Columbia Law School
Scholarship Archive
Faculty Scholarship
Faculty Publications
2016
Overview of Copyright Law
Jane C. Ginsburg
Columbia Law School, jane.ginsburg@law.columbia.edu
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship
Part of the Intellectual Property Law Commons
Recommended Citation
Jane C. Ginsburg, Overview of Copyright Law, OXFORD HANDBOOK OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY LAW, ROCHELLE
DREYFUSS & JUSTINE PILA, EDS., OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS, 2018; COLUMBIA PUBLIC LAW RESEARCH PAPER NO.
14-518 (2016).
Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/1990
This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It
has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For
more information, please contact scholarshiparchive@law.columbia.edu.
Overview of Copyright Law
Forthcoming, Oxford Handbook of Intellectual Property, Rochelle Dreyfuss & Justine Pila,
Eds.:
Jane C. Ginsburg, Columbia University School of Law*
Abstract
This article offers an overview of copyright in general in common law and civil
law countries, with an emphasis on the U.S. and the European Union. It addresses
the history and philosophies of copyright (authors’ right), subject matter of
copyright (including the requirement of fixation and the exclusion of “ideas”),
formalities, initial ownership and transfers of title, duration, exclusive moral and
economic rights (including reproduction, adaptation, public performance and
communication and making available to the public, distribution and exhaustion of
the distribution right), exceptions and limitations (including fair use), and
remedies. The article also covers the liability of intermediaries, and new
copyright obligations concerning technological protections and copyright
management information. It concludes with some observations concerning the
role of copyright in promoting creativity and free expression.
Key words:
intellectual property, copyright, authors' right, Berne Convention, WCT, originality, fixation,
moral rights, reproduction right, adaptation right, performance/communication rights, making
available right, distribution right, three-step test, fair use, Information Society Directive,
intermediary liability
a.
History and philosophies of copyright (authors’ right)1
Copyright is the law of literary and artistic property. It regulates the ownership and
exercise of rights in creative works. Copyright laws vest exclusive rights in the creators of
works of authorship. The justifications for copyright spread along a spectrum from natural
rights-based ownership of the fruits of one’s intellectual labors to utilitarian expectations that
granting authors property rights in their works will encourage them to create works for the
greater benefit of society. On the one end, authorship alone commands strong proprietary rights;
* Thanks to Jacob Grubman, Columbia Law School class of 2016 for research assistance.
1 The regime that common law countries denominate ‘copyright’ in civil law countries is generally called ‘author’s
right’ (eg, ‘droit d’ auteur’ in French, ‘diritto d’autore’ in Italian, ‘Urheberrecht’ in German). Although the
difference in nomenclature may denote philosophical differences of orientation, with common law countries
focusing on the object of protection, and civil law countries on the subject of protection, these differences are
relatively insignificant in practice, and therefore for simplicity, this article will refer throughout to ‘copyright.’
1
on the other, those rights result only, and sparingly, from a necessary bargain on behalf of the
broader public. Civil law regimes most often tend toward the creators’ entitlement end of the
spectrum, and common law systems generally situate at the social contract end. But these
characterizations are largely caricatures: mixed motives in fact pervade civilian and common law
copyright systems alike, and a given national law’s location on the spectrum is often more a
matter of emphasis than of fundamental orientation. Moreover, evolving economic, social and
technological conditions inevitably alter the intensity of that emphasis.
Copyright laws emerged from printing monopolies. Following the invention of printing,
a system of printing privileges, paired with State control over the content of the works,
developed in many European States, particularly in Venice, the Papal States, and France. The
governing authority, having verified the work’s political and religious orthodoxy, granted the
petitioner, usually a printer-bookseller, but sometimes the work’s author, a time-limited
monopoly over the printing, selling, and importation of copies of the work.2 England departed
from this scheme in vesting in the publishers themselves the control over the dissemination of
books. In 1557, the Crown granted to the Stationers’ Company, made up of the leading
publishers of London, a monopoly over book publication (excepting persons who received
printing privileges directly from the Crown), thus placing in the hands of the guild the power to
restrain the publication of seditious or heretical works. Publishers were given an exclusive and
perpetual right of publication of works that passed muster with the Government and the Church
(by way of the Star Chamber).3 As with many systems of printing privileges, the English
monopoly primarily promoted investment in the material and labor of producing and distributing
books; protecting or rewarding authors was generally an ancillary objective.4
After the English licensing laws lapsed at the end of the 17th century, Parliament enacted
the Statute of Anne in 1710. The Act’s title and first section announce the objectives that
underlie much copyright law and policy. Titled “An act for the encouragement of learning,” the
Statute of Anne continued: “Whereas printers, booksellers, and other persons have of late
frequently taken the liberty of printing, reprinting, and publishing, or causing to be printed,
reprinted, and published, books and other writings, without the consent of the authors or
2 On printing privileges, see, eg, Elizabeth Armstrong, Before Copyright: The French Book-Privilege System 1498–
1526 (CUP 1990); Maria Grazia Blasio, Cum Gratia et Privilegio: Programmi editoriali e Politica Ponteficia a
Roma 1487-1527 (Rome 1988); Carlo Castellani, ‘I privilegi di stampa e la proprieta’ letteraria in Venezia dalla
introduzione della stampa nella citta’ (1888) 36 Archivio Veneto 127–39; Pierina Fontana, ‘Inizi della proprietà
letteraria nello stato pontificio (saggio di documenti dell’Archivio vaticano)’ (1929) 3 Accademie e Biblioteche
d’Italia 204-21; Rudolph Hirsch, Printing, Selling and Reading, 1450-1550 (Otto Harrassowitz 1974); Angela
Nuovo and Christian Coppens, I Giolito e la stampa nell’Italia del XVI secolo (Droz 2005); Jane C Ginsburg,
‘Proto-property in Literary and Artistic Works: Sixteenth-Century Papal Printing Privileges’ (2013) 36 Colum J L &
the Arts 345 (hereafter Ginsburg, ‘Proto-property in Literary and Artistic Works’). See also sources cited, infra, n 3.
3 See John Feather, A History of British Publishing (Routledge 1988) 31–32 (hereafter Feather, A History of British
Publishing) (describing how the Stationers Company ‘became an equal partner with the Crown in the suppression of
undesirable books’).
4 See, eg, Cyprien Bladgen, The Stationers’ Company: A History 1403–1959 (George Allen & Unwin 1960); Lotte
Hellinga and JB Trapp (eds), Cambridge History of the Book in Britain, Vol. 3, 1400–1557 (CUP 1998); Mark Rose,
Authors and Owners: The Invention of Copyright (Harvard University Press 1993) (hereafter Rose, Authors and
Owners); Feather, A History of British Publishing (n 3). Authors could directly hold privileges, however, and in
some systems of printing privileges, particularly the Papal privileges, but to a lesser extent in Venice and France as
well, authors in fact frequently applied for and received monopolies over their works’ publication and distribution.
2
proprietors of such books and writings, to their very great detriment, and too often to the ruin of
them and their families: for preventing therefore such practices for the future, and for the
encouragement of learned men to compose and write useful books . . .” The Act granted to
authors exclusive rights of printing, reprinting and importation of copies to last for 21 years for
existing works and for 14 years for works published in the future. Moreover, were the author still
living at the end of the first 14-year term, the exclusive rights of reproduction and distribution
would revert to the author for an additional 14 years. Registration of the title at Stationers’ Hall
was a condition of obtaining the remedies of statutory copyright.
Where justifications for printing privileges most often rested on the need to prevent freeriding off of the printer’s investment,5 the Statute of Anne echoed this theme, but focused instead
on authors. It thus became the first law explicitly and systematically to vest copyright in the
work’s creator. Two factors, one philosophical, one economic, motivated this shift in
orientation. First, making authors the owners of the exclusive right reflects the Enlightenment
tenet that property derives from labor. From ownership of the physical fruits of agricultural and
other labors, it is not a long step to ownership of the incorporeal fruits of intellectual labor.
Indeed, if John Locke voiced the former argument in his Treatises on Government, he made the
latter in his writings on the expiration of the Licensing Act.6 The replacement of the Licensing
Act with laws vesting property rights in authors also sought to break the monopoly of the
Stationer’s Company by promoting the rise of other publishers with whom authors might
negotiate.7 In that respect, one may perceive the author’s reversion right not only as a creatororiented endeavor to ensure that authors share in the success of their works, but also as a measure
to promote competition among booksellers, for the author who retrieves his rights is free to grant
the second fourteen-year term to another publisher.8
The United States copyright tradition also recognizes both the general public interest in
fostering creativity, and the individual rights of creators – for limited times – over the fruits of
their intellectual labors. The Constitution’s copyright clause provides “The Congress shall have
power . . . To promote the progress of science and useful arts, by securing for limited times to
authors and inventors the exclusive right to their respective writings and discoveries.”9 The
clause echoes the Statute of Anne’s incentive rationale, but its authorization to Congress to
promote the progress of learning “by securing for limited times to authors . . . the exclusive right
to their . . . writings” also reveals undercurrents of natural property claims, for “securing”
suggests that some kind of exclusive right already inhered in works of authorship. Hence
Madison’s reference in Federalist 43 to copyright in Britain as “a right of common law.” The
clause’s direction that the exclusive right be “for limited times,” in the plural, may also advert to
5 That said, authors who received printing privileges also often invoked the need for a privilege to prevent others
from reaping the benefits of their labors, see, eg, Ginsburg, ‘Proto-property in Literary and Artistic Works’ (n 3).
6 On these writings, see Laura Moscati, ‘Un “Memorandum” di John Locke tra Censorship e Copyright’ (2003)
LXXVI Rivista di storia del diritto italiano 69 (hereafter Moscati, ‘Un “Memorandum” di John Locke’).
7 See Feather, A History of British Publishing (n 3); Moscati, ‘Un “Memorandum” di John Locke’ (n 6); Rose,
Authors and Owners (n 4).
8 On the reversion right in the Statute of Anne and its successors in British and U.S. Copyright law, see Lionel
Bently and Jane C Ginsburg, ‘“The sole right shall return to the Author”: Anglo-American Authors’ Reversion
Rights from the Statute of Anne to Contemporary U.S. Copyright’ (2011) 25 Berkeley Tech LJ 1475.
9
US Constitution, art 1, § 8, cl 8.
3
the Statute of Anne’s conditional second term of copyright, and thereby implicitly endorse the
author’s reversion right established by the English example.
The first U.S. copyright statute adopted many features of the Statute of Anne, including
the dual 14-year terms with reversion to the surviving author, and registration and deposit
formalities. The rights secured were to “print, publish and vend,” and the subject matter covered
“any map, chart or book.” In the handful of major copyright revisions (principally, 1831 and
1909) through the 1976 Act (and in the more frequent amendments since), Congress has
gradually increased the kinds of works that are eligible for copyright and the kinds of exclusive
rights afforded to the copyright owner. As Congress has increasingly aligned the U.S. copyright
system with international norms, it has also progressively extended the period of copyright
protection and reduced the significance of compliance with statutory formalities.
b.
Subject matter
Copyright protects creative works of the human mind. The threshold of creativity is low,
and carries no requirement of artistic merit, civic virtue, or commercial value. In the E.U., a
showing that the work is the “author’s own intellectual creation,”10 or in the U.S., a showing of
“at least some minimal degree of creativity,”11 meet the standard. Nor, despite the grounding of
one rationale for copyright in entitlement to the fruits of intellectual labor, need an author
demonstrate that she labored mightily: the fruit of a moment’s inspiration, as well as the result of
long hours of research and reflection both can qualify. By the same token, expenditure of labor
(or “sweat of the brow”), without some increment of creativity, for example in the selection or
arrangement of information, however painstakingly gathered, does not suffice.
Human agency in the creation of a work is implicit, hence no copyright inheres in objects
produced by purely natural or feral forces, for example, driftwood or paintings by chimpanzees.
By contrast, copyrightable authorship can result when human beings manipulate or build on such
objects, for example by reshaping, combining or coloring pieces of driftwood. Similarly,
computer-assisted works, such as digitally altered images, can qualify, but purely computergenerated outputs, such as automatic translations, would not.12
Most copyright systems distinguish the creation of works from their “interpretation”
through performance, reserving “copyright” to the former (such as musical compositions) and
denominating the latter (such as vocal or instrumental performances of the compositions) as the
subject matter of “neighboring rights.” (The U.S., however, considers audio-recorded
performances – called “sound recordings” – to come within copyrightable subject matter.)
10
Directive 2001/29/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 22 May 2001 on the harmonisation of
certain aspects of copyright and related rights in the information society [2001] OJ L167/10 (hereafter ‘InfoSoc
Directive’); Case C-5/08 Infopaq International A/S v Danske Dagblades Forening [2009] ECR I-6569 (hereafter
Infopaq).
11
Feist Publ’ns Inc v Rural Tel Serv Co 499 US 340, 345 (1991).
12
The U.K. Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988, however, includes a provision on computer-generated works.
It is not clear whether their copyright coverage is consistent with the autonomous EU norm of originality articulated
in Infopaq (n 10).
4
Apart from their characterization of performances or interpretations of works, national
copyright laws may also diverge in their expression of what constitutes copyrightable subject
matter: some laws provide only a general description, such as “works of the mind,” while others,
primarily in common law countries, list categories of works, such as literary works, musical
compositions, audiovisual works, etc. It is not clear whether these categories are illustrative or
limitative, thus whether an unlisted type of work would still be protected if it manifests original
creativity but cannot be analogized to a recognized category.
Fixation
In addition, many, mostly common law, national regimes require that the work be fixed
in a tangible medium of expression before copyright will attach. In the U.S. the Constitutional
reference to “writings” has been thought to require fixation. These national laws, however, are
generally open-ended as to the medium of fixation; it need not be a traditional format, such as
paper, and the work need not be directly perceptible, for example, it may be a musical
composition fixed in a phonogram. The media of fixation also encompass new technologies
such as computer memory. National laws also differ regarding whether the author must
authorize the fixation to bring the work within the subject matter of copyright. For example, the
U.S. requires that the author, or someone authorized by her, make the fixation,13 while the U.K.
considers that even an unauthorized fixation (such as a surreptitious recording) brings the work
within copyright (and also may make the person doing the unauthorized fixation an infringer).
Fixation serves an evidentiary purpose; it makes it possible to ascertain what the work is.
The probative role of fixation may explain why, in the U.S. the fixation must permit the work to
be “perceived, reproduced or otherwise communicated for a period of more than transitory
duration.”14 But the medium of the fixation should not be confused with the work itself. The
work is incorporeal Fixation is the threshold which all works must cross to qualify for copyright
protection in those countries that require fixation, but once across, the work exists independently
of any particular material object in which it may be concretized. For example, a choreographic
work may be filmed, or fixed in notation, but neither of these instantiations are the work. Once a
work is “fixed,” and therefore within the scope of copyright coverage, it no longer matters for
purposes of infringement whether the work was copied from a fixed or unfixed source. Thus, for
example, copying a protected dramatic work from a book containing the text of the play will
infringe the work (assuming no applicable exceptions), but so will the unauthorized recording or
transcription of the dialog from a live performance of the work.
By the same token, even when the medium of fixation, for example, a photograph of an
ice sculpture, may be a work of authorship in its own right, the second-level work of authorship
that portrays an underlying work should not be confused with, and for the reasons discussed
above, confers no rights in, the work portrayed. The photograph may fix the ice sculpture, thus
13 Exceptionally, and pursuant to international obligations under article 14(1) of the World Trade Organization
Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property (TRIPS), the U.S. Copyright Act has since 2004
provided for musical performers’ rights to authorize the fixation or transmission of their unfixed performances, 17
USC § 1101; the U.S. criminal code also imposes penalties for unauthorized audio or audiovisual fixation and
distribution of musical performances, see 18 USC § 2319A.
14
17 USC § 101.
5
preserving the record of the work after the original has melted, but the two works are as distinct
as if the photograph had depicted a previously fixed sculpture, such as a statue in bronze.
Quantum of creativity
If the level of creativity is low, it is nonetheless unclear whether the work itself must
achieve some degree of heft. In U.S. copyright doctrine, short phrases and commonplace designs
are thought to lack minimal creativity,15 or are likely to be needed as basic elements for others’
creations. The more a phrase is generic or descriptive, or the more it gives instructions to
accomplish a functional objective, the less U.S. courts are inclined to permit copyright to
interfere with others seeking to make practical use of the words.16
But, as the headlines to news stories often demonstrate, a short phrase may in fact be very
creative, yet also be very brief. Brevity is, after all, the soul of wit; why should it be a bar to
copyright? The building blocks rationale makes sense if the objective of excluding short phrases
is to prevent private claims of right in elements so basic as to belie anyone’s “creation.” By
contrast, if the goal is simply to expel expressions that fail to cross some unstated threshold of
heft regardless of their level of creativity, then it is not clear what if any sensible copyright
policy the exclusion advances.
E.U. copyright doctrine appears less wedded to quantity. The Court of the Justice of the
European Union, construing the EU Information Society Directive, ruled in Infopaq International
A/S v. Danske Dagblades Forening that a sequence of 11 words could meet the “author’s own
intellectual creation” standard.17
Derivative works and compilations
Because the threshold of originality is low, copyright also protects works that are based
on or build on pre-existing works (“derivative works”). Thus translations, musical arrangements,
motion pictures derived from novels, and other adaptations all can be copyright subject matter
(though if the pre-existing work is still under copyright, the author’s or proprietor’s permission
to adapt the underlying work will generally be necessary). Similarly, compilations of works or
of data may be protected if either their selection or organization is minimally creative. In the
cases both of derivative works and of compilations, the adapter’s or compiler’s copyright covers
only to the “new matter,” that is, to the original contribution to the underlying material, and does
not extend to or affect the copyright status of that material. For example, a modern-day sequel to
a 19th-century novel will enjoy a copyright in its expression of new plot and character elements;
the sequel will not remove the prior literary work from the public domain, nor will it prevent
See Copyright Office Regulations, 37 CFR § 202.1(a) (excluding, inter alia, ‘Words and short phrases such as
names, titles, and slogans; familiar symbols or designs’).
16.
See, eg, Magic Mktg v Mailing Servs 634 F Supp 769 (WD Pa 1986) (refusing to extend copyright to such phrases
as ‘priority message: contents require immediate attention’). See also Southco Inc v Kanebridge Corp 390 F 3d 276
(3d Cir 2004) (en banc) (holding part numbers used to assemble machine parts not copyrightable); Spilman v MosbyYearbook Inc 115 F Supp 2d 148 (D Mass 2000) (holding grammatical alterations and ‘stylistic tweaking’ are not
copyrightable); Apple Computer v Microsoft Corp 799 F Supp 1006 (ND Cal 1992) (holding phrase ‘Get Info,’ used
as part of computer graphical interface, was not copyrightable).
17
Supra, n 10.
15
6
other authors from going back to the 19th-century source to create works using the characters and
plots as they were developed in the source work. A compilation of data does not confer
protection on the compiled information, apart from its original presentation in the compilation.
Thus, for example, the author of a guide listing and rating restaurants may prevent the wholesale
copying of the ratings, which constitute the author’s original contribution to the information, but
she may not prevent others from reproducing the information in her guide regarding the names
and addresses of the restaurants she listed.
Idea/expression distinction
Copyright does not protect everything contained within an original work of authorship.
We have seen that with respect to works incorporating preexisting public domain works or data,
copyright covers only the author’s original treatment of those elements, and not the underlying
material itself. Copyright excludes not only information (data), but also ideas and processes.
While the latter two might be original and creative, the law considers them to be necessary
building blocks toward everyone’s creativity, and thus leaves them “to range freely.”18 This
doctrine is known in some countries as the “idea/expression dichotomy.” Thus, for example,
Marcel Duchamp’s drawing of a moustache and a goatee on a postcard of the Mona Lisa may
have been highly creative (as well as provocative), but any copyright in the work which
Duchamp (equally provocatively) titled “L.H.O.O.Q.”19would not have entitled him to prevent
others from acquiring reproductions of the Mona Lisa or any other public domain iconic image
and superimposing different combinations or depictions of facial hair or coiffure. The exclusion
of processes further seeks to separate the domains of copyright and of patent. Patents protect
functional works, if they meet the much higher standard of prerequisite creativity (novelty and
non-obviousness, or “inventive step”). Copyright doctrine does not permit “end-runs” around
the more restrictive standard for a patent by resort to copyright’s lesser level of creativity. 20
Where a work of authorship combines expressive and functional elements, copyright will protect
only the form of expression in which the ideas or processes are communicated. Moreover, if in
order to duplicate or put into use an unprotected idea, concept, or system, it is necessary
substantially to copy another’s otherwise copyrightable expression, such copying is not an
infringement. In those instances, the expression “merges” with the idea, and shares the idea’s
unprotectable status.21
Applied art
See Henri Desbois, Le droit d’auteur (3rd edn, Dalloz 1978) 22 (‘[les idées] sont par essence et par destination de
libre parcours’).
19
Pronounced aloud in French, the letters read ‘elle a chaud au cul’ (more delicately translated as ‘she is in a state
of sexual desire’).
20 Handbook editors will cite to Estelle Derclaye’s chapter
21 Software may present the most frequent example of the difficulties of distinguishing expression from function.
International treaties mandate copyright protection for computer programs, but also declare the exclusion of ‘ideas,
procedures, methods of operation or mathematical concepts as such.’ Compare Agreement on Trade-Related
Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (opened for signature 15 April 1994, entered into force 1 January 1995) 33
ILM 81 (hereafter TRIPS), art 10(1) and WIPO Copyright Treaty (opened for signature 20 December 1996, entered
into force 6 March 2002) 36 ILM 65 (hereafter WCT), art 4(1) with TRIPS art 9(2) and WCT art 2.
18
7
Works of applied art, such as furniture design, present particular difficulties, to which
national laws have responded differently. In some countries, the original design of a useful
article may enjoy a copyright so long as the article’s function does not command the design
elements. In other countries, including the U.S., the availability of a “multiplicity of forms”
through which the same function might be achieved does not suffice; the design elements must
be “separable” from the article’s function. Such a rule tends to confine most works of applied art
to the realm of design patents or other specific design protection laws.
c.
Formalities
Copyright formalities—conditions precedent to the existence or enforcement of
copyright, such as provision of information about works of authorship that will put the public on
notice as to a work’s protected status and its copyright ownership, or deposit of copies of the
work for the national library or other central authority—have performed a variety of functions in
copyright history. Formalities that condition the existence or enforcement of copyright on
supplying information about works of authorship may have been intended to enable effective
title searching, thus furthering the economic interests both of copyright owners and of potential
exploiters. Copyright-constitutive formalities, such as notice of copyright, deposit, registration
and renewal, erect a barrier to the existence of protection, concomitantly casting into the public
domain published works that fail to comply. These formalities thus (at least in theory) have
divided works of perceived economic significance worth the effort of compliance from the mass
of other creations, leaving the latter free for others to exploit. When failure to comply with
formalities results in forfeiture of the copyright, this extreme sanction arguably protects
exploiters who, in the absence of notice, might not otherwise have known that its author has
claimed copyright in the work. Authors might have exclusive rights to print, reprint and vend,
but they first would be put to the burden of making their claims clear.
The extent to which any system of formalities in fact achieved all or any of the above
objectives is open to question. By the beginning of the 20th century most countries had
abandoned formal prerequisites to protection and had made the obligation to deposit copies for
the national library a free-standing duty, thus divorcing it from the existence or enforcement of
copyright. The U.S., however, retained the notice formality until it joined the Berne Convention
in 1989 and modified its law to comply with that treaty’s prohibition on conditioning the
enjoyment or exercise of copyright on fulfillment of formalities. The U.S. continues to make
registration of works with the Copyright Office a prerequisite to judicial enforcement of
copyright (for works of U.S. origin) and to awards of statutory damages or attorney’s fees (for all
works regardless of country of origin).22
The waning of mandatory formalities has, some contend, rendered rights clearance
excessively complicated because without notice or registration it is difficult to ascertain if the
work is still protected, or who owns the rights that a third party might seek to exploit. As a
result, works might be “orphaned,” cast in a limbo in which they retain copyright protection, but
resist licensing because the would-be licensee cannot locate an owner with whom to transact.
The public thus is deprived of beneficial republications or adaptations of these works. It is not
17 USC §§ 411, 412. See generally, Jane C Ginsburg, ‘The US Experience with Mandatory Copyright
Formalities: A Love/Hate Relationship’ (2010) 33 Colum J L & the Arts 311.
22
8
clear to what extent the “orphan works” problem in fact flows from the waning of mandatory
formalities, as opposed to longer copyright terms (see infra). In many countries, collecting
societies maintain records of copyright ownership, or there are other voluntary registries of
works and their owners, and digital identifiers may now and in the future facilitate locating and
transacting with copyright owners even in the absence of a centralized, State-managed registry.
d.
Entitlement/Ownership
1.
Initial ownership
Copyright laws generally vest the exclusive rights comprising a copyright in the author,
the human creator of the work. Where the work results from the collaboration of more than one
author it may be considered a “joint work” or “work of collaboration,” and its rights will be held
in common, absent a contract to the contrary. But countries differ over the characterization of a
work as “joint.” For example, in the U.K. “a ‘work of joint authorship’ means a work produced
by the collaboration of two or more authors in which the contribution of each author is not
distinct from that of the other author or authors.”23 But in the U.S., “a ‘joint work’ is a work
prepared by two or more authors with the intention that their contributions be merged into
inseparable or interdependent parts of a unitary whole” (emphasis supplied).24 Thus, for
example, under U.K. law, a song produced by the collaboration of a composer and a lyricist
would be two separate distinct works, words and music, while under U.S. law, music and lyrics
created in collaboration would be a single “musical work[], including any accompanying
words.”25 On the other hand what constitutes a collaboration may differ not only across national
copyright regimes, but, in the U.S., across federal circuit courts of appeal. In some jurisdictions
an intent to collaborate may not suffice; it may in addition be necessary to show that each coauthor’s contributions would separately have been copyrightable26 (a standard perhaps in tension
with the statutory inclusion of inseparable contributions), or that the alleged co-author was the
“mastermind” of the resulting work27 (a standard perhaps in tension with a concept of shared
authorship).
In some countries all co-authors must agree on the grant of exclusive or non exclusive
rights in a joint work; in others, including the U.S., any one joint author may license non
exclusive rights without the others’ accord, but must account to them for profits. Co-authors
need not each have contributed equally to the work’s creation, but courts may exclude from coauthorship status a person who has merely brought ideas to the development of the work, such as
an editor in a publishing house, or whose contribution consisted primarily of executing the
technical know-how to give a work concrete form, such as a welder who assembles a
monumental sculpture under the artist’s direction.
Employee and commissioned works
23
UK Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988, s 10(1).
17 USC § 101.
25
17 USC § 102(a)(2).
26 See, eg, Thomson v Larson 147 F 3d 195 (2d Cir 1998).
27 Aalmuhammed v Lee 202 F 3d 1227, 1233 (9th Cir 2000).
24
9
National copyright laws diverge over the initial ownership of copyright by employers or
other hiring parties. In the U.S., but also in the U.K. and the Netherlands, for example, the
copyright in works prepared by employees in furtherance of their employment vests in the
employer.28 The U.S. copyright act goes so far as to denominate the employer of the creator of a
“work made for hire” the “author” of that work. U.S. “Works made for hire” come in two
varieties, (1) employee-created works; and (2) certain specially ordered or commissioned works,
so long as the type of work figures among a limitative list set out in the copyright act (the list
includes contributions to audiovisual works and compilations and collective works; the latter
category covers newspapers and periodicals), and both parties to the commission have signed a
writing that states that the work will be “for hire.” If these conditions are met, the hiring party
will own all rights in the work. If not, for example, if the commissioned work does not fall
within the statutory categories, or if a proper writing is not executed, then the creator remains the
“author” and first owner of all rights under copyright.
With respect to certain categories of work, particularly audiovisual works and computer
software, some countries either deem employers the initial owners of copyright or presume that
the actual creators have transferred their rights to the employer or producer.29 Some suspicion
that the nature of the authorship entailed in a computer program is more industrial than artistic
may underlie those countries’ departure from the usual rule of creator-ownership. By contrast,
with respect to audiovisual works, practical considerations, rather than perceptions of a lack of
the right kind of creativity, explain the vesting of, or presumption of transfer of copyright to,
producers of audiovisual works: these works often involve too many creative contributors for a
co-authorship ownership regime feasibly to enable the work’s exploitation.
2.
Transfers of ownership
Copyright, like other forms of tangible and intangible property, can be transferred from
the author to another, inter vivos or by will or by intestate succession, in whole or in part.30 To be
an effective transfer, an assignment of copyright or a grant of exclusive rights must be in writing
and signed by the grantor; in some countries, including the U.S., a non-exclusive grant may be
valid even though oral or inferred from conduct. Copyright ownership is “divisible:” the author
need not assign all her copyright interest, but may limit the scope of the grant to a particular time
period or territory, for example, a one-year license to perform a dramatic work in New York
City, or to a medium of expression, for example, the right to publish a novel but not the right to
28 17 USC § 201(b); Copyright, Designs, and Patents Act 1988, c 48, s 11 (UK); Auteurswet [Copyright Act], Stb
1912, 60, art 7 (Neth).
29 See, eg, Code de la propriété intellectuelle [Code of Intellectual Property] (hereafter France, Code of Intellectual
Property) arts L 113-9 (employers are presumptive owners of employee-created software); L 132-24 (presumption
of transfer of rights from statutory co-authors to producer of audiovisual work).
30 In ‘monist’ systems that follow the German copyright tradition, the economic rights and moral rights are
inseparably linked in one common right (like the trunk of a tree with two branches); because the moral
right/personality right is inalienable, the entire right cannot be transferred except upon the death of the author. As a
result, during the author’s lifetime, rights to economic uses may be licensed but not assigned. See Michael
Gruenberger, ‘Germany,’ sec 4[2][a] in Lionel Bently (ed), International Copyright Law and Practice (Matthew
Bender 2015) (hereafter Bently, International Copyright Law and Practice). Thanks to Dr. Silke von Lewinski for
the arboreal metaphor.
10
adapt it into a motion picture. Similarly, having granted some exclusive or non exclusive rights
to one co-contractant, the author or copyright owner can grant other rights to other parties, for
example, the novelist might grant English-language rights to one publisher, and foreign language
rights to other publishers.
Protections of authors as weaker parties
Because, at least until recently, most authors have been ill-equipped to commercialize
and disseminate their works on their own, authors have granted rights to intermediaries to market
their works. Since most authors are the weaker parties to publishing, production, or distribution
contracts, the resulting deal may favor the interests of the intermediary to the detriment of the
authors. Even putting aside the parties’ relative bargaining power, the highly speculative value
of literary, artistic and musical works at the time of their creation can mean that a contract for the
exploitation of a work of authorship may not fairly allocate the benefits of the work’s subsequent
success. Many national copyright laws have introduced a variety of corrective measures, starting
with the very first copyright act, the 1710 British Statute of Anne, which instituted the author’s
reversion right31 (still in force, albeit much modified, in US copyright law32) precisely in order to
enable authors to grant rights anew, with fuller knowledge of the work’s market value. Many
continental European copyright laws have imposed detailed limitations on the form and scope of
grants, for example ruling some rights to be inalienable, and/or requiring the precise articulation
of the scope of the rights granted (thus requiring ambiguities, such as the coverage of new media,
to be construed against the grantee), the provision of royalties for each mode of exploitation, and
“bestseller clauses” that grant or allow the author to negotiate for a higher percentage return in
the event of a significant disproportion between the agreed-upon remuneration and the work’s
actual success.33
Chattel rights
Finally, copyright law distinguishes between ownership of a copyright, or of any of the
exclusive rights under a copyright, and ownership of the material object in which the work is
embodied. The distinction first arose in the common law world in the 1741 Chancery decision in
Pope v. Curll,34 concerning the unauthorized publication of letters by Alexander Pope, of which
Act for the Encouragement of Learning, 8 Ann, c 19, s 11 (1710) (Gr Brit) (hereafter Statute of Anne) (‘the sole
right shall return to the author’ if still living at the expiration of the initial 14-year copyright term).
32
17 USC § 203 (inalienable right to terminate grants 35 years after the execution of the contract).
33
See, eg, France, Code of Intellectual Property (n 29) arts L 131-1–132-30; §§ 31–32(B)
Urheberrechtswahrnehmungsgesetz [Copyright Administration Act] v 9.9.1965, BGB1 I S 1294 (FRG); Loi Relative
au Droit D’Auteur et aux Droits Voisins [Law on Copyright and Neighboring Rights] of 30 June 1994 (as amended
by the Law of 3 April 1995), Moniteur Belge [MB] [Official Gazette of Belgium], 27 July 1994, 19297, arts 3, 11,
24, 26, 55. For analysis of particular national laws’ provisions on authors’ contracts, see, eg, Bently, International
Copyright Law and Practice (n 30). On amendments to the German author-protective provisions, see, eg, Wilhelm
Nordemann, ‘A Revolution of Copyright in Germany’ (2002) 49 J Copyr Soc’y 1041; William R. Cornish, ‘The
Author as Risk-Sharer’ (2002) 26 Colum J L & the Arts 1, 8–16. See generally, Paul Katzenberger, ‘Protection of
the Author as the Weaker Party to a Contract under International Copyright Contract Law’ (1988) 19 IIC 731.
34
Pope v Curll (1741) 2 Atk 342, discussed, eg, in Mark Rose, 'The Author in Court: Pope v. Curll (1741)' (1991–
92) 10 Cardozo Art & Ent LJ 475; Ronan Deazley, ‘Commentary on Pope v. Curll (1741)' (Primary Sources on
Copyright (1450-1900), 2008) < http://www.copyrighthistory.org/cam/tools/request/showRecord?id=commentary_
uk_1741a> accessed 27 April 2016.
31
11
Edmund Curll had obtained lawful possession. Pope contended that, as the letters’ author, he
retained the exclusive right to publish them; Curll rejoined that the publication right belonged to
him as the owner of the letters. Lord Chancellor Hardwicke distinguished the corporeal
“property of the paper,” which passed to the recipient of the letter, and thence to Curll, from the
incorporeal property in the words, which remained with their author. In modern copyright law,
this principle has been generalized to all kinds of works of authorship.35 Thus, for example, if an
artist paints a work and sells the finished canvas, she retains all exploitation rights in the work,
absent a contract to the contrary. As a result, the artist, not the purchaser of the painting, would
have the sole right to create postcards—a derivative work—based on the painting. But the artist
cannot prevent the buyer from selling the physical object—the canvas—which the buyer now
owns, because disposal of the chattel falls within the ownership rights of the purchaser of the
physical object that embodies a copy of the work of authorship. 36 Neither, in the U.S., can the
artist prevent the owner of the physical object from publicly displaying it so long as the viewers
are present in the place where the object is displayed.37
e.
Duration
The copyright term begins with the creation of the work. It is no longer necessary to
publish the work, or to comply with formalities of notice, registration or renewal of registration,
for copyright to attach or to persist. The minimum term of protection under the Berne
Convention is fifty years post mortem auctoris. Many countries, including the U.S. and the
member states of the European Union, have adopted a longer term of 70 years pma. When the
work is of joint authorship, the term is calculated from the death of the last surviving co-author.
The duration of copyright in works whose terms cannot be calculated by reference to the
death of a human author generally runs from a period of years from publication or creation of the
work. In the E.U. anonymous and pseudonymous works endure for 70 years from the date on
which the work was first lawfully made available to the public;38 in the U.S. the term of
copyright in anonymous and pseudonymous works and works made for hire is 95 years from
publication or 120 years from creation, whichever expires first.39
The duration of neighboring rights in the E.U. was extended in 2011 from 50 to 70 years
from publication or first lawful communication to the public. The 2011 Directive also included
elaborate provisions for the reversion of rights to performers if following fifty years from first
publication or communication to the public, the phonogram producer does not exploit the
35 In the 19th and first half of the 20th centuries, however, some countries, including France, and some states within
the U.S., imposed a presumption that sale of the original copy of a work of art transferred the rights to publish the
image in prints or engravings, thus placing the burden on the artist to reserve publication rights.
36
See, eg, 17 USC §§ 109, 202. In some countries, the resale of the painting may give rise to an obligation to pay
royalties to the artist, see discussion infra (‘droit de suite’).
37 17 USC § 109(c).
38
Directive 2006/116/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 12 December 2006 on the term of
protection of copyright and certain related rights [2006] OJ L372/12, art 1(3).
39
17 USC § 302(c).
12
phonogram.40 Coupling reversion rights with term extension echoes the first copyright act: the
Statute of Anne provided that were the author still living at the end of the initial 14-year term,
“the sole right shall return to the Author” for a new 14-year term.41 Performers’ (much watereddown) recapture of rights may also have made the controversial addition of 20 years to the period
of protection more palatable, particularly for those unimpressed with pleas for parity with a
copyright term that the E.U. had extended by 20 years in 1993.
In both cases, a term of protection 20 years in excess of the already long international
standard of life+50 for copyright, and the more modest 50 years from fixation for neighboring
rights,42 has provoked criticism on at least two grounds. First, the extension keeps works out of
the public domain for an additional 20 years, thus depriving the public, and other authors, of free
use of the works, with little evidence that authors and performers (or their heirs) of these aging
works in fact benefit from the additional period of protection. Second, the longer the term of
protection, the more difficult it may become to locate a work’s current rightholders, thus
increasing the transaction costs of obtaining licenses, or making licenses unobtainable.
Initiatives to facilitate exploitation of “orphan works” or “unavailable works” have been adopted
or are under discussion in the E.U. and other countries.43
f
Rights
1.
Moral Rights
Authors’ rights are both “moral” and economic. The civil law tradition has long
recognized the moral dimension of author’s rights, linked to the personality of the author and
inherent in the property right that arises from the act of creation. Moral rights encompass the
author’s right to be recognized as the creator of the work (right of attribution or “paternity”), and
the right to prevent alterations to her work that are deleterious to her honor or reputation. The
latter prerogative is known as the right of integrity, but the denomination is somewhat
misleading to the extent that the right entitles the author to a remedy for deleterious changes to
her work, but, in most countries, not against the total destruction of her work. The right to
determine whether, when, and how to disclose her work to the public (right of divulgation)
shares both moral and economic features; in the latter guise, common law countries have
40
Directive 2011/77/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council of 27 September 2011 amending Directive
2006/116/EC on the term of protection of copyright and certain related rights [2011] OJ L 265/1, art 1(2)(c). See
generally, Jane C Ginsburg, ‘Durée de la protection des enregistrements sonores : Comparaison des régimes EU et
UE’ (2012) 1 Juris Art et Culture 27.
41
AEL 1710 (n 31) s 11.
42
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works (opened for signature 9 September 1886,
entered into force 5 December 1887) 1161 UNTS 30, art 7; Rome Convention for the Protection of Performers,
Producers of Phonograms and Broadcasting Organizations (opened for signature 26 October 1961, entered into force
20 December 1996) 496 UNTS 43, art 17.
43
See, eg, Directive 12/28/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council of 25 October 2012 on certain
permitted used of orphan works [2012] OJ L 299/5; US Copyright Office, Report on Orphan Works and Mass
Digitization (June 2015) <http://copyright.gov/orphan/reports/orphan-works2015.pdf> accessed 21 April 2016; Loi
no 2012-287 du 1er mars 2012 relative à l’exploitation numérique des livres indisponibles du XXe siècle (1) [Law
2012-287 of Mar. 1, 2012 on the Digital Exploitation of Unavailable Books of the Twentieth Century], JO du 2 mar
2012 , p 3986, (effective as of the publication of décret n°2013-182 of 27 February 2013 on the application of
articles L.134-1 à L.134-9 of the Code of Intellectual Property).
13
recognized a “right of first publication.” Common law systems have adopted the moral rights of
attribution and integrity more recently, and more sparingly, than in civil law states; the U.S.,
notwithstanding its 1989 adherence to the Berne Convention, still fully protects neither interest.
The only moral rights-specific legislation in the U.S. is limited to a narrowly-defined class of
“works of visual art.”44
The Berne Convention, art. 6bis, establishes that moral rights subsist independently of a
transfer of economic rights, but that instrument does not declare moral rights to be inalienable.
National laws diverge: in some states, notably France, their inalienability extends not only to
authors residing in France, but to exploitations in France of foreign authors. Thus, France will,
for example, protect the right of an American creator to oppose the dissemination in France of
altered versions of her work, even though she may have signed a contract governed by U.S. law
that specifies that she transfers any moral rights she may have respecting any country covered by
the contract.45 By contrast, in most common law countries, moral rights (or the economic rights
that protect analogous interests) are freely alienable, though the law may require the contract to
specify which moral rights are transferred for what purposes.46
The duration of moral rights also varies by country. In some states they endure for the
life of the author, in others for the duration of the term of economic rights, and in a few states,
including France, they are perpetual.47 Because enforcement of moral rights may dissipate over
time, particularly if there are no longer any heirs, the state may confer standing on an authors’
society or on the ministry of culture to advance interests in the work’s integrity or attribution.48
2.
Economic Rights
a. Reproduction right
Among the exclusive rights comprised within a copyright, the reproduction right, or right
to produce copies, is historically the most basic of all. The right protects against copying in any
medium, including within the temporary memory of a computer. Just how temporary the copy
may be before it is deemed too transient to constitute an actionable reproduction is a matter of
some dispute in the U.S., in contrast to the E.U. The 2001 E.U. Information Society Directive
addresses “temporary acts of reproduction . . . , which are transient or incidental [and] an integral
and essential part of a technological process” and, under specified conditions, requires their
exemption from the scope of the reproduction right.49 The provision of a mandatory exception
44 17 USC §§ 101, 106A.
45 See, eg, Huston v Turner Ent, Cass civ [Supreme Court], 1re ch, 28 May 1991, 149 RIDA 197 (1991), 23 IIC 702
(1992) (English translation); Jane C Ginsburg and Pierre Sirinelli, ‘Authors and Exploitations in International
Private Law: The French Supreme Court and the Huston Film Colorization Controversy’ (1991) 15 Colum-VLA J L
& the Arts 135.
46
Eg, Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990 (VARA), 17 USC § 106A.
47
See, eg, France, Code of intellectual property (n 29), art L 121-1, cl 2.
48
André Lucas, Henri-Jacques Lucas and Agnès Lucas-Schloetter, Traité de la propriété littéraire et artistique (4th
edn, LexisNexis 2012) 537, para 614 (hereafter Lucas, Traité de la propriété littéraire et artistique) suggest that
article L 121-3 authorization to the ministry of culture to act in the event of the heirs’ abusive exercise or non
exercise of the deceased author’s divulation right could be extended to authorize the ministry of culture to act on
behalf of the deceased author’s attribution and integrity rights in the absence of heirs.
49 InfoSoc Directive (n 10), art 5(1).
14
for these transient copies suggests that they would otherwise be considered actionable copies. In
the U.S., by contrast, the Second Circuit Court of Appeals has held that the statute’s equation of
copies with fixations, which are defined as “permit[ting] the work to be perceived, reproduced or
otherwise communicated for a period of more than transitory duration,”50 means that a buffer
copy lasting 1.2 seconds cannot be a copy for purposes of infringing the reproduction right. 51
The court declined to indicate how much longer a transient fixation in computer memory must
endure to become an actionable copy, though it acknowledged that some minutes (rather than
seconds) might suffice.
Scope of the reproduction right
The reproduction right is not limited to verbatim (or the visual or musical equivalent)
copying; it also protects against paraphrasing. But the right prohibits only actual use of the
copyright owner’s work as a model, either directly or indirectly; it does not cover coincidental
similarities in a work created independently and without reference to the first. Thus, for example,
resemblances that result from the contending authors’ independent resort to common prior
sources (as not infrequently occurs in the case of popular songs) are not actionable. Independent
generation is therefore a complete defense to an infringement action. But if copying occurred, it
need not have been willful; even unconscious copying can infringe. 52
In all events, the second author must have copied protected material. As explained earlier,
a second author may freely copy a copyrighted work’s ideas and discrete facts, so long as he or
she does not also copy the expression or particular manner in which the first author set forth
these ideas and facts. In addition, to violate the exclusive right of reproduction, the second
author’s copying must be “substantial.” Substantiality of copying depends very much on context;
even a small, but qualitatively important, extract from a larger work may be found to infringe,
depending on the nature of the copyrighted work and of the portion copied.
Many of these precepts are easier said than applied. For example, the line between
unprotected “idea” and protected “expression” is notoriously indistinct. As one of the greatest
U.S. copyright jurists, Learned Hand, admitted, “Obviously, no principle can be stated as to
when an imitator has gone beyond copying the ‘idea,’ and has borrowed its ‘expression.’
Decisions must therefore inevitably be ad hoc.”53 The same federal judge coined the
“abstractions test” for analyzing claims of infringement when the defendant has not lifted
verbatim extracts. The “test” in fact is less a rule or standard than a restatement of the problem:
[W]hen the plagiarist does not take out a block in situ, but an abstract of the
whole, decision is more troublesome. Upon any work, and especially upon a play,
a great number of patterns of increasing generality will fit equally well, as more
and more of the incident is left out. The last may perhaps be no more than the
most general statement of what the play is about, and at times might consist only
of its title; but there is a point in this series of abstractions where they are no
longer protected, since otherwise the playwright could prevent the use of his
50 17 USC § 101 (emphasis supplied).
51 Cartoon Network v CSC Holdings 536 F 3d 121 (2d Cir 2008).
52. See, eg, Bright Tunes Music Corp v Harrisongs Music Ltd 420 F Supp 177 (SDNY 1976).
53. Peter Pan Fabrics Inc v. Martin Weiner Corp 274 F 2d 487 (2d Cir 1960).
15
“ideas,” to which, apart from their expression, his property is never extended.
Nobody has ever been able to fix that boundary, and nobody ever can.54
The determination of how generously to mark off protectable “expression” will also
depend on the nature of the work, for example, whether the work is fictional or fanciful, on the
one hand, or is factual or functional, on the other. Too narrow a characterization of material in
the latter kinds of works as protectable expression risks rendering the copyright so “thin” as to
discourage the effort or investment in the work’s production. But too broad a characterization
runs a greater risk of interfering with the copyright policies favoring free access to ideas,
methods, systems and the like. Judge Easterbrook of the Seventh Circuit Court of Appeals
recognized this quandary in a controversy concerning a work of historical exposition and
speculation:
Intellectual (and artistic) progress is possible only if each author builds on
the work of others. No one invents even a tiny fraction of the ideas that make up
our cultural heritage. Once a work has been written and published, any rule
requiring people to compensate the author slows progress in literature and art,
making useful expressions “too expensive” forcing authors to re-invent the wheel,
and so on. Every work uses scraps of thought from thousands of predecessors, far
too many to compensate even if the legal system were frictionless, which it isn’t.
Because any new work depends on others even if unconsciously, broad protection
of intellectual property also creates a distinct possibility that the cost of
litigation—old authors trying to get a “piece of the action” from current
successes—will prevent or penalize the production of new works, even though the
claims be rebuffed. Authors as a group therefore might prefer limited protection
for their writings—they gain in the ability to use others’ works more than they
lose in potential royalties. . . .
Yet to deny authors all reward for the value their labors contribute to the
works of others also will lead to inefficiently little writing, just as surely as
excessively broad rights will do. The prospect of reward is an important stimulus
for thinking and writing, especially for persons . . . who are full-time authors.
Before the first work is published, broad protection of intellectual property seems
best; after it is published, narrow protection seems best. At each instant some new
works are in progress, and every author is simultaneously a creator in part and a
borrower in part. In these roles, the same person has different objectives. Yet only
one rule can be in force. This single rule must achieve as much as possible of
these inconsistent demands. Neither Congress nor the courts has the information
that would allow it to determine which is best. Both institutions must muddle
through, using not a fixed rule but a sense of the consequences of moving
dramatically in either direction.55
Ultimately, in copyright law, unprotectable “ideas” and “facts” are not epistemological concepts
but legal conclusions; the scope of the reproduction right turns on notions—often unarticulated
and unproven—of appropriate competition. Thus, copyright doctrine attaches the label “idea” to
aspects of works which, if protected, would (or, we fear, might) preclude, or render too
expensive, subsequent authors’ endeavors.
54. Nichols v Universal Pictures Corp 45 F 2d 119, 121 (2d Cir 1930).
55
Nash v CBS Inc 899 F 2d 1537, 1540–1541 (7th Cir 1990).
16
b. Adaptation (derivative works) right
The adaptation right, or right to make derivative works, overlaps somewhat with the
reproduction right, since an adaptation, whether into another medium, such as a poster depicting
a painting, or into another language, or into a different form of expression, such as a play based
on a novel or a motion picture based on a play, will necessarily incorporate the adapted work in
whole or in part. Indeed, some copyright laws, such as France’s, do not provide explicitly for a
right of adaptation, instead treating unauthorized derivative works as infringements of the
reproduction right.56 In U.S. copyright law, a derivative work “is a work based upon one or
more pre-existing works,” and includes “any . . . form in which a work may be recast,
transformed, or adapted.”57 In countries whose laws expressly cover adaptation rights, the
concept embraces not only additions to a prior work, but also deletion, abbreviation and
abridgment as well as elaboration and embellishment. The derivative works right thus provides
authors their closest U.S.-law analog to the moral right of integrity (for those authors who retain
derivative work rights). For example, the heavy editing of television programs without the
consent of the Monty Python comedy group, who were the copyright owners of the underlying
scripts, was held to infringe.58
While capacious, the derivative works right is not unlimited. Not every work that is
“inspired by” or “goes with” the underlying work, or, more broadly, that capitalizes on the
economic value of the underlying work, is necessarily a “derivative work.” For example, a
playwright who, having seen “West Side Story,” is inspired to pen her own ethnic variation on
“Romeo and Juliet,” has not created an infringing derivative work, Her work may be
“derivative” as a matter of literary criticism, and she may be capitalizing on a market the first
author created for ethnic transpositions, but if she has embroidered only on the prior author’s
ideas, she has not incorporated the prior work’s expression, and so cannot be deemed to have
infringed. Similarly, a work, such as a bibliography or abstract, that recapitulates only factual
information from or about a prior work, has not copied or adapted its “expression,” and so does
not infringe.
By the same token, mere reference to a prior work does not create an infringing
derivative work, even if the association of the two works economically benefits the second. For
example, if an entrepreneur markets a sound recording of 1920s popular music as a perfect audio
background for reading The Great Gatsby, the suggestion that one freestanding work makes an
ideal accompaniment to another does not convert the complementary work into a “derivative
work.” (By contrast, an audiobook that included the music in the soundtrack of a recorded
reading of the book would, by virtue of the incorporation of the two works into one, probably
constitute a recasting, transforming or adapting of the novel, as would the audiobook without
accompanying music.)
c. Rights of public performance/communication to the public
56 See, eg, Lucas, Traité de la propriété littéraire et artistique 251, para 254 (‘the rights of translation and of
adaptation are considered as corollaries of the rights of reproduction and of public performance and therefore are not
elevated to distinct prerogatives’).
57 17 USC § 101.
58 Gilliam v American Broadcasting Companies 538 F 2d 14 (2d Cir 1976).
17
While exploitation of works of authorship through distribution of copies long dominated
the economy of copyright, the rights of public performance and communication to the public
now, thanks principally to digital media, equal or surpass the reproduction right in economic
significance.59 In most countries, the right of “public performance” refers to performances of
works to a public present at the place of performance, while “communication to the public” and
its subset, “making available to the public” concern transmissions by wired or wireless means to
members of the public, whether separated in space, as for example, with radio and television
broadcasting, and/or in time, as with on-demand digital transmissions.60 By contrast, the rights
of public performance and display in U.S. copyright law cover performances and displays both in
places open to the public, and by transmissions to members of the public, including those
separated in space and/or time.61
Under the “making available right,” which addresses individualized access by members
of the public, it is not necessary that the enterprise have in fact transmitted the content to any
member of the public; it suffices that the enterprise have offered to transmit the content. The
right, as its name indicates, covers the proposal of individualized access to the work. In most
countries, the making available right covers both streaming and downloading. The U.S.
copyright act does not explicitly include a “making available right”; the public performance right
extends to offers of transmissions of performances of works, that is, of works that can be viewed
or listened to contemporaneously with their transmission (streams), but not to transmissions of
digital files that will not be heard or seen until the user opens the file that has been sent to her
computer (downloads).62 As we will see, the U.S. distribution right encompasses the digital
delivery of files, but there may be some uncertainty whether that right also reaches the offer to
deliver a digital file. That ambiguity may cast doubt on whether the U.S. protects all aspects of
the making available right as envisioned by international norms.63
In most countries, musical performers have the exclusive right to authorize the fixation or
transmission of their live performances,64 and performers and producers of phonograms enjoy
neighboring rights of reproduction, and communication to the public, In the U.S., sound
recordings have no right of public performance in places open to the public or by broadcasting,
but their digital communication gives rise to remuneration rights for non interactive
transmissions, and to exclusive rights for interactive transmissions. 65
“The public”
The exclusive right to perform works in public entered most copyright laws at least a
generation later than the right to reproduce the work in copies, although in France, the right of
59 See, eg, Jane C Ginsburg, Essay, ‘From Having Copies to Experiencing Works: The Development of an Access
Right in US Copyright Law’ (2003) 50 J Copyr Soc 113.
60 See, eg, InfoSoc Directive (n 10), art 3.
61 17 USC §§ 101, 106(4)(5)(6).
62. See, eg, US v American Society of Composers, Authors and Publishers 627 F 3d 64 (2d Cir 2010).
63 But see US Copyright Office, The Making Available Right in the United States: A Report of the Register of
Copyrights (2016) 74–76 (hereafter US Copyright Office, The Making Available Right in the United States)
(concluding that U.S. copyright law adequately covers all aspects of the making available right set out in
international treaties).
64 Article 14(1) of the TRIPs Agreement requires that WTO member states protect performers’ rights of fixation
and transmission.
65 17 USC §§ 106(6), 114(d)–(j).
18
playwrights to authorize or prohibit the public performance of their works, introduced as part of
the 1791 revolutionary law regulating theaters, preceded by two years the general right of
authors to control copying and publication of their works. Most controversies concerning the
right have tested the meaning of “in public” or “open to the public” in light of most laws’
exemptions for performances within a “family circle” or “circle of family and social
acquaintance.”66
The meaning of “the public” with respect to the right of communication to the public (or,
in the U.S., of public performance or display by transmission) encompasses a broad variety of
modes of remote communication. These include traditional “push” technologies, in which the
transmitting entity, such as a broadcaster or a cable or satellite operator, communicates works
simultaneously to as many members of the public as choose to turn on their receiving devices.
The right of communication to the public also covers “pull” technologies in which individual
members of the public receive transmissions of on-demand content at a place and time chosen by
them. The right also reaches hybrid models in which the members of the public individually
access the service, but the transmitting entity selects the specific content to transmit, perhaps
based on profiles of individual user preferences.
Construing “the public” has proved much more fraught in the context of secondary
transmissions of an initial authorized transmission.67 Case law in the U.S. and the E.U. has
created more complexity than clarification. In the U.S., there is uncertainty regarding when
services that offer individualized transmissions from remotely stored digital copies made from
initial public transmissions should be considered to be providing the works “to the public.”68 In
the E.U., the Court of Justice has ruled that secondary transmissions to the public do not violate
the right of communication to the public unless the transmission reaches a “new public” not
contemplated by the original transmission, or is achieved by a “different technical means” from
the initial mode of transmission.69 Under this approach, a hyperlink that leads directly to the
targeted content makes the work available, but not to a “new public,” because the mode of access
is “the Internet,” and the public that accesses the work via the link is the same public as could
have accessed the content directly from the source website (provided that content was initially
made available without access restrictions). U.S. courts have reached a similar result on
different reasoning, holding that the source website publicly performs or displays the work
because the content resides on its server; the website or search engine that provides the link, but
on whose server the content does not reside, accordingly does not “perform” or “display” the
work even though the user accesses the content by means of the linking site.
Performing rights organizations
Public performances and communications to the public tend to be both ubiquitous, given
the multiple venues for live performances and the pervasive media of communication, and to
exploit large quantities of works. It may be burdensome and expensive for exploiters to locate
and obtain licenses from all the individual right holders, as well as for the right holders to police
all the exploiters. These difficulties, albeit augmented with the development of remote
communications, were already present well before the advent of the radio. Once legislatures
66 Eg, ibid § 101.
67 Many secondary transmisions may also be the objects of compulsory licensing in national laws.
68 American Broadcasting Companies Inc v Aereo Inc 134 S Ct 2498 (US 2014).
69 Case C-466/12 Nils Svensson and Others v Retriever Sverige AB [2014] ECLI:EU:C:2014:76.
19
brought within the scope of authors’ exclusive rights live public performances, not only in
theaters, but also restaurants, taverns and other places where music is performed, it became
apparent that individual composers could not separately enforce their rights against the plethora
of enterprises who owned or controlled the places where music was played.
The need for effective enforcement gave rise to the formation of performing rights
societies, first in Europe, and subsequently throughout the world. These societies license the
public performance and communication to the public rights in nondramatic musical
compositions, pursue unlicensed users, and distribute royalties to their composer, lyricist, and
publisher members. By representing the interests of large numbers of copyright holders, the
performing rights societies are able to secure better enforcement and compensation than could
individual claimants. The collective nature of the licensing also benefits users: rather than seek
out individual authors, a party wishing to perform quantities of copyrighted music may obtain all
the requisite authorizations from one or two sources in each country of exploitation (multiterritorial licenses are currently in prospect, but local licensing still enables performing rights
societies to include foreign works within the scope of the licenses because of reciprocal
agreements among the societies). Performing rights societies are the most well-established
examples of collective licensing entities and have served as a model for licensing arrangements
for institutional and enterprise photocopying and digital copying of books and periodicals, as
well as (principally outside the U.S.) for other high-volume exploitations of the subject matter of
copyright and neighboring rights. Because collective licensing societies pool works and fix
prices, they invite antitrust scrutiny. ASCAP and BMI, the major U.S. performing rights
societies, operate under antitrust consent decrees, and E.U. and national competition authorities
regulate the activities of local collective management entities.
d. Distribution right
The copyright owner also has the exclusive right to distribute copies of the work to the
public. In most countries the distribution right covers only tangible copies, while in the U.S., the
right also includes digital copies disseminated over digital networks, such as the Internet. U.S.
authorities consider that a digital delivery that results in the fixation of a copy of the work in
computer memory without contemporaneous perception of the work by the recipient – i.e., a
download rather than a stream – comes within the statutory distribution right; the latter, as we
have seen, is considered a public performance by transmission. (In many other states, delivering
or offering to deliver a download is considered a communication to the public.) The U.S. statute
equates distribution with “transfer of ownership,” a concept that may initially have presumed an
analog environment. A transfer of ownership of an analog copy implicitly involves the
transferor’s divestiture of her copy so that the transferee may take possession. A book sold by a
bookstore leaves the store with the customer; there is one fewer copy in the store’s inventory.
With digital copies, by contrast, one typically “sends” a copy, but retains one’s “original” or
“own” copy in one’s computer memory. There is no divestiture; rather at least two people now
own copies where before there was only one owner. Nonetheless, in the context of digital
dissemination, U.S. courts focus not on the sender’s retention of a copy, but on the creation of a
new copy in the computer of the recipient, a copy that the recipient now owns.70
70 London-Sire Records Inc v Doe 542 F Supp 2d 153 (D Mass 2008). See also 17 USC § 115(d): ‘A “digital
phonorecord delivery” is each individual delivery of a phonorecord by digital transmission of a sound recording
20
The distribution right entitles the copyright owner to authorize or prohibit the first sale of
the copy of the work. The corollary right to prevent importation of copies (a right that goes back
to the first days of printing privileges) also enables the copyright owner to prevent entry onto a
given territory of copies made abroad; though, as we shall see, national laws differ regarding the
right of the copyright owner to prevent importation of authorized foreign-made copies. After the
first lawful sale within a given territory, the right is “exhausted,” and the copyright owner cannot
control further sale of that copy. National laws diverge over whether rightholders can control, or
be remunerated for, other forms of disposition of the physical copy after its first sale, most
importantly by leasing or lending it. While the E.U. provides for rental rights, and for mandatory
remuneration to authors and performers,71 U.S. law, with two exceptions for phonograms and
copies of computer programs, considers that the right to control the disposition of the tangible
copy by rental is transferred with the ownership of the physical copy. 72 From the U.S.
perspective, it follows from the distinction between incorporeal intellectual property rights on the
one hand and chattel rights in the physical object on the other, that the owner of the latter has the
right to exploit or dispose of the physical object, so long as she does not make further copies; the
additional copies come within the domain of the copyright, while the single tangible copy
acquired by sale or gift is an item of personal property.
Courts in several countries have addressed what the “copy” means for purposes of the
exhaustion doctrine. A change in the tangible medium of fixation may result in the creation of a
different copy than the one sold under the authority of the copyright owner. The Court of Justice
of the European Union has recently ruled that the exploiter of a process that separates a
photographic image from the paper on which it was printed, allowing the image to be transferred
to a different medium, could not shelter under the exhaustion doctrine, even though no additional
copies were made, because the process yielded a different object:
The fact that the ink is saved during the transfer cannot affect the finding that the
image’s medium has been altered. What is important is whether the altered object
itself, taken as a whole, is, physically, the object that was placed onto the market
with the consent of the rightholder.73
By contrast, the Supreme Court of Canada, on almost identical facts, came to the opposite
conclusion.74 In the U.S., the U.S. Copyright Office and lower courts have construed the
statutory limitation of the first sale doctrine to “that copy” to preclude a “digital first sale
which results in a specifically identifiable reproduction by or for any transmission recipient of a phonorecord of that
sound recording . . .’ Accord, US Copyright Office, The Making Available Right in the United States (n 63) 21-22
(distribution right covers digital copies created in recipient’s computer memory). Moreover, on further examination,
a ‘distribution’ need not always result in a loss of possession, even in the analog world. For one very old
technological example, consider the biblical loaves and fishes. English versions of the gospels recount that Jesus
ordered his disciples to ‘distribute’ the loaves and fishes to the public. Though the supply seemed inadequate, all the
public were served, yet at the end, the same number of loaves and fishes remained in the baskets as at the outset.
Matthew 14:20 (King James); Mark 6:41 (King James); Luke 9:16 (King James); John 6:11 (King James). For
another bread-related example of a distribution which does not require the donor to part with her possession, a baker
can parcel out to other bakers batches of sourdough ‘starter’ yet retain an amount sufficient to prepare her own
loaves.
71 Council Directive 92/100/EEC of 19 November 1992 on rental right and lending right and on certain rights
related to copyright in the field of intellectual property [1992] OJ L 346/61, art 4.
72 17 USC §§ 109(a)–(b).
73 Case C-419/13 Art & Allposters International BV v. Stichting Pictoright [2015], ECLI:EU:C:2015:27, para 45.
74 Théberge v Galerie d’Art du Petit Champlain Inc, 2002 SCC 34.
21
doctrine,” because, even if the sender deletes the copy from her own computer’s memory, the
process of digital dissemination entails the creation of a new copy in the computer of the
recipient.75
National laws also differ with respect to the geographic scope of the exhaustion doctrine.
Under E.U. law, once a lawfully-made copy has been sold within the E.U., the principle of free
movement of goods requires that it may be resold in every other E.U. member state. But the
copyright owner may prevent the entry into the E.U. of a copy from outside the E.U., even if that
extra-E.U. copy was lawfully made under license from the copyright owner.76 By contrast, in the
U.S., the Supreme Court has held that the statutory right to prevent importation of copies does
not apply to copies lawfully made abroad under license from the U.S. copyright holder.77
Contractual avoidance of the exhaustion doctrine?
As we have seen, the sale (or other transfer of ownership) of a copy triggers the
exhaustion doctrine. By contrast, if the copyright owner alienates possession of a copy without
in fact selling it, and thus engages in rental, lease or lending, the copyright owner can control
secondary markets for the recirculation of the copy because the distribution right will not yet
have been “exhausted” by a sale; lawfully possessing a copy does not suffice without ownership.
Not surprisingly, then, some copyright owners, particularly in certain industries, prefer to “lease”
rather than to “sell” copies of their works. If copyright owners could simply recharacterize any
“sale” as a “lease,” however, there would be little left to the exhaustion doctrine, because, if the
apparent sale is in fact only a “lease,” the copyright owner may prevent the possessor-lessee
from reselling the copy. The case law addressing the question whether a purported “lease”
should be deemed a “sale” appears to turn on the degree of restrictiveness of the license
conditions and their and effectiveness.78
Droit de suite
The “droit de suite,” or artists’ resale royalty right, qualifies the exhaustion doctrine: the
right requires that, for the duration of the copyright term, the creator receive a specified
percentage of the price of every subsequent public resale. Because there may be no market for
reproduction or communication to the public of many works of art, exploitations of incorporeal
copyright rights may not benefit many artists; the droit de suite therefore seeks to provide artists
75
See
US
Copyright
Office,
DMCA
Section
104
Report
(August
2001)
111
<http://www.loc.gov/copyright/reports/studies/dmca/sec-104-report-vol-1.pdf> accessed 23 April 2016; US
Copyright Office, The Making Available Right in the United States (n 63) 22 n 94; Capitol Records, LLC v ReDigi
Inc 934 F Supp 2d 640 (SDNY 2015); US Department of Commerce Internet Policy Task Force, Copyright Policy,
Creativity, and Innovation in the Digital Economy (January 2016) 35–69.
76 See, eg, Case C-355/96 Silhouette International Schmied GmbH v Hartlauer Handelsgesellschaft mbH [1998]
ECLI:EU:C:1998:374 (trademarks, but same result would apply to regional exhaustion of copyright).
77 Kirtsaeng v John Wiley & Sons Inc 133 S Ct 1351 (US 2013).
78 See, eg, Vernor v Autodesk 621 F 3d 1102 (9th Cir 2010) (whether the work has traditionally been distributed
with restrictive license conditions so that the possessor would not have expected to be able freely to dispose of her
copy); Case C-128/11 UsedSoft GmbH v Oracle International Corp [2012] ECR I-0000 (whether a copy has been
‘sold’ depends on whether ‘licensee’s’ right to use is unlimited in time, and on other restrictions). Compare UMG
Recordings Inc v Augusto 628 F 3d 1175 (9th Cir 2011) (CDs bearing legend that they remained the property of
producer held insufficient to convert a sale into a license; producer lacked control over disposition of copies and,
unlike software, CDs traditionally were sold, not leased).
22
a revenue stream by ensuring that they share in the subsequent profitable disposition of lawfully
owned copies of their works. Though the droit de suite is the subject of an E.U. Directive, many
non EU countries, including the U.S., have not adopted it.
g
Exceptions and limitations
Copyright protection is not absolute. We have seen that copyright provides no remedy
for the copying of “ideas,” information and processes, no matter how laboriously derived, and no
matter what their commercial value. Nor does copyright protect against independent generation
of the same or similar expression. Moreover, not all copying or communication of protected
expression infringes. National copyright laws, acting within the framework imposed by
international agreements, impose a variety of exceptions and limitations on the scope of
copyright. Exceptions entitle the user to engage in the permitted act without having to pay the
copyright owner; limitations permit the use, but require payment, at rates usually set by
government authorities who establish compulsory licenses.
Compulsory licenses may be particularly widespread in the realm of secondary
transmissions of broadcast performances, given the Berne Convention article 11bis explicit
authorization of that limitation. They also exist in many states to provide compensation for
private copying and for a variety of non-profit educational purposes.79 The Berne Convention,
article 13, authorizes member states to permit the recording of non dramatic musical
compositions on to phonograms for distribution to the public, subject to compulsory licenses, but
the U.S. is one of the few countries that continue to impose this limitation. Unremunerated
exceptions vary considerably across national laws, but some of the most widespread include
copying for purposes of research and private study, quotations from works for purposes of
criticism and commentary, including parody, and public performances or displays of works for
purposes of teaching.
In all events, international norms require that national laws creating exceptions and
limitations satisfy the “3-step test,” set out at article 9(2) of the Berne Convention with respect to
the reproduction right, and reiterated in article 13 of the TRIPS Agreement and article 10 of the
WIPO Copyright Treaty with respect to all rights under copyright.
It shall be a matter for legislation in the countries of the Union to permit the
reproduction of such works in certain special cases, provided that such
reproduction does not conflict with a normal exploitation of the work and does
not unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of the author.
79 For example, the 2001 EU Information Society Directive, art. 5(2)(e) permits ‘in respect of reproductions of
broadcasts made by social institutions pursuing non-commercial purposes, such as hospitals or prisons, on condition
that the rightholders receive fair compensation.’ Art. 5(2)(b) permits private copying, subject to fair compensation,
but the Court of Justice of the European Union has held that a condition of the application of private copying
limitations is their confinement to copies made from a legitimate source. See Case C 435/12, ACI Adam BV and
Others v Stichting de Thuiskopie [2014] ECLI:EU:C:2014:254.
23
As interpreted by the WTO dispute resolution panel in a proceeding contesting a U.S. exemption
for retransmissions of public performances of radio and television broadcasts in bars, restaurants
and retail establishments,80 national legislatures must ensure:
(1) That the exemption is limited to a narrow and specifically defined class of
uses [“certain special cases”];
(2) That the exempted use does not compete with an actual or potential source of
economic gain from the ways rightholders normally exercise rights under
copyright [“conflict with a normal exploitation of the work”]; and
(3) That the exempted use does not unreasonably harm rightholder interests that
are justifiable in light of general copyright objectives [“not unreasonably
prejudice the legitimate interests of the rightholder”]; the unreasonableness of the
harm may be allayed if the member state imposes a compensation-ensuring
compulsory license in lieu of an outright exemption.
Significantly, “[t]he three conditions apply on a cumulative basis, each being a separate
and independent requirement that must be satisfied. Failure to comply with any one of the three
conditions results in the Article 13 exception being disallowed.”81 Thus, for example, if the
exploitation at issue is “normal,” then subjecting it to a compulsory license would not be
permissible. As a result, if educational uses constitute the principal market for a book (such as a
collection of grammar exercises), then a member state would violate article 13 if it imposed a
compulsory license to permit the book’s reproduction. By the same token, a member state would
not comply with article 13 if its exception or limitation were not confined to “certain special
cases,” even if the impact of the exception or limitation did not “conflict with a normal
exploitation” nor “unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of the rightholder.”
Some commentators have disputed the WTO Panel’s requirement that each step be
independently satisfied. For example the Wittem Project “European Copyright Code”, 82 article
5.5, essentially foregoes the first step:
Any other use that is comparable to the uses enumerated in article 5.1 to 5.4(1)
[Uses with minimal economic significance; Uses for the purpose of freedom of
expression and information; Uses Permitted to Promote Social, Political and
Cultural Objectives; Uses for the purpose of enhancing competition (advertising
and reverse engineering)] is permitted provided that the corresponding
requirements of the relevant limitation are met and the use does not conflict with
the normal exploitation of the work and does not unreasonably prejudice the
legitimate interests of the author or rightholder, taking account of the legitimate
interests of third parties.
The first step, as interpreted by the WTO Panel, would appear to favor “closed list”
systems of exceptions and limitations, such as found in the 2001 E.U. “Information Society”
Directive,83 over open-ended systems, of which the U.S. “fair use” exception is the best-known
80 Panel Report, United States—Section 110(5) of US Copyright Act, WTO Doc WT/DS 160/R (adopted 27 July
2000).
81 ibid, para 6.97.
82 European Copyright Code <http://www.copyrightcode.eu/> accessed 23 April 2016.
83 InfoSoc Directive (n 10), art 5.
24
example. In “closed list” systems, the ability to fit the challenged use within one of the
enumerated categories is determinative. Uses that fall outside the categories do not qualify. The
flexibility of the system thus depends on the capaciousness and adaptability of the categories. 84
In open-ended systems, there is no per se barrier to the types of uses that may qualify.
Consistency with the WTO panel’s requirement that the exemption be clearly articulated and
narrowly defined thus turns on the success of the argument that the uses for which a fair use
defense prevails will ultimately fit the bill. 85 Even were that so (as we shall see, it is in fact
uncertain that the class of uses qualifying as “fair” are so limited), that determination would be
arrived at only after assessment of the facts and law relating to the second two steps, so the U.S.
approach does not appear to treat the first step as a necessary and exclusive threshold for analysis
of the “normal market” and “unreasonable prejudice” considerations.
Originally a judge-made doctrine devised in the mid-19th century, albeit with British
antecedents dating to the mid-18th century, fair use was codified in Congress’ general revision of
copyright law in 1976.86 Section 107 of the U.S. Copyright Act applies to all works of
authorship and to all exclusive rights. That section lists several illustrative uses subject to the
defense, including criticism, comment, news reporting, teaching, scholarship, and research.
Nonetheless, a defendant who has reproduced, adapted, or publicly distributed, performed, or
displayed a copyrighted work without authorization must do more than invoke one of the above
socially beneficent purposes. The statutory examples do not operate like a closed list; the statute
also enumerates four factors to be reviewed in the disposition of the defense, and application of
the factors may render an unlisted use fair, just as it may disqualify a listed use. These factors
are: the nature of the defendant’s use; the nature of the copyrighted work; the amount and
substantiality of the portions taken from the copyrighted work; and the effect of the taking upon
the potential market for the copyrighted work. These four factors are not exhaustive. Because the
fair-use doctrine is still “an equitable rule of reason,” courts are free to consider other factors, or
to give greater weight to some factors than to others, depending on the given case. A defendant
invoking the fair-use defense must establish that the balance of the statutory and any additional
judicial criteria weighs in his or her favor.
The potential disparities between the U.S. fair use exception and the three-step test have
long attracted the attention of scholars.87 First, as we have seen, section 107 on its face is not
84 See Brent Hugenholtz & Martin RF Senftleben, ‘Fair Use in Europe: In Search of Flexibilities’ (2011) <
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1959554> accessed 22 April 2016 (analyzing E.U. categories and arguing that they are not
as restrictive as might appear).
85 Council for Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights, Review of Legislation on Copyright and
Related Rights, United States, WTO Doc IP/Q/USA/1 (30 October 1996) 4 (U.S. delegation’s report to TRIPS
Council asserts that ‘The fair use doctrine of US copyright law embodies essentially the same goals as Article 13 of
TRIPS, and is applied and interpreted in a way entirely congruent with the standards set forth in that Article.’).
86 Fair use is codified at 17 USC § 107. Folsom v Marsh 9 F Cas 342 (CCD Mass 1841) (No 4901), is generally
credited as the first U.S. case law iteration of the doctrine; Folsom synthesized a century of British case law
expounding the ‘fair abridgement’ doctrine. For a full analysis of the English decisions, see Isabella Alexander,
Copyright and the Public Interest in the Nineteenth Century (Hart Publishing 2010). On fair abridgement as a
precursor to fair use, see, eg, Matthew Sag, ‘The Prehistory of Fair Use’ (2011) 76 Brook L Rev 1371; on Folsom v
Marsh and its role in U.S. fair use law, see, eg, R. Anthony Reese, ‘The Story of Folsom v. Marsh: Distinguishing
Between Infringing and Legitimate Uses’ in Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss and Jane C Ginsburg (eds), Intellectual
Property Stories (Foundation Press 2005) 259.
87 See, eg, Sam Ricketson and Jane C Ginsburg, International Copyright and Neighbouring Rights: The Berne
Convention and Beyond (OUP 2006) para 13.33; Ruth Okediji, ‘Toward an International Fair Use Standard’ (2006)
39 Colum J Transnatl L 75, 161–62; James Bongiorno, ‘Fair Use of Copyrighted Images After Perfect 10 v.
25
limited to “certain special cases.” Second, while the fourth fair use factor’s consideration of the
impact of the use upon the potential market for the work seems to echo the second of the three
steps (not conflict with a normal exploitation), section 107 does not offer a third step fall-back of
substituting compensation for control over the use at issue. Rather, fair use is an on/off switch:
all or nothing. Either the challenged use is an infringement of copyright,88 or it is a fair use,
which section 107 declares “is not an infringement of copyright.” As a result, either the
copyright owner can collect damages and/or stop the use, or the user not only is dispensed from
obtaining permission, but also owes no compensation for the use.
h.
Remedies
The most important, and most ancient, remedy for copyright infringement is injunctive
relief. The copyright owner’s principal objective often will be to ensure that infringing copies or
communications are no longer available to the public. Hence the frequent corollary remedy of
seizure and destruction of infringing copies and even their means of protection, or, as the 1710
Statute of Anne provided, the “Offender or Offenders shall forfeit such [infringing] Book or
Books to the Proprietor or Proprietors of the Copy [exclusive rights] thereof, who shall forthwith
Damask and make Waste Paper of them . . .”89 Monetary remedies include damages for lost sales
and the infringer’s profits. U.S. remedies permit the successful copyright plaintiff to elect
statutory damages in lieu of actual damages. Statutory damages may exceed the cost of a
market-rate license, and thus may play an admonitory – albeit not punitive – role, but their
greatest utility may be in cases in which actual damages are difficult to prove, notably because
the defendant has not kept reliable records of its sales of infringing copies. Statutory damages
are, however, available only if the work was registered with the U.S. Copyright Office before the
occurrence of the infringement, or, if the work was infringed upon its initial publication, if the
copyright owner registered within three months of first publication. 90 The judge has discretion to
award statutory damages within a statutory range. For non profit educational institutions who
believed in good faith that their uses were not infringing, the court has power to remit an award
of statutory damages altogether.91 Statutory damages have the greatest deterrent and remedial
bite when the defendant infringes large quantities of works; phonogram and film piracy by
commercial actors furnished the traditional instances for the application of statutory damages for
willful infringement. More recently, however, individual end-users engaged in massive file“sharing” have faced the prospect of millions of dollars of personal liability, though the few
adjudicated cases have awarded substantially less, albeit nonetheless considerable amounts.92 The
Amazon.com: Diverging From Constitutional Principles & United States Treaty Obligations’ (2009) 12 Touro Intl L
Rev 107, 153–54.
88 For which, in addition to damages, a usual remedy is injunctive relief, see 17 USC §§ 502, 504. The Supreme
Court has suggested, however, that a court might withhold injunctive relief if a fair use defense fails but the
defendant’s work advances expression or learning. See Campbell v Acuff Rose 510 US 569, 577 n 10 (1994). To
date, it appears that no court has taken up the invitation to impose a judge-made compulsory license in a fair use
case.
89 AEL 1710 (n 31) s 2.
90 17 USC § 412.
91 17 USC § 504(c).
92 Capitol Records Inc v Thomas-Rasset No 06-1497, slip op (D Minn 19 June 2009); BMG Music Ent v
Tenenbaum No 07cv11446-NG (D Mass 7 December 2009).
26
attention these awards have drawn have enhanced prior criticisms of heavy-handed copyright
enforcement and excessive damages awards.93
New copyright obligations: Protection of technological protection measures and copyright
management information
Since 1996, international agreements have imposed two additional obligations devised
for the digital environment, one regarding technological protection measures, the other
concerning copyright management information.94 The first requires member states to “provide
adequate legal protection and effective legal remedies against the circumvention of effective
technological measures that are used by authors in connection with the exercise of their rights
under the World Intellectual Property Organization Copyright Treaty [WCT]) or the Berne
Convention and that restrict acts, in respect of their works, which are not authorized by the
authors concerned or permitted by law.” The second protects against the knowing removal or
alteration of electronic information “which identifies the work, the author of the work, the owner
of any right in the work, or information about the terms and conditions of use of the work”
These obligations respond to the perception that the development of a digital marketplace
would require building copyright owner confidence that digital dissemination would not result in
rampant unauthorized redissemination. Their implementation, notably in the U.S. through the
Digital Millennium Copyright Act (DMCA) of 1998,95 and in the E.U. through the 2001
Information Society Directive,96 seeks to promote lawful digital dissemination by ensuring that
“technological protection measures” that copyright owners choose to apply to their works—such
as scrambling or encrypting digital versions of recordings, films and books—are not
circumvented without proper authorization. Such technological protection measures are intended
to prevent usable copies of the copyright-protected work from being copied, stored or
communicated to others. By the same token, protection of identifying information promotes
electronic commerce by ensuring that information regarding the author, the work and the prices
for its enjoyment are easily accessible and reliable.
With respect to technological protection measures, several questions arise. First, do
states party to the WCT incur an obligation to protect not only against the act of circumvention
but also against the distribution of circumvention devices? Second what kinds of measures are
covered: controls against copying or communicating the work, or also controls over access to the
work? Third, how can legal protection of technological measures accommodate copyright
exceptions or limitations? While the text of art. 11 specifies “the circumvention” and therefore
93 See, eg, Pamela Samuelson & Tara Wheatland, ‘Statutory Damages in Copyright Law: A Remedy in Need of
Reform’ (2009) 51 Wm & Mary L Rev 439, 454–55. The U.S. copyright act also provides for criminal penalties, see
17 USC § 506, 18 USC § 2319.
94 WCT (n 21), arts 11, 12; WIPO Performances and Phonograms Treaty (opened for signature 20 December 1996,
entered into force 20 May 2002) 36 ILM 76, arts 18–19.
95 17 USC § 1201.
96 InfoSoc Directive (n 10), arts 6–7.
27
arguably addresses only the act of circumvention, protection would largely be ineffective were
circumvention devices to circulate freely. Hence, national laws implementing art. 11 generally
cover both. National laws also generally cover access controls as well as copy controls; while
simply apprehending a work is not necessarily a copyright-infringing act (depending on whether
an actionable copy is made in the user’s computer), authors use technological measures “in
connection with the exercise of their rights,” notably of communicating the work to the public.
By contrast, some technological measures control access to spare parts, telephone networks, or
other goods or services that are not works of authorship. U.S. courts have generally rejected
attempts to leverage control over access to computer programs that in turn control access to noncopyright goods or services.97 Similarly, the U.S. Copyright Office, in its triennial rulemaking
procedures to declare exemptions for certain classes of copyrighted works as to which acts of
circumvention may be permitted in order to ensure the availability of non infringing uses, has
authorized such acts as “jailbreaking” of cellphones so that users can retain their hardware when
changing service networks.98
Finally, with respect to exceptions and limitations, WCT art 11 requires protection only
for those technological measures “which are not authorized by the authors concerned or
permitted by law.” Thus, a technological measure that impedes a lawful use may be
circumvented. The difficulty is that the same technological measure may also impede unlawful
uses, and the measure may not “know” when its user is making a lawful or unlawful use.
National laws have responded differently to this conundrum. The U.S. Copyright Office’s
triennial rulemaking offers one approach to accommodating copyright exceptions. The EU
Information Society Directive essays another approach: it requires member states to “take
appropriate measures to ensure that rightholders make available to the beneficiary of an
exception or limitation provided for in national law in accordance with [certain exceptions and
limitations enumerated in the Directive] the means of benefiting from that exception or
limitation, to the extent necessary to benefit from that exception or limitation and where that
beneficiary has legal access to the protected work or subject-matter concerned.”99 Where the
U.S. approach places the burden on the beneficiaries of the claimed exemption to establish its
necessity, the E.U. puts the onus on rightholders to ensure that lawful uses remain available.100
Regarding copyright management information, the principal implementation issues, at
least in the U.S., have concerned the standard of knowledge required to constitute a violation.
Both WCT art, 12 and the DMCA set out a dual knowledge standard: the alleged violator must
have knowingly removed or altered the information, knowing that that removal or alteration
97 See, eg, Lexmark Int’l v Static Control Components Inc 387 F 3d 522, 547 (6th Cir 2004); Chamberlain Group v
Skylink Techs 381 F 3d 1178 (Fed Cir 2004).
98 17 USC § 1201(a)(1)(B)–(D); the most recent rulemaking was published at Exemption to Prohibition on
Circumvention of Copyright Protection Systems for Access Control Technologies, 60 Fed Reg 65944–64 (28
October 2015).
99 InfoSoc Directive (n 10), art 6(4) para 1.
100 This duty does not, however, apply to technological measures that secure the on-demand delivery of works of
authorship and other protected subject matter. See ibid para. 4.
28
would facilitate or conceal an infringement. Thus, even intentional removal or alteration of
copyright management information is not unlawful if the copyright owner cannot show that the
person who removed or altered the information knew that the removal would encourage or
facilitate copyright infringement. While the first element of knowledge may be relatively easy to
establish, the second has proven more elusive.101
Liability of intermediaries
Finally, the Internet has accentuated the role of intermediaries, such as search engines,
hosting platforms, and link aggregators, in the communication of protected content. Questions
therefore have arisen concerning the direct or secondary liability of these actors for copyright
infringement. While these intermediaries may not always be engaged in acts that (depending on
national laws) would constitute reproductions or communications to the public, they often derive
considerable economic benefits from their role in the chain of making works available. In the
U.S. and the E.U. providers of Internet access, hosting services, and (in the U.S.) search engines
enjoy exemptions from direct or indirect liability if their conduct meets statutory prescriptions
designed to ensure substantive and economic neutrality regarding works that the services host or
to which they link.102 In other countries, or with respect to activities falling outside the scope of
the statutory exemptions, national principles or torts or unfair competition may provide a basis of
indirect liability.
Conclusion
Copyright law secures human creativity in works of authorship. Enforceable authorial
property rights advance the public interest by promoting an ecosystem of authorship: a robust
copyright environment encourages authors to create works that inform and enrich the polity, and
from which other authors may draw ideas, information and reasonable amounts of protected
expression in their own authorial endeavors. Copyright promotes artistic freedom and free
speech by enabling authors to earn a living from their creativity. As Victor Hugo proclaimed at
the International Literary Congress convened in 1878 to urge international protection for authors:
Literary property is in the public interest. All the old monarchic laws have rejected, and
continue to reject literary property. To what end? In order to enslave. The writer who is an
owner [of his literary property] is a writer who is free. To take his property away is to
deprive him of his independence.103
Copyright thus promotes a diversity of expressions that might otherwise remain unvoiced. Some
might hasten to add that it does so, as Lord Macaulay charged, by imposing “a tax on readers for
101. Compare Gordon v Nextel Comms 345 F 3d 922 (6th Cir 2003); Schiffer Pub, Ltd v Chronicle Books LLC 73
USPQ 2d (BNA) 1090 (ED Pa 2004) (knowledge standard not met) with McClatchey v AP 82 USPQ 2d 1190 (WD
Pa 2007) (knowledge standard met when party who deletes or alters the information redisseminates the work to the
public without the information).
102 17 USC § 512; Directive 2000/31/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 8 June 2000 on certain
legal aspects of information society services, in particular electronic commerce, in the Internal Market ('Directive on
electronic commerce') [2000] OJ L 178/1, arts 12–15.
103
Société des Gens de Lettres de France, Congrès Littéraire International de Paris 1878 (Paris 1879) 106
(translation mine).
29
the purpose of giving a bounty to writers.” But as the great historian also acknowledged, “The
advantages arising from a system of copyright are obvious. It is desirable that we should have a
supply of good books; we cannot have such a supply unless men of letters are liberally
remunerated; and the least objectionable way of remunerating them is by means of copyright.”104
Thomas B. Macaulay, ‘Speech before the House of Commons’ (Feb. 5, 1841), in GM Young (ed), Macaulay:
Prose and Poetry (Harvard University Press 1970) 733–34.
104
30