The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
The Intellectual Context of F. A. Hayek’s
The Road to Serfdom
Peter Boettke
George Mason University
Rosolino Candela
George Mason University
______________________________________________________
Abstract
Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom is often read as a policy book and a political
tract for its time. It is also often read as little more than a “slippery slope”
argument, leading inevitably down a road from a free society to the gulag.
In this paper, we counter the claim that The Road to Serfdom provides a
slippery slope argument and explain that, while it was often read and used
as a political tract for its time, Hayek’s book is part of a broader project
dealing with the institutional infrastructure within which economic activity
takes place.
______________________________________________________
JEL Codes: B2, B3, B53, P51
Keywords: Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, political economy of socialism
I. Introduction
It has been over seventy years since F. A. Hayek published The Road
to Serfdom (1944), and since that time, Hitler was defeated and World
War II ended in victory for the Allies of the Western democratic
states. The Cold War between the Western democratic states and the
Soviet Union and its satellite countries ensued from roughly 1945 to
1991. The West’s constitutional democracies were transformed into
social democratic states as governments in these countries grew in
size and expanded their scope from 1945 through 1980. In the
intellectual realm, the ascendancy of Keynesian macroeconomic
theory and the policy of demand management were matched by the
development of microeconomic market failure theory and policies
regulating commerce and industry. With the breakdown of the
These remarks were prepared for the 84th Annual Meeting of the Southern
Economic Association, November 22–24, 2014. We thank an anonymous referee
for helpful comments and suggestions on a previous draft of this paper.
30
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
Keynesian consensus in the 1970s with stagflation, the deregulation
of commerce and industry in the 1980s, and the collapse of
communism in the 1990s, it seemed to many that Hayek’s ideas put
forth in The Road to Serfdom were at least superficially vindicated by
history.
Hayek’s most famous work is often read as a policy book and a
political tract for its time. It is also often read as little more than a
“slippery slope” argument, and thus one wrong step leads one down
a road from a free society to the gulag. Alves and Meadowcroft have
argued in a recent article that “Hayek’s slippery slope argument set
out in The Road to Serfdom is empirically false” (2014, p. 859). Their
claim is based on illustrating a positive relationship between
government spending as a percentage of GDP in the Western
democracies and data from the Economic Freedom Network and
Freedom House ratings on political freedom. While the authors are
careful not to draw any causal link between government spending
and economic and political freedom, their claim is that these figures
are prima facie evidence that Hayek’s argument failed to anticipate
the reality of the post-WWII Western democracies.
In this paper, we will try to counter both claims by explaining
that Hayek’s book is part of a broader project on The Abuse of Reason,
dealing with the institutional infrastructure within which economic
activity takes place. His argument, rather than being a slippery slope,
is an immanent critique of the socialist program as advocated by
British socialists, who were his primary target in the 1940s.
Hayek would be joined in his effort to warn intellectuals about
the growth of government interference in the market economy by
Milton Friedman (popular) and James Buchanan (analytical) in the
second half of the twentieth century. Buchanan’s works, such as The
Calculus of Consent (1962) and The Limits of Liberty (1975), sought to
grapple with the analytical questions of how to structurally bind the
government in a way that is consistent with the ordinary behavioral
assumptions of economic analysis to minimize the predatory state
and empower the protective and productive state. Buchanan’s work
had a wide academic influence, but limited popular appeal.
Friedman’s works, such as Capitalism and Freedom (1962) and Free to
Choose (1980), had an amazing popular appeal and practical impact in
the world of public affairs. All three—Hayek, Friedman, and
Buchanan—would be recognized with the Nobel Prize for their
contributions to economic science, and all three would also serve as
president of the Mont Pelerin Society, reflecting their stature as
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
31
leading modern representatives of classical liberalism. But I think it is
safe to say for our purposes that it was the work of Hayek and
Friedman that had the more direct impact on the practical affairs of
men.
The three critical events to highlight this impact would be the
shift of policy focus in China under Deng Xiaoping, in the United
Kingdom under Margaret Thatcher, and in the United States under
Ronald Reagan. The rhetoric of these policy shifts always
outdistanced their reality—so in China, it may not matter what color
the cat is as long as it catches the mouse, but it matters that the party
maintains central control. Thatcher and Reagan may have respectively
slowed government growth, but they didn’t reverse it in either the
United Kingdom or the United States, respectively. Still, the relative
move toward policies of economic freedom in the 1980–2005 period
as compared to the policies of economic regulation of 1945–1980
caused significant improvements in the economic well-being of
billions of individuals across the globe, as documented in Andrei
Shleifer’s article “The Age of Milton Friedman” (2009). Moreover,
Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom has witnessed a renaissance in popularity,
not only among transitional political reformers in post-Soviet Russia,
such as Anatoly Chubais (Shapiro 2001, p. 18), but also among
political commentators, such as Glenn Beck, Rush Limbaugh, and
Mark Levin, reacting to the Obama administration’s economic
policies (see Farrant and McPhail 2010, 2012; Boettke and Snow
2012).
So the world has experienced much since the publication of The
Road to Serfdom in 1944. It would be absurd to claim a direct causal
link between its publication and improvements in living standards
throughout the world (with the notable troubling exceptions of
Africa and Latin America). It might even be absurd to claim a causal
link between the publication and the practical affairs of public
policy—as if policy is directly about ideas, rather than the interests
that form and coalesce around certain public policies. But ideas frame
the policy debate, and in so doing can indirectly impact human
affairs.
Hayek’s work—not only The Road to Serfdom but also The
Constitution of Liberty (1960)—had such an indirect influence. But
rather than allow these works to be relegated to coffee-table status—
which we are not denying they achieved—we want to make sure we
don’t just think about how many copies were sold and which
powerful politicians claim to have been influenced, so we will focus
32
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
here on discussing the intellectual context and substantive argument
that Hayek puts forth in The Road to Serfdom. In section 2, we outline
the Misesian roots of Hayek’s argument within the context of the
socialist calculation debate that ensued from the 1920s through the
1940s. Having placed Hayek’s argument in the context of this debate,
section 3 outlines Hayek’s transition from a technical economist to an
institutional economist. It was during the socialist calculation debate
that Hayek, along with Mises, began “a process of improved selfunderstanding” (Kirzner 1988, p. 3), not only of the entrepreneurial
market process, but more importantly of the institutional conditions
within which the market process generates tendencies toward the
mutual adjustment of decentralized decision-makers (Hayek 1937, p.
53). In section 4, we contend that rather than making a claim of
“inevitability,” Hayek’s slippery slope argument was a claim about the
instability between the organizational logic of planning, which is to
centralize political and economic decision-making, and its effect on
liberal institutions, which is to substitute the rule of law for the rule
of men, the worst of whom are incentivized to exercise political
power. Section 5 concludes.
II. The Misesian Roots of Hayek’s Argument
The Road to Serfdom picks up where Hayek’s edited volume Collectivist
Economic Planning (1935) left off. By that we mean simply that Hayek
operated under the impression that the works by the economists he
reprinted in Collective Economic Planning had decisively demonstrated
the failure of socialists to centrally plan the economy. In particular,
Ludwig von Mises’s work had demonstrated the theoretical
impossibility of the socialist economic planner to engage in rational
economic calculation. Without this ability to engage in rational
economic calculation, the socialist planner will be unable to meet
socialist objectives via socialist means. The project suffered from a
devastating internal contradiction.
This was Hayek’s theoretical touchstone, and it must never be
forgotten in understanding the argument in The Road to Serfdom. Mises
is right, but intellectuals and practical men of affairs are not listening.
They are proceeding as if they have either answered Mises’s objection
or successfully sidestepped it. So what Hayek is demonstrating is
what happens when folks pursue a policy path even though it has
been demonstrated to be logically incoherent. The intellectual
autopsy that he performs thus shows how this effort killed its
advocates’ aspirations.
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
33
The Road to Serfdom is the playing out of this scenario. As well, the
British market socialist theorists who, in the decade after Collectivist
Economic Planning, thought they had successfully designed schemes to
counter Mises, also were committed to the proposition that their
version of socialism would be completely compatible with the longer
British traditions of individualism, democratic freedom, and the rule
of law. So in his autopsy, Hayek was determined to show British
intellectuals that this compatibility was also a figment of their
imaginations in the same way that their schemes to address (or
sidestep) the Misesian challenge were.
Mises’s argument establishes that due to the inability to engage in
rational economic calculation, the socialist ends of increased material
progress cannot be achieved through socialist means. We should be
careful here because (a) definitions matter, so a claim about meansends relies on consistency in the terms’ meaning; and (b) establishing
that something is logically incoherent doesn’t mean that individuals
will not attempt to pursue this path anyway. So first, socialism at the
time of Mises’s writing had a specific meaning in the context of
economic policy. It was to rationalize production to such an extent
that mankind would experience a burst of productivity and propel it
from the “kingdom of necessity” to the “kingdom of freedom.”
Rationalizing production would eliminate the waste of capitalism that
results from the groping efforts of errant entrepreneurs in their quest
for profits, even under favorable conditions, and are exacerbated in
situations of monopoly power and macroeconomic volatility. By
curbing capitalism’s monopolistic tendencies and inherent instability,
rationalizing production through socialist economic planning would
result in a new level of material progress that would provide the basis
for the end of class conflict, and would usher in a new era of peaceful
and harmonious relations between all men. So that is the goal, but we
still have to be clear on the means of socialist economic planning.
The means are the abolition of private property in the means of
production, the establishment of collective ownership, the
substitution of administered prices for the free fluctuation of prices
dictated by the exchange relationships in the market, and the
development of economic plans based on production for direct use
rather than production for profit. Mises iterated his challenge by
simply asking the following: Are the socialist means of collective
ownership of the means of production, such as administered prices
and production for direct use, capable of achieving the socialist ends
34
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
of rationalizing production, producing advanced material progress,
and harmonizing the social relations between the classes?
His answer was no, and the reason was the inability of socialist
planners to engage in rational economic calculation of the alternative
use of scarce productive resources. Production under socialism
would be rudderless and would, in fact, be little more than steps in
the dark. Without private property, there are no market prices, and
without market prices, there can be no rational calculation. It is that
simple and that profound. Economic calculation is critical to the
efficient operation of an economy because it is precisely that
mechanism that enables economic actors to sort out from the
plentiful array of technologically feasible projects those which are
economically viable.
Following our line of argument, The Road to Serfdom that Hayek
describes is the by-product of the truth of the Misesian argument
biting against the socialist aspirations of practical political decisions in
actual policy implementation. As Hayek argued in The CounterRevolution of Science (1952, pp. 68–69):
The problems which they [social sciences] try to answer arise
only insofar as the conscious actions of many men produce
undesigned results, insofar as regularities are observed which
are not the result of anybody’s design. If social phenomena
showed no order except insofar as they were consciously
designed, there would be indeed be no room for theoretical
sciences of society and there would be, as is often argued,
only problems of psychology. It is only insofar as some sort
of order arises as a result of individual action but without
being designed by any individual that a problem is raised
which demands a theoretical explanation.
The problems Hayek identifies are the unintended and
undesirable (from the advocate’s point of view) by-products of the
policymaker’s attempt to pursue socialist policies and confront the
reality of the Misesian critique. As Hayek would put the point: “That
democratic socialism, the great utopia of the last few generations, is
not only unachievable, but that to strive for it produces something so
utterly different that few of those who now wish it would be
prepared to accept the consequences, any will not believe until the
connection has been laid bare in all its aspects” (1944, p. 31).
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
35
III. Hayek’s Journey from Technical Economist to Political
Economist
Hayek began his career as a technical economist focused on the
problem of imputation, intertemporal coordination, and industrial
fluctuations. But as a consequence of his debate with other
economists over socialism’s viability, he was led increasingly to
explore the market economy’s institutional foundations and the
underlying philosophical issues that clouded rather than clarified their
understanding of those foundations. Hayek intended The Road to
Serfdom to be part of a larger project that he never completed, dubbed
The Abuse of Reason, out of which he also published The Counter
Revolution of Science (1952). Moreover, the emphasis on the rule of law
and spontaneous order that were prefigured in The Road to Serfdom
would be stressed in Hayek’s later works, such as The Constitution of
Liberty (1960) and Law, Legislation, and Liberty (1973, 1976, 1979).
Putting The Road to Serfdom into the context of this larger project
also provides further evidence against not only the inevitability thesis
in Hayek’s slippery slope argument, but also against the notion that
Hayek was trying to generate point predictions about the future of
the Western democracies. As Bruce Caldwell states:
Hayek denied this reading both in the book itself and in
subsequent responses to his critics. That the book was
originally intended as part of the Abuse of Reason project
provides further evidence in Hayek’s favor. One of the major
themes of the “Scientism [and the Study of Society]” essay is
that the historical search for general laws that would allow
one to predict the future course of history is chimerical.
Would it make sense for the author of such an essay to then
turn around later in his work and attempt to predict the
future course of history? (2004, p. 241, fn. 4)
While the empirical data that Alves and Meadowcroft provide are
factually correct, they take Hayek’s argument out of its proper
theoretical context, in which Hayek was trying to explain why
countries like Russia, Italy, and Germany had gone down the road to
serfdom. It was not to establish any “scientistic” point predictions
about a one-to-one relationship between government spending and
freedom—both economic and political—as Alves and Meadowcroft
would argue.
Economic analysis proceeds on the basis of the establishment of
clearly defined and strictly enforced private property rights. This is
the basis of exchange relationships (buying or abstaining from
36
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
buying) in the market that give us the price system, as well as the
complex division of labor that emerges as prices guide production
decisions. Since the institutional infrastructure was fixed and given, it
was too easily glossed over by modern economists in their analysis of
alternative economic systems. Hayek sought to correct for this
oversight.
So as Hayek transitioned from being a technical economist in the
1920s and 1930s to being a political economist—dare we say, the
social philosopher that he would be for the rest of his career—it is
vital to remember the underlying economics in his argument. The
basic economic calculus persists throughout his work, and the idea of
the epistemic properties of alternative institutional arrangements
remains his analytical focus. There is, in this rendering, a unity in
Hayek’s project, not a departure after his debate with Keynes or his
debate with Lange-Lerner. But when Hayek decides to write The Road
to Serfdom, he is ready to deploy his basic economic mode of analysis
to address the institutional questions that real-world socialist
economies would need to face and the situational logic that socialist
decision makers must confront.
He would not only make the Misesian argument that socialist
means are incoherent with respect to socialist ends, but he would also
argue that the metamorphosis of the system that occurs in the
attempt to pursue this impossible task results in a political and
economic reality from which the socialist thinker would recoil. The
logic of the situation and the logic of organization under socialist
planning are such that democracy and the rule of law are
unsustainable in substantive content, and the system, if pursued to its
logical end, would result in the concentration of political power in the
hands of the men least capable of constraining the abuse of power.
The worst of us, it seems, will end up on top, a result confirmed by
the coincidence of the twentieth century’s three leading political mass
murderers—Hitler, Stalin, and Mao—rising to the top of socialist
systems and also reflected in the practice of more recent socialist
leaders such as Pol Pot, Castro, and Chavez. Hayek’s argument is not
an argument of inevitability (more on that in the next section), but
merely a simple application of the principle of comparative advantage
to the realm of politics, particularly when politics is demanding such
a comprehensive command-and-control stance to be taken by those
in leadership.
Similarly, Hayek’s analysis of socialism’s compatibility with
democratic freedoms and the rule of law relies on his analysis of the
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
37
situational logic. Socialism requires a level of political agreement to
operationalize its policies that is far greater in detail than what
liberalism requires. Liberalism only requires agreement on the general
rules by which we interact with each other. “Don’t hurt people and
don’t take their stuff” is rather straightforward. But questions of a
more detailed nature are progressively more difficult to resolve in
such a straightforward manner. As Hayek (1944, pp. 91–92) puts it:
The question raised by economic planning is, therefore, not
merely whether we shall be able to satisfy what we regard as our
more or less important needs in the way we prefer. It is whether it
shall be we who decide what is more, and what is less, important for
us, or whether this is to be decided by the planner. Economic
planning would not affect merely those of our marginal needs that we
have in mind when we speak contemptuously about the merely
economic. It would, in effect, mean that we as individuals should no
longer be allowed to decide what we regard as marginal.
And in the next paragraph he continues:
The authority directing all economic activity would control
not merely the part of our lives which is concerned with
inferior things; it would control the allocation of the limited
means for all our ends. And whoever controls all economic
activity controls the means for all our ends and must
therefore decide which are to be satisfied and what not. This
is really the crux of the matter. Economic control is not
merely control of a sector of human life which can be
separated from the rest; it is the control of the means for all
our ends. And whoever controls the means must also
determine which ends are to be served, which values are to be
rated higher and which lower—in short, what men should
believe and strive for.
Earlier in The Road to Serfdom, Hayek had already made the
argument that since any idea of coherent planning requires it to be
comprehensive and based on agreement at each successive stage—an
agreement that democracy cannot guarantee—the situational logic
will agitate toward a move beyond the process of democratic
deliberation, and instead, a concentration of power will be trusted to
the responsible authorities, unfettered by democratic procedures
(1944, p. 67).
The organizational logic of planning is to concentrate decisionmaking power; the situational logic of such an organization
incentivizes those who have a comparative advantage in exercising
38
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
political power over others to rise to the top of the decision-making
authority. “Just as the democratic statesman who sets out to plan
economic life will soon be confronted with the alternative of either
assuming dictatorial powers or abandoning his plans,” Hayek tells his
reader, “so the totalitarian dictator would soon have to choose
between disregard of ordinary morals or failure. It is for this reason
that the unscrupulous and uninhibited are likely to be more
successful in a society tending toward totalitarianism” (1944, p. 135).
IV. This Isn’t a Slippery Slope
The counterreaction to the Mises-Hayek critique by British socialists
was to argue that socialist policy and economic and political freedom
were compatible. E. F. Durbin in a review article on The Road to
Serfdom, published in the Economic Journal (1945, p. 358), argued that
Hayek was wrong because “we all wish to live in a community that is
as rich as possible, in which consumers’ preferences determine the
relative output of goods that can be consumed by individuals, and in
which there is freedom of discussion and political association and
responsible government.” Durbin also states, “Most of us are
socialist in our economics because we are ‘liberal’ in our philosophy.”
Even Hayek’s close friend and comrade in the debate with market
socialists, Lionel Robbins, came to argue in The Economic Problem in
Peace and War (1947, p. 28) that “an individualist who recognizes the
importance of public goods, and a collective who recognizes the
desirability of the maximum of individual freedom in consumption
will find many points of agreement in common. The biggest dividing
line of our day is, not between those who differ about organization as
such, but between those who differ about the ends which
organization has to serve.”
We contend that both Durbin and Robbins are led down this
argumentative alley because they (a) misinterpret Hayek as having
abandoned (correctly in their estimation) Mises’s “impossibility of
rational economic calculation” thesis, and (b) read Hayek as making a
slippery slope argument rather than what we will call the “instability”
argument. In the argument we have been putting forth, we have an
organizational logic and a situational logic going hand in hand to
produce an instability in the policy space as a consequence of the
incoherence of socialist policy means with socialist policy ends. As
Hayek argues, the decision authority must choose to go further along
the amassing of centralized power, or abandon the policy agenda
being pursued (Boettke 2005, p. 1048).
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
39
There is no iron-clad inevitability in Hayek’s argument, as
presented in The Road to Serfdom. The argument, instead, is a warning
of a tragic possibility that would be viewed as abhorrent from the
point of view of those who believe they are “socialists in their
economics because they are liberals in their philosophy.” What Hayek
was addressing to socialists of the time, particularly in England, was
the lagging link between socialist ideas and how such socialist ideas
would later demand institutional changes that are inconsistent with
liberal principles, transforming democratic institutions into
instruments of totalitarian rule:
I know that many of my English friends have sometimes
been shocked by the semi-Fascist views they would
occasionally hear expressed by German refugees, whose
genuinely socialist convictions could not be doubted. But
while these English observers put this down to their being
Germans, the true explanation is that they were socialists
whose experience had carried them several stages beyond that
yet reached by socialists in this country. It is true, of course,
that German socialists have found much support in their
country from certain features of the Prussian tradition . . . But
it would be a mistake to believe that the specific German
rather than the socialist element produced totalitarianism. It
was the prevalence of socialist views and not Prussianism that
Germany had in common with Italy and Russia—and it was
from the masses and not from the classes steeped in the
Prussian tradition, and favoured by it, that National-Socialism
arose (1944, p. 9).
The connections that Hayek said must be laid bare are done so
by this link between organizational logic and situational logic against
the backdrop of Mises’s impossibility thesis. Hayek’s “economic
calculus” does not rely on maximizing agents with full and complete
information operating in a frictionless environment. Such omniscient
automatons are not what Hayek or Mises are working with in
developing the economic way of thinking. But the stumbling and
bumbling actors that populate Hayek’s analytical framework are also
not forever clueless; they are capable, but fallible human actors
engaged in economic activity within specified organizational and
institutional contexts.1
1 See Hayek, Individualism and Economic Order (1948, pp. 11–13), for a discussion of
what we now might term his open-ended model of human choosing, and how this
model feeds into his appreciation of the institutions of secure property rights, the
40
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
The market socialist writers of the 1930s and 1940s were ignoring
the vital theoretical point about context mattering. They were instead
myopically pursuing economic reasoning as if institutions did not
matter, and as if instead resource decisions were purely technical.
They were misled in this endeavor by a preoccupation with an
equilibrium state of affairs where, by definition, all the work that
institutions have to do in shaping and guiding economic decisions is,
in fact, done. But absent those very institutions that were now being
ignored, the economic forces that would be at work would be
different. This is where Hayek’s organizational logic and situational
logic reenter the analysis. Institutions structure the incentives one
faces in making decisions and dictate the flow and quality of
information available to guide those decisions. In a world of scarcity,
trade-offs abound, and decision makers must have a means to
negotiate those trade-offs. If it isn’t the institutions of property,
prices, and profit and loss that are aids to the human mind,
something else must structure incentives and guide decisions (see
Boettke and Candela 2015). Absent the institutional infrastructure of
a liberal economy, you cannot get the results generated by that
infrastructure. Liberalism may indeed be a philosophy, but it has an
institutional embodiment, and that institutional embodiment has an
imprint.
In short, you cannot be a socialist in economics and realize the
philosophical goals of individual autonomy, productive specialization,
and peaceful social cooperation. As Hayek made his institutional
turn, starting with his 1937 paper “Economics and Knowledge” but
gaining in momentum through the 1940s and 1950s, the
argumentative focal point moved decidedly off the individual actors’
behavioral assumptions and to the alternative institutional contexts
within which they acted. The same players under different rules
produce different games.
So rather than postulating a slippery slope determinacy, it is
better to read Hayek as making a radical argument for a form of
pattern prediction indeterminacy, not unlike the sort of theorizing in
the social sciences later promoted by Russell Hardin (2005) and
Vernon Smith (2003) in arguing for “ecological rationality” in
contrast to “constructivist rationality.” Depending on the institutional
context, the situational logic will produce systemic tendencies in this
transference of those property rights through consent, and the keeping of promises
via contract for the operation of a free economy that is able to harness productive
specialization and produce peaceful cooperation.
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
41
or that direction. If the political decision maker, when confronted
with the failure of their socialist plans, chooses to abandon those
plans and instead institute more liberal economic policies, then the
organizational logic and situational logic will work in one way. But if
not, and instead our socialist planner pushes for further command
and control measures, then the organizational logic and the
situational logic will go in a different direction.
This pattern-predictive indeterminacy style of reasoning that
Hayek’s work reflects should also put to rest the mythology that the
failure of Britain to devolve into Stalin’s gulag, or for Sweden to
avoid that fate, somehow demonstrates the weak predictive power of
Hayek’s argument in The Road to Serfdom. First, Hayek didn’t make a
deterministic slippery slope argument. He made an indeterminate
instability argument—a choice must be made, and if the wrong
choice is made, the organizational logic and the situational logic will
produce another decision node in which frustration of failed plans
forces a choice upon those in authority. Second, while the
organizational logic and situational logic produce strong tendencies
within the alternative institutional contexts, the fact that Hayek wrote
The Road to Serfdom and that it has had such widespread success (even
among its critics) meant that his ideas were part of the endogenous
public choosing influences (Witt 1992). That Hayek’s warning might
have successfully done its job in stopping the realization of his worse
prediction in Britain and the United States cannot be dismissed so
easily.
Economic patterns are not invariant to institutional context. That
“sophisticated” social science ever thought they were is a sign of the
intellectual bedlam that can result when philosophical currents and
methodological fashion are allowed to cloud basic economic theory
grounded in the strictures of critical reasoning.
V. Conclusion
As we reflect on the seven decades since Hayek published The Road to
Serfdom, we should be amazed at the intellectual and practical progress
that has been made. The Western democracies have gone through a
period of relative opening up of markets compared to the
overregulation of those economies during the 1950–1980 period. The
“great social experiment” with communism came to an end as these
unfortunate countries suffered under the yoke of economic
deprivation and political tyranny. The relative freedom experienced
by the economies of Eastern and Central Europe and the former
42
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
Soviet Union, as well as those of East Asia, India, and China, has led
to rapid improvements in the material conditions of mankind across
the globe.
But we cannot simply be satisfied with the triumph of the ideas
one finds in Hayek (and also in Friedman and Buchanan). The reality
of the democratic West is that the fiscal situation has largely been
undisciplined after the ascent of Keynesian policies, which has
produced an era of economic illusion to be reckoned with (Buchanan
and Wagner 1977; Wagner 2012; Tanzi 2011). These policies have led
to a global financial crisis that once again has been blamed on a
nonexistent laissez-faire economy. Hayek’s discussions of democracy
and decision, of security and freedom, of economic freedom and
political freedom are as relevant to our discussions today as they were
at the time he sat down to write The Road to Serfdom. It wasn’t Hitler
and Stalin who concerned Hayek; it was the totalitarians in our midst
that animated his effort. We face that same problem today, and we
must be ever vigilant. As economists and political economists, we
must be capable of competently deploying the technical economic
principles that are necessary to analyze how alternative institutional
arrangements impact the system’s ability to realize the gains from
productive specialization and peaceful social cooperation among free
individuals. But to put it frankly, we must also be willing to expose
and critically explore the fundamental philosophical issues that are
too often smuggled in whenever we discuss the appropriate scope of
governmental activities.
The good news is that after the global financial crisis, the oldtime Keynesian narrative about the instability of capitalism has not
gone unchallenged and thus has not been able to wrest hold of the
intellectual zeitgeist the way it did after the Great Depression. But the
bad news is that in the policy space, the old-time Keynesian remedies
still are reflected in the tacit presuppositions of political economy
throughout the Western world. Our work remains cut out for us. We
have indeed made a mess of things in the twentieth century, and we
are doing our best to make matters worse in the twenty-first century
by blowing the opportunity to learn from the lessons of the twentieth
about the failed alliance of scientism and statism. But perhaps the
challenge we face today is the same one that Hayek identified in the
concluding words of The Road to Serfdom:
If they [the nineteenth century liberals] had not yet fully
learned what was necessary to create the world they wanted,
the experience we have since gained ought to have equipped
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
43
us better for the task. If in the first attempt to create a world
of free men we have failed, we must try again. The guiding
principle that a policy of freedom for the individual is the
only truly progressive policy remains as true today as it was in
the nineteenth century (1944, p. 240).
References
Alves, André Azevedo, and John Meadowcroft. 2014. “Hayek’s Slippery Slope, the
Stability of the Mixed Economy and the Dynamics of Rent Seeking.” Political
Studies, 62 (4): 843–61.
Boettke, Peter J. 2005. “On Reading Hayek: Choice, Consequences and The Road to
Serfdom.” European Journal of Political Economy 21: 1042–53.
Boettke, Peter J., and Rosolino A. Candela. 2015. “What Is Old Should Be New
Again: Methodological Individualism, Institutional Analysis and Spontaneous
Order.” Sociologia, 2: 5–14.
Boettke, Peter J., and Nicholas A. Snow. 2012. “The Servants of Obama’s
Machinery: F. A. Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom Revisited? – A Reply.” Eastern
Economic Journal, 38(4): 428–33.
Buchanan, James M. 1975. The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Buchanan, James M., and Gordon Tullock. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical
Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Buchanan, James M., and Richard E. Wagner. 1977. Democracy in Deficit: The Political
Legacy of Lord Keynes. New York: Academic Press.
Caldwell, Bruce. 2004. Hayek’s Challenge: An Intellectual Biography of F. A. Hayek.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Durbin, E. F. 1945. “Professor Hayek on Economic Planning and Political
Liberty.” Economic Journal, 55(220): 357–70.
Farrant, Andrew, and Edward McPhail. 2010. “Does F. A. Hayek’s Road to Serfdom
Deserve to Make a Comeback?” Challenge, 53(4): 96–120.
Farrant, Andrew, and Edward McPhail. 2012. “The Servants of Obama’s
Machinery: F. A. Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom Revisited?” Eastern Economic
Journal, 38(4): 423–27.
Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Friedman, Milton, and Rose Friedman. 1980. Free to Choose: A Personal Statement.
New York: Harcourt.
Hardin, Russell. 2005. Indeterminacy and Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Hayek, F. A., ed. 1935. Collectivist Economic Planning. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Hayek, F. A. 1937. “Economics and Knowledge.” Economica, 4(13): 33–54.
Hayek, F. A. 1944. The Road to Serfdom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hayek, F. A. 1948. Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Hayek, F. A. 1952. The Counter-Revolution of Science. Glencoe: Free Press.
Hayek, F. A. 1960. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
44
Boettke & Candela / The Journal of Private Enterprise 32(1), 2017, 29–44
Hayek, F. A. 1973. Law, Legislation, and Liberty, Vol. 1: Rules and Order. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Hayek, F. A. 1976. Law, Legislation, and Liberty, Vol. 2: The Mirage of Social Justice.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hayek, F. A. 1979. Law, Legislation, and Liberty, Vol. 3: The Political Order of a Free
People. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kirzner, Israel M. 1988. “The Economic Calculation Debate: Lessons for
Austrians.” Review of Austrian Economics, 2(1): 1–18.
Robbins, Lionel. 1947. The Economic Problem in Peace and War. London: Macmillan.
Shapiro, David L. 2001. “Hayek’s Slippery Slope: Is There a Third Way?” Journal of
Private Enterprise, 16(2): 16–29.
Shliefer, Andrei. 2009. “The Age of Milton Friedman.” Journal of Economic Literature,
47(1): 123–35.
Smith, Vernon. 2003. “Constructivist and Ecological Rationality in Economics.”
American Economic Review, 93(3): 465–508.
Tanzi, Vito. 2011. Government versus Markets: The Changing Economic Role of the State.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wagner, Richard E. 2012. Deficits, Debt, and Democracy: Wrestling with Tragedy on the
Fiscal Commons. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.
Witt, Ulrich. 1992. “The Endogenous Public Choice Theorist.” Public Choice, 73(1):
117–29.