.
The essential role of the prefrontal cortex in consciousness may be an
absolute in the sense of a necessary pre-requisite to full consciousness.
There is a certain element of pre-frontal self-awareness, emanating from this
area, with a higher control ordering of anticipation, goal selection,
monitoring of behaviour, i.e. feedback and self-criticism. In addition
selectivity of material presented and control of reaction may all be higher
cortical functions of the frontal lobe without with consciousness becomes
meaningless. Add to that, that the functionality of lower levels of the brain is
still necessary, especially the limbic system in general, and you can, see the
start of a certain global concept of consciousness. We are attacking the
notion that consciousness remains a mystery, bit by bit.
Neurological disorders and their relationship to what consciousness may
be and to what defines a person.
We shall examine an eclectic number of disorders because I am
building a case towards a theory of consciousness which involves knowing
what full function might be. This list is not meant to be inclusive and only
some of the disorders or deficits which may have an effect on consciousness,
or the sense of person, are included. I will focus on diseases or conditions
which appear directly related to specific functions as it might then become
apparent what consciousness may be, in addition to a sense of personhood. I
thank Wikipedia for some of these brief summaries of neurological
disorders. Once again, I must apologize for that, but living 8 hours drive
from good libraries, forces certain choices.
The reason that there are so many complex disorders included here is
simple. I should have put a far larger number. These are only some of the
neurological disorders which directly have an effect on consciousness. Each
85
little defect (though not little to a patient) may alter and diminish the level of
consciousness in that person, to the point that the definition of that human
being as a person is called into question.
Abarognosis: is a loss of the ability to detect the weight of an object held in
the hand or to tell the difference in weight between two objects. This deficit
may be caused by damage to the parietal lobe on the side of the brain
opposite of the deficit.
Agenesis of the Corpus Callosum (ACC) is a rare birth defect (congenital
disorder) in which there is a complete or partial absence of the corpus
callosum. Characteristics common in individuals with callosal disorders
include vision impairments, low muscle tone, poor motor coordination,
delays in sitting and walking, low perception of pain, delayed toilet training,
and chewing and swallowing difficulties. Laboratory research has
demonstrated that individuals with ACC have difficulty transferring more
complex information from one hemisphere to the other. They also have been
shown to have some cognitive disabilities (difficulty in complex problem
solving) and social difficulties (missing subtle social cues), even when their
Intelligence Quotient is normal. Recent research suggests that specific social
difficulties may be a result of impaired face processing. Perhaps more
interesting is that many of these children go on to essentially normal lives.
Agnosia is a loss of ability to recognize objects, persons, sounds, shapes, or
smells while the specific sense is not defective nor is there any significant
memory loss. It is usually associated with brain or neurological illness,
particularly after damage to the occipitotemporal border, which is part of the
ventral stream. This usually happens with strokes, dementia, or tumours, or
infection, some are hereditary. The list of diseases or subdivisions of agnosia
is extensive and includes:
86
Name
Description
Alexia
Inability to recognize text.
Akinetopsia
The loss of motion perception.
Alexithymia
While not strictly a form of agnosia, Alexithymia may be
difficult to distinguish from or co-occur with socialemotional agnosia. Alexithymia is deficiency in
understanding, processing, or describing emotions
common to around 85% of people on the autism spectrum.
Alexithymia is believed to be due to an information
processing delay in the combined processing of
information in the left and right hemispheres, resulting in
poor differentiation between body messages and emotions.
AmusiaReceptive
amusia
Is agnosia for music. It involves loss of the ability to
recognize musical notes, rhythms, and intervals and the
inability to experience music as musical.
Anosognosia
This is the inability to gain feedback about one's own
condition and can be confused with lack of insight but is
caused by problems in the feedback mechanisms in the
brain. It is caused by neurological damage and can occur in
connection with a range of neurological impairments but is
most commonly referred to in cases of paralysis following
stroke. Those with Anosognosia with multiple impairments
may even be aware of some of their impairments but
completely unable to perceive others. This is a critical loss
87
of function in consciousness.
Apperceptive
agnosia
Apraxia
Associative
agnosia
Patients are unable to distinguish visual shapes and so have
trouble recognizing, copying, or discriminating between
different visual stimuli. Unlike patients suffering from
associative agnosia, those with apperceptive agnosia are
unable to copy images.
Apraxia is a form of motor (body) agnosia involving the
neurological loss of ability to map out physical actions in
order to repeat them in functional activities. It is a form of
body-disconnectedness and takes several different forms: Speech-Apraxia in which ability to speak is impaired,
Limb-Kinetic Apraxia in which there is a loss of hand or
finger dexterity and can extend to the voluntary use of
limbs. In Ideomotor Apraxia the gestures of others can't be
easily replicated and patients are unable to execute goaldirected movements. Ideational Apraxia leads to an
inability to work out which actions to initiate and struggles
to plan and discriminate between potential gestures.
Apraxia of Gait in which co-ordination of leg actions is
problematic and it is difficult to kick a ball, Constructional
Apraxia causes a person to be unable to co-ordinate the
construction of objects or draw pictures or follow a design,
Oculomotor Apraxia causes the ability to control visual
tracking is impaired.
Patients can describe visual scenes and classes of objects
but still fail to recognize them. They may, for example,
know that a fork is something you eat with but may
mistake it for a spoon. Patients suffering from associative
agnosia are still able to reproduce an image through
88
copying.
Auditory
agnosia
With Auditory Agnosia there is difficulty distinguishing
environmental and non-verbal auditory cues including
difficulty distinguishing speech from non-speech sounds
even though hearing is usually normal.
Is associated with the inability to orient parts of the body,
Autotopagnosia and is often caused by a lesion in the parietal part of the
posterior thalamic radiations.
Refers to the inability to recognize a color, while being
Color agnosia able to perceive or distinguish it. I don't think Wittgenstein
covered this one.
Cortical
deafness
Refers to people who do not perceive any auditory
information but whose hearing is intact. My wife says I
suffer from this one.
Is the inability to distinguish the fingers on the hand. It is
Finger agnosia present in lesions of the dominant parietal lobe, and is a
component of Gerstmann syndrome.
Form agnosia
Patients perceive only parts of details, not the whole
object.
Integrative
In this disorder one has the ability to recognize elements of
89
agnosia
something but yet be unable to integrate these elements
together into comprehensible perceptual wholes. A very
important constituent of normal functioning consciousness.
One of the symptoms of Hemispatial neglect. Patients with
Hemispatial neglect were placed so that an object was in
their neglected visual field but a mirror reflecting that
Mirror agnosia- object was visible in their non-neglected field. Patients
could not acknowledge the existence of objects in the
neglected field and so attempted to reach into the mirror to
grasp the object.
Pain Agnosia
Also referred to as Analgesia, this is the difficulty in
perceiving and processing pain; thought to underpin some
forms of self injury.
Phonagnosia
Is the inability to recognize familiar voices, even though
the hearer can understand the words used.
Also known as faceblindness and facial agnosia: Patients
Prosopagnosia cannot consciously recognize familiar faces, sometimes
even including their own. This is often misperceived as an
inability to remember names.
Semantic
agnosia
Those with this form of agnosia are effectively 'object
blind' until they use non-visual sensory systems to
90
recognise the object. For example, feeling, tapping,
smelling, rocking or flicking the object, may trigger
realisation of its semantics (meaning).
Simultanagnosia
Social
emotional
agnosia
Patients can recognize objects or details in their visual
field, but only one at a time. They cannot make out the
scene they belong to or make out a whole image out of the
details. They literally "cannot see the forest for the trees."
Sometimes referred to as Expressive Agnosia, this is a
form of agnosia in which the person is unable to perceive
facial expression, body language and intonation, rendering
them unable to non-verbally perceive people's emotions
and limiting that aspect of social interaction.
Agnosia or Astereognosia is connected to tactile sense that is, touch. Patient finds it difficult to recognize objects
by touch based on its texture, size and weight. However,
Somatosensory they may be able to describe it verbally or recognize same
kind of objects from pictures or draw pictures of them.
Thought to be connected to lesions or damage in
somatosensory cortex.
Tactile agnosia Impaired ability to recognize or identify objects by touch
alone.
Time agnosia
Is the loss of comprehension of the succession and duration
of events. This element of consciousness could be one of
91
the most critical in any distinction from other animals, who
mostly live in the present moment. Patients with this
somewhat rare disorder are most confused.
This is a form of visual agnosia in which a person cannot
rely on visual cues to guide them directionally due to the
Topographical
inability to recognise objects. Nevertheless, they may still
agnosia
have an excellent capacity to describe the visual layout of
the same place.
Verbal auditory This presents as a form of meaning 'deafness' in which
agnosia
hearing is intact but there is significant difficulty
recognising spoken words as semantically meaningful.
Is associated with lesions of the left occipital lobe and
Visual agnosia temporal lobes. Many types of visual agnosia involve the
inability to recognize objects.
Difficulty comprehending the meaning of written words.
Verbal agnosia The capacity to read is usually intact but comprehension is
impaired.
The Agnosias have been described in some detail, mainly because
they represent such fundamental functional parts of “consciousness”.
A few more general syndromes are described below, to add to the
overall functional picture of consciousness.
92
Alien hand syndrome (also known as anarchic hand or Dr. Strangelove
syndrome) is an unusual neurological disorder in which one of the sufferer's
hands seems to take on a mind of its own. AHS is best documented in cases
where a person has had the two hemispheres of their brain surgically
separated, a procedure sometimes used to relieve the symptoms of extreme
cases of epilepsy. An alien hand sufferer can feel normal sensation in the
hand and leg, but believes that the hand, while still being a part of their
body, behaves in a manner that is totally distinct from the sufferer's normal
behavior. They feel that they have no control over the movements of the
'alien' hand, but that, instead, the hand has the capability of acting
autonomously — i.e., independent of their voluntary control. Alien behavior
can be distinguished from reflexive behavior in that the former is flexibly
purposive while the latter is obligatory. Sometimes the sufferer will not be
aware of what the alien hand is doing until it is brought to his or her
attention, or until the hand does something that draws their attention to its
behavior. This is an interesting condition with relevance to "conscious will".
Allochiria is a neurological disorder in which the patient responds to stimuli
presented to one side of their body as if the stimuli had been presented at the
opposite side. Thus a touch to the left arm will be reported as a touch to the
right arm ("somatosensory allochiria"). If the auditory or visual modalities
are affected, sounds (a person's voice for instance) will be reported as
occurring on the opposite side to that on which they occur and objects
presented visually will be reported as having been presented on the opposite
side. Often, but not universally, patients may express allochiria in their
drawing, copying in mirror image. The disorder comes from damage to the
contralateral parietal lobe.
Alzheimer's disease (AD) In the early stages, the most commonly
recognised symptom is inability to acquire new memories, such as difficulty
in recalling recently observed facts. As the disease advances, symptoms
include confusion, irritability and aggression, mood swings, language
breakdown, long-term memory loss, and the general withdrawal of the
sufferer as their senses decline. Progressive deterioration eventually hinders
93
independence; with subjects being unable to perform most common
activities of daily living. Speech difficulties become evident due to an
inability to recall vocabulary, which leads to frequent incorrect word
substitutions (paraphasias). Reading and writing skills are also progressively
lost. Complex motor sequences become less coordinated as time passes and
AD progresses, so the risk of falling increases. During this phase, memory
problems worsen, and the person may fail to recognise close relatives. Longterm memory, which was previously intact, becomes impaired.
Behavioural and neuropsychiatric changes become more prevalent. Common
manifestations are wandering, irritability and labile affect, leading to crying,
outbursts of unpremeditated aggression, or resistance to caregiving.
Approximately 30% of patients develop illusionary misidentifications and
other delusional symptoms. Subjects also lose insight of their disease
process and limitations (anosognosia). Urinary incontinence can develop.
During the last stage of AD, the patient is completely dependent upon
caregivers. Language is reduced to simple phrases or even single words,
eventually leading to complete loss of speech. Despite the loss of verbal
language abilities, patients can often understand and return emotional
signals. Although aggressiveness can still be present, extreme apathy and
exhaustion are much more common results. Patients will ultimately not be
able to perform even the most simple tasks without assistance. Muscle mass
and mobility deteriorate to the point where they are bedridden, and they lose
the ability to feed themselves. The basic “personhood” may indeed be totally
lost. I had one patient who accused her husband (they were both in their late
70s) of having affairs because when she looked in a mirror she saw a strange
woman she could not identify.
The description of Alzheimer's Syndrome, though lengthy, is important as it
is one of the best known, and seen, deteriorations of the whole
consciousness and personality.
Aphasia from the Greek root word "aphatos", meaning speechless, is an
acquired language disorder in which there is an impairment of any language
94
modality. This may include difficulty in producing or comprehending
spoken or written language.
People with aphasia may experience any of the following behaviors due to
an acquired brain injury, although some of these symptoms may be due to
related or concomitant problems such as dysarthria or apraxia and not
primarily due to aphasia. Apraxia refers to physical speech disorders. That is
to say it is a disorder of motor planning. Aphasia refers more to the inability
to produce or comprehend language.
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
inability to comprehend language
inability to pronounce, not due to muscle paralysis or weakness
inability to speak spontaneously
inability to form words
inability to name objects
poor enunciation
excessive creation and use of personal neologisms
inability to repeat a phrase
persistent repetition of phrases
paraphasia (substituting letters, syllables or words)
agrammatism (inability to speak in a grammatically correct fashion)
dysprosody (alterations in inflexion, stress, and rhythm)
incompleted sentences
inability to read
inability to write
limited verbal output
difficulty in naming
Auditory Processing Disorder (APD), also known as (Central) Auditory
Processing Disorder ((C)APD) is an umbrella term for a variety of
disorders that affect the way the brain processes auditory information. It is
not a sensory (inner ear) hearing impairment; individuals with APD usually
have normal peripheral hearing ability. However, they cannot process the
information they hear in the same way as others do, which leads to
difficulties in recognizing and interpreting sounds, especially the sounds
95
composing speech. Auditory Processing Disorder is a listening disability. It
can be considered a processing disability.
Binswanger's disease is a form of multi-infarct dementia caused by damage
to the white brain matter. It differs from Alzheimer’s in that it is subcortical.
Patients with this condition may have a normal memory but difficulty
planning, thinking abstractly or inhibiting appropriate actions.
Lower down in the anatomical divisions of the brain is the Pontine area and
disorders in this area are still critical to consciousness.
Central pontine myelinolysis is a neurologic disease caused by severe
damage of the myelin sheath of nerve cells in the brainstem, more precisely
in the area termed the pons. The most common cause is the rapid correction
of low blood sodium levels hyponatremia).It has been observed following
hematopoietic stem cell transplantation. Symptoms:- Frequently observed
symptoms in this disorder are acute para- or quadraparesis, dysphagia,
dysarthria, diplopia, loss of consciousness, and other neurological symptoms
associated with brainstem damage. The patient may experience Locked-in
Syndrome where cognitive function is intact, but all muscles are paralyzed
with the exception of eye blinking. These result from a rapid myelinolysis of
the corticobulbar and corticospinal tracts in the brainstem. We have looked
at Locked-in Syndrome in more detail, elsewhere.
Creutzfeldt–Jakob disease or CJD is a degenerative neurological disorder
(brain disease) that is incurable and invariably fatal. It is the most common
among the types of transmissible spongiform encephalopathy found in
humans. The first symptom of CJD is rapidly progressive dementia, leading
to memory loss, personality changes and hallucinations. This is accompanied
by physical problems such as speech impairment, jerky movements
(myoclonus), balance and coordination dysfunction (ataxia), changes in gait,
rigid posture, and seizures.
Dyscalculia or math disability is a specific learning disability or difficulty
involving innate difficulty in learning or comprehending mathematics. It is
akin to dyslexia and can include confusion about math symbols. Dyscalculia
96
can also occur as the result of some types of brain injury. Dyscalculia has
been associated with lesions to the supramarginal and angular gyri at the
junction between the temporal and parietal lobes of the cerebral cortex. The
following are but a few of the symptoms:
• Difficulty with everyday tasks like checking change and reading
analog clocks.
• Inability to comprehend financial planning or budgeting, sometimes
even at a basic level; for example, estimating the cost of the items in a
shopping basket or balancing a checkbook.
• Difficulty with multiplication-tables, and subtraction-tables, addition
tables, division tables, mental arithmetic, etc.
• May do fairly well in subjects such as science and geometry, which
require logic rather than formulae, until a higher level requiring
calculations is obtained.
• Many of those who suffer from dyscalculia may have parents who
perform well to excellent in Mathematics-related fields (such as
architects, engineers, or math teachers), though this connection has yet
to be genetically linked.
• Difficulty with conceptualizing time and judging the passing of time.
May be chronically late or early.
• Particularly problems with differentiating between left and right.
• Frequent difficulties with arithmetic, confusing the signs: +, −, ÷ and
×.
Dysgraphia (or agraphia) is a deficiency in the ability to write, regardless
of the ability to read, not due to intellectual impairment. People with
dysgraphia usually can write on some level, and often lack other fine motor
skills and may be cross dominant, finding tasks such as tying shoes difficult.
It often does not affect all fine motor skills. They can also lack basic
grammar and spelling skills (for example, having difficulties with the letters
p, q, b, and d), and often will write the wrong word when trying to formulate
97
thoughts (on paper). This condition may be genetic or indeed from trauma,
even in adults.
Dyslexia is a learning disability that impairs a person's ability to read, and
which can manifest itself as a difficulty with phonological awareness,
phonological decoding, orthographic coding, auditory short-term memory,
and/or rapid naming. Dyslexia is separate and distinct from reading
difficulties resulting from other causes, such as a non-neurological
deficiency with vision or hearing, or from poor or inadequate reading
instruction. It is estimated that dyslexia affects between 5 and 17 percent of
the population.
Macropsia (also known as megalopia) is a neurological condition affecting
human visual perception, in which objects within an affected section of the
visual field appear larger than normal, causing the subject to feel smaller.
Macropsia, along with its opposite condition, micropsia, can be categorized
under dysmetropsia. Macropsia has a wide range of causes, from
prescription and illicit drugs, to migraines and (rarely) complex partial
epilepsy, and to different retinal conditions, such as epiretinal membrane.
Physiologically, retinal macropsia results from the compression of cones in
the eye. It is the compression of receptor distribution that results in greater
stimulation and thus a larger perceived image of an object. The most obvious
symptom of macropsia is the presence of exceptionally enlarged objects
throughout the visual field. For example, a young girl might see her sister’s
books as the same size as her sister. Stemming from this symptom, someone
with macropsia may feel undersized in relation to his or her surrounding
environment. Implications for consideration of levels of consciousness are
obvious.
Nonverbal learning disorder or nonverbal learning disability (NLD or
NVLD) is a proposed condition characterized by a significant discrepancy
between high verbal and lower performance scores on an IQ test, with
deficits in motor, visual-spatial, and social skills. Some proponents of the
category believe that this discrepancy is attributable to dysfunction in the
right cerebral hemisphere.
98
NLD involves deficits in perception, coordination, socialisation, non-verbal
problem-solving and understanding of humour, along with well-developed
rote memory. As most people with Asperger’s syndrome (AS) fit the criteria
for NLD, a diagnosis of AS is often preferred. The basic Autism Spectrum
Disorder is a disease of social interaction. Linguistic and cognitive
development are intact and, indeed, often above normal.
Palinopsia (Greek: palin for "again" and opsia for "seeing") is a visual
disturbance that causes images to persist to some extent even after their
corresponding stimulus has left. These images are known as afterimages and
occur in persons with normal vision. However, a person with palinopsia
experiences them to a significantly greater degree, to the point where they
become difficult or impossible to ignore. This often results in mild to severe
anxiety and/or depression. Palinopsia sometimes appears on its own, but is
more often accompanied by other visual disturbances such as visual snow,
and can be attributed to a number of conditions affecting the brain including
medications, seizure disorders, tumors, occipital lobe or visual pathway
lesions, subcortical hemorrhage, and dural arteriovenous malformations.
Synesthesia—is a neurologically-based condition in which stimulation of
one sensory or cognitive pathway leads to automatic, involuntary
experiences in a second sensory or cognitive pathway. People who report
such experiences are known as synesthetes. In one common form of
synesthesia, known as grapheme → color synesthesia or color-graphemic
synesthesia, letters or numbers are perceived as inherently colored, while in
ordinal linguistic, numbers, days of the week and months of the year evoke
personalities. In spatial-sequence, or number form synesthesia, numbers,
months of the year, and/or days of the week elicit precise locations in space
(for example, 1980 may be "farther away" than 1990), or may have a (threedimensional) view of a year as a map (clockwise or counterclockwise). For
example a patient with OLP (Ordinal-linguistic personification) may see
numbers as coloured and having personalities and letters also. There may be
99
a deficit in the cross-activation pathways, actually sometimes a failure to
have eradicated certain pathways from birth.
We now consider some different kinds of disorders.
Disorders that are more metabolic in origin:- We have seen from the
above, many disorders that affect consciousness in various ways and, once
again, we see what mechanisms therefore constitute consciousness. Yet one
whole area sometimes omitted from consideration of consciousness is the
issue of body metabolism. So this is illustrated below by endocrine, or
chemical, disorders.
Hyperadrenocorticism or hypercorticism
or Cushing's syndrome is a
hormone (endocrine) disorder caused by high levels of cortisol
(hypercortisolism) in the blood. This can be caused by taking glucocorticoid
drugs, or by tumors that produce cortisol or adrenocorticotropic hormone
(ACTH). Cushing's syndrome is not confined to humans and is also a
relatively common condition in domestic dogs and horses. Patients
frequently suffer various psychological disturbances, ranging from euphoria
to psychosis. Depression and anxiety are also common. This is an example
of chemical balance disorder but illustrates the need for functioning anatomy
as well as internal chemistry for full consciousness and intact personhood.
Menkes disease (MNK), also called Menkes syndrome, copper transport
disease, steely hair disease, is a disorder that affects copper levels in the
body, leading to copper deficiency. It is an x-linked recessive disorder, and
is therefore considerably more common in males: females require two
defective alleles to develop the disease. MNK is characterized by sparse and
coarse hair, growth failure, and deterioration of the nervous system. Onset of
Menkes syndrome typically begins during infancy. Signs and symptoms of
this disorder include weak muscle tone (hypotonia), sagging facial features,
seizures, mental retardation, and developmental delay. Of note for our
purpose is that something as seemingly unrelated as serum copper levels
would affect levels of consciousness and sense of personhood.
100
Non-24-hour sleep-wake syndrome (Non-24) is a chronic circadian rhythm
sleep disorder. It can be defined as "a chronic steady pattern comprising oneto two-hour daily delays in sleep onset and wake times in an individual
living in society." The pattern of delay persists literally "around the clock,"
typically taking a few weeks to complete one cycle. People with Non-24
"resemble free-running, normal individuals living in a time-isolation facility
with no external time cues." In people with this disorder, the body
essentially insists that the day is longer than 24 hours and refuses to adjust to
the external light/dark cycle. It is far more common in blind people than in
sighted people. It causes major disruptions in their ability to function, jobs,
holidays, daylight saving changes etc.
Schizophrenia is a behavioural disorder characterized by a disintegration of
the process of thinking and of emotional responsiveness. It most commonly
manifests as auditory hallucinations, paranoid or bizarre delusions, or
disorganized speech and thinking, and it is accompanied by significant social
or occupational dysfunction. Onset of symptoms typically occurs in young
adulthood. Unusually high dopamine activity in the mesolimbic pathway of
the brain has been found in people with schizophrenia. It is commonly, and
mistakenly in my opinion, called a “mental disease” but should be
considered a disease of a person as a whole.
We have mentioned above under Cushing's Disease, the importance of
certain chemicals. It may be of interest here to mention the main
neurotransmitters that we currently know about and the roles they play in
emotions and consciousness. They are discussed, not necessarily in order of
importance.:
Serotonin:- this chemical has an effect on mood, sleep, appetite and
is involved in several mood disorders e.g. depression, anxiety and bipolar
affective disorder. It is perhaps the major player among neurotransmitters.
Dopamine:- Dopamine can affect movement cognition, pleasure and
motivation. It is produced mostly in the Substantia Nigra and thus affects
101
Parkinson's Disease, as mentioned elsewhere. Not only does it affect motion
but a lack of this one chemical in certain parts of the brain appears to be
linked causally to ideation diseases, delusions and psychosis.
Glutamic Acid and Gamma-aminobutyric acid or GABA:Memorising and learning are affected by differing levels of this
neurotransmitter. It has wide-reaching effects in such diseases as
Alzheimer's and ALS.
There are others such as acetylcholine and epinephrine/nor
epinephrine which also play an important role in more fundamental parts of
consciousness, anxiety, movement, stress response etc.
Summary: I am sorry to burden the reader with so many horrendous
diseases, many of which, I myself, as a physician, have never come across.
However the point of this extensive list is to see into the "mind" and
consciousness of human beings. I wish to illustrate the immense substrate of
consciousness, both anatomical and biochemical. Each and every one of
these disorders, and the many further neurological disorders, illustrate what
is needed for normal functioning of a full consciousness. It is not a complete
description of consciousness by any means, yet these disorders show the
fundamental functioning blocks. By studying these annoying and sometimes
fatal and terrible disorders, we can see in fact the normal functional elements
of consciousness and personhood in an incredibly detailed way.
We are solving what makes up a human being by seeing the sum total
of mechanisms that can go wrong. Until they do fail we have not been able
to note that there was a mechanism for this particular function. Many of
these are genetic, and in the future, cures may come from stem cell
implantation. Some diseases seen here involve anatomical injury, some
chemical imbalance, both of which are critical substrates of consciousness.
We cannot easily separate physical states from “mental” conditions or
“mental” functions. This has been done too much in the past, and in
medicine we need a far closer relationship between psychiatric medicine and
102
the rest of the medical studies. A simple change in my blood sugar can
radically alter my “consciousness”, and so can my thyroid hormone levels or
circulating cortisol levels. They are all part of what creates the harmonious
total of consciousness.
Consciousness becomes the sum total of a normal functional brain and
these elements above are just part of the actual constituents of
consciousness. We can see clearly the enormous complexity of the notion of
consciousness, but we begin to remove some of the unfathomable mystery.
Consciousness only has meaning and comprehension in the context of a
living being. It will not become objectively pinned down outside of the life
of a perceiving being. It is a composite concept of certain living beings and
it then requires many structures and chemical balances to be in place. How
far into the animal kingdom we extend the concept remains to be seen, but
has been part of this investigation.
Future research will undoubtedly tease out more and more of the
elements of full consciousness and philosophers will once again fade into the
background somewhat. This happened with theories of matter, but there is
still a place for philosophers to inject clarity into discussions and help
scientists avoid pitfalls. One of the most important areas is in naming. There
is such a profound difference between a simple empirical object, such as a
parietal lobe and a concept such as thinking. The existence of a parietal lobe
is hard to question. The existence and nature of "a thought" is quite different.
The philosopher's role in ontological clarity is crucial. Now whether a
machine could ever be “conscious” is an interesting question but I think we
still have the massive number of neurons and the plasticity and variability to
make it very hard for anyone to construct a machine that does more than
have us say “oh cute”. So far we have not, but I am sure we will build
biological or DNA, or quantum based computers that will enable robots to
become almost conscious, at least from the observers point of view!
The mention of just one of these disorders "Time Agnosia" where the
patient has a neurological deficit affecting their ability to judge the passage
of time, is particularly interesting. Time has mostly been considered to be of
103
two varieties, firstly general clock-calendar time or Relativistic
mathematical space-time continuum. Such a patient will have a very
localised neurological deficit, intact in all other ways, so a very small area of
cerebral infarction. Time for philosophers has generally been considered
"Newtonian" in the sense of an objective flow of events in the external
world. Events would be considered as following one another, and time itself
is measurable. This corresponds to the clock-calendar time mentioned above.
The relativistic notions of time, do not generally apply in human experience,
so we can consider that our own biological adaptation has been to sidereal
time. That is to say we have probably adapted our brains to deal with
variations in daylight and earth's rotation and may have internalized this into
somewhere in the limbic system, or more specifically to the suprachiasmatic
nuclei, as well as in the temporal or parietal lobes. Dopamine and norepinephrine may also play a role in our ability to judge time.
To think, then, that such a precious concept as time, comes down also
to the normal functioning of consciousness, is certainly humbling. In the
human being, we can dispense with the philosophical notion of the
impossibility of present time and simply accept the concept of a present
moment. We can, as it were, arrest nature. Physicists, especially quantum
physicists, are stuck with being unable to assume a before and after and do
not have an arrow of time. We, as non-physicists, definitely do. But it may
be that Immanuel Kant was correct in assuming that such perceptions are
entirely man-made.
104
Diagram: SCN, the Suprachiasmatic Nucleus.
Although in general it is dangerous and presumptuous to localize
function in any one small area, the SCN is particularly in control of
circadian rhythm. It has evolved to operate on a 24 hour cycle in general but
in fact is 24h 11mins. It received input directly from the retina and
communicates with the visual cortex and also the pineal gland, where it
assists in regulating body temperature and various hormones, such as
melatonin and cortisol.
This brief look at time concludes the description of the apparatus
required for consciousness, the substrate of consciousness. I have omitted a
discussion of hallucinogenic drugs, largely through lack of personal
experience, but it is feasible that in opening the sensory apparatus wider, the
person undergoing such an experience is negating the “forgetting” function
of the cortex. Thereby he or she sees far more and experiences far more
detail on simple objects of perception. Given that we are yet only using a
small amount of our brain potential most of the day and night, it is feasible
that mind-altering drugs do increase our potential to view “reality”. The
price to pay may be that the brain is designed to forget so much, as a sanity
saving device, and return us to a somewhat mundane level of “normal”
functioning. In a sense we are describing what constitutes “normal”
105
consciousness. It is not my intention to get into the multiple aspects of
“higher” or “enhanced” consciousness. Some of the described disorders do
in fact lead to heightened awareness or consciousness and then again it may
be induced by certain drugs. Yet my point is that “normal” consciousness
requires a great deal of inhibition of these pathways to increased
consciousness and thus the topic remains to be examined in other studies.
We will now take a look at the more philosophical aspects of mind,
consciousness and the difficult issue of self-awareness.
106
Chapter XI
Mind-v-Consciousness and the subject-object issue.
We have not really delved into a discussion of "Mind" per se,
preferring to deal with consciousness, but some points can be made. The
issues of what defines a person is serious, medically, legally and
philosophically. Personhood is defined in various ways and does not seem to
contain the necessity for a full functioning "Mind". Mind itself is a
somewhat nefarious term which has so many connotations as to make it
almost an annoying concept. Personally I would like to see it abolished, not
mind itself, just the concept. OK that's a paradox and contradiction. Let's just
say the concept of mind may have become superfluous in today's scientific
world. It may not be quite that simple however, and there still may be a need
for a distinction between mind, consciousness, and personality.
An article by Susan Greenfield in The British Journal of Psychiatry
(2002) 181:91-93
titled "Mind, brain and consciousness" offers some
opinions. She feels that "mind" is what it feels like to be yourself whereas
"personality" is how others see us. The distinction remains blurred in my
mind! "Mind" may be like "The Unconscious" i.e. a phenomenological
invention of dubious ontological status, but of cultural utility. We just need
not fall into the trap of believing that nouns refer to existent entities.
"Goodness" and "Justice" and many other examples fall into the category of
useful noun concepts that do not imply existence. I can describe what I
might mean by "Justice" by examples and description but I need not imply
that there is any such existent entity. "Mind" may be seen this way and it
serves a cultural and linguistic purpose then. Of course we do create a virtual
reality of the outside world inside our perceptive world and this Kantian
notion does lend support to the unknowability of the "Ding-An-Sich", as it is
often referred to. In the evolution of language, it was probably a long time
before we evolved away from all nouns referring to “things”.
So mind may be more of a descriptive aid that will continue to serve
us whereas consciousness becomes the more concrete concept of a
physiological nature and an object of study.
107
The notion of subjective awareness that there is somehow an
executive in control of this consciousness i.e. "me" is most probably one of
those linguistic delusions or category errors that Gilbert Ryle described.
Wittgenstein's notion of Language Games is of use here, as many different
language games may be in process of being played when we discuss such
complex concepts. The so-called "Hard Problem" of subjective awareness
or self-reflectivity remains exactly that, hard and perhaps even insoluble, but
we really should not permit the problem as stated to completely block lateral
thinking on the issue.
Mysterians, led by Colin McGinn, argue that the
human mind at present, is incapable of solving this problem. This is an
attractive viewpoint, as we are undoubtedly evolving over the centuries, yet
there may be, for a long time yet, the barrier of explaining "Qualia", or inner
sensations, like pain from toothache, the taste of wine. And this is where the
hard problem comes in. I cannot really ever experience how wine tastes to
you.
So Qualia are very personal, known only to my own subjective
consciousness, seemingly incommunicable to others. In many series of
colour testing pilots in my medical office, I find perhaps 20% with
significant colour blindness, so I am quite aware that they are not seeing the
same world out there as mine. They read different numbers out of the colour
charts. So the explanatory gap between private sensations and other minds is
indeed a real one. Is the red traffic light really red if only 80% of the
population see it as "red". I see it as red, but I it is hard to imagine what it is
you are seeing if you misread the colour charts. I really don't think the
colour blind person says "oh the top light just changed from off to brown,
but wait a minute that is what they call red, so I must stop".
The answer is simpler. The facts are that the colour blind person
actually sees "red", it just isn't the same red that most of us see! Now that is
tricky for a philosopher. But it is just a matter of distinctions that an artist
who works with many different shades, will appreciate, where I am unable
to.
108
Physicists and physiologists tend to a mechanistic understanding of
colour. In this, the colours are objective and a property of objects in the
world. That is to say, they are not simply invented or constructed by our
perceptive apparatus, though they may be perceived differently by different
subjects. A person learns a given colour by paradigm examples. So it is hue,
saturation, and lightness which will then alter one's perception of colour.
The exact role of the perceiver may be more complex than stated here but as
to the many theories of colour, we really do not need to dwell on them here.
The whole issue of "seeing" and colours is quite complex of course
and we can only hope to touch on a few issues of relevance here. Many
years ago, when first reading the Philosophical Investigations, I wrote a
short article "On Seeing", which I do not have anymore. It concerned the
multiple uses of the phrase. Specifically it dealt with "Seeing without
seeing". A propos here is the notion of Eidetic Memory, a somewhat
controversial subject. Stephen Wiltshire, an architect in the U.K. has
apparently such an extensive photographic memory, that he was taken on a
helicopter flight, and, after landing, was able to draw, with pretty well every
detail, the complete London landscape. So did he register in any way at the
time, all this detail? Did he in fact "see" it? If you can see something with no
conscious registration, at the time, of "seeing" it, and then recall the item
perfectly later, we do have a new meaning of the word "see". Perhaps it
makes sense to say that you can "see" without "seeing". Maybe it is
unconscious seeing. Now we do not want an interminable philosophical
discussion here, but it does illustrate the richness of language and the
immense subtlety and complexity of consciousness. "Seeing in one's mind's
eye", is a perfectly acceptable and comprehensible expression. We also see
things with our eyes closed, not just after images.
The fact that my Qualia may be different than yours does not
mean that they both did not originate from the same source, it just refers to
the link between subjective experience and the outside world (and by that I
would include the amazing colours generated by pressure on the eyeball).
We do not really need to worry too much about the actual real world source
of all qualia. In other words it is a loose connection. The explanatory gap
109
may be examined further by taking the question of qualia or senseperception as a physical sensation (wherever it may occur) and then we are
either paying attention to it or not. So there may be a colour patch generated
by pressure and I may be aware of all the colours or in fact I may ignore all
but green for whatever reason. So now I may not be conscious of the qualia
at all. I might recall it under hypnosis (another very complex subject for
philosophers!). So sometimes our internal world indicates something real
and empirical and sometimes it indicates something completely imaginary.
Colour vision itself presents a minefield for philosophers. Colour
blindness is mostly genetic and possibly even of some evolutionary
advantage, it is, as mentioned above, quite common at lesser levels.
Classified on clinical appearance, color blindness can be total or partial.
Total color blindness is less common than partial color blindness. There are
two major types of color blindness: those who have difficulty distinguishing
between red and green, and those who have difficulty distinguishing
between blue and yellow. Being weak on green is the most common form of
colour blindness. A darker shade of green would be called black.
110
An Ishihara test number-: most people will see 74, those with basic
red/green deficiency will see perhaps 21, a person with total colour
blindness will not see a number.
It is important to note that a red apple does not simply look "green" to
someone with red/green deficiency, a red apple will look very faded and
similarly a green apple will be very faded. Such a person may not be able to
distinguish the red traffic light from an amber light and a green light might
look dirty white.
Does this affect our philosophical arguments? Well we need to dive
back into private sensations or qualia. Let's take the taste of lemon. Do I
know what lemon tastes like? Well sure, but how would I tell you? "Well it
is kind of bitter but with a delicious tinge to it". Yes but that might indicate a
hundred different things. It will still be difficult to get someone else to
identify lemon from any description we can come up with. How did we
"learn" the taste of lemon in the first place. Presumably my parents fed me
something lemony and said "this is lemon". After a few meals I would learn
it. But the only way I can indicate to anyone else is never going to be
dependent solely on my private sensation, but I will use that pathway of
neurons and cerebral cortex memory circuit to assist me in indicating to
someone else what lemon is like. I will still ultimately need a lemon or
111
lemon juice to assist in teaching. The point to make here is that I can never
use the private language, it is just that- private. What is public is what we
share in the world.
Lemon taste is easier than a feeling, but I still need more than
language to describe the lemon. With feelings it is almost impossible in
spoken language, to convey my inner meaning. So if I feel sad, I might just
say "I feel sad" and you might believe me, but you are more likely to believe
me if I now compose or play a really "sad" piece of music that affects your
feelings deeply. Good, so there are ways around the impasse, just not
linguistic. There are people that see numbers as colours and can do amazing
mathematics with a feeling of redness. Again the sense of language is being
extended. We, as philosophers are so locked into words.
Wittgenstein says:- ""In my own case I know that when I say 'I have
pain' this utterance is accompanied by something:- but is it also
accompanied by something in another man?" In as much as his utterance
needn't be accompanied by my pain I may say he isn't accompanied by
anything" ( Ludwig Wittgenstein "Philosophical Occasions" Edited by
James Klagge and Alfred Nordmann, Hackett Publishing Company 1993, p
206. ) We can flit from qualia to qualia here in thinking through this process,
there are some differences between sensations caused by outside events and
internally generated feelings, but the problem of conveying them is similar
in some ways. The sensations derived more specifically from the external
world are closer to Russell's objects of acquaintance, or sense-data. However
with feelings, we need to consider the cultural milieu of the speaker and then
the poetry, music, gestures, dance etc will convey what it means to have a
certain feeling to another, at least well enough. With sensations there is the
addition that although they can arise spontaneously with no link to the
external world, things such as colour and sounds generally relate to a colour
or sound "out there". It need not be the same one I am naming, for that
depends on many things.
So we are saying there are ways around the impasse that Wittgenstein
may well have been implying in his doctrine of "showing" as opposed to
112
pedantic teaching. It is possible that this is what created the big problem as
to how one could ever understand Wittgenstein if you were not one of his
students. I had the pleasure to be, at least for a while, taught by one of his
students, Dr M O'C Drury in Dublin and also to have contact with Rush
Rhees, another of his “acolytes”. In some of their private correspondence,
now coming to light at the University of Limerick (courtesy of the Drury
family and Professor John Hayes) I found several references to their
realization that future generations might not understand him from any later
published works. The "Tractatus" was different, but Wittgenstein was quite
reticent to publish anything else in his lifetime. I always found that
frustrating, but anyone who isn't extremely frustrated by Wittgenstein has
not really started to understand him. So the implication again is that you
needed to have been a student and have become an acolyte. Now this may
mean that Wittgenstein failed in his mission to teach the world a new way of
doing philosophy but it may still mean that we have to read between the
lines a little more. His doctrine of showing may be his most subtle.
We are of course, playing with the notion of "Language Games" as
introduced by Wittgenstein in his work in the 1930s, but we want to extend
the notion to a complete cultural milieu to comprehend meaning in a wider
sense than Wittgenstein spelled out, but which he may well have been trying
to show us. The Language Games idea is just a tool to help us to think more
clearly. We have to get very comfortable with vagueness in language and the
ability to proceed without clear definitions of "things" or concepts.
G.E.Moore in his lecture notes from the early thirties, records that
Wittgenstein gave one lecture a week for years and then met later in the
week with the students, to discuss. He remarked to Moore that it was a good
job Moore was taking notes as otherwise if he was to die there would be no
record of his thoughts. Moore mentions some fascinating points about
Wittgenstein's "new method" of doing philosophy in the same
"Philosophical Occasions:“Wittgenstein "went on to say that, though philosophy had now been
"reduced to a matter of skill", yet this skill, like other skills, is very difficult
113
to acquire. One difficulty was that it required a "sort of thinking" to which
we are not accustomed and to which we have not been trained--a sort of
thinking very different from what is required in the sciences. And he said
that the required skill could not be acquired merely by hearing lectures:
discussion was essential. As regards his own work, he said it did not matter
whether his results were true or not: what mattered was that 'a method had
been found'." ( Ludwig Wittgenstein "Philosophical Occasions", p 113.)
Again to further elucidate that which Moore certainly found
surprising, i.e. that we now wanted skilful philosophers as opposed to
"great" philosophers, Moore writes in his notes (ibid pp 113-4)
"He did not try to expressly tell us what the "new method" which had been
found was. But he gave some hints [27] (sic) as to its nature. He said, in [11]
(sic) that the new subject consisted in "something like putting in order our
notions as to what can be said about the world", and compared this to the
tidying up of a room where you have to move the same object several times
before you can get the room really tidy. He said also that we were "in a
muddle about things", which we had to try to clear up; that we had to follow
a certain instinct which leads us to ask certain questions, that we don't even
understand what these questions mean; that are asking them results from "a
vague mental uneasiness", like that which leads children to ask "why"; and
that this uneasiness can only be cured "either be showing that a particular
question is not permitted, or by answering it"."
Moore goes on to say (page 114 PO) "I ought, perhaps, finally to repeat what
I said in my first article (P. 51)", (sic), namely that he held that though the
"new subject" must say a great deal about language, it was only necessary
for it to deal with those points about language which have led, or are likely
to lead, to definite philosophical puzzles or errors. I think he certainly
thought that some philosophers now-a-days have been misled into dealing
with linguistic points which have no such bearing, and the discussion of
which therefore, in his view, forms no part of the proper business of a
philosopher."
114
This little aside, above, leads to the way ahead from Wittgenstein, and
to possible solutions to seemingly impossible problems, by demonstrating
that they may indeed be pseudo-problems.
David Chalmers, in his classic paper from 1995: Journal of
Consciousness Studies 2 (3), 1995, pp. 200-219 “Facing Up to the Problem
of Consciousness”, outlines the easy problems of consciousness as the
following:
• the ability to discriminate, categorize, and react to environmental
stimuli;
• the integration of information by a cognitive system;
• the reportability of mental states;
• the ability of a system to access its own internal states;
• the focus of attention;
• the deliberate control of behavior;
• the difference between wakefulness and sleep.
Chalmers adds that the above problems are amenable, or will be, to
scientific study and neurophysiology in particular. The “Hard” problem on
the other hand, is the subjective experience of consciousness or experience.
This might mean the visual experience of redness in an object, but it means
it in the sense of awareness of this sensation, the self-reflective aspect.
I am simply a conscious creature, to add that "I know I am a conscious
creature" adds a level of removal which then creates the "Hard" problem.
Consciousness is an explicable phenomenon. We need a lot more science to
"understand" it better and we may reach certain barriers, such as science has
reached in theories of matter, time, cosmic explanations, but I do not feel
that this one has to be such a barrier.
As Chalmers says further in his article, we seem to be able to access
more of our inner goings on. Chalmers states it thus:
115
”Why is it that when electromagnetic waveforms impinge on a retina
and are discriminated and categorized by a visual system, this discrimination
and categorization is experienced as a sensation of vivid red? We know that
conscious experience does arise when these functions are performed, but the
very fact that it arises is the central mystery.”
Part of my point here is that we may well be wrong in creating, or
asking about, the "Hard Question" and creating the stumbling block, and
perhaps there are other questions that can be asked to let us move on with
the subject.
Let us look at the immensely complex brain we have been painting a
picture of and also the neurological deficits which cause many visual
illusions, hallucinations, etc. We then realize then that we do create our total
image of the world in this very complex brain. Qualia may be taken as
subjective but they do not need to imply that there is not a measurable
physiological process taking place. It certainly does not need to entail any
notion of duality, nor indeed the subject-object dichotomy. No, I will never
be able to feel your pain, nor you mine, but the grammar of pain is the
problem here not the implied propositional status.
The next line of inquiry takes us into language and the supposed, or
theoretical, origins of thought. Discursive Language or verbal language,
which should be seen strictly as a subdivision of symbolic expression, is of
critical importance as our window into consciousness. The whole issue of
symbolic expression may be the subject of a future investigation, following
on from the works of Susanne Langer, but for now we will focus on
language and the evolution of that form of expression.
116
Chapter XII
The history of Language and the role of Language in Consciousness.
Some indication of the role of language in thinking and in the notion
of evolution of consciousness can be inferred from the history of language.
Many years ago, I spent several years working in the High Arctic of
Canada. My time with the Inuit taught me a great deal about non-verbal
communication. The Inuit do not waste too much time on unnecessary
verbalization. A child will indicate yes by raising his/her eyebrows, and no
by simply scrunching the nose. Little head movements speak volumes and
many visits to nearby houses were conducted with long periods of silence. It
took a while to get used to this and gradually I began to realize that we waste
an awful amount of time on superficial verbosity.
What we do need to examine now is the evolution of language in our
species and then also in the individual and look at comparative philology to
see if we can draw conclusions about the nature of consciousness as a
biological entity.
The Australopithecine, one of the two early species of hominids,
flourished in the diminishing African forest but appears not to have had the
development of speech. As Fischer in "A History of Language" (Reaktion
Books Ltd. 1999) mentions, these were "Walking Great Apes" but not
"Talking Great Apes". Again I owe much of this chapter to Fischer's book.
Fischer states that "The physical attributes for human articulate speech
appear to have evolved rather quickly, between 1.6 million and 400,000
years ago. From the latter date comes our earliest hominid fossil indicating a
possible use of vocal speech. This possible use emerged with a wholly new
species of hominid Homo Erectus". Homo Erectus appears to have
developed a complex form of planning, as is evidenced by tools and dietary
remains, indicating that this species may have constructed bamboo-log rafts
117
and crossed a 17 km strait in Java. So approximately 1 million years ago an
earlier species of human may have developed a form of syntax with
conditional sentences such as "If we do this, then this may result". This may
not have come with vocal speech as we know it, because the control of
exhalation was not yet present. Let us not forget, at this juncture, that we
have already seen a highly developed mammal whose level of
consciousness may have been higher than any ancestor of ours at a time
many million years before the above example.
Around 350,000 BCE (Before Current Era) we find human remains
with evidence of brain size having reached modern proportions. Homo
Sapiens, as we know, began to exist around this time but Neandertals still
existed also, only becoming extinct 30,000 years ago and with some
evidence, from modern DNA testing, of interbreeding. The origin and
evolution of human speech does require that certain anatomical features of
speech organs as well as certain brain developments evolved. These evolved
pari-passu with the advancement of gestures interestingly enough, according
to experts. We do not know how or why this happened but it seems to have
been necessary. We can have occasion here to mention the infamous gesture
by Piero Sraffa, the economist. Sraffa was a contemporary of Wittgenstein'
at Cambridge and was a member of an informal coffee group, consisting of
Wittgenstein, Frank Ramsey, and John Maynard Keynes. Apparently they
discussed economic theory and probability. However it is in legend that
Wittgenstein was talking about the necessity of a proposition having the
same logical form as that which it describes (a peculiar notion developed in
the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus). Sraffa made, what appears to be an
extremely rude gesture and asked Wittgenstein "What is the logical form of
that?" From this and other doubts Wittgenstein changed his view on the
relation of propositions to the external world.
118
(Diagram: who needs speech! )
The Neandertals went through some interesting evolution, seemingly due to
ice age adaptation around 180,000 BCE. They changed from tall and thin, to
stocky and barrel-chested, an adaptation to cold. Neandertal man may have
had speech ability close to later Homo Sapiens, but only gradually did the
complex syntax of words referring to other words evolve. Words such as
"to" and "which" and "because" are well beyond the toddler straight
reference. They would be called "Relational Words". However between
50,000 and 30,000 BCE the Neandertals became extinct while Homo
Sapiens developed better tools and better clothing, and base camps for
hunting. But modern Homo Sapiens emerged before that, at about 120,000
BCE when the big ice wall covering Europe retreated. The beginnings of
culture, i.e. art and maybe music date from say 100,000 BCE. Language
truly started developing only around 30,000 BCE. Social groups of hominids
ruled in small bands, perhaps a radius of 40-50 Kms, but language
disseminated fast and furious with many dialects and perhaps as many as a
thousand languages by 14,000 BCE. Shortly after a major warming 12,000
years ago we developed a form of grain, Triticum Dicoccum or emmer and
modern farming society began.
Written Language:
Written language first emerged (as opposed to pure referential art) as
a trading tool. Keeping tallies and being able to label, came before poetry,
literature and philosophy, sad to say. The act of writing may indeed, have
been seen as a magical process and the scribe possessed of such powers. The
119
effect on human evolution, for our purposes, has been immense, in a period
of just over say 5000 years. Significant advances were the original
hieroglyphs, followed by small clay disks and then reed styli, to engrave on
pots. One of the most advanced, the early Egyptian script used about 2,500
glyphs which graphically represented the object to be named. Consonants
developed long before vowels. Egyptian hieroglyphs were generally written
with ink on papyrus or on leather or pottery. Writing changed from pictorial
shapes to characters and by about 2000 BC we had a Coptic or early Greek
alphabet. The cuneiform script developed from the Sumerian-Akkadian
culture of the Middle East and was widespread, influencing even the Indus
Valley languages.
However the West Semitic script gradually took over and generated
Arabic, Manchu, Syrian, Aramaic and Pahlavi, as well as Brahmi and others
in southern Asia. It would seem that the world's oldest alphabetic script
dates at around 1600 BC from the area of modern Israel. The early Greeks
were the first to incorporate vowels (from their spoken language) into the
older Phoenician script. Somewhere in this process we went from direct
representation to abstraction, this evolution was of critical importance. In
developing a theory of consciousness we need to examine the way words
and concepts have developed over the millennia. Obviously if a word does
not need to point to an object, or an idea, which needs to exist, then we can
develop many concepts, which may be so abstract as to lead us astray in the
sense that we may think they still represent something which they do not. So
philosophical concepts such as "thinking about thinking" may be pure
linguistic nonsense. The concept of self-awareness might need very careful
analysis to become meaningful.
You may well be asking, at this stage, why we are working through
the history of spoken and written language. Well, it is mainly to see if we
can parallel cultural development with the rise of "consciousness" in humans
as our tools and brains evolved. We cannot say at what point we became
conscious, thinking human beings, but obviously it occurred somewhere in
this evolution, and not suddenly. But we have seen that the separation of
object and idea have been fundamental. The philosophical implications, i.e.
120
that this was simply a natural evolution of language, not entailing any
ontological implications, have not been clearly spelled out in philosophy
often enough. Wittgenstein, in his picture theory in the "Tractatus" was
entranced by the feeling that a word and object were closely related.
Language moved past that a long time ago.
The Greeks adopted a basic alphabet but made critical innovations and
adapted the Semitic language to Indo-European by adding vowels to written
language, this increased the transmission of thought. By adding individual
sounds to certain 8th or 9th century BC Phoenician sounds they created the
full Greek alphabet, from which all of Eastern and Western Europe and
most of North America derive their current written language.
Asiatic and Meso-American scripts appeared to have developed as
primarily object names but then Chinese writing created up to 2500 glyphs
from pictograms, and may have been used between 1000-2000 BC. The
intricacies of these scripts, and Japanese, fall outside of our purposes and
any comments on the relevance of thought processes to their scripts would
have to be left to another analyst. Writing in Central America developed
between 700 BC and 1200 BC and culminated in the Maya script. The
lovely collection in the Royal Mayan Library was totally destroyed by the
barbaric behaviour of the Spanish invaders, yet one further example of our
"advanced cultural status" as humans.
So virtually all languages begin as object depiction and then scripts
become pictographic. It evolves to "logographic" with glyphs standing for
objects (no longer directly pictorial) and ideas as well. We then advance to
"syllabic" writing which shortens the glyphs basically and finally we have
alphabetic. The picture has gone and we have vowels and consonants but
still phonetic in so many ways.
The last point we can make from Fischer's lovely book is that all
writing systems fail ultimately to reproduce what we are capable of saying in
speech. Intonation, stress on different parts of a word (desert, dessert, for
example, say it both ways!), and other factors cause the English alphabet to
121
come up short, whereas Chinese script expresses far more that way. Suffice
it to say we do not know the exact connection between different languages
and the ability to think philosophically in a specific language. Nor do we
know exactly at what point actual use of language gives us the conclusion
that consciousness has now reached the level that we can say there is in any
way a universal standard of consciousness. So consciousness will differ in
the infant to the young child, to the adult. It will be markedly different
between adults, such that we may doubt its existence in some, but there will
also be variations within the individual that will alter it significantly. There
will be differences between cultures and races. Yet there is a connection
between maturity of language, spoken and written and consciousness.
Similarly, we do not need to examine here all the non-discursive methods of
transmission of information. They have also matured with evolution, and
consciousness has developed with the poetry, music, dance and other forms
of emotional and intellectual expression. For further and a detailed
examination of that whole area, read Suzanne Langer’s later books.
I will now try to bring together some of the differing topics in the
book so far and look at neurophenomenology and the notion that
consciousness has evolved.
122
Chapter XIII
Conclusions and comments on Neurophenomenology, and the
"Evolution" of Consciousness.
In what sense can we talk about the evolution of consciousness? Well
quite simply in fact. Human beings have evolved, brains have evolved.
Consciousness is a direct emergent biological property of this development.
We have seen that we can describe it as a collection of functioning
neurological connections and areas in a healthy human being, i.e. with
regards to metabolic and organ function. We have looked at various more
primitive forms of consciousness, both in other animals and in Homo
Sapiens. So then how have we evolved? Firstly:- the complexity of modern
thinking, not just in the sense of scientific advances, but also the advances in
abstract and conceptual thinking, are signs of changing consciousness. The
development of advanced thought, associated with subtle changes in
language structure, are part of that evolution. The paths through Relativity
and Quantum mathematics and the subtleties of modern mathematical logic
all indicate great advances in thinking. Presumably the brain itself is still
evolving and thus consciousness will alter over generations to come.
Consciousness is not evolving by natural selection alone, anymore,
but rather by cultural spread through art, poetry, dance, cinema etc and not
just by any genetic means. It is evolving more by cultural influences which
may be hundreds of years even thousands, apart. The substrate is also,
presumably, still evolving. Where human consciousness does need to
evolve, at this stage in our evolution, is away from arrogant
anthropocentricity. The notion that in this small galaxy, in the middle of
myriads of other galaxies, this one small creature living for only an instant,
when seen through astronomical and cosmological viewpoints, was of any
singular importance, is simply ridiculous.
Hypnosis and the "The Unconscious Mind " are both concepts we
will be closer to understanding as we do more research. I do not have any
123
difficulty in seeing them incorporated into a biological theory. Focusing,
concentration, attention and ignoring are all mechanisms functioning within
the concept of consciousness itself. I suspect that one of the most important
lines of research into consciousness will be in finding the pathways which
control and disseminate input. By control, I mean arrest. So although
consciousness is taking in vast amounts of data, we, as beings, can only deal
with so much. So mechanisms exist to limit access and to actively forget
certain inputs, and focus on what may be more important. This was
important to survival and is central to so-called normal “sanity”. This again
brings in the area of hallucinogenic drugs as a research tool.
By delimiting the control mechanisms, or by use of meditation or
hallucinogenic drugs, we are likely permitting a higher awareness. As
mentioned previously, it is my opinion that “normal” sanity does depend on
this limitation ability of the brain. At the same time we are then limiting the
access to a vast number of neurons, which as far as we can tell, we are
underutilizing. But I have to emphasize that my study, in this book, is about
the basic mechanisms of consciousness and I cannot extend it, at this time, to
any higher levels.
As we have seen in the last paragraph, our consciousness is
"capacity-limited". We have to learn more about those mechanisms
involved. The control mechanisms in the limbic system and the frontal
cortex will get far more attention than they currently receive, We will also
pin down the neurophysiological analogues of many neurological deficits.
This will not be confined to humans. To further enhance our ability to
discover new and better behavioural adaptations to our environment, may
mean, for the first time in our history, taking into account that the whole
animal kingdom, excluding us, was not created for our benefit.
There are many reasons that books on consciousness and mind will
continue to be written. It is the last frontier in many ways. It is also close to
the heart for so many of us, whether we are doctors, neuroscientists,
philosophers, or simply curious human beings. The future developments in
124
neuropathology and neurophysiology are going to shed increasing light on
what still appears to be such a mystery.
I have tried to paint a picture of a physiological notion of
consciousness which can provide paths for further research. It does imply
that certain philosophical problems may be insoluble and best left to those
willing to waste their days deciding if we have free will or if all is predetermined. So the "Hard problem" of consciousness may well remain an
insoluble philosophical perplexity precisely because it need never have been
invented. I have tried, also, to show that language in its evolution,
symbolically, may go beyond what it can and should do, into realms of
fantasy that no longer bear a relation to reality. Maybe it does need to extend
into realms of fantasy but the problem has been the tendency to link the
apparent structure of language to existential reality.
We can borrow from anthropology here, because of the tremendously
useful distinction between "emic" and etic" studies. "Emic" studies come
from within a culture, more subjective, whereas "etic" would be the
observed behaviour. This was first used by Kenneth Pike, a linguist, as an
attempt to portray the difficulties of any truly objective "outside" account of
behaviour. It becomes a methodological solution to an epistemological issue.
We can never truly know what it feels like to be a bat, but, as stated before, I
am not sure we can even truly know what it feels like to be another human
being. Until we make "emic" attempts from the outside we will never
penetrate that barrier. In other words we make the barrier disappear by
methodology. I may never know what it is like to be a bat but I will never
get close to finding out until I make maximum attempts to enter the bat
world. I need to try and study the little devil from his own viewpoint as far
as possible.
In the latter stages of finishing up this theoretical investigation, I came
across an interview between Susan Blackmore and Francisco Varela in
"Conversations on Consciousness", Oxford University Press, 2005. In it was
the concept of neurophenomenology, which was new to me. It struck a chord
immediately as another way to eliminate this terrible forced dichotomy of
125
subject-object. I realize naturally, that Eastern mystics would think us funny
for even considering that there is a problem. Varela, and indeed Blackmore
herself, both have a decided interest in Eastern philosophy and Varela was a
convert to Buddhism from an early age. He was not the first to make the
attempt to link phenomenological thinking with neuroscience. "First-Person
Science" has been seen as an oxymoron and remains highly controversial,
but the idea is not new, and in medical research we are starting to accept the
importance of Qualitative Medical Research, so it should not be such a
paradigm shift to accept neurophenomenology. Varela himself, sadly, died
of Hepatitis C in 2001, at a relatively young age and the world lost an
innovative thinker and researcher.
Qualitative Medical Research is in a sense a backlash to standard
empirical science. Instead of coming up with theory first, it utilizes even
subjective responses and then forms a so-called Ground-Based Theory
which is then subject to more rigorous experimentation.
Varela's critical concept was that of the Embodied Philosophy, i.e.
that cognition and consciousness are only to be understood in terms of the
body. The body needs to be seen as a total biological entity and
phenomenologically experienced for this to be a productive line of enquiry.
Varela stated, in a letter entitled "The Cosmos letter", sent to the Expo '90
Foundation, in Japan, that he believes we have evolved from our more
primitive dualistic and representational/computational mode of thinking :"Slowly the cards turned into considering that the basis of mind is the body
in coupled action, that is, the sensory-motor circuits establish the organism
as viable in situated contexts. From this perspective the brain appears as a
dynamical process (and not a syntactic one) of real time variables with a rich
self-organizing capacity (and not a representational machinery). So in this
sense the mind is not in the head since it is roots in the body as a whole and
also in the extended environment where the organism finds itself".
Personally I cannot over-emphasize enough the dangers of lingering
dualism in our culture and especially in medicine and even more so in
"mental health". Just as in Qualitative Medical Research, the whole point of
126
accepting subjective ideas is to amalgamate them into science and make
predictions and perform the normal scientific operations on any hypotheses
generated.
I would like to quote from an abstract of an article published in the
British Medical Journal BMJ 1998; 316 : 1230 (Published 18 April 1998) :"Qualitative research and evidence based medicine" authored by Judith
Green and Nicky Britten. I will quote the abstract as a whole as it echoes, in
a cogent manner, my own understanding of how to breach this
epistemological gap-:
"Qualitative research may seem unscientific and anecdotal to many
medical scientists. However, as the critics of evidence based medicine are
quick to point out, medicine itself is more than the application of scientific
rules. Clinical experience, based on personal observation, reflection, and
judgment, is also needed to translate scientific results into treatment of
individual patients. Personal experience is often characterised as being
anecdotal, ungeneralisable, and a poor basis for making scientific decisions.
However, it is often a more powerful persuader than scientific publication in
changing clinical practice, as illustrated by the occasional series “A patient
who changed my practice” in the BMJ.”
“In an attempt to widen the scope of evidence based medicine, recent
workshops have included units on other subjects, including economic
analysis and qualitative research. However, to do so is to move beyond the
discipline of clinical epidemiology that underpins evidence based medicine.
Qualitative research, in particular, addresses research questions that are
different from those considered by clinical epidemiology. Qualitative
research can investigate practitioners' and patients' attitudes, beliefs, and
preferences, and the whole question of how evidence is turned into practice.
The value of qualitative methods lies in their ability to pursue systematically
the kinds of research questions that are not easily answered by experimental
methods.”
127
“We use the example of asthma treatment to illustrate how qualitative
methods can broaden the scope of evidence based medicine. Although there
is consensus over evidence based practice in the treatment of asthma,
questions remain about general practitioners' use of clinical guidelines and
patients' use of prescribed medication.”
So like a therapist I have to be empathic to my subject, so that I will
start to see the world from his/her viewpoint. It is no different with, for
example, a very primitive tribe of humans, or an infant. We are trying to
decipher what they might be getting at. They are all communicating, just as
most animals are. So we need the humility to breach the communication gap.
Trying to understand what a lion might be saying is difficult because we are
not lions, but that makes it a more interesting challenge.
We cannot even make the assumption, as in the movie "Contact", that
the language of mathematics, especially prime numbers would be intergalactic. A life form based on a different element may be feasible but would
be very different from us in every way. Would it be looking at the same
universe? Would science still work the same way? We have no way of
knowing. If another form of creature is not DNA based, it would be very
strange to us. However we ought to be able to figure out more easily what a
lion is trying to say and at least let Wittgenstein know finally.
As a philosopher, I want consciousness to be less of a mystery, and to
feel confidence in its investigation. Neurophysiology must play a greater
role. In terms of the pervasive paradigm, inherited from Descartes, we do not
need further Mind/Body split theories in any form, holding back both
philosophy and science. As a physician, I would like to see the whole
concept of diseases of the humans to be seen strictly as that, i.e. diseases of
human beings. That is to say of a complete human being, not one little
dissected or created part. So diabetes and schizophrenia would both be
diseases of the human being. Psychiatry would become far closer to
mainstream medicine and neurophysiology would provide the link. A
psychiatrist would simply be a specialist in disorders of behaviour,
perception, emotion, ideation, but definitely not a specialist in "mental
128
disease". Logotherapy would still have a place but not be linked to
mysterious entities such as minds. Cognitive behavioural modification is an
advance in terminology. The process of eliminating "mind" is somewhat
utilitarian. You gradually realize that you were operating with a concept that
you quite simply do not require anymore. It will remain as a cultural item
with non-specific ontology.
I am certainly not saying that neuroscience completely "explains"
consciousness but I am saying that we should not expect an explanation or
definition of consciousness. If we can show more of the workings and move
on with science assisted by some philosophical clarification, then we will
approach a clearer comprehension of this concept of consciousness.
I also wish to stress that I do not believe that the only role philosophy
has is to clarify, or play the therapist. Philosophy has an important
clarification role and also can lay claim to be theoretically constructivist
when it needs to be. If it generates theories which are then shot down by
either other philosophers or by scientists, that is how it should be.
For the mystery of consciousness itself we will probably see a gradual
erosion of philosophical perplexity, as neurophysiology, and more
specifically neurophilosophy, answer more and more of the details of this
mystery.
129
Index
Abarognosis, 86
African Grey parrot, 29
Agnosia, 86,
Alien hand syndrome, 93
amoebae, 2
amygdala, 62
Animal, 27
animal kingdom, 13, 70, 103,
anthropocentric, 22, 31, 43
Aphasia, 94
Apraxia, 88
Aristotle, 4, 82
Arnold B. Scheibel,, 58
ATP, 2
Australopithecine, 117
bacteria, 65
Basal Ganglia, 61
Bat, 71
Bertrand Russell, IX
Big Bang, 1
Biosemiotics, 34
bird, 22, 30
blind-sight, 41
brain, 10,
15, 17, 18, 20, 23, 24, 25, 31,
32, 43,
46, 53, ,
74,
83,
Broca, 50
Burgess Shale, 5, 6
Cambrian, 5,
cerebral cortex, 4, 47,
52, 57, 97, 111
Chalmers, 78, 115
chimpanzee, 26
Chimps, 21
Coacervates, 2
cognitive, 50, 86, 96, 99, 115
consciousness, 4,6,14,22,26,33,53,62,64
,66,73,81,83,98,103,107,120,129
Cyanobacteria, 2
Darwin, 4, 39
Descartes, 128
deutocerebrum, 16
DNA, 3, 4, 118, 128
Dolphins, 31, 55,
Donald Griffin, 27
Dr M O'C Drury, 103
Ectoderm, 49
emergent, 71, 113
emic, 22, 125
emotions, 4, 20, 26, 28,54
, 89, 104, 108, 118
empirical, 46,103
ethologists, 27
etic, 22, 125
Evolution, 4, 113
Fish, 15,44
130
G.E.Moore, 123
Galapagos Islands, 22
Gazzaniga, 27, 52
Gilbert Ryle, 108
Gorilla, 39
Hard problem, , 108, 125
Homo Sapiens, 108
human consciousness, 4, 27, 66,
Jane Goodal, 46
Jeffrey Masson, 48
Kant, Immanuel, 104
Kenneth Pike, 125
Koko,32, 39
Locked-in Syndrome, 70, 86
Luria, 51, 68, 84
Marc Bekoff, 38
Margaret Klinowska,
55
mind, 8, 41,53,80,
Monkeys,27
neurophilosophy, 129
pain, 15,32, 40, 53,
86, 90, 108, 112
Philosophical Investigations, 40, 109
prebionts, 2
Qualia, 108, 115
Qualitative Medical Research, 125
Russell, Bertrand 72, 112
Stephen Jay Gould, 4
Stephen Wiltshire, 109
Steven Roger Fischer, 29
Susan B.Eirich, 35
Susan Greenfield, 107
Susanne Langer, 106
Temple Grandin,16
Thomas Grandin, 13, 14, 80
Thomas Knierim, 53
Thomas Nagel, 71
Varela, Francisco115, 116
Wernicke, 67
Whitehead, 42
Windsor Chorlton, 22
Wittgenstein L,11, 39, 40, 89,
108, 112, 121,
131