Hegel’s Naturalism?
Roi Bar
University of Leipzig
ABSTRACT: The recent tendency to detect naturalism in Hegel’s epistemology is more than just a phenomenon
within contemporary Anglophone scholarship, insofar as it mirrors a questionable state of the art at the
intersection between philosophy of science and philosophy of mind. According to the naturalist reading, Hegel
maintains that the natural world is the only presupposition for satisfying the needs of self-consciousness. Such
reading considers the essence of self-consciousness as naturally embodied in its essence, while downplaying the
intersubjective dimension of reciprocal recognition needed for self-consciousness. Self-consciousness, as the
thinking subject or the mind, is then lead to allegedly unavoidable delimitation of any knowledge-claims. On this
reading, the natural is an insurmountable obstacle to the mind. Hegel, on his side, evidently offers an ongoing
multifaceted dialogue with divergent streams of naturalism. Yet, the question arises: in which sense can we
appropriately speak of Hegel’s naturalism? This paper presents the recent naturalistic approaches to Hegel, along
with deliberations on Hegel’s possible response to them, namely his concept of the transsubjective thinking
mind, the Geist.
KEYWORDS: Hegel, naturalism, epistemology, mind, Quine.
1. Introduction: Hegel’s ‘naturalistic turn’
There is an observable tendency in the last few decades to refer to Hegel “as a great
naturalist”1 and to certain parts of his philosophy as consistent with various kinds of
naturalism.2 It was argued that Hegel’s “apparent indulgence in metaphysics” is actually “a
Article received on 29/10/2015 and accepted for publication on 17/01/2016.
1
DEVRIES, W.A. Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity. An Introduction to Theoretical Spirit. Ithaca &
London: Cornell University Press, 1988, p. xii.
2
The works to be mentioned in the following are: BEISER, F.C. German Idealism: The Struggle Against
Subjectivism, 1781-1801. Camridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2002; BEISER, F.C. Introduction: Hegel
and the Problem of Metaphysics. In: Beiser, F.C. (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Hegel. New York, NY:
Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 1–24; DEVRIES. W.A. Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity. An
Introduction to Theoretical Spirit. Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press, 1988; PAPAZOGLOU, A.
Hegel and Naturalism. In: Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain. Nov. 2012, pp. 21–37; PINKARD,
T. Hegel’s Naturalism. Mind, Nature, and the Final Ends of Life. New York, NY: Oxford University Press,
2012; PIPPIN, R. Hegel’s Practical Philosophy. Rational Agency as Ethical Life. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge
University Press, 2008; REDDING, P. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of the Hegelian Thought.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007; WESTPHAL, K. Hegel’s Epistemology: A Philosophical
Introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit. Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett, 2003; TESTA, I. Hegel's
Naturalism or Soul and Body in the Encyclopaedia. In: Stern, D.S. (Ed.). Essays on Hegel’s Philosophy of
Subjective Spirit. New York, NY: SUNY Press, 2013.
197
A matéria publicada nesse periódico é licenciada sob forma de uma
Licença CreativeCommons – Atribuição 4.0 Internacional
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
form of scientific naturalism”3 and that his “absolute idealism” involves “a much greater
degree of naturalism” than Kant’s idealism.4 Hegel’s philosophy of spirit, in particular his
psychology, was presented as “deeply naturalist.”5 Even where ‘hard’ naturalism in Hegel has
been rejected, there are assertions that his epistemology contains “naturalist elements”6 or a
“naturalistic dimension”7 and that Hegel advocates a form of “Aristotelian naturalism.”8 The
naturalistic turn in Hegel’s reception corresponds to the general intensification of naturalism
in contemporary philosophy, giving thus rise to the question of Hegel’s relation to naturalism:
can we appropriately speak of Hegel’s naturalism? In this debate, everything depends on what
is meant by ‘naturalism.’
2. Hegel as a naturalist: a lover of nature and a natural historian
If a naturalist is a scholar who extensively deals with the study of nature, then, in some
respect, Hegel can be considered as a naturalist. Hegel’s study of nature began in his early
drafts to Philosophy of Nature in the Jenaer Systementwürfe (1803–6) and went on with
several conceptual issues concerning natural laws and natural powers developed in the
Phenomenology of Spirit (1807). His study culminated in the dedication of not less than onethird of the Encyclopaedia (1830) to Philosophy of Nature. The term ‘naturalist’ can refer
more specifically to ‘natural historian,’ a person who studies ‘natural history,’ the
observational study of plants and animals. As Hegel’s biographer notes:
In 1802 and 1803, Hegel began to assemble clippings concerning natural science
from various journals and newspapers, and he returned intensively to one of his
earlier interests as a schoolboy in Stuttgart, the study of physics and mathematics.9
This old love had borne fruit: in 1804, the same year Hegel was elected to the Westphalia
Society for Natural Research, he had become an assessor of the Jena Mineralogical Society,
and due to that appointment, he was issued a pass for a trip to Göttingen and the Harz
3
BEISER. Introduction, p. 8.
BEISER. German Idealism, 1781-1801, pp. 3, 355.
5
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 55.
6
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 52..
7
REDDING. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of the Hegelian Thought, p. 234.
8
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 19.
9
PINKARD, T. Hegel. A Biography. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 186.
4
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
198
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
mountains for geological study. 10 Hegel even identified himself in the title page of the
Phenomenology of Spirit from 1807 as “Dr. and Professor of Philosophy in Jena, Member of
the Ducal Mineralogical Society, Assessor to the Society and Member of other learned
Societies.” In this respect, Hegel was a dedicated lover of nature.
Yet, perhaps since Hegel performed natural studies for only a few years, the authors
involved in the naturalism debate do not consider Hegel as a naturalist because of his love of
nature or his inquiry into natural history, but because of having certain naturalist views in his
philosophy of science. Studying nature, irrespective of the method, is not a sufficient
condition for subscribing to naturalism, and so a consideration of the versions of naturalism
that can be ascribed to Hegel is necessary for our inquiry. Let us begin with naturalism in
general and the versions of naturalism to which Hegel evidently is not inclined.
3. Hegel refutes classical naturalism
Classical ontological naturalism is the belief that all is nature, which means that the
whole reality, the universe or cosmos, is exhausted by what nature is and thus subjected to
nature’s laws. This monist pan-naturalism, also called metaphysical or philosophical
naturalism, is in its broadest sense as old as the moment Thales of Miletus formulated his
principle of hydor, holding that everything consists out of a moist natural substance.
Spinoza’s deus sive natura helped developing such pantheistic naturalism that divides every
being into natura naturans or natura naturata. The French materialists around Baron
d’Holbach have modified this view in a so-called enlightened manner that is still alive and
popular in the works of Daniel Dennett and Paul Churchland under the title ‘eliminative
materialism.’
Now, perhaps since the term ‘naturalism’ does not appear in Hegel’s titles and does not
seem to be a main topic in his writings, Hegel’s own explicit reaction against classical
naturalism seems to have sunk into oblivion, to the extent that it seems that “Hegel never
explicitly talks about naturalism.”11 It was forgotten that Hegel uses this term several times
and even expands on it, always in a pejorative context and while clearly taking a stance
against it. The first time is in a review in his Critical Journal of Philosophy (1802), where he
10
Cf. VERENE, D.P. Hegel’s Nature. In: Houlgate, S. (Ed.). Hegel and the Philosophy of Nature. New York,
NY: SUNY Press, 1998, p. 209.
11
PAPAZOGLOU. Hegel and Naturalism, p. 74.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
199
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
issues a withering assessment on Schulze’s philosophical system, summing it up as nothing
more than a “mere naturalism [...] with artificially inlaid formulas.”12 In his empiricism
critique in the Encyclopaedia’s Logic Hegel supplies a still-pertinent determination of
naturalism, arguing that the “consistent system of empiricism is materialism, or naturalism. –
Kant’s philosophy sets the principle of thinking and of freedom in strict opposition to this
empiricism.”13 Hegel defines classical naturalism more precisely in his interpretation of
Vanini’s naturalism in the Lectures on History of Philosophy as the belief “that it is Nature
that is the Deity, that all thing have a mechanical genesis.” 14 Vanini “explained the whole
universum in its connection by efficient causes alone, not by final causes.”15 Hegel’s
definition of Spinozistic naturalism may seem today to the reader to be irrelevant for the
naturalism debate because one does not associate naturalism with pantheism, but this
definition does expose one of the old roots of the still-existing logical problem in the very
concept of naturalism: its totality-claim. To underline his objection to naturalism, Hegel
derides the “superficial” and “dull” works of French materialists and naturalists, such as
D’Holbach’s The System of Nature.16 It is difficult not to hear the anti-naturalistic critique and
the mockery.
In contrast to these clear reservations, there is only one place where Hegel seems to
praise naturalism, claiming that it has overcome the “positive element in religion.”17 By
“religion” Hegel means any dogmatic doctrine which is based on absolute faith, not on the
“negative” element of thinking. Herewith, Hegel recognizes the value of historical naturalism
as a possible cognitive stance within the wide system of philosophical attempts. However,
immediately after his positive words, Hegel sharply denounces the same naturalism for its
three mistakes: misidentifying the absolute as something present, denying natural and spiritual
purposiveness, hence freedom, and only reaching to insufficient dead abstractions of “a nature
The original text: “bloßer Naturalismus, mit ... Formeln künstlich eingefaßt.” HEGEL, G.W.F. Werke in 20
Bändern. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970, vol. 2, p. 279.
13
HEGEL, G.W.F. The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with
the Zusätze. Trans. with Introduction and Notes: Geraets, T.F.; Suchting, W.A.; Harris, H.S. Indianapolis,
Indiana: Hackett publishing, 1991, p. 107, §60.
14
HEGEL, G.W.F. Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume 3, Medieval and Modern Philosophy.
Trans. Haldane, E.S.; Simson, F.H. (Eds.). Lincoln, Nebraska: Bison Books/Univ. of Nebraska Press, 1995, p.
139.
15
HEGEL. Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume 3, p. 139.
16
HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 20, p. 294: “Die Gedanken sind sehr oberflächlich, le grand tout de la
nature ist das Letzte; das ganze wiederholt sich auf allgemeine Weise, die Darstellung ist matt”.
17
HEGEL. Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume 3, p. 384.
12
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
200
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
undetermined in itself, to sensation, mechanism, self-seeking, and utility.”18 As Frederick
Beiser rightly argues, Hegel rejects the naturalistic view that holds that holds that “not only
everything objective, physical, or material” but also “everything ideal, normative and formal
is explicable according to laws of nature.”19 Robert Pippin explicitly agrees on this point as
well.20 If so, what other kinds of naturalism does Hegel reject?
4. Hegel refutes Quinean naturalism
As Kenneth Westphal rightly claims, it is agreed that Hegel does not hold naturalism “in
one of its currently popular senses in epistemology, that the only genuine justification is
natural-scientific justification.”21 The reference is to Quine’s Naturalized Epistemology which
argues that since the knowing subject is naturally embodied, knowledge itself is a natural
phenomenon and thus epistemology should be pursued as a natural empirical science:
“Epistemology [...] simply falls into place as a chapter of psychology and hence of natural
Science. It studies a natural phenomenon, viz., a physical human subject.”22 Roughly, even if
Hegel agrees with Quine that epistemology falls into psychology, as the highest part of
‘Subjective Spirit’ in the Encyclopaedia, Hegel still thinks that to regard psychology only as
natural science, as Quine does, is nothing but a bad form of empiricism and formalism.
Quine’s methodological naturalism vastly differs from Hegel’s approach, because Quine, in
contrast to Hegel, regards empirical natural science as the only proper way to true knowledge.
Indeed, as Paul Redding argues, Hegel’s critique of metaphysics is not consistent with this
kind of anti-transcendental naturalism, which is “more common to analytic philosophy.”23
Hegel rather holds that “while we are each fundamentally limited and conditioned in our
particular cognitive capacities, we are, nevertheless, in virtue of our rational natures,
somehow capable of going beyond those limits.”24 Moreover, it is plausible to claim that
18
HEGEL. Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume 3, p. 385.
BEISER. German Idealism, p. 598, note 4.
20
Cf. PIPPIN. Hegel’s Practical Philosophy, p. 33.
21
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, pp. 52f.
22
QUINE, W.V.O. Naturalized Epistemology. In: Quine, W.V.O. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays.
New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 1969, pp. 82ff.
23
REDDING. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of the Hegelian Thought, p. 20.
24
REDDING. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of the Hegelian Thought, p. 222.
19
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
201
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
Hegel grounds the particular epistemological capacity of human beings in “the recognitively
intersubjective structures of spirit to which we all belong.”25
Be this as it may, there is a specific passage in the Philosophy of Nature that seems to
incriminate Hegel as a confirmed methodological naturalist in the Quinean spirit: “Not only
must philosophy be in agreement with our empirical knowledge of Nature, but the origin and
the formation of the Philosophy of Nature presupposes and is conditioned by physics”.26
Westphal has already brought this citation as a conclusive proof for Hegel’s naturalism.27 Yet,
as it is understandable from the rest of the text, this statement only goes to show that Hegel
does not affirm a principal collision between philosophy and empirical knowledge of nature,
for he regards the latter also as containing rational-conceptual elements – even if the
physicists are unaware of them as such. Without mentioning the case of Westphal, Terry
Pinkard justly notes that this citation only seems like a proof for Hegel’s Quinean naturalism,
while it is not.28 As Pinkard has shown in his interpretation, the nature described by natural
sciences, which deal only with the finite, is not the ‘whole’ or ‘absolute’ that Hegel looks for,
which means that Hegel does not accept the results of the natural sciences as the ‘absolute
idea.’29 Consequently, philosophy of spirit, which includes epistemological considerations
and culminates in the discussion of the ‘absolute spirit’ and ‘philosophy’ itself, can explicate
the essence of nature in even a more comprehensive and self-reflective way than philosophy
of nature.30 Hegel claims that natural sciences are not that purely empirical as they maintain,
for they involve the mathematical a priori.31 Hegel, like Aristotle,32 does not think that the
physicists alone can fully explicate the general content of all the conceptual schemes
employed in their science. Hegel demands from philosophy only ‘compatibility’ with natural
science, not ‘identity,’ for the natural science is just a presupposition in the sense of a ‘starting
point’ for philosophy.33 In addition, Pinkard rightly suggests that the importance of Hegel’s
25
REDDING. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of the Hegelian Thought, p. 222..
HEGEL, G.W.F. Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: Part Two of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical
Sciences (1830). Trans. Miller, A.V. from Nicolin and Poggeler’s edition (1959) and from the Zusätze in
Michelet’s text (1847). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970, p. 6, §246 note.
27
Cf. WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 52.
28
Cf. PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism. p. 19.
29
Cf. PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, pp. 19ff.
30
Cf. PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, pp. 19ff.
31
Cf. PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, pp. 19ff.
32
Cf. ARISTOTLE. Metaphysics. In: Aristotle in 23 Volumes. Trans. H. Tredennick, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd, 1989, vol. 17, chapter IV, 1005a, 40-50.
33
Cf. PAPAZOGLOU. Hegel and Naturalism, p. 23. Interestingly, Papazoglou presents a similar reading like
Pinkard, yet, while citing Hegel directly from Pinkard and ignoring Pinkard's critique, Papazoglou reproaches
26
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
202
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
first drafts to Philosophy of Nature from 1803–6 lies in the way they already show that Hegel
“needed a non-reductionist and non-naturalist account of the genesis of spirit out of nature.”34
Hegel completed this kind of account in his logical explication of the transition from the
category of ‘nature’ to that of ‘spirit’ in his Encyclopaedia from 1817.
Yet, in spite of this refutation of naturalism in Hegel, there are claims for Hegel’s own
version of naturalism, which treats the mind as a purely natural phenomenon. We shall turn
now to analyze such claims.
5. Naturalistic readings of Hegel
The common argument for Hegel’s naturalism has the structure of first refuting ‘strong’
ontological and methodological, just as we did until now, and then circumspectly finding a
‘weak’ or ‘soft’ version of naturalism in Hegel. These readings benevolently seek to defend
Hegel’s philosophy from being diagnosed as dubious and unscientific, perhaps metaphysical,
religious or even theistic. It is therefore worthy to observe the naturalistic arguments and offer
queries and questions.
5.1. Spirit as “powers within nature” (Beiser)
Frederick Beiser’s interpretation of Hegel is committed to naturalism about the mental,
as he believes that for Hegel “spirit is only the highest degree of organization and
development of the organic powers within nature”35 and therefore Hegel explains the
“transcendental self-consciousness according to its place within nature.”36 Beiser designates
Hegel’s view as nothing else than a “form of scientific naturalism:”37 “everything subjective,
mental, or conscious is explicable according to laws of nature,” not only “everything
objective, physical, or material.”38 In a rhetorical manner, reminding the ‘false dilemma,’
Beiser offers only bad alternatives to naturalism: determinist historicism, positivistic
Pinkard for not understanding the citation and for falsely holding Hegel to be a Quinean naturalist – exactly the
opposite of what Pinkard argues.
34
PINKARD. Hegel. A Biography, p. 187.
35
BEISER. Introduction, p. 9.
36
BEISER. German Idealism, p. 355.
37
BEISER. Introduction, p. 8.
38
BEISER. German Idealism, p. 598, note 4. For a slightly different view from Beiser, a more critical one, see
STONE, A. Hegel, Naturalism and the Philosophy of Nature. In: Hegel Bulletin, vol. 34, issue 1, May 2013.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
203
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
mysticism39 or “a form of speculation about supernatural entities, such as God, Providence,
and the soul.”40 He argues:
Schelling and Hegel also insist that their metaphysics has nothing to do with the
supernatural. Their conception of metaphysics is indeed profoundly naturalistic.
They banish all occult forces and the supernatural from the universe, explaining
everything in terms of natural laws. 41
Beiser thus claims that the “highest being,” which is at the heart of the metaphysical question
and which Hegel calls “the absolute,” is according to Hegel “the universe as the whole” and
that this is simply equivalent with nature.42 This formulation, however, is very far from
Hegel’s own thoughts. The question arises as to why spirit should mean to Hegel the highest
degree of organization of the ‘organic powers within nature’ and not, as Hegel puts it himself,
of the Idee, i.e. the ‘form’ or the ‘type’ of being. Beiser irretrievably locates the knowing
subject ‘only in the organic nature,’ not in ‘the world,’ i.e. the human world as well as the
world of thought. Such theory of knowledge that places the conscious being only ‘in nature’
corresponds to a mystical animalization of consciousness. This constrained naturalization
holds ab initio an indefensible presupposition: it does not identify the ‘noumenal’ in the realm
of pure thought, nor in the social realm, but in the naked animality. The imagined bearer of
the obscuring ‘powers within nature’ becomes itself an indeterminate entity working
somehow ‘in’ the things.
Hegel, on his part, criticized in Phenomenology of Spirit in Observing Reason the
mystical use of the category Kraft as a rather problematic metaphysical construction which is
from its essence not a purely natural ‘given.’ For Hegel, the search for powers in nature as
well as the very assumption of such powers is an activity of reason, which determines these
powers according to its own conceptual schema, to its own power, the power of reason. For
Hegel, spirit is not simply a product of nature, because nature, which is finite, temporal and
mortal, cannot go beyond the limits of itself and produce something like spirit, which is
infinite in its essence. In fact, Hegel argues that spirit and nature are both products of the Idee,
which ‘posits’ itself and ‘returns’ to itself. Hegel does not reduce spirit only to the ‘powers
within nature,’ because he believes that spirit is free in a way that nature is not. Hegel
39
Cf. BEISER. German Idealism, p. 2.
BEISER. German Idealism, p. 5.
41
BEISER. German Idealism, p. 2.
42
BEISER. Introduction, p. 8.
40
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
204
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
designates the belief that takes the principle of Geist to be some kind of natural force as the
Naturreligion that identifies the divine somehow with the natural.43 He criticizes that since the
‘immediate’ natural religion still does not acknowledge that the spiritual implies a self-aware
subjectivity, it does not reach a true concept of freedom, but only a pantheistic one. Given
Hegel’s own terms, Beiser’s interpretation – and generally, the whole conception of the
naturalism about the mental – is more likely to correspond to the belief of Naturreligion than
to Hegel’s genuine view. Beiser maintains quite rightly that Hegel himself criticized
Schelling’s idea of the absolute as “excessive naturalism” that underestimates “the realm of
spirit that consists in society, the state, and history.”44
Beiser has noticed the need to revise and moderate his view, as he attacked Hegel’s
scholarship for letting Hegel’s thoughts “appear more respectable to contemporary analytic
philosophy.”45 Beiser could have in mind, for example, Westphal, who describes the key
theses of Hegel’s epistemology as “fallibilism, pragmatism and non-foundationalism,”46 using
distinctly and exclusively a set of contemporary terms and almost none of Hegel’s original
expressions. Westphal, whose view will be presented in the next section, wrongly believes
that Hegel’s ideas are valuable just because they can be completely found in contemporary
theory of knowledge. At some point, Beiser himself stopped speaking of Hegel’s naturalism
and began criticizing scholars for flattening Hegel’s claims with non-hermeneutical
methods.47 He came to the remarkable conclusion that “the predominant concern of
Anglophone scholarship on German idealism has been to emasculate, domesticate and
sanitize it, to make it weak, safe and clean for home consumption.”48 The significance of
Beiser’s position consists in the element of its self-critique and in its upholding of
hermeneutic effort in the inquiry. Beiser, however, indirectly attacks his own position,
In Hegel’s Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, in the section “A. Immediate Religion, or Nature
Religion,” pp. 209–223; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 16, pp. 259–278. In order not to confuse the
terms, Hegel stresses that the unreasonable “nature religion” should not be mixed up with Rousseau’s or Kant’s
enlightened idea of intellectual Vernunftreligion, which was also called “natural religion.”
44
BEISER. German Idealism, pp. 9f.
45
BEISER. German Idealism, p. 508.
46
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 51.
47
In Beiser’s essay: Dark Days: Anglophone Scholarship since the 1960s. In: Hammer E. (Ed.). German
Idealism, Contemporary Perspectives. London: Routledge, 2007, pp. 70–90. Still, when Beiser comes again to
speak of Hegel’s non-mechanical paradigm of the organic nature, he offers a rather Schellingian model,
according to which “the mental realm is only the highest degree of organization and development of the organic
powers of nature; the mental and physical differ only in degree rather than kind: the mental is the invisible form
of the physical, the physical the visible form of the mental” (BEISER. Dark Days, p. 83). Schelling’s idea of
nature was indeed decisive for Hegel, but mostly to the extent that Hegel argues also ‘against’ it.
48
BEISER. Dark Days, p. 70.
43
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
205
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
because he himself does not provide the reader with any hermeneutic investigation that deals
with Hegel’s original texts. Although he recognizes the problem of the “non-metaphysical”49
interpretation of Hegel as responsible for ‘dark days,’ he does not associate it explicitly with
the problem of attributing naturalism to Hegel.
5.2. The “biological needs” of self-consciousness as a proof that thought presupposes nature
(Westphal)
Westphal believes that “Hegel’s naturalistic account of thought” 50 is to be found in
Hegel’s discussion on desire in the chapter Self-Consciousness in the Phenomenology of
Spirit. According to Westphal, Hegel claims that the condition for the existence of selfconsciousness is a ‘law-like natural structure,’ because
any world in which we human beings can be self-conscious is one that has a natural
structure unto itself that provides us with at least a minimum necessary degree of
regularity and variety among the contents of our sensations.51
Westphal elaborates his thesis and claims that:
Naturalist elements appear in Hegel’s epistemology in his theses that biological
needs (one root of consciousness) involve elementary classification of objects, that
the contents of conscious awareness derive from a public world, and that
classificatory thought presupposes natural structures in the world.52
Even though one can indeed agree with the premise that self-consciousness is capable of
‘classifying’ objects of desire in the shared outerworld, several objections to this argument as
a whole arise.
To begin with, Hegel himself does not speak of “biological needs” (biologische
Bedürfnisse), at least not in the context of self-consciousness. He speaks of Begierde, which
means “desire”, and which Westphal falsely translates as “need” (Bedürfnis). Desire is for
Hegel not simply biological, but like volition, an intentional act of a self-conscious being.
49
This term was coined by Klaus Hartmann in his essay: HARTMANN, K. Hegel: A Non-Metaphysical View.
In: MacIntyre, A. (Ed.). Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays. Garden City: Doubleday, 1972.
50
WESTPHAL, K. Hegel’s Epistemological Realism: A Study of the Aim and Method of Hegel’s
Phenomenology of Spirit. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989, p. 160.
51
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, pp. 70f.
52
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 52.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
206
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
Even if it is true that Hegel refers to the desire of self-consciousness as directed towards
objects of consumption, Westphal ignores the fact that Hegel clearly says that selfconsciousness attains true satisfaction of its “desire” only by another self-conscious being, not
just by a natural object.53 For Hegel, self-consciousness reaches satisfaction by Anerkennen,
the ‘act of mutual recognition,’ not by “classifying,”54 the translation that Westphal seems to
prefer for Anerkennen. To claim that consciousness consumes biological objects in order to
physically exist in the living world is to show only one side of the coin, while hiding the
other. The other side of this coin, which Hegel also highlights, if not even more strongly, is to
claim that consciousness consumes other kinds of ‘objects,’ namely self-conscious beings. It
belongs to the heart of the Hegelian idea of self-consciousness that it needs another selfconsciousness in order to become truly self-conscious and so to reach its fully developed
concept. Westphal insists on Hegel’s “naturalism” because he believes that to acknowledge
any interaction between nature and consciousness already means to be a naturalist. Yet it is
not clear why such a premise should be an adequate interpretation of Hegel’s philosophical
intentions.
In fact, the problem with Westphal’s reading is that Westphal himself also confirms that
self-consciousness ought not to be identified with a “biological organism”55 and that “Hegel
argues that our capacity for classificatory thought is not merely a natural phenomenon.”56 He
acknowledges that Hegel’s idea of absolute spirit corresponds to the “social whole” and the
“human community.”57 But at the same time, he ignores the hard problem of Hegelian
epistemology: the question of how to justify the intellectual possibility of an unconditioned
point of view that enables true self-knowledge. In Westphal’s view, spirit remains overall
“within its natural setting”58 and always presupposes a “natural environment.”59
Westphal’s naturalist reading may seem to attain confirmation from the following
sentence in Hegel’s “Philosophy of Spirit:” “From our point of view Mind has for its
53
Cf. HEGEL, G.W.F. Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. Miller, V. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977, p. 110;
HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 3, p. 144.
54
Cf. HEGEL. Phenomenology of Spirit, p. 112; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 3, p. 147.
55
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemological Realism, p. 161.
56
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 63.
57
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 63.
58
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 63.
59
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 59.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
207
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
presupposition Nature.”60 For Hegel, however, it would be only a common-sense view to
think that mind needs nature in order to be, and that hence nature is more ‘important’ than
nature and comes ‘before’ it. Only naive realism grasps nature as objectively and totally
different from the mind and totally independent of it. Hegel’s theory of Reflexion at the
beginning of the Logic of Essence, maintains the operative category of ‘presupposition’
(Voraussetzung) does not articulate in any way that the ‘presupposed’ (Vorausgesetzte) is a
casual ‘reason’ for that which presupposes it (Voraussetzende). On the contrary, for Hegel,
the presupposed is logically subordinate, an abstract essence whose content is less
determined. In our case, this means concretely that nature is not the logical reason for spirit,
but an entity less determined. Hegel’s sentence, thus, does not come to express the primacy of
nature over spirit, but the opposite: only for us, the cognitive individual subjects, it seems that
nature is nothing but a given reality. Furthermore, by examining Hegel’s words closely, we
find that in the original not only the word “presupposition” is italicized, but also the words
“nature” and “from our point of view.”61 William Wallace has dropped from the translation
that which makes the significant difference: the function of highlighting “from our point of
view”, which says in the original ‘for us’ (für uns), is to indicate the state of mind that is still
subjective and insufficient. Hegel stresses the supremacy of spirit over nature in the
Encyclopaedia Logic when he claims that “nature is not just something fixed and complete on
its own account, which could therefore subsist even without spirit; rather, it is only in spirit
that nature attains to its goal and its truth.”62
Westphal’s final verdict on Hegel’s Psychology, namely that “Hegel’s philosophical
psychology is deeply naturalist,”63 is consistent with his own naturalistic view, but it is
perplexing because Hegel’s Psychology is located in Philosophy of Spirit, not Philosophy of
Nature, and it explicitly treats ‘spirit as spirit,’ and not as ‘natural soul.’ The latter is
conceived only as spirit’s initial default ‘natural moment’ which Hegel discusses in his
Anthropology, not Psychology.
60
HEGEL, G.W.F. Philosophy of Mind. Translated from the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences
with Five Introductory Essays. Trans. Wallace, W. New York, NY: Cosimo, Inc, 2008, p. 6, §381; HEGEL.
Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 10, p. 17.
61
HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 10, p. 17. Michael Inwood has revised Wallace’s translation and
improved it: “For us mind has nature as its presupposition” (HEGEL, G.W.F. Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind,
with Zusätze. Trans. Wallace, W. and Miller, A.V. Revised by Inwood, M.J. New York: Oxford University
Press, 2007, p. 9, §381).
62
HEGEL, G.W.F. The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part 1, p. 153, §96, Addition; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern,
vol. 8, p. 204.
63
WESTPHAL. Hegel’s Epistemology, p. 55.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
208
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
Pinkard’s reading stresses the same natural factor in the embodiment of the human
knowing subject, yet with different arguments. In what follows I shall demonstrate Pinkard’s
reasons for reading Hegel’s spirit through a naturalistic lens.
5.3. “Disenchanted” naturalism: the natural freedom of natural mind (Pinkard)
Pinkard declares in Hegel’s name that: “We are embodied agents, bound by the limits of
our organic nature and always working within a particular, bounded social space.”64 If this
were Hegel’s main thought regarding spirit or science, he could indeed have been considered
as ascribing to a skeptical form of naturalism about the mental. However, Pinkard presents
more concrete arguments in favor of Hegel’s naturalism.
(1) In a quite surprising manner, Pinkard explains Hegel’s alleged view concerning the
natural character of human consciousness with a ‘neuroscientific’ anecdote:
The human agent, ‘by virtue of certain biological characteristics having to do with
its brain and its nervous systems’ (among other things), actualizes something that is
already in play in animal life but that, as put to work in that way, becomes
fundamentally different from it.65
The question arises, however, as to whether the text in apostrophes is also claimed by Hegel.
Even if one agrees with the assumption that human life, grasped as spirit life, is in Hegel
‘fundamentally different’ from animal life, Pinkard’s own explanation for the difference is
‘biological’ in its essence and based on the ‘particularity’ of the ‘human brain.’ The phrase
“by virtue of” suggests a kind of causality that is rather in question. Pinkard locates the
anthropological difference at the natural instead of the cognitive level. He does not emphasize
that the capacity of thinking is the significant factor in the constitution of human selfconsciousness. He appears to speak of animals and people, but in fact refers to the zoological
characteristics of animals, believing that “Hegel holds that human agents, by virtue of
thinking of themselves as animals, thereby become special animals, namely, self-interpreting
ones.”66 Pinkard does not account for his own ‘assimilationism’ dressed up as
‘differentialism.’ In a contradictory manner, he actually endorses a view that relapses into
strong naturalism à la Beiser: “Human subjectivity emerges as a kind of reflexive
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, pp. 104f.
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 48 (my apostrophes).
66
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 18.
64
65
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
209
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
complication of this kind of organic, animal self-relation, not as something radically other
than animal life.”67 In this, Pinkard is not alone. A precedent was set by Willem DeVries who
claimed that Hegel “saw man as arising out of and continuous with nature and capable of
being understood only in this natural context.”68 But does Hegel really hold that man arises
‘only’ in a natural context? In Hegel’s Preliminary Conception of logic in the Encyclopaedia
we find the following thought: “Insofar as he is spirit, man is not a natural being.”69 Likewise,
at the outset of the Philosophy of Spirit we learn that spirit: “does not emerge in a natural
manner from nature. [...] this emergence is not in the flesh but spiritual, it is not to be
understood as a natural emergence but as a development of the concept.”70 After the transition
from nature to spirit, spirit does not remain natural in its essence and what comes back to
itself is not nature, but rather the spirit or the Idee. Hegel explicitly says that at some point in
the transition from nature to spirit “nature has vanished” and is only aufgehoben in spirit.71 In
Pinkard’s interpretation, Hegel’s philosophy of spirit as a whole would seem to have
evaporated.
Pinkard’s epistemological naturalism corresponds to the assimilationist cognitiveethologistic approach which we have explicated before. It misses a critical Hegelian argument
in the Phenomenology of Spirit, according to which the intelligence of individuals is rather, as
Stekeler articulates it, an “effect of the collectively passed on general forms of human life.”72
Such tradition-making, i.e. passing-on-praxis, is not done by a single brain of an individual,
no matter how developed, but by a concepts-sharing community, which is a universal
transsubjective being. The evolution of the individual brains has a rather biological
explanation: they evolve for the sake of species longevity. 73
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 30.
DEVRIES, Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity, p. xii.
69
HEGEL. The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part 1, p. 63, §24, Addition 3; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 8,
p. 90.
70
HEGEL. Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind, with Zusätze, p. 15, §381, Zusatz; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern,
vol. 10, p. 25.
71
HEGEL. Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind, with Zusätze,, p. 9, §381; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 10, p.
17.
72
STEKELER, P. Hegel’s Phenomenologie des Geistes: Ein dialogischer Kommentar. Hamburg: Meiner,
2014, p. 38: “Effekt gemeinsam tradierter allgemeiner Formen menschlichen Lebens.”
73
STEKELER. Hegel’s Phenomenologie des Geistes, pp. 37f: “Zentral und fundamental ist dabei Hegels Kritik
an der bis heute üblichen ‘empiristischen’ und ‘individualistischen’ Auffassung, die Intelligenz des Einzelnen
und die geistige Welt überhaupt würde einfach hervorgebracht durch das Verhalten und oder die Gehirne der
einzelnen Menschen, wie sie sich im Laufe der Evolution nach den aus der Biologie bekannten Weisen zum
Zweck des Überlebens der Gattung herausgebildet hatte.”
67
68
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
210
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
(2) To further prove that Hegel banishes all “nonnatural powers”, Pinkard suggests that
Hegel refutes a “dualist account of freedom as involving nonnatural powers”74 by referring to
Hegel’s words on ‘law-like freedom:’ “We have said that freedom is to be asserted as the
basic essence of spirit, the freedom from and in the natural, which, however, must not be
taken as arbitrary choice (Willkür) but rather as law-like freedom.”75 Although Hegel clearly
argues that freedom belongs to the essence of spirit and is free from the natural, Pinkard still
presumes that the idea of the law-likeness of freedom, the idea of law in general, belongs only
to the domain of nature and somehow ‘refutes’ the nonnatural element. Hegel criticizes this
view in the chapter Observing Reason, where he argues that law (Gesetz) in general, hence
also natural law, is a product of spirit’s own act of ‘positing’ (Setzung), of thinking about the
various forms of being and formulating the relations between them. Insofar as the spirit
‘posits’ the laws, it finds, validates and formulates them. ‘Legislation’ (Gesetzgebung) is thus
an act executed and altered by the spirit, not by nature. When the spirit looks for laws of
nature and articulates them, it actually deals with itself and articulates something very
fundamental about itself. The laws Hegel has in mind include social laws (norms), state laws
(legislation) and divine laws (commands). They all stem from a free subject or a community
of subjects, and they are all brought forth by the faculty of ‘reason.’ As such, they are grasped
as a self-conscious process of collective self-determination. Therefore, contrary to the
common sense view, Hegel does not hold that the concept of ‘law-like freedom’ is a
contradictio in adjecto.
(3) Pinkard also attempts to prove Hegel’s naturalism by contraposition, arguing that
Hegel is not a spiritualist, for he “does not hold that natural, material objects are (to use an
admittedly slippery term) reducible in any kind of way to mental or spiritual objects.”76 Even
if one agrees with Pinkard that Hegel is certainly not a mad Jenseits-spiritualist who imagines
that all is spirit, objections to Pinkard’s definition can be raised. Firstly, not everyone who is
not a proper spiritualist is automatically a naturalist. To prove naturalism reliably, one should
rather prove that all the mental or spiritual objects are effectively reducible to natural objects.
One cannot only prove that the opposite does not occur. Secondly, and more significantly, in
the chapter Sensation in Anthropology, Hegel shows that just as the soul enacts the natural
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 30.
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 43 note 62. This citation stems according to Pinkard, who translated it
himself, from “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel et al., Vorlesungen über die Philosophie des Geistes: Berlin
1827/1828 (Vorlesungen / Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel; Hamburg: F. Meiner, 1994), xxxviii, 321 pp., p. 19.”
76
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 38, note 28.
74
75
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
211
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
objects by “sensing” (empfinden) them, i.e. by making them into an intelligible part of itself,
to an ‘ideality’ within the soul, the soul also externalizes itself into the outer nature in order to
become visible and so to be “found” (gefunden). Hegel interprets certain corporal phenomena
as supervening on spirit’s motions: the spirit embodies itself through mimic, gesture,
blushing, laughing and crying, and in this way becomes perceptible for another sensing soul.
In both cases, in the internalization and the externalization, the soul itself is the actualizing
agent, not nature.
(4) Finally, Pinkard claims that Hegel is a naturalist because he acknowledges the
existence of soul in animals, in contrast to what Pinkard regards as the anti-naturalist religions
which purportedly deny soul in animals: “Hegel divides animals from people not on the
religious ground that animals do not have souls – on Hegel's account, they do have souls – but
on the ground that they cannot think, that is, cannot entertain reasons as reasons.”77 It is not
clear, however, what exactly the ‘religious ground that animals do not have soul’ is. Which
religion does Pinkard mean? Branches of Christianity may differ over whether the soul of
animals is immortal: Baptists doubt it, as does the Church of Christ, and some Catholics
negate it.78 But which religion in the world deprives animals of having a soul at all? Pinkard
apparently relies on the Preface to the Second Edition of the Encyclopaedia, where Hegel
deals with the issue. Hegel, however, writes there:
It is thinking that first makes the soul – with which the lower animals are endowed
too – into spirit; and philosophy is only a consciousness concerning [...] spirit [...]
which distinguishes it from the lower animals, and makes it capable of religion.79
Also in the second paragraph in the Encyclopaedia we read that one ought not to forget that
due to thinking “only man is capable of religion, and that the lower animals have no
religion.”80 In both cases Hegel speaks of Tier, ‘animal,’ not exactly ‘lower animals’ – a
translation which rather confirms the vague prejudice that man ‘is’ animal, only a ‘higher’
one, and the other ‘animals’ are from their nature just ‘lower animals.’ Pinkard’s
interpretation conveys therefore the impression that the attribute ‘naturalism’ is used against
PINKARD. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 44 note 72.
http://do-animals-have-souls.info/organised-religions.html.
79
HEGEL. The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part 1, p. 12.
80
HEGEL. The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part 1, p. 25.
77
78
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
212
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
religion in general, while it is not evident that Hegel would adopt this line of thought. What
Hegel originally claims is not generally hostile to religion.
Out of the discourse of naturalism about the mental, there emerges a further reading that
interprets the social-habitual consciousness as the naturalistic side of Hegel’s collective spirit:
the view of social naturalism.
5.4. Social naturalism (Testa)
Italo Testa stands in the recent tradition of naturalistic readings of Hegel as he
convincingly refutes any “physicalist, reductionist or eliminativist” naturalism in Hegel’s
system,81
while
simultaneously
establishing
a
naturalistic
thesis
about
Hegel’s
“epistemological realism:” “This thesis could be called ‘Hegel's naturalism:’ the idea that
there is one single reality – living reality – and different levels of description of it.”82 On the
surface, this definition may sound plausible. However, Testa argues that Hegel holds an
‘explicit’ epistemological position, namely a “natural theory of mind,”83 that is expressed in
the sentence: “Spirit, for us, has Nature as its presupposition.”84 Testa’s goal is to look for the
sense in which this ‘natural theory of mind’ can be correctly related to the “social space.”85
Based only on two appearances of the term ‘second nature’ in paragraphs 4 and 151 in the
Elements of the Philosophy of Right, Testa identifies in Hegel what he labels “social
naturalism,”86 a form of McDowellian “second-natural naturalism.”87 Testa declares that
social life in the form of the “social and institutional bodies” ‘is’ the ‘second nature’ of
humans, because “the institutions of social life are extensions and objectifications of human
nature and of individual mind.”88
Looking carefully at Hegel’s words in the paragraphs which Testa left without a
commentary, we actually find that in both paragraphs Hegel says “as a second nature” (als
81
TESTA, I. Hegel's Naturalism or Soul and Body in the Encyclopaedia. In: Stern, D.S. (Ed.). Essays on
Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjective Spirit. New York, NY: SUNY Press, 2013, p. 35.
82
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, pp. 23f.
83
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 30.
84
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 21.
85
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 31.
86
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 31.
87
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 28. What follows here is not designed to be a refutation of ‘second-natural
naturalism,’ as developed by McDowell in World and Mind, but only of the evidence given by Testa for its
existence in Hegel.
88
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 35.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
213
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
eine zweite Natur), not “is a second nature.”89 This difference may appear to be hair-splitting,
but the question arises as to what precisely Hegel compares with “second nature” and why. As
such, consideration of the context in which this term appears is appropriate.
In paragraph 4, it is evident that the object of Hegel’s analysis is the idea of “right”
(Recht), not society. He clearly grounds this idea in the spiritual realm and in the free will, not
in nature. His claim is that, by producing the realm of right, the spirit produces its own world
which, while like a second nature in some respect, is actually not nature, but culture. Nature
develops by itself, but culture requires effort and a process of learning. Hegel’s conception
here is set in an analogy with nature as that which is which is ‘produced’ (hervorgebracht), as
natura naturata, not natura naturans.
In paragraph 151, Hegel argues that the ethical habit, das Sittliche, appears ‘as’ a second
nature, only if it is taken to be identical with what ‘individuals simply do,’ how they are
without the effort to change. Again, he does not define the ethical realm itself as natural in
any sense. In fact, by this Hegel shows that he is aware of the Aristotelian origin of the
concept of “second nature”. Whereas Testa uses the term “second nature” in quite a trivial
manner and even literally, Hegel, like Aristotle, does not mean nature or even the social
realm, but a property an individual cannot easily change. Furthermore, in paragraph 146
Hegel argues that the individual subjects believe that the valid ethical laws possess even
‘more authority’ than the natural constraints. Here we find the analogy with nature as a
‘mighty power,’ which is experienced by the individual subjects ‘as if’ it were ultimately
independent and self-determined. For Hegel, to say that nature is really independent is wrong,
because nature is conceptually formed in contrast to the independent spirit. This would be as
wrong as saying that social realities must be considered as unalterable givens.
Testa, who neither elaborates on McDowell’s second-natural naturalism, nor refers to the
Aristotelian origin, ignores that Hegel also deals with the question of ‘habit’ as ‘second
nature’ from the perspective of the Philosophy of Spirit, especially in the Anthropology in
paragraphs 409–10. In these paragraphs, the mechanism of habit is viewed as ‘one moment’
in the life of the ‘practicing spirit,’ namely the ‘self-feeling subjective spirit.’ But undoubtedly
this is only one layer in the concept of spirit, namely the initial still-unconscious part. In this
moment, the idea of spirit is intentionally treated in the ‘immediate form,’ in which it appears
to the individuals, not to the ‘absolute spirit,’ and hence not as it is truly ‘in and for itself.’
89
My emphasis.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
214
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
Testa would seem to be aware of Hegel’s philosophy of spirit ‘as a whole’ and hence of the
problem of concentrating exclusively on parts of the subjective spirit, e.g. on the idea of
second nature, when he says: “If the Hegelian philosophy of Spirit reflects such an approach –
some form of methodological and ontological holism – then we cannot claim to have dealt
with the mind-body question adequately if we have concentrated exclusively on subjective
Spirit.”90 However, while fully reducing the Hegelian conception of the institutionalizing
‘objective spirit,’ let alone the sphere of ‘absolute spirit,’ to a programmatic naturalization of
social habituation, Testa does not draw the full consequences from his own correct restriction.
After considering the various naturalistic readings, doubts arise about the actual content
of Hegel‘s concept of nature. We thus turn to the presentation of his concept of nature, in
order to reconstruct the core issues and to show them as a possible response to naturalism.
6. Hegel’s concept of nature as one of the self-manifestations of ‘the idea’
At the outset of Philosophy of Nature Hegel uses the term Idee, ‘idea,’ to determine
nature: nature is the idea ‘in the form of otherness,’ the seemingly paradoxical idea that is
‘outside’ itself, a pure ‘externality.’ As a form of the idea, ‘nature,’ like spirit, functions in
Hegel’s organization of the sciences as a universal metacategory. Hegel’s conception of
nature as ‘idea’ may immediately sound as going against the basic tenet that nature is ‘not’ an
idea, but rather the whole of matter – a plenitude of atoms or molecules or infinite amount of
things yet to be discovered. A consequence of this tenet is the assumed indeterminacy of
nature, the problem of guaranteeing any a priori structure to the multifaceted nature. Being
aware of this problem, Hegel designates the concept of nature as being in ‘contradiction’ with
nature’s being, an ‘unresolved contradiction.’ Concerning the extension of the term ‘nature,’
after reading the Philosophy of Nature we understand that Hegel regards the natural realm,
unlike the spiritual, as finite. The systematic transition from the category of nature to that of
spirit is parallel to the transition within the last part of the logic, ‘the idea,’ from the idea of
‘life’ to that of ‘recognition.’
While explicating his view of nature, Hegel articulates a non-dualistic distinction
between nature and spirit: the ‘form of the idea’ of nature is different from the form of the
idea of spirit, insofar as nature does not hold in itself its own Begriff – the concept of itself as
90
TESTA. Hegel’s Naturalism, p. 16.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
215
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
‘idea.’ An animal cannot be self-conscious in the way human spirit can be. Nature is for
Hegel only ‘one’ finite realization of the idea, not the only one. Surely, one can object to the
suggested priority of spirit over nature and claim that nature produces precious goods like life.
Hegel, who does not hold an ‘anti-nature’ plea, claims the same, only that he determines the
spirit and its products, like works of art, as even livelier, containing “a higher kind of life [...]
than the natural form.”91 It is of the spirit, not of nature, that Hegel says that it is “the truth
and the final goal of Nature and the genuine actuality of the Idea.”92
The interrelation between nature and spirit has a teleological meaning: “Spirit, just
because it is the goal of Nature, is prior to it.”93 One has to think of this relation in logical
terms, not chronological: since spirit is nature’s ‘end,’ i.e. its ‘final purpose’ (Endzweck), it
can be set by the same token as the ‘initial reason’ for nature’s being. Hegel’s radical position
is that spirit has ontological priority over nature because spirit ‘posits’ nature, i.e. spirit is that
which ‘thinks’ nature and relates to it conceptually. In Hegel’s system, both the organic nature
and the idea of spirit exemplify paradigms of the infinite teleology and hence of the Idee, in
contrast to the finite teleology of mere objectivity. In contrast to the domesticating reading of
Hegel, which admits only the convenient epistemological priority of spirit over nature,
94
Hegel’s insight in Science of Logic is rather that spirit is both ratio cognoscendi and ratio
essendi of nature, for nature is not just an immediate given. The ontological priority of the
spirit is not expressed in terms of ‘pure being’ or ‘abstract essence,’ but of the ‘concept.’
Precisely for this reason, Hegel argues that the “substance” should be also construed as
‘subject.’ The naturalistic approach conceals spirit’s dialectical relationship with nature,
which is not dependent or needy. Contrary to ontological naturalism, Hegel takes nature to be
only finite realization of the idea, not the whole one.
Even though Hegel conceives, like the naturalist, the soul, the first moment of spirit, as
Naturgeist, as the life of the physical soul and thereby as part of the general natural life, he
still rejects the understanding of spirit’s activity ‘only’ in the context of natural life.95 Spirit,
which only has a vague clue of itself in nature and does not really find itself in it, clearly goes
91
HEGEL. Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature (1830), p. 18, §248, Remark; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 9,
pp. 28f, §248. Hegel writes: “eine höhere Lebendigkeit ... als die natürliche Form.”
92
HEGEL. Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature (1830), p. 24, §251; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol, 9. p. 36,
§251.
93
HEGEL. Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature (1830), p. 444, §376, Addition; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol.
9, p. 538, §376, Zusatz.
94
Cf. PAPAZOGLOU, Hegel and Naturalism, p. 33.
95
HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol, 10, p. 53 (§392), Zusatz.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
216
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
beyond mere natural life and becomes independent. This means that the spirit attains its own
‘self’ and is selbständig, ‘stands by itself’, while ruling the universe – in the broadest sense –
with its power of thought. Hegel’s conclusion that “the general natural life” is “only a
subordinated moment” in the spirit, that the “Mind is just this elevation above nature and
physical modes,”96 brings to distinctive expression the supremacy of spirit over nature,
especially in the question of knowledge.
7. Hegel’s possible response to naturalism
Hegel takes only ‘one sphere’ of the concept of spirit to be ‘natural,’ namely the ‘initial
moment’ of its development, which is the beginning of knowing before consciousness turns to
be self-consciousness and then spirit. The fully self-conscious spirit represents the scientific
viewpoint, which is ready for the ‘absolute knowledge,’ conceptualized as ‘pure science’ or
simply ‘logic.’ The initial natürliches Bewusstsein, ‘natural consciousness,’ ‘begins’ with a
natürliche Vorstellung, a ‘natural opinion’ or a ‘natural assumption.’ Like doxa, Vorstellung
means to Hegel a common belief held by an ‘ordinary’ consciousness, which just ‘begins’ its
scientific education, its Bildung. This approach has a conceptual grounding: nature is ‘our
idea’ for what is not yet conscious of itself ‘as’ idea. Therefore, naturality in general, which
Hegel regards as the ‘otherness’ or ‘the negative’ of the idea, designates to him only spirit’s
departure point in its cognitive evolution. Hegel formulates his observation regarding
philosophical cognition as follows: as long as consciousness conceives itself only in terms of
nature and not ‘as’ idea, it cannot ‘go’ beyond itself and eventually become episteme,
conceived as true self-knowledge. Although consciousness has a natural-physical aspect, as a
whole, it is not subjected to a biological structure, is not just a ‘natural kind.’ As Hegel
argues: “Whatever is confined within the limits of natural life cannot by its own efforts go
beyond its immediate existence; but it is driven beyond it by something else [...]
Consciousness, however [...] is something that goes beyond limits, and [...] beyond itself.”97
In Hegel’s Encyclopaedia, we find another clear response to the quasi-Kantian naturalistic
96
97
HEGEL. Philosophy of Mind, p. 59, § 440.
HEGEL. Phenomenology of Spirit, p. 51 (§80); HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 3, p. 74.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
217
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
claim about the alleged factuality of the human epistemological finitude, namely “that man is
certainly finite and mortal on the side of his nature, but that he is infinite in cognition.”98
Hegel’s response to the naturalistic worry of a dualistic dichotomy between spirit and
nature is that they are ‘both’ forms of the realized Idee, albeit distinguished ones. It is not the
case that all is spirit, but rather that all phenomena of the real, both the natural and the
spiritual, are related with each other stepwise and each one is related to the infinite idea qua
its formation. One ought not to envisage Hegel’s Idee as a ‘mere idea,’ Vorstellung, the
picturing power of imagination that creates a representation of a particular object running
through the mind, nor as bloß Gedachtes, a thought without a content, without reference to the
‘real,’ to the wirklich, i.e., a thought without an ‘actual effect’ on reality. Rather, the Idee is
the most ‘concrete’ being: “the adequate Notion, that which is objectively true, or the true as
such.”99 Hegel’s thought aims at reaching a conceptual unity in the sense of ‘oneness’ or
‘being one and the same’ by means of the very idea of absolute idea, where the ‘conscious
being’ and the ‘objective being’ are united in their being. Nature and spirit are two distinct
manifestations of the same self-identical idea, being in a unity which naturalism aspires to
achieve as well with its ‘monism of nature.’ Per definition though, the naturalist fails to name
the ‘nonnatural’ ingredient in this unity he seeks. Naturalism neglects to acknowledge the
manifestation of the nonnatural being, which is beyond or before nature and is thus capable of
grasping nature as a whole: being spirit.
8. Conclusion
Although Hegel’s philosophy can be read as offering an ongoing multifaceted dialogue
with diverse streams of naturalism, his own conception of nature and spirit is neither
consistent with classical naturalism, nor with Quinean epistemological naturalism, nor with
general naturalism about the mental. An und für sich, Hegel is not a naturalist, even though
the forms of natural study were of interest to him. For Hegel, the different versions of
naturalism are ‘natural’ in the sense of initial and common. The main problem Hegel detects
in naturalism is that it wishes to perceive all beings ‘im-mediately,’ without the medium of
logos, its conceptual framework that let us see every being ‘as such’ in the first place. For
98
HEGEL. The Encyclopaedia Logic, p. 63, §24, Addition 3; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 8, p. 90.
HEGEL. G.W.F. Science of Logic. Trans. Miller, A.V. Atlantic Highlands. NJ: Humanities Press
International, 1969, p. 755; HEGEL. Werke in 20 Bändern, vol. 6, p. 462.
99
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
218
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
Hegel, scientific thinking, in contrast to the philosophically ‘uneducated’ thought, is what
ought ‘not’ to consist in such de-conceptualizing element.
Obviously, and for a good reason, the endeavor to rehabilitate Hegel from being a
nonnaturalist wishes to purify his name from being ‘unscientific.’ Yet, the naturalistic
approach to philosophical texts naturally avoids rigorously scientific hermeneutical methods
of interpreting, particularly from providing a critique of Hegel’s original texts and from
questioning the various translations.100 In the nature of naturalism, and other ism-terms, lies
the tendency to define one’s school of thought by delimiting and stressing only one level of
the being. Naturalism itself, however, is a free form of the idea, a possible way of human
thinking, which therefore cannot be said ‘without any doubt’ to be conditioned necessarily by
specific natural laws or any natural objects known to us. If we think it through to the end, the
self-annihilating argument of naturalism about the mental is naturalism’s ‘own goal.’
Notwithstanding, the various kinds of current naturalism in Hegel research, in the socalled deflationary ‘non-metaphysical’ reading of Hegel, virtually embody the justified lasting
attempt to read spirit in its unity with nature and thus continue to be a fair challenge in a
genuine philosophical manner, an ‘unresolved contradiction.’ The value of the question of
naturalism is that it leads us to look for the appropriate way to relate to the being, including
nature. Finally, the human condition of sharing a self-aware spirit, not just a common nature,
underlies and justifies the normative-ontological space of ethical principles, among them the
environmental responsibility towards nature. This is an issue for another essay. The only way
to correct naturalism’s ‘own goal’ is to score another goal, beginning with gradually directing
the intellectual sight from the natural to another horizon.
Roi Bar
Universität Leipzig
Institut für Philosophie
Beethovenstraße 15
04107 Leipzig
roibarmail@yahoo.de
For further critique of the naturalistic ‘post-metaphysical reading’ of German idealism see: GARDNER, S.
The Limits of Naturalism and the Metaphysics of German Idealism. In: Hammer, E. (Ed.). German Idealism,
Contemporary Perspectives. London: Routledge, 2007, pp. 19–49.
100
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
219
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
BIBLIOGRAPHY
ARISTOTLE. Metaphysics. In: Aristotle in 23 Volumes, vols. 17, 18. Translated by H.
Tredennick. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd,
1989.
BEISER, Friederick Charles. Dark Days: Anglophone Scholarship since the 1960s. In:
Hammer, E. (Ed.). German Idealism, Contemporary Perspectives. London: Routledge,
2007, pp. 70–90.
BEISER, Friederick Charles. German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781–
1801. Harvard: Harvard University Press, 2002.
BEISER, Friederick Charles. Introduction: Hegel and the Problem of Metaphysics. In: Beiser,
F.C. (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Hegel. New York, NY: Cambridge University
Press, 1993, pp. 1–24.
DEVRIES, Willem A. Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity. An Introduction to Theoretical
Spirit. Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press, 1988.
GARDNER, Sebastian. The Limits of Naturalism and the Metaphysics of German Idealism.
In: Hammer, E. (Ed.). German Idealism, Contemporary Perspectives. London:
Routledge, 2007, pp. 19–49.
HARTMANN, Klaus. Hegel: A Non-Metaphysical View. In: MacIntyre, A. (Ed.). Hegel: A
Collection of Critical Essays. Garden City: Doubleday, 1972.
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind, with Zusätze. Translated
by W. Wallace and A.V Miller. Revised by M.J. Inwood. New York: Oxford University
Press, 2007.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
220
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: Part Two of the
Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830). Translated by A.V. Miller. From
Nicolin and Poggeler’s edition (1959) and from the Zusätze in Michelet’s text (1847).
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970.
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Volume 3,
Medieval and Modern Philosophy. Translated by E.S. Haldane; F.H. Simson (Eds.).
Lincoln, Nebraska: Bison Books/University of Nebraska Press, 1995.
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by A.V. Miller.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977.
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Philosophy of Mind. Translated from the
Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences with Five Introductory Essays. Translated
by W. Wallace. New York, NY: Cosimo, Inc, 2008.
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia
of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze. Translated with Introduction and Notes by
T.F. Geraets; W.A. Suchting; H.S. Harris. Indiana polis, Indiana: Hackett publishing, 1991.
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Science of Logic. Translated by A.V. Miller. Atlantic
Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press International, 1969.
HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Werke in 20 Bändern. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,
1970.
PAPAZOGLOU, Alexis. Hegel and Naturalism. In: Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great
Britain, Nov., 2012, pp. 21–37.
PINKARD, Terry. Hegel. A Biography. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
221
HEGEL’S NATURALISM?
ROI BAR
PINKARD, Terry. Hegel’s Naturalism. Mind, Nature, and the Final Ends of Life. New
York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2012.
PIPPIN, Robert. Hegel’s Practical Philosophy. Rational Agency as Ethical Life.
Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
QUINE, William Van Orman. Naturalized Epistemology. In: Quine, W.V.O. Ontological
Relativity and Other Essays. New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 1969, pp. 69–
90.
REDDING, Paul. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of the Hegelian Thought.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
STEKELER, Pirmin. Hegel’s Phenomenologie des Geistes: Ein dialogischer Kommentar.
Hamburg: Meiner, 2014.
STONE, Alison. Hegel, Naturalism and the Philosophy of Nature. In: Hegel Bulletin, vol. 34,
issue 1, Mai 2013.
TESTA, Italo. Hegel's Naturalism or Soul and Body in the Encyclopaedia. In: Stern, D.S.
(Ed.). Essays on Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjective Spirit. New York, NY: SUNY Press,
2013.
VERENE, Donald Phillip. Hegel’s Nature. In Houlgate, S. (Ed.). Hegel and the Philosophy
of Nature. New York, NY: SUNY Press, 1998.
WESTPHAL, Kenneth. Hegel’s Epistemological Realism: A Study of the Aim and
Method of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989.
WESTPHAL, Kenneth. Hegel’s Epistemology: A Philosophical Introduction to the
Phenomenology of Spirit. Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett, 2003.
Revista Eletrônica Estudos Hegelianos ano. 13, Nº 22 (2016)
222