Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2011, Australasian Journal of Philosophy
…
4 pages
1 file
AI-generated Abstract
This book review discusses Michael Devitt's collection of essays, 'Putting Metaphysics First: Essays on Metaphysics and Epistemology,' which defends metaphysical realism and naturalism against various forms of antirealism. The review highlights Devitt's arguments and critiques regarding semantics, truth-conditional theories, and deflationism, ultimately positing that naturalism provides a better understanding of semantics through empirical metaphysics. Despite some areas of contention in Devitt's reasoning, the review affirms the book's merit for those interested in metaphysical discourse.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2012
Mind, 2015
Zeitshchrift Fur Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, 2004
This paper presents an argument for metaphysical realism, understood as the claim that the world has structure that would exist even if our cognitive activities never did. The argument is based on the existence of a structured world at a time when it was still possible that we would never evolve. But the interpretation of its premises introduces subtleties: whether, for example, these premises are to be understood as assertions about the world or about our evidence, internally or externally, via assertibility conditions or truth conditions-and what sorts of beings are included in the 'we' upon whose cognitions the antirealist supposes the structure of the world to depend. I argue that antirealism can provide no defensible, fully articulated interpretation of the premises that either shows them not to be true or defeats the reasoning.
A Handbook of the Philosophy of Language (OUP, eds. E. Lepore and B. Smith), 2006
2016
In section 1, I explain why a specifically Dummettian conception of realism will be relevant only in a restricted range of cases. In section 2, I suggest that Crispin Wright could be read as holding that the truth of certain judgements depends on our capacity to know it (if and) only if their being true consists in their being superassertible. In section 3, I point out that insisting on knowability, as both Dummett and Wright do, prevents one from seeing that their are other legitimate forms of realism. I argue against the claim attributed to Wright in section 2, which leads me to suggest that it is a mistake to construe the realism debates as being essentially concerned with the nature of truth. The purpose of this paper is to explain and criticize a conception of realism which is suggested by the general approach to the realism debates which Crispin Wright has developed, mainly in his Truth and Objectivity [Wright 1992]. This book largely contributed to restructuring the whole pro...
dialectica, 1988
Devitt's book is a sustained defense of what he takes the central thesis of realism to be. It attempts both to disentangle that defense from what he views as irrelevant considerations that have crept into recent discussions, and to respond to the arguments of various philosophers who present themselves as anti-realists. The main two parts of the book consist of the attempt to articulate and argue for the central thesis (Part 11, "Proposals") and the attempt to rebut such anti-realist critics (Part 111, "Polemics"). Surrounding these parts are a brief, lucid introduction and a summary of the conclusions reached. Realisms of various sorts have recently been described as views about truth (e.g. that a correspondence theory of truth appealing to evidence-transcendent truth-conditions is correct) and/or as view about semantics (to the effect, e.g., that the terms of mature scientific theories typically refer). Devitt finds this not merely misguided but counterproductive, leading us into various disputes that simply do not need to be settled in order for us to resolve the question of whether realism is true. Though I have some reservations about the strict separation of metaphysics on the one hand and epistemology and semantics on the other on which Devitt insists, I think that this is basically on the right track and a useful corrective to the turn that the realism debate has taken in much of the literature. 1 hope to illustrate the basis for both my approval and my reservations in what follows. Realism, for Devitt, is a doctrine about the nature of things. Or rather two doctrines, one about the nature of the observable things posited by common sense and another about the nature of the unobservable things posited by scientific theories. One reason for this separation is that the arguments designed to secure them, though of the
Abstract. I explore the significance of self-appropriation in Bernard Lonergan’s metaphysics, which he once conceived using the metaphor of horizon—a circle comprising of a central, questioning subject open to being, as the surrounding, infinite object. I pay particular attention to what Lonergan calls the “notion of being,” the reality at the center that he helped us appropriate in many ways. Drawing on Giovanni Sala I explain why, although this “notion of being” constitutes an a priori, there is no entailment of idealism. I provide some elementary puzzles that may illuminate, and bring to awareness, this a priori, and I suggest that critics of Lonergan such as John Knasas, presumably in their inability to appropriate Lonergan’s notion, tend to impute idealist consequences from Lonergan’s apriorism precisely for this reason
Traditional metaphysics, I argue, serves two epistemological functions: first, it delineates the specific commitments we must embrace in order to engage in a specific kind of practice; second, metaphysical theories offer us a justificatory ground capable of satisfying skeptical challenges to know (e.g. the Agrippan Trilemma). This familiar ‘two-step’ structure, I continue, binds metaphysics to a specific mode of argumentation, i.e. transcendental argumentation. As a species of what has become known as an ‘indispensability argument,’ transcendental argumentation remains subordinate to epistemic practices. This is how they purport to solve Hume’s problem and circumvent the Agrippan Trilemma. But this means that one cannot do metaphysics for metaphysics’ sake. This entails, moreover, that speculative realist metaphysics is self-defeating. I develop this latter idea by introducing an evaluative criterion, which I call ‘shallowness.’ Shallow metaphysics, I show, fails to establish a relevant relationship between antecedent assumptions and consequent ontological claims. Transcendental arguments avoid shallowness precisely because they remain indexed to our concrete first-person or epistemic practices. Without this kind of connection to originating practices, metaphysics is functionless and hence contentless. I then delineate the criteria we need to satisfy in order to mount a successful indispensability argument. By way of a conclusion I then show how the absence of such a necessary connection between metaphysics and epistemic practice vitiates Harman’s central argument for object-oriented philosophy. That is, on pain of shallowness, Harman cannot offer an argument for ‘substance,’ (or withdrawn objects) that denies the priority of the first-person epistemic perspective. And this means that Harman’s attempt to extend the Heideggerian notion of withdrawnness cannot be generalized to encompass ‘objects as such.’ Finally I suggest that, although Harman identifies a central problem for metaphysics, a different account is needed. Keywords: Indispensability Argument, Justification, Metaphysical Ground, Object-Oriented Philosophy, Speculative Realism, Transcendental Argument,
Metaepistemology is, roughly, the branch of epistemology that asks questions about the existence, nature and authority of epistemic facts and reasons. i Typically, the metaepistemological landscape is divided into three parts on the basis of the ontological distinction between epistemic realism, epistemic anti-realism and constitutivism\constructivism. According to the standard reading of the distinction, epistemic realism is the position that asserts the existence of mind-independent epistemic facts and reasons for belief. ii The nature of mind-independent epistemic facts and reasons for belief may be understood either in broadly naturalist (e.g. consequentialist) or non-naturalist ways, depending on the type of epistemic realism one adopts. iii In any case, epistemic realism typically considers mind-independent epistemic facts as categorically reason-giving to rational agents. iv That is, as facts that exert authority over us and constrain what we ought to believe if we are rational, independently of our desires, goals, wishes, intentions, whims, et cetera.
Disputatio
According to metaphysical realism, we would have to compare our thought with mind-independent reality, if we want to gain knowledge about the world. Such a comparison is impossible. Yet we can gain knowledge about the world. So metaphysical realism is false. — I take this to be the historically most influential argumentative line opposing metaphysical realism. The paper develops this argument, the Main Anti-Realist Argument, in more detail and offers a brief critical discussion of its crucial assumptions.
Politikatudományi szemle, 2020
Journal of Hazardous Materials, 2010
Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad de Costa Rica, 2018
Hydrology and Earth System Sciences, 2007
Indiana, 2020
Reviews of Geophysics, 1996
British Journal of Cancer, 2006
Orientalistische Literaturzeitung, 2017
Journal of Geophysical Research: Atmospheres, 1997
Journal of Language and Education, 2023
Indian Law Review
Journal of Hospitality & Tourism Education, 2017
Revista Mundi Sociais e Humanidades (ISSN: 2525-4774)