Modern Intellectual History, 9, 1 (2012), pp. 89–107
doi:10.1017/S1479244311000497
C Cambridge University Press 2012
kuhn’s education: wittgenstein,
pedagogy, and the road to
structure∗
joel isaac
Faculty of History, University of Cambridge
E-mail: jti20@cam.ac.uk
[C]ertain ways in which certain persons talk about a science are a part of the teaching of a
science, and the ways in which the science is taught and learned may be taken as essential
to an understanding of what that science is.
Stanley Cavell1
Among the topics discussed in Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions, those of education, training, and pedagogy are apt to seem the least
compelling. Certainly, the earliest debates about Structure focused on other, more
controversial, matters: incommensurability, meaning change, the rationality of
theory choice, normal science—the list goes on.2 Over the past two decades,
however, a growing concern among historians and sociologists of science with
∗
1
2
I am grateful to Peter Gordon, John Forrester, and Samuel Moyn for helpful comments
on an earlier draft of this essay. The research and writing that went into this piece
was generously supported by the Centre for Research in the Arts, Social Sciences and
Humanities at the University of Cambridge.
Stanley Cavell, “Foreword: An Audience for Philosophy,” in idem, Must We Mean What
We Say? A Book of Essays (Cambridge, 2002), xxxii.
For a summary of these early debates, see John H. Zammito, A Nice Derangement of
Epistemes: Post-positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour (Chicago, 2004),
65–95. Key interventions include Donald Davidson, “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual
Scheme,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47 (1973),
5–20; Margaret Masterman, “The Nature of a Paradigm,” in Imre Lakatos and Alan
Musgrave, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge, 1970), 59–89; Karl
Popper, “Normal Science and Its Dangers,” in ibid., 51–8; Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth,
and History (Cambridge, 1981); Israel Scheffler, Science and Subjectivity (Indianapolis,
1967); Dudley Shapere, “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions,” Philosophical Review
73/3 (1964), 383–94; idem, “Meaning and Scientific Change,” in Robert Colodny, ed., Mind
89
90 joel isaac
the nature of scientific apprenticeship has stimulated greater appreciation of the
importance of questions of teaching and learning to the philosophical position
sketched in Structure.3 This paper seeks to develop further our understanding of
these issues as they bear on Kuhn’s theory of science.
Nothing is more crucial to the description of scientific development presented
in Structure than the claim that scientists-in-training acquire the tools and
skills of their discipline by learning to work with model puzzle solutions.
According to Kuhn, a “community’s paradigms” were constituted by “a set of
recurrent and quasi-standard illustrations of various theories in their conceptual,
observational, and instrumental applications.” These standard illustrations, in
turn, were “revealed in [the community’s] textbooks, lectures, and laboratory
exercises.” So crucial was this view of learning-through-paradigms to Kuhn’s
historical epistemology that he framed around it his description of the major
stages of a scientific revolution. Kuhn was frank that what he called “normal
science” could be explained only by the pedagogy of paradigms. This alone could
account for the persistence of a research tradition in what Kuhn insisted was the
evident absence of consensus on methodological, theoretical, and ontological
fundamentals. In the process of research, meanwhile, anomalies could emerge
only because paradigms conditioned scientists to expect certain kinds of solution
to certain kinds of problem; nothing could be said to have “gone wrong” in the
3
and Cosmos: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy (Pittsburgh, 1966), 41–85;
idem, “The Paradigm Concept,” Science 172 (1971), 706–9.
Antonio Garcia-Belmar, Jose Ramon Bertomeu-Sanchez, and Bernadette BensaudeVincent, “The Power of Didactic Writings: French Chemistry Textbooks of the Nineteenth
Century,” in David Kaiser, ed., Pedagogy and the Practice of Science: Historical and
Contemporary Perspectives (Cambridge, MA, 2005), 219–51; Gerald L. Geison, “Research
Schools and New Directions in the Historiography of Science,” Osiris 8 (1993), 226–38; Karl
Hall, “‘Think Less about Foundations’: A Short Course on Landau and Lifshitz’s Course of
Theoretical Physics,” in Kaiser, Pedagogy and the Practice of Science, 253–86; David Kaiser,
“Cold War Requisitions, Scientific Manpower, and the Production of American Physicists
after World War II,” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 33 (2002), 131–59; idem,
“Nuclear Democracy: Political Engagement, Pedagogical Reform, and Particle Physics in
Postwar America,” Isis 93 (2002), 229–68; David Kaiser and Andrew Warwick, “Kuhn,
Foucault, and the Power of Pedagogy,” in Kaiser, Pedagogy and the Practice of Science, 393–
409; David Kaiser, “Introduction: Moving Pedagogy From the Periphery to the Center,” in
Kaiser, Pedagogy and the Practice of Science, 1–8; Kathryn M. Olesko, “Physics Instruction
in Prussian Secondary Schools before 1859,” Osiris 5 (1989), 94–120; idem, Physics as a
Calling: Discipline and Practice in the Königsberg Seminar for Physics (Ithaca, 1991); idem,
“Tacit Knowledge and School Formation,” Osiris 8 (1993), 16–29; Buhm Soon Park, “In the
‘Context of Pedagogy’: Teaching Strategy and Theory Change in Quantum Chemistry,”
in Kaiser, Pedagogy and the Practice of Science, 287–319; Sharon Traweek, Beamtimes and
Lifetimes: The World of High Energy Physicists (Cambridge, MA, 1988); Andrew Warwick,
Masters of Theory: Cambridge and the Rise of Mathematical Physics (Chicago, 2003).
kuhn’s education
conduct of an experiment or calculation without the violation of expectations
set by socialization into a normal-scientific tradition. Likewise, the chronic
“technical breakdown” associated with a scientific crisis was explicable only if the
habitual manner of modeling research on standard solutions—a habit acquired
in the earliest stages of training and carried beyond the PhD—repeatedly failed
to account for the phenomena produced in the course of inquiry. In such cases
the stage was set for a revolution in which a new paradigm replaced the old.4
Only the most casual readers of Structure will be surprised by these
observations. Nevertheless, we have yet fully to appreciate the commitments
and experiences that drew Kuhn to this particular pedagogical conception of
scientific knowledge. We can begin to grasp the importance of this historical
context for understanding Kuhn’s intervention when we note that Structure
was conceived and written during a transformative period in the history of
educational theory and practice in the United States. When, in the autumn
of 1945, Kuhn began jotting down his earliest thoughts on the epistemology of
the sciences, American higher education was undergoing profound structural
changes caused by the Second World War and its immediate aftermath. During
the war, an infusion of funds from the state dramatically scaled up the operations
of research in the physical, biological, and engineering sciences. Wartime research
on nuclear weapons, radar, digital computing, psycho-acoustics, and much else
besides demanded not only high capital expenditures of the sort only the state
could afford, but also increased professional manpower in the form of professors,
postdocs, graduate students, and rank-and-file technicians.5 In the decade after
1945, disciplines like physics and engineering became institutional behemoths
that consumed resources and spewed out skilled practitioners, research papers,
and new technologies at unprecedented rates.6
If the embryonic national security state stimulated much of the demand for
Big Science in the early years of the Cold War, the supply side of the equation
was taken care of by the Servicemen’s Readjustment Act of 1944. Under Title
II of the G.I. Bill, some 2.25 million veterans attended America’s colleges and
universities in the years following the end of the war. Of that number, nearly
4
5
6
Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd edn (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1996), 43, 46–7, 57, 69.
Peter Galison, Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics (Chicago, 1997), 239–93.
Roger L. Geiger, Research and Relevant Knowledge: American Research Universities Since
World War II (New York, 1993); Peter Galison and Bruce Hevly, eds., Big Science: The
Growth of Large-Scale Research (Stanford, CA, 1992).
On the postwar bubble in physics, see David Kaiser, “The Postwar Suburbanization of
American Physics,” American Quarterly 56 (2004), 851–88; idem, “The Physics of Spin:
Sputnik Politics and American Physicists in the 1950s,” Social Research 73 (2006), 1225–52.
91
92 joel isaac
40 percent, or 867,000, became credentialed professionals.7 The specialization
inherent in the veteran-led boom in higher education heightened existing worries
among academics about the cultural fragmentation that appeared to be a central
feature of the new world of capital- and labor-intensive science. In the immediate
postwar years, Harvard president James Bryant Conant was one among many
educationalists calling for programs of “general education” in America’s schools
and colleges that could allow future generations of public and business leaders to
make sound judgments in an era of hyperspecialization and increasing reliance
on scientific expertise.8 The Harvard “red book,” otherwise known as General
Education in a Free Society (1945), was perhaps the sole instance of wartime Big
Humanities, and set the scene for a running debate about general education in
an era of unprecedented enrolments at colleges and graduate schools across the
nation.9 Throughout the 1950s, the emergence of a pedagogy of scale in the liberal
arts and sciences continued apace, with physics in particular taking the lead in
developing the institutional forms associated with educational Fordism.10
A further round of educational reform was prompted by the launch of the
Soviet Sputnik satellite in 1957.11 The National Defense Education Act, passed
by Congress in 1958 in response to perceived deficiencies in American science
and language teaching, pumped money into training and research programs in
physics, mathematics, engineering, and area studies.12 Whatever its intellectual
achievements, this investment strategy led to exponential increases in enrolments
and PhD awards in these fields.13 Sputnik also brought to the surface a critique
of pedagogy that had been building in American psychology and educational
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
Kathleen Frydl, The GI Bill (Cambridge, 2009), 308.
“President’s Report,” Official Register of Harvard University 45 (1 Dec. 1948), 13.
General Education in a Free Society: Report of the Harvard Committee (Cambridge, MA,
1945). See also Peter S. Buck and Barbara Gutman Rosenkrantz, “The Worm in the Core:
Science and General Education,” in Everett Mendelsohn, ed., Transformation and Tradition
in the Sciences: Essays in Honor of I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge, 1984), 371–94; Earl James
McGrath, Science in General Education (Dubuque, IA, 1948); idem, “Science in General
Education,” Scientific Monthly 71 (1950), 118–20.
See especially David Kaiser, Drawing Theories Apart: The Dispersion of Feynman Diagrams
in Postwar Physics (Chicago, 2005); idem, “Cold War Requisitions”; idem, “Postwar
Suburbanization.”
For a general account of the reaction to Sputnik see Robert A. Divine, The Sputnik
Challenge (New York, 1993); Wayne J. Urban, More than Science and Sputnik: The National
Defense Education Act of 1958 (Tuscaloosa, 2010).
Barbara Barksdale Clowse, Brainpower for the Cold War: The Sputnik Crisis and National
Defense Education Act of 1958 (Westport, CT, 1981).
For information on physics and area studies, see David C. Engerman, Know Your Enemy:
The Rise and Fall of America’s Soviet Experts (New York, 2009); Kaiser, Drawing Theories
Apart; idem, “Cold War Requisitions.”
kuhn’s education
theory for a generation. Popular bromides like Mortimer Smith’s And Madly
Teach (1949) and Rudolf Flesch’s Why Johnny Can’t Read—And What You Can
Do about It (1955) laid the foundations for a thoroughgoing attack on the
tradition of progressive education associated with John Dewey and his followers.14
Many considered the student-led Deweyan curriculum lacking in the rigor and
theoretical grounding necessary to produce innovative scientists and engineers.
The Woods Hole Conference of 1959 was an especially important staging post in
the battle for a new curriculum in science education, not least because it provided
a forum for the reception of work in child development and the psychology of
learning carried out by the Swiss psychologist Jean Piaget and by a founding
figure in postwar cognitive psychology, Jerome Bruner.15
It is without hyperbole, then, that one can describe the fifteen or so years
following the end of the war as a time of major upheaval in American education
and pedagogical theory. A good deal of Kuhn’s involvement with these changes on
the educational scene is either well covered in the literature, or else obvious after
a quick scan of Structure and related writings. It is widely known, for example,
that Kuhn got his start in the history of science as an assistant on James Bryant
Conant’s natural-science course in Harvard’s fabled postwar general education
program.16 On the other hand, much of Kuhn’s early writing about the stages of
scientific development abounds with references to work in developmental and
cognitive psychology. Around the time that Structure appeared in print, Kuhn
was kibitzing with psychologists, learning theorists, economists, sociologists, and
historians who were animated by the great post-Sputnik obsession with the social,
economic and psychological conditions of technological innovation.17
14
15
16
17
Rudolf Flesch, Why Johnny Can’t Read—And What You Can Do about It (New York, 1955).
Mortimer Brewster Smith, And Madly Teach: A Layman Looks at Public School Education
(Chicago, 1949).
On Bruner’s work in this period see Jerome S. Bruner, ed., The Process of Education
(Cambridge, MA, 1960); idem, On Knowing: Essays for the Left Hand (Cambridge, MA,
1962); idem, Toward a Theory of Instruction (Cambridge, MA, 1966). For Piaget’s impact
on these debates see Yeh Hsueh, “Piaget in the United States, 1925–1971,” in Ulrich Müller,
Jeremy I. M. Carpendale and Leslie Smith, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Piaget
(Cambridge, 2009), 358.
Much is made of this connection in Steve Fuller, Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History
for Our Times (Chicago, 2000).
Kuhn, “The Essential Tension: Tradition and Innovation in Scientific Research,” in
Calvin W. Taylor, ed., The Third (1959) University of Utah Research Conference on the
Identification of Creative Scientific Talent (Salt Lake City, 1959), 162–74; idem, “Comment
on MacKinnon,” in The Rate and Direction of Inventive Activity: Economic and Social
Factors (Princeton, NJ, 1962), 379–84; idem, “Comment on Siegel,” in ibid., 450–7; idem,
“The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research,” in A. C. Crombie, ed., Scientific Change:
93
94 joel isaac
Taken together, these observations suggest, if they do not yet explain,
important connections between the theory of science limned in Structure and the
transformation of American education at multiple levels during the 1940s and
1950s. For historians of science pedagogy, as well as for intellectual historians and
historians of science generally, Structure is, or ought to be treated as, more than
a useful methodological resource: it is itself to be considered a significant text
in the intertwined histories of education, science, and epistemology during the
passage from world war to Cold War. Having made this rather bold claim, I must
admit that there are some considerable exegetical difficulties standing in the way
of our appropriating Structure as a work of philosophy of science suffused with
contemporary concerns with pedagogy, education, and training. In particular,
there remains in Structure a significant hermeneutic puzzle concerning Kuhn’s
conception of pedagogy and its place in scientific epistemology. My aim in the
rest of this paper is to describe the puzzle and then show how it can be solved
by examining the pedagogical traditions in which Kuhn’s early theory of science
was formed.
∗∗∗
Although he appealed to an exemplar-based theory of learning to explain why
most scientists stuck to the normal-scientific tradition in which they had been
socialized, Kuhn did not, as David Kaiser has noted, “explore in any historical
or anthropological detail how such exemplars emerged, how students in various
generations actually learned to solve exemplars and build upon them in their
own research, or whether students at different training centers learned about
and learned upon exemplars in distinct ways.”18 Lack of detail is the least of it:
when we turn to the passages of Structure in which Kuhn asserted the primacy
of exemplars in binding scientists into a normal-scientific tradition, we see that
Kuhn offered no examples whatsoever of pedagogical regimes in the history of
science.19 In Structure, as well as in important essays touching on science pedagogy
like “The Essential Tension” (1959) and “The Function of Measurement in Modern
Physical Science” (1961), Kuhn presented some distinctive views about the role
of demonstration and textbook exercises in the formation of normal-scientific
practice. But in none of these cases did his remarks follow from an historical
assessment of traditions of scientific education; at most, he assumed that treatises
18
19
Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social and Technical Conditions for Scientific Discovery
and Technical Invention, From Antiquity to the Present (London, 1963), 347–69.
Kaiser, “Introduction,” 2. Kaiser is also characterizing the work of Michael Polanyi, which
is obviously not at issue in the present paper.
Kuhn, Structure, 43–51.
kuhn’s education
like Newton’s Opticks had functioned as the “books from which men learned
science” and left the matter there.20 What we need to understand is what, given
the lack of scholarly machinery driving Kuhn’s otherwise determined discussion
of pedagogy and professional training, could have motivated his account of
learning-through-paradigms.
One explanation is readily available. In Structure, Kuhn’s description of
exemplar-based learning appeared to hinge on an analogy with the account
of the learning of kind-terms given in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations
(1953). Kuhn took Wittgenstein’s problem to be how terms like “chair,” “leaf,” or
“game” came to be applied “unequivocally and without argument” by members
of a speech community—even though the members of that community could
not be said to agree upon some universal rule of application or criterion of
identification governing the connections between a word and its referents.21
Wittgenstein’s point had been that rules or criteria were not themselves sufficiently
robust or unambiguous to provide a secure basis for mutual understanding.22 For
Kuhn, Wittgenstein’s answer to this problem was that what looked like explicit
agreement on rules or criteria was in fact an overlap of the model applications
or samples through which each individual member of the speech community
learned the term in question. A sufficient overlap between these sets of model
applications was sufficient to ensure mutual understanding between speakers
and, in most cases, agreement on how to apply terms in new cases. The standard
illustrations or paradigms acquired in the course of scientific training, Kuhn
suggested, functioned in much the same way: scientists did not learn theories,
laws, or concepts as fully explicit and autonomous systems of rules, despite
what contemporary proponents of logical positivism or operationism may have
suggested; instead, “these intellectual tools [were] from the start encountered in a
historically and pedagogically prior unit that display[ed] them with and through
their applications.”23
When we reflect upon these crucial passages in Structure, it is tempting to
conclude that the Wittgensteinian philosophy is driving the appeal to pedagogy. 24
A little more digging into the history of the composition of Structure, however,
shows us that Wittgenstein’s cameo appearance is a red herring—at least insofar
20
21
22
23
24
Kuhn, “Essential Tension”; idem, “The Function of Measurement in Modern Physical
Science,” Isis 52 (1961), 161–93.
Kuhn, Structure, 44–5.
Something like this argument is given in Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations:
The German Text, with a Revised English Translation (Malden, MA, 2003), 27–36.
Kuhn, Structure, 46.
Daniel Goldman Cederbaum, “Paradigms,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science
14 (1983), 173–213.
95
96 joel isaac
as it makes Kuhn’s invocation of a paradigm-based pedagogy into a consequence
or working-through of his indebtedness to Wittgenstein’s philosophy. I aim to
show that the matter is better put the other way around: that Kuhn’s whirlwind
romance with the Investigations represented the philosophical aftereffects of a
long and complex effort to strike a balance between competing experiences of
pedagogy, professional training, and epistemology.
For Kuhn, questions of education and professional training were far from
academic. His path to Structure took him through more or less every major
pedagogical program the United States had to offer in the tumultuous middle
decades of the twentieth century. Before he took up a place at Harvard College
in 1940, Kuhn spent a substantial part of his childhood and adolescence in
progressive schools in the Northeast. At the Lincoln School of Teachers College
in New York, a bastion of Deweyan pedagogy, and later at the Hessian Hills
School in Croton-on-Hudson, Kuhn absorbed the progressive ethos that would
later come under attack in the 1950s. This was a pedagogy without textbooks,
rote learning, or any of the other facets of “dogmatic initiation” that Kuhn would
later identify with professional training in the sciences.25 In contrast, during his
years at Harvard, Kuhn encountered intensive mass training at its most intensive:
although he had chosen to major (or, in local parlance, to “concentrate”) in
physics, Kuhn was rapidly inducted into a compressed wartime program in
electrical engineering, which provided Kuhn with a grounding in electronics
rather than physics. Graduating in three rather than four years, Kuhn was
immediately set to work on radar countermeasures in Harvard’s Radio Research
Laboratory, where he spent most of his time, as he later recalled, “cooking
standard formulas . . . on doing radar profiles as a function of distance.”26 While
the dominant theme of his college education, intensive training was mixed in
Kuhn’s undergraduate career with a lingering interest in the literary and the
philosophical: he served as president of Harvard’s literary Signet Society and
editor of the Harvard Crimson, and availed himself of some courses in the
history of philosophy. Faced with choosing a career after the Allied victory,
Kuhn found a way of hedging professional training and avocational interests.
At the same time as beginning graduate work at Harvard on solid-state physics,
under the direction of John Van Vleck, Kuhn received special permission to take
courses in philosophy that could count as credits toward the doctoral degree.
In addition, he provided the alumni voice in response to the Harvard report on
25
26
Jensine Andresen, “Crisis and Kuhn,” Isis 90 (1999), S43–S67; Aristides Baltas, Kostas
Gavroglu, and Vassiliki Kindi, “A Discussion with Thomas S. Kuhn,” in James Conant and
John Haugeland, eds., The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with An
Autobiographical Interview (Chicago, 2000), 255–9.
Baltas, Gavroglu, and Kindi, “A Discussion,” 267–9.
kuhn’s education
general education, and was eventually asked by Conant, in the spring of 1947,
to prepare a class for his general education course. This brief led Kuhn to yet
another unconventional turn in his professional training. His work for Conant
allowed him to jump ship from physics to the history of science, and from the
physics department to the resolutely cross-disciplinary Society of Fellows.
The Society of Fellows had been established by senior Harvard faculty in
the early 1930s specifically to serve as a bastion against vocationalism in the
arts and sciences; in the society’s first incarnation, Junior Fellows were not, at
least in principle, permitted to take advanced degrees.27 Kuhn already had a
PhD when he took up his fellowship in 1948, but he certainly used the freedom
granted him by three years of research to undertake an eclectic training program
that encompassed reading across five or six different fields, from psychology
to sociology, history, philosophy, and logic. It is more accurate to say of this
postdoctoral fellowship that Kuhn trained not as a historian of science, and
certainly not as a professional historian, but instead as a professor of general
education in science with interests across a range of fields. By the terminal year of
his fellowship, Kuhn was working full-time on the history of the experimentalsciences course, Natural Sciences 4, in the Harvard general education program.
During the years that he held an assistant professorship in general education,
Kuhn worked on historical and sociological problems concerning the study of
scientific theory. Even when denied tenure at Harvard, Kuhn’s peculiar, hybrid
existence as a nonspecialist continued when he was given a unique, and ultimately
unhappy, joint appointment in history and philosophy at Berkeley, where he
stayed until a couple of years after the publication of Structure.
It is against the background of this eclectic educational career that we can begin
to understand the role that notions of pedagogy and professional training would
have in Kuhn’s earliest work as a historian and philosopher of science. Kuhn seems
to have registered strongly the contrast between the open-ended, independentminded character of his adolescent studies in New York state progressive schools
and the compressed period of intensive training provided by his initiation into
electrical engineering as a physics major at wartime Harvard. The liberal and
aesthetic leanings of the former made the rigidity of his truncated training in
physics and electronics clear enough to instill in Kuhn a yen for, and conviction
in, the wider philosophical and even metaphysical significance of science. This
formative set of experiences, in turn, led Kuhn to a postwar education in physics,
history, and philosophy that at once was deeply informed by the practices and
norms of professionalization and yet, for one reason or another, escaped its
exigencies.
27
George Caspar Homans, The Society of Fellows, ed. Crane Brinton (Cambridge, MA, 1959).
97
98 joel isaac
Kuhn’s dissatisfaction with the limits of his undergraduate crash course in
physics emerged early. In the summer of 1943, having just turned twenty-one and
on the cusp of taking up his position at the Radio Research Laboratory, Kuhn
admitted in a letter to his aunt that he felt “if anything younger than before: that
is further from any satisfactory creative intellectual or social functionings, not
freer from responsibility.” Referring to an earlier letter, which would appear to
have discussed his hopes for a future career, Kuhn confessed that the “dreaming
goes on . . . I lean, in short, increasingly toward the academic, and to philosophy
of & through science rather than to pure physics. But I am to [sic] far from
knowing where it will end to waste your time here.” It will perhaps be evident
that Kuhn’s inclination toward “philosophy of and through science” reflected his
desire to access the philosophical, speculative, or psychological features of science
that would have been lacking in his Harvard education up to that point. It was
therefore significant that he followed his expression of yearning for philosophy by
voicing his disappointment with his then-current reading: Freud’s Introductory
Lectures on Psychoanalysis. “I like the frankness,” Kuhn wrote of the book, “I
believe in the therapy . . . but I don’t trust the generalizations. Above all, I fail to
find even a fragmentary basis for a psychological epistemology, and my selfish
hope had been to discover some such.”28
Remarks like these can be interpreted in terms of Kuhn’s recurrent experience
of intellectual crisis during his college and graduate years.29 Here I want
to take a different tack and emphasize Kuhn’s already firm commitment to
identifying the psychological and philosophical underpinnings of science—and
this just as he had graduated and was set to embark upon puzzle-solving
work in radar countermeasures. Something in Kuhn resisted the professional
mindset. It is reasonable to speculate that a combination of an unsystematic
initiation in physics, due to the exigencies of the wartime Harvard curriculum,
in combination with the trust in his own intellectual instincts engendered by
progressive schooling, produced in Kuhn this unformed but strong impulse to
philosophize. Whatever the exact source of Kuhn’s unschooled philosophical
interests, they intensified during his graduate and postdoctoral studies in physics
and the history of science. In the immediate postwar years, Kuhn’s inclination
toward “philosophy of and through science” led to a dalliance with professional
philosophy. At the outset of his graduate training in physics, in the autumn of
1945, Kuhn was given permission to take undergraduate philosophy courses. This
28
29
Kuhn to Mrs Ivan Fischer, 27 July 1943, box 12, MC240, Papers of Thomas S. Kuhn, Institute
Archives, MIT. Hereafter TSKP.
Andresen, “Crisis and Kuhn”; John Forrester, “On Kuhn’s Case: Psychoanalysis and the
Paradigm,” Critical Inquiry 33 (2007), 782–819.
kuhn’s education
experiment was swiftly curtailed. As Kuhn later recollected, he felt he had no
clear point of access to the discipline:
I realized that there was just a lot of philosophy I hadn’t been taught, and didn’t understand
. . . I didn’t know quite why people were doing the things they were doing. And I fairly
rapidly decided, yes, I was interested in philosophy, but my God, I was a graduate, I had
been through the war in some sense or other, I couldn’t go back and sit still for that
undergraduate chicken-shit and go on from there.30
Once again the spectre of specialist training had raised its head, and once
again Kuhn recoiled. But he was far from ready to give up on the idea of a
philosophical or epistemological or metaphysical something that was needed to
account for scientific knowledge. In one of the philosophical papers he produced
that autumn, entitled “The Metaphysical Possibilities of Physics,” Kuhn spoke
directly to the sense of vertigo he experienced during the war when he lamented
that “the philosophic base of the physical sciences has been lost by the physicist so
often that it has become necessary to convince people that physics is more than
an adjunct of engineering and a complex means for answering trick problems.”
“Too seldom is it realized,” Kuhn declared, “that physics is also a philosophical
science searching for absolute truths concerning the nature and structure of the
universe.”31
Enter James Bryant Conant and the Harvard general education program.
As someone tutored in both extremes of mid-century American pedagogy—
the progressive tradition and wartime intensive training—Kuhn was already
interested, by the end of the war, in “the need for the redesign of science
instruction.”32 When asked by the Harvard Alumni Bulletin in 1945 to offer a recent
undergraduate’s perspective on the general education report, Kuhn produced an
opinion piece that focused primarily on the tension between specialist training
and liberal education, as this was registered in the student experience of what
were called “distribution” courses: required courses taken in addition to the major.
Both survey and advanced courses for distribution had been designed for those
intending to major in the field, with the consequence that, for non-concentrators
in these subjects, there was small chance of gaining either a specialist or, more
importantly, a liberal education. Hence both the introductory course, composed
of a compendium of basic facts and techniques, and the upper-level course, which
was so narrow as to be of no general benefit to the nonspecialist, failed to serve
as a “vehicle for general education.” Kuhn, signaling his agreement with the
central tenets of the report, argued that “the increase in the bulk of knowledge
30
31
32
Baltas, Gavroglu, and Kindi, “A Discussion” 273.
Kuhn, “The Metaphysical Possibilities of Physics,” n.d. (c. 1945), box 1, TSKP.
Baltas, Gavroglu, and Kindi, “A Discussion,” 272.
99
100 joel isaac
during the last century necessitates a basic alteration of educational methods, for
liberal education is no longer a probable end-product of conventional teaching
methods.”33 These pedagogical problems arising from postwar debates about
general education and the fissiparous college curriculum spoke directly to Kuhn’s
ongoing attempt to educe philosophical or liberal meanings from the resolutely
professionalized enterprise of Big Science. By the time Conant asked Kuhn to
prepare a case study on seventeenth-century mechanics for Natural Sciences 4,
the disillusioned young physicist and philosopher manqué was ready to find in
his pedagogical brief a philosophical vocation. The Harvard general education
program offered Kuhn a space in which to pursue his version of philosophy
after professional physics and orthodox philosophy had led him into dead ends.
Crucially, however, this also meant that he began to frame his epistemological
concerns in terms of the pedagogical distinctions that his new role as a teacher
of general education in science encouraged him to draw.
As soon as he received Conant’s invitation, Kuhn began to sketch out thoughts
about general education in science that covered his long-standing epistemological
interests in the non-mechanical, ideological aspects of scientific inquiry. In a May
1947 memorandum on the “Objectives of a General Education Course in the
Physical Sciences,” Kuhn was already importing his philosophical commitments
into the prerequisites of a nonspecialist teaching program in physics. Students
taking the course, Kuhn stated, would need to appreciate the central role played
in experimental science by selective “abstraction” and also by the “acceptance
of a conceptual structure” in the form of a systematic, predictive theory. In
addition, Kuhn was beginning to insist upon the “limited role of pure logic” in
understanding science. Pace the advocates of formal approaches to the assessment
of scientific theories, induction was for Kuhn “a name for ‘the experimental
method’ rather than for a logically, or even operationally, defined route from
the particular to the general.” “Scientific generalization” was therefore to be
considered “a creative imaginative process.”34 Kuhn was certainly prepared for
his famous epiphany upon grasping the meaning of “motion” in Aristotle’s
Physics, which occurred a couple of months later. In cracking Aristotle’s code,
Kuhn found a concrete illustration of the extra-logical dimensions of scientific
theory posited in his earlier statements about scientific epistemology.35 Through
33
34
35
Kuhn, “Subjective View: Thomas S. Kuhn on Behalf of the Recent Student, Reflects on the
Undergraduate Attitude,” Harvard Alumni Bulletin 48 (1945), 29–30.
Kuhn, “Objectives of a General Education Course in the Physical Sciences, May 1947,”
May 1947, box 1, TSKP.
See also Kuhn’s notes on Conant’s first iteration of the general education course in the
experimental sciences: Kuhn, “Natural Sciences 11(a),” 1947, box 1, TSKP. On the Aristotle
epiphany, see Kuhn, “Preface,” in idem, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific
kuhn’s education
his interpretation of Aristotle, Kuhn had hit upon a way of extracting philosophy
from history, and he had done so in considering the teaching of science to
nonspecialists.
∗∗∗
Throughout the following fifteen years, as Kuhn followed a meandering path
toward the publication of Structure, this fusion of pedagogical, professional,
and philosophical concerns shaped the manner in which the neophyte historian
of science sought to understand scientific development. In particular, Kuhn’s
instinctual sense of the limits of the professional self-understanding of
science, evident as early as 1943, was reinforced in both his pedagogical and
his philosophical endeavors. This sense showed up pedagogically in Kuhn’s
distinction, common in the Harvard discussion about general education, between
specialist training and liberal learning in the arts and sciences. A fundamental
challenge for Conant and the authors of General Education in a Free Society
had been to rethink the foundations of liberal education in the face of an ever
more specialized curriculum.36 The central tenet of this way of thinking was that,
whatever else a general education in the sciences might be, it could not resemble
the usual combination of survey and advanced courses in a discipline, for this
had become the first step on the path to a professional career. As a teacher of
science to laymen, one’s objective was to convey what Conant called the “tactics
and strategies of science” without recourse to the pedagogical infrastructure of
the sciences themselves: textbooks, lab work, and the rest. In unpublished talks
given on science and general education delivered during the late 1940s and early
1950s, Kuhn repeatedly underscored the point that the general education courses
in science at Harvard were for the “non-scientist” and involved “no labs.”37 “No
one of these courses is a survey course,” he told a group of educators at a 1951
conference; “all sacrifice portions of ‘content’ or subject matter that would be
essential to the specialist.”38
The substitute for the specialist’s pedagogical toolkit, for Kuhn and his mentor
Conant, was the case history. Many of the cases employed in Conant’s, and
36
37
38
Tradition and Change (Chicago, 1977), xi–xii; idem, “What Are Scientific Revolutions?” in
The Road since Structure, 16–18.
General Education in a Free Society; James Bryant Conant, On Understanding Science: An
Historical Approach (Oxford, 1947).
Kuhn, “Washington University Conference, talk delivered 12 May 1949,” May 12, 1949, box
12, TSKP; idem, “Untitled Talk to Faculty Conference on General Education,” 1951, box 12,
TSKP.
Kuhn, “The Sciences in the Harvard General Education Program,” n.d. (c. early 1950s),
box 12, TSKP.
101
102 joel isaac
later Kuhn’s, general education course, Natural Sciences 4, were later written up
and published in two volumes as the Harvard Case Histories in Experimental
Science (1957).39 Each of the case histories was designed to reveal what Conant
described as “the evolution of a new conceptual scheme” in a particular research
tradition.40 Students would not acquire new technical skills or a comprehensive
body of knowledge; rather, the case histories would develop their sense of the
practical wisdom involved in the conduct of exemplary scientific investigations.
This connection between case studies and experienced judgment in practical
affairs had been the motif of the development of the so-called “case system” of
pedagogy at Harvard during the decades after Christopher Columbus Langdell
first introduced it in the Law School in the 1870s. At the time Conant took up the
case method in general education, it was employed both in the Harvard Business
School and by Conant’s uncle by marriage, the biochemist and Pareto disciple L.
J. Henderson, who taught courses in history of science and applied sociology.41
Kuhn adopted Conant’s case system wholesale, and noted that the case method
was “not [an] economical approach to science teaching,” which was why it was
“quite properly omitted from standard science courses.”42 This way of framing the
difference between specialist and generalist education reaffirmed at a pedagogical
and philosophical level Kuhn’s existing distinction between the mechanisms of
professional training, on the one hand, and the wider values and commitments
that such training obscured from the trainee scientist, on the other. Textbooks
and practical instruction animated science as a vocational enterprise, but case
histories were needed to call attention to the creative revisions of conceptual
schemes that defined scientific revolutions, and which were the bread-and-butter
of a general education in science.
These professional and pedagogical orientations had important consequences
for Kuhn’s emerging theory of science in the early 1950s. With the critical
39
40
41
42
James Bryant Conant, ed., Harvard Case Histories in Experimental Science, 2 vols.
(Cambridge, MA, 1957).
James Bryant Conant, ed., “The Overthrow of the Phlogiston Theory: The Chemical
Revolution of 1775–1789,” in Harvard Case Histories, 1: 67.
I recount the history of the case method at Harvard in detail in Working Knowledge:
Making the Human Sciences from Parsons to Kuhn (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 2012). For useful discussions of this topic see Galison, Image and Logic, 55–8.
Bruce A Kimball, “Warn Students that I Entertain Heretical Opinions, Which They Are
Not to Take as Law”: The Inception of Case Method Teaching in the Classrooms of
the Early C. C. Langdell, 1870–1883,” Law and History Review 17 (1999), 57–140; idem,
“The Proliferation of Case Method Teaching in American Law Schools: Mr. Langdell’s
Emblematic ‘Abomination,’ 1890–1915,” History of Education Quarterly 46 (2006), 192–
247.
Kuhn, “Can the Layman Know Science?” 13 Dec. 1955, box 12, TSKP.
kuhn’s education
distance he had gained on the professional scientific enterprise both from his
own education and from the demands of creating an independent domain for
general education in science, Kuhn gradually came to see that the dogmatic
procedures of specialist training in the sciences could explain how what he
called the “ideological” features of science were able to keep particular research
traditions within fairly narrow and stable parameters. Nevertheless, the moments
of dramatic change in conceptual schemes assessed in the Harvard case histories
were, in this period of Kuhn’s intellectual development, simply not be accounted
for by the effects of scientific pedagogy; the explanation of revolutions had to work
with the generalist’s toolkit: intellectual history, sociology, psychology, and so on.
When Kuhn suggested in his earliest years as a lecturer for Natural Sciences 4
that “creative science” was “totally different” from the kind of scientific practices
resulting from a specialist education, he was marking the limits of pedagogy
as an engine of scientific development.43 What I want to show, in conclusion,
is that this view led Kuhn into what he came to consider a cul-de-sac in his
philosophy of science, and that he overcame the impasse by identifying the
dogmatic procedures of professional training as the very source and condition of
possibility of revolution. Although he gave Wittgenstein some of the credit for
this transformation in the published version of Structure, he resolved his problem
by writing the case-based teaching method he acquired in the general education
program into his theory of specialist training.
In each of these steps on the road to Structure, textbooks and the necessarily
blinkered nature of professional training in science played an important, but
subtly shifting, role. Very soon after Kuhn began his stint in the Society of
Fellows, he started to translate his convictions regarding the pedagogical function
of textbooks in specialist education into a philosophical critique of attempts
to “formalize” or “logicize” scientific knowledge. Readers of Structure will
know that when Kuhn undertook to criticize positivist philosophies of science
like operationism and logical empiricism, he did so not through systematic
assessments of these positions, but rather by consistently associating them with
the textbook vision of science as a static, logically interrelated set of concepts and
laws.44 The difficulty Kuhn had with these philosophical positions, to the rather
limited extent he discussed them in Structure, was that they were epistemologies
of the textbook; by contrast, everything Kuhn had learned in thinking about
a general education in science pointed to the significance of non-formalizable
elements in shaping the actual process of research and discovery. More than
43
44
Kuhn, “Untitled Talk.”
Alan Richardson, “‘That Sort of Everyday Image of Logical Positivism’: Thomas Kuhn and
the Decline of Logical Empiricist Philosophy of Science,” in Alan Richardson and Thomas
Uebel, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Logical Empiricism (Cambridge, 2007), 346–69.
103
104 joel isaac
a decade before Structure was published, Kuhn was in the habit of associating
textbooks with formalization programs in the philosophy of science. In one of
earliest outlines for Structure, likely written in the late 1940s, Kuhn attacked the
treatment of scientific theories as logical calculi or mechanical operations, but
drew his reflections to a conclusion by observing that “text-books represent a
relatively logicized form of language,” and were thus the root of the philosophical
error represented by the formalism of contemporary philosophy of science.45 A
1951 letter took a similar line: “the major methodological tradition since Bacon
and Descartes,” Kuhn wrote in outlining his chosen topic for a series of public
lectures, “has drawn its conclusions from a study of the logical structure of the
end-products of scientific research and has proceeded as if it assumed the study
of science to be synonymous with a study of textbooks reporting on completed
scientific conceptualizations.”46 When Kuhn gave those lectures at the Lowell
Institute in Boston, also in 1951, he once again lumped together formal treatments
in philosophy under the heading of “textbook science.”47
In the Lowell lectures, the antithesis of textbook science was “creative science,”
understood by Kuhn as the actual process of scientific research, and involving
especially the preconceptions, conceptual schemes, and ideological commitments
that animated it. This was of course exactly the sort of thing that the case histories
given in general education science courses were designed to uncover. In practice,
however, Kuhn demonized the textbook as a source of philosophical data, only to
bring the dogmatic pedagogical function of textbooks in scientific training back as
the explanation for the hold of conceptual schemes on the conduct of science. That
would become the double life of textbooks and professional training in Structure:
at once the source of illusion concerning the nature of scientific knowledge and
the indispensable means by which the preconceptions and ideologies that made
normal-scientific inquiry possible were inculcated within a scientific community.
What is usually passed over in assessments of this feature of Structure is that, before
the final draft of Structure went to press, Kuhn piloted and then abandoned an
account of what kind of shared understanding was brought about by educational
initiation into the conceptual schemes of a field.
Much of this turned on Kuhn’s evolving view of what the non-formalizable,
ideological elements of scientific theories were composed of. When he was in the
Society of Fellows between 1948 and 1951, Kuhn read extraordinarily widely in
the search for a characterization of the conceptual frames that conditioned the
scientific pursuit of knowledge.48 However, by the early 1950s his understanding of
45
46
47
48
Kuhn, “The Book,” n.d. (c. 1948–51), box 1, TSKP, underlining in original.
Kuhn to David Owen, 6 Jan. 1951, box 3, TSKP.
Kuhn, “Introduction: Textbook Science and Creative Science,” 1951, box 3, TSKP.
Kuhn, “Notes & Ideas,” 1949, box 1, TSKP.
kuhn’s education
the efficacy of professional education became increasingly sociological. Although
they receded into the background as mental sets or gestalts, the ideologies
conveyed in textbook training were to be considered stocks of beliefs or rules
on which all members of a scientific community agreed. Some of this was already
evident in Kuhn’s Lowell lectures, as when he claimed that the “predispositions”
that conditioned inquiry had “social sources.”49 Responding in 1952 to an
invitation from the physicist and philosopher Philipp Frank to participate in
a study group on the sociology of science, Kuhn suggested that “in twentiethcentury western science socially conditioned, implicit, professional ‘faiths’ have
assumed many of the roles in the guidance of research and the acceptability
of scientific theories which religions and metaphysical systems played in the
physical science of the seventeenth century.” As Kuhn saw it, “this professional
consensus has important bearing upon the problems which a scientist considers
worth attacking, the experiments which he employs to resolve his problems,”
and also on the various “logical and experimental criteria” demanded of a
“‘valid’ argument.”50 Similarly, when Kuhn sent his editor an informal prospectus
for Structure in 1953, he emphasized, in contrast to “the formal content of a
theory,” the “functions of a theory as a profession[al] ideology for the practicing
scientist.” Theory qua ideology, Kuhn claimed, “dictates preferred techniques of
interpretation, and . . . sets standards of precision in experiment and of rigor in
reasoning”; it was, in sum, “a source simultaneously of essential direction and of
disastrous inhibition to the creative imagination.”51
It was this radical disjuncture between ideology-driven ordinary science and
the creative imagination that would collapse as Kuhn moved, during the late
1950s, to identify the “essential tension” between dogma and innovation in
scientific research. The cause of this collapse was precisely the notion that ideology
rested on consensus on rules or shared beliefs and value-commitments. Even as
Kuhn began to speak, in his drafts for Structure, of the paradigms involved in
textbook-based pedagogy, he continued to believe that what those paradigms
delivered to the initiate were common values and beliefs. As late as the summer
of 1960, when he completed the “penultimate draft” of Structure, Kuhn was
still labeling his discussion of the sociology of professionalization “Normal
Science as Rule-Determined.” Revealingly, Chapter 5 of the published edition
of Structure, “The Priority of Paradigms,” was not in the penultimate draft—and
nor was any of the material, including the discussion of Wittgenstein, that it
contained. At this juncture, however, Kuhn was eager to confess that his earlier
view—that “periods of normal science were periods of consensus, during which
49
50
51
Kuhn, “Introduction.”
Kuhn to Philipp Frank, n.d. (c. 1952, letter unsent), box 25, TSKP.
Kuhn to Charles Morris, 31 July 1953, box 25, TSKP.
105
106 joel isaac
the entire scientific community agreed about the rules of the game,” and that
revolutions were therefore “episodes through which the rules of the game were
changed”—was “very probably wrong.” His highlighting of the role that standard
textbook examples and laboratory demonstrations played in forging agreement
had revealed that “the number of rules that can be educed by such study never
seems sufficient to define the puzzles that scientists normally undertake or to
restrict scientific attention to their pursuit.”52
Although Kuhn had nothing to say at this stage in the drafting process about
Wittgenstein, he did something more revealing: having held textbook and creative
science apart for the better part of a decade, along with the mechanisms of
specialist and generalist training in science, he now implied that the standard
samples and applications given in scientific training regimes played a more subtle
role in forming the scientist’s mental set than merely hammering in consensus
on rules and standards. Instead, the model puzzle solutions found in textbooks
and practical demonstration possessed some of the pedagogic properties of the
exemplary cases hitherto reserved for studying moments of creative ferment in
science in the general education program: these exemplars honed the judgments
of students, their facilities in practical reasoning in a given area, such that
their judgments on salient problems and appropriate solutions would tend to
converge in the absence of explicit agreement on theoretical or methodological
fundamentals. It was because they learned in this case-based manner, Kuhn
argued, “that scientists can so regularly agree in their evaluations of particular
problems and particular solutions without manifesting any similar agreement
about the full set of rules that appear to underlie their judgment.”53 This was
exactly the sort of practical wisdom about the nature of the scientific research
process that Conant’s case histories were supposed to inculcate in non-scientists.
Moreover, the training in this sort of non-mechanical, practical judgment had
defined the case method in teaching at Harvard for almost a century. In a much
overlooked passage of the published version of Structure, Kuhn invoked this
tradition of the case method as the pedagogy of practical wisdom when he
proposed that a paradigm in science “like an accepted judicial decision in the
common law” was “an object for further articulation and specification under
new or more stringent conditions.”54
The way was now clear for Kuhn, in the final draft of Structure, to insist
upon the priority of paradigms both in fixing the course of normal science, and
in explaining the emergence of anomalies, crises, and revolutions as internally
related to the predispositions instilled by specialist education. Kuhn’s lifelong
52
53
54
Kuhn, “Penultimate draft of Structure, before June 1960,” 1960, box 4, TSKP.
Ibid.
Kuhn, Structure, 23.
kuhn’s education
alternation between two traditions of pedagogy had led to an account of scientific
training, and of scientific knowledge, that combined them both. No doubt Kuhn’s
encounter with Wittgenstein, that other great theorist of practical reason in
human affairs, gave him a way of framing these matters philosophically.55 But
when Kuhn spoke, in Structure and elsewhere, about paradigms and professional
training, without any direct historical study of training regimes in science, he was
riffing on pedagogical themes that had marked his personal and professional life
during the long march to Structure.
55
Allan Janik, “Impure Reason Vindicated,” in Alois Pichler and Simo Säätelä, eds.,
Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and His Works (Working Papers from the Wittgenstein
Archives at the University of Bergen, No. 17) (Bergen, 2005), 263–80.
107