Williamson on Knowledge
Patrick Greenough and Duncan Pritchard
Print publication date: 2009
Print ISBN-13: 9780199287512
Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: Feb-10
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199287512.001.0001
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
Stephen Schiffer (Contributor Webpage)
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199287512.003.0012
Abstract and Keywords
A single argument template — the EPH template — can be used to generate
versions of the best-known and most challenging sceptical problems.
In Knowledge and its Limits, Timothy Williamson presents a theory of
knowledge and evidence which he clearly intends to provide a response to
scepticism in its most important forms. This chapter lays out EPH scepticism
and reviews possible ways of responding to it. It then shows how elements
of Williamson's theory motivate a hitherto unexplored way of responding
to EPH-generated sceptical arguments. It offers reasons to doubt the
correctness of Williamson's response.
Keywords: EPH template, knowledge, Timothy Williamson, sceptical problems, theory of
knowledge, evidence, scepticism
A single argument template—the EPH template—can be used to generate
versions of the best‐known and most challenging skeptical problems. In his
brilliantly groundbreaking book Knowledge and its Limits Timothy Williamson
presents a theory of knowledge and evidence which he clearly intends to
provide a response to skepticism in its most important forms. After laying
out EPH skepticism and reviewing possible ways of responding to it, I show
how elements of Williamson's theory motivate a hitherto unexplored way of
responding to EPH‐generated skeptical arguments. Then I offer reasons to
doubt the correctness of Williamson's response.
Page 1 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
1. EPH Skepticism
The EPH argument template has as its ingredients an uncontentious fact E, a
run‐of‐the‐mill proposition P, and a skeptical hypothesis H such that:
• common sense supposes that one would know and be justified in
believing P on the basis of E;
• H entails both E and not P; and
• it appears that if E cannot justify one in believing not H, then
there is nothing else available to justify one in believing not H.
Using these ingredients, the skeptic argues as follows, where by stipulation
the subject “I” is a rational thinker who is fully and actively aware that P and
H are incompatible and that H entails E:
1. I am not justified in believing P unless I am justified in believing
not H.
2. I am not justified in believing not H unless something other than
E justifies me in believing not H.
3. There is nothing other than E to justify me in believing not H.
4. ∴ I am not justified in believing P.
•
(p. 184 )
5. If I am not justified in believing P, then I do not know P.
6. ∴ I do not know P.
When we take E to be the proposition that I am having such‐and‐such
sensory experiences as of a red cube, P the proposition that there is a red
cube before me, and H the hypothesis—call it BIV—that I am a brain floating
in a cubeless vat of nutrients and attached to a device that is causing me
to have the such‐and‐such sensory experiences as of a red cube which I am
now having, then we get:
•
External World
1. I am not justified in believing that there is a red cube before me
unless I am justified in believing not BIV.
2. I am not justified in believing not BIV unless something other
than the fact that I am currently having such‐and‐such sensory
experiences as of a red cube justifies me in believing not BIV.
3. There is nothing else to justify me in believing not BIV.
4. I am not justified in believing that there is a red cube before me.
5. If I am not justified in believing that there is a red cube before
me, then I do not know that there is a red cube before me.
6. ∴ I do not know that there is a red cube before me.
Page 2 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
By a straightforward extrapolation and generalization, the argument may be
continued to show that no facts about my sensory experiences can justify
me in believing anything about the external world, and that therefore my
sensory experience cannot give me knowledge of the external world. And
if “I”—that is, a rational thinker in epistemically optimal conditions—cannot
have knowledge or justified belief of the kind in question, then no one can
have such knowledge or justified belief.
When we take E to be the fact that I have egg on my shirt and seem to
remember eating eggs for breakfast, P the proposition that I had eggs for
breakfast, and H the hypothesis—call it new—that the universe just this
moment came into existence, completely as is, with the fact that I have egg
on my shirt and seem to remember eating eggs for breakfast, then we get:
•
Past
•
1. I am not justified in believing that I had eggs for breakfast unless
I am justified in believing not new.
2. I am not justified in believing not new unless something other
than the fact that I have egg on my shirt and seem to remember
eating eggs for breakfast justifies me in believing not new.
3. There is nothing else to justify me in believing not new.
(p. 185 )
4. ∴ I am not justified in believing that I had eggs for breakfast.
5. If I am not justified in believing that I had eggs for breakfast,
then I do not know that I had eggs for breakfast.
6. ∴ I do not know that I had eggs for breakfast.
By a straightforward extrapolation and generalization, the argument may be
continued to show that no facts about the present can justify me in believing
anything about the past, and that therefore such facts cannot give me
knowledge of the past. And if I—a rational thinker who is actively aware of
relevant entailments—cannot have knowledge or justified belief of the kind in
question, then no one can have such knowledge or justified belief.
When we take E to be the fact that Al broke his toe by stubbing it against a
rock and is screaming and writhing on the ground, P the proposition that Al is
in pain, and H the hypothesis—call it zombie—that Al is a zombie who has no
sentient mental states, even though he broke his toe by stubbing it against a
rock and is screaming and writhing on the ground and in general behaves in
ways I expect sentient humans to behave, then we get:
•
Other Minds
Page 3 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
1. I am not justified in believing that Al is in pain unless I am
justified in believing not zombie.
2. I am not justified in believing not zombie unless something other
than the fact that Al broke his toe and is screaming and writhing on
the ground justifies me in believing not zombie.
3. There is nothing else to justify me in believing not zombie.
4. ∴ I am not justified in believing that Al is in pain.
5. If I am not justified in believing that Al is in pain, then I do not
know that Al is in pain.
6. ∴ I do not know that Al is in pain.
By a straightforward extrapolation and generalization, the argument may be
continued to show that no facts about the behavior of, or causes acting on,
another body can justify me in believing anything about the sentient mental
states of others, not even that others have such states, and that therefore
such facts cannot give me knowledge of other minds, not even that there are
other minds. And if “I” cannot have knowledge or justified belief of the kind
in question, then no one can have such knowledge or justified belief.
When we take E to be the fact that all observed ravens have been black,
P the proposition that the next observed raven will be black, and H the
hypothesis—call it nonuniformity—that, while all observed ravens have been
black, no observed ravens after now will be black, then we can even get: (p.
186 )
•
Induction
1. I am not justified in believing that the next observed raven will
be black unless I am justified in believing not nonuniformity.
2. I am not justified in believing not nonuniformity unless something
other than the fact that all observed ravens have been black
justifies me in believing not nonuniformity.
3. There is nothing else to justify me in believing not nonuniformity.
4. ∴ I am not justified in believing that the next observed raven will
be black.
5. If I am not justified in believing that the next observed raven will
be black, then I do not know that the next observed raven will be
black.
6. ∴ I do not know that the next observed raven will be black.
By a straightforward extrapolation and generalization, the argument may
be continued to show that no facts about past regularities can justify me in
believing that any past regularities will continue to hold, and that therefore
Page 4 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
such facts can give me no knowledge of the future. And if “I” cannot have
knowledge or justified belief of the kind in question, then no one can have
such knowledge or justified belief.
It is important to appreciate that the different skeptical paradoxes are
instances of the same argument form, because that motivates a defeasible
expectation that, if any one of the four skeptical arguments goes wrong in a
particular way, then they all go wrong in that way. In other words, we should
not expect there to be one solution to the problem of the external world and
a different solution to, say, the problem of other minds.
Skeptical arguments may take other forms, but it is reasonable to suppose
that a resolution of the problems raised by EPH arguments will have
application to the skeptical arguments that take those other forms, and that
any fully adequate response to those other arguments will have application
to the EPH arguments.
For the rest of this chapter I shall focus just on the EPH argument template
as it concerns justified belief—that is, on the template:
•
EPH
1. I am not justified in believing P unless I am justified in believing
not H.
2. I am not justified in believing not H unless something other than
E justifies me in believing not H.
3. There is nothing other than E to justify me in believing not H.
4. ∴ I am not justified in believing P.
It is not that no one has thought to challenge premise (5) (if I am not justified
in believing P, then I do not know P). Some have challenged the claim that
knowing P entails believing P, while others have conceded that knowing P
(p. 187 ) entails believing P but have challenged the claim that knowing P
entails being justified in believing P. I am not sure why no one has thought to
challenge the claim that knowing P entails that P is true, since we sometimes
say such things as “I knew she would say yes” when we know that she did
not say yes, and that sort of use of “know” is pretty much on all fours with
the examples that are supposed to loosen the ties between knowledge and
belief or justification. In any case, I am not aware of any good reasons to
deny (5); Williamson evidently would not deny it; and, even if (5) were false,
an argument that concludes that we cannot be justified in believing the
things we are certain we are justified in believing is itself, needless to say, a
skeptical paradox worth grappling with.
Page 5 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
EPH is a valid argument form, and we come to the skeptical arguments
already believing that their conclusions are false. The plausibility of the
premises, however, must be earned. We will be in a better position to
appreciate the nature of Williamson's innovative response to EPH skepticism
if I first briefly review enough of what might be said in support of each of the
three EPH premises to justify treating the EPH arguments as paradoxes—
valid arguments with apparently true premises and apparently false
conclusions (thereby showing, once again, that you cannot always go by
appearances).
Premise (1) (I am not justified in believing P unless I am justified in believing
not H). Recall that the “I” of the argument is by stipulation a rational thinker
who is actively aware that P entails not H. Given that, the plausibility of (1) is
entailed by the plausibility of the closure principle:
JBC For any propositions P, Q, one who is actively aware that P
entails Q is justified in believing P only if she is also justified in
believing Q.
It is easy to see why JBC is plausible. If one may be justified in believing P
but not Q when one is actively aware that P entails Q, then it need not be
irrational for one to believe that P is true and to doubt whether Q is true
even while being fully and actively aware that it is impossible for P to be
true unless Q is true. But it is doubtful that such a combination of attitudes is
possible, let alone can be rationally held.
I do need to say something about the intended meaning of “is justified in
believing” as it occurs in EPH, and thus in JBC. Three justification relations
need to be distinguished:
IS E is a justification for S to believe P.
HAS E is a justification that S has to believe P.
IN E justifies S in believing P.
On the intended reading of IS, E can be a justification for S to believe P even
though S is not aware of E and does not believe P. For example, a certain
(p. 188 ) symptom may be conclusive evidence that I have a certain disease,
even though I am unaware of the symptom, unaware that I have the disease,
and would be unaware that the symptom was evidence of the disease even if
I were aware of it.
On the intended reading of HAS, in order for E to be a justification that S has
to believe P, S must know, or at least believe, E—or at least simply have E, if
E is an experience or sensation. (If we assume Williamson's theory, wherein
Page 6 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
only evidence can justify and a proposition belongs to S's total evidence just
in case S knows it,1 then E is a justification that S has for believing P if and
only if E is a justification for S to believe P and S knows E.)
On the intended reading of IN, E can be a justification that S has for believing
P and yet not be what justifies S in believing P, even though S is justified in
believing P. For example, S may know a certain fact about a DNA fingerprint
found in a hair sample at the scene of a murder; this fact may be virtually
conclusive evidence that the chauffeur was the murderer; and S may not
know that the DNA fingerprint implicates the chauffeur yet still be justified in
believing that the chauffeur committed the murder on the basis of knowing
that two independent and uninvolved witnesses say they saw the chauffeur
commit the murder. To be justified in believing P is to believe P and to be
justified in doing so, and for E to be what justifies S in believing P it must be
that S believes P on the basis of S's having, knowing, or at least believing
E, in a sense of “on the basis of” that awaits explication but can be used to
sort cases. Assuming Williamson's theory of evidence (see below), we may
say that evidence E justifies S in believing P only if S's knowing E accounts
for the fact that S is justified in believing P. This in turn implies that, all other
things being equal, if E justifies S in believing P, then S would not be so
justified if S did not know E.
Premise (2) (I am not justified in believing not H unless something
other than E justifies me in believing not H). The argument for premise (2) is
this:
(i) We may take it as given that (a) I know for certain that H entails
E; (b) I come to know E at a certain time t*2; and (c) prior to t*, both
E and H were uncertain to me.
(ii) If (i), then E is evidence for H for me at t*.
(iii) E cannot be part of what justifies me in believing not H at t* if E
is evidence for H for me at t*.
(iv) ∴ I am not justified in believing not H at t* unless something
other than E justifies me in believing not H at t*.
(p. 189 )
Only (ii) and (iii) need justification. Let t* continue to be the time alluded to
in the argument, and let
•
Probold=probability on all the evidence acquired up to the time just
before t*, the time at which Prob(E) becomes 1.
Now, it is a theorem of probability theory that
Page 7 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
•
[(Probold(E/H) = 1) & (0 < Probold(E) < 1) & (0 < Probold(H) > 1] →
typo: should be <
Probold(H/E) > Probold(H),
and it is transparently plausible that
•
E is evidence for H for S at t* if (a) S knows E at t* and (b) Probold(H/
E) > Probold(H),
and from those two things (ii) follows. Two points also secure (iii). First, E is
evidence against not H for me if E is evidence for H for me (this is reflected
in probabilistic terms by the theorem that Prob(H) + Prob(¬H) = 1). And,
secondly, E cannot be part of what justifies me in believing not H if E is
evidence against not H for me—after all, if E is evidence against not H
for me, then E should lower my confidence in not H, and something that
lowers my confidence in a hypothesis cannot be part of what justifies me in
believing it.
Premise (3) (There is nothing other than E to justify me in believing not H).
One cannot provide a prima facie justification for the instances of premise
(3) in question without regard to the particular values of H and E. But in
each case there is the same pattern of argument: there is nothing other
than E to justify me in believing not H because (a), if there is to be evidence
against H, it will ultimately (p. 190 ) come down to evidence of the kind to
which E belongs for propositions of the kind to which P belongs; but (b), as
the instance of EPH shows, no E‐type fact can justify one in believing a P‐
type proposition unless there is a justification for disbelieving an H‐type
hypothesis that is independent of that E‐type fact. Here is how this plays out
with respect to External World:
1. Since BIV is a contingent empirical hypothesis, I would be
justified in disbelieving it only if I have empirical evidence against
it.
2. But any such evidence would itself have to consist in propositions
belief in which was directly or indirectly justified by my sensory
experience.
3. Since any such experience will encounter its own BIV hypothesis,
if any sensory experience could justify me in believing not BIV, my
such‐and‐such sensory experiences as of Cube could, too.
4. But, as we have seen, my such‐and‐such sensory experiences as
of Cube cannot justify me in believing not BIV.
5. So, there is nothing other than my such‐and‐such sensory
experiences as of Cube to justify me in believing not BIV.
Page 8 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
2. RESPONSES TO EPH SKEPTICISM
EPH skeptical arguments presuppose that whatever justifies you in believing
P if you really do know P will also justify you in believing P if the skeptical
hypothesis H is true, and vice versa. Let us call this the same‐justification
assumption (SJA). It will be helpful to restate SJA in the following Williamson‐
inspired way. In order to make my discussion more concrete, I will be
concerned with SJA only with respect to External World. The EPH skeptic
launches External World against the presupposed background of a best‐
case scenario (BCS): a scenario that is consistent with BIV but is otherwise
optimal for my having perceptual knowledge that there is a red cube before
me, if there is a red cube before me (so, if there is a red cube before me
and I cannot know it there, then I cannot know it anywhere). The skeptic
then envisages two incompatible further descriptions of BCS. Let us adopt
Williamson's untendentious labels and call one of these further descriptions
Good and the other Bad:
•
Good: BIV is false and I perceive, and thus know, that there is a red
cube before me (Cube, for short).
•
Bad: BIV is true (and therefore I do not know Cube), but otherwise
my situation is as much like Good as it's possible for it to be.
Then SJA, applied to BCS, has it that, if anything justifies me in believing
Cube in either realization of BCS—that is, either in Good or in Bad—then it
also (p. 191 ) justifies me in believing Cube in the other, and that that one
thing is the fact that I am having such‐and‐such sensory experiences as of
Cube.3
Most responses to External World accept SJA.
This is true of the contextualist response, which finds indexicality in
External World and holds that it expresses a sound argument in certain
“high‐standards” contexts, such as a context in which skepticism is being
discussed (like there is another context in which you would find External
World?).
It is true of the only way of denying premise (1)—namely, denying the
closure of justified belief under known entailment—which I think is advocated
only by Fred Dretske.4
It is true of the only way of denying premise (2), the “dogmatism” whose
proponents include John Pollock, Jim Pryor, Tyler Burge, and Christopher
Peacocke.5
Page 9 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
It is true of the inference‐to‐the‐best‐explanation response to premise (3),
which claims that, while the evidence is the same in Good and Bad, we
are justified in believing not BIV because the commonsense explanation of
the fact that I am having my sensory experiences as of Cube, according to
which my experience is a veridical perception, can be said to be a better
explanation than BIV of that fact just on the basis of an invidious comparison
of BIV with the commonsense explanation with respect to theoretical virtues
and vices.6
And it is true of the response to premise (3)—flirted with by Crispin Wright
and accepted by others7—which holds that by default we are a priori justified
in disbelieving BIV simply by virtue of the presuppositional status the
commonsense material world hypothesis enjoys in our belief system.
For the record, I do not find any of these responses plausible.
There are, however, in principle two different ways to deny SJA, and either
would enable one to challenge premise (3). One way is to claim that I have
no justification for believing Cube in Good which I also have in Bad, even
on the assumption that the fact that I am having such‐and‐such sensory
experiences as of Cube justifies me in believing Cube in Bad. This is the so‐
called disjunctivism of John McDowell and others, according to which I may
be justified in believing Cube, and thus in disbelieving BIV, in both Good and
Bad, but that what justifies me is different in the two cases, a perception of
a red cube in the one case, and a hallucination of a red cube in the other,
these not being states that share a qualitative sensory state that would itself
provide justification for believing (p. 192 ) Cube.8 I think that disjunctivism is
an implausible response to skepticism for several reasons, two of them being
that it yields no response to Induction and an extremely strained response to
Other Minds.
The second way of denying SJA holds (i) that, even in Bad I am justified in
believing Cube, (ii) that what justifies me in believing Cube in Bad is the fact
that I am having such‐and‐such sensory experiences as of Cube, (iii) that
that justification is also a justification for believing Cube that I have in Good,
but (iv) that in Good there is another, knowledge‐securing justification for
believing Cube, which I do not have in Bad, that justifies me in believing
Cube. No one to my knowledge has ever responded to EPH skepticism in this
way—unless this is the response to which Timothy Williamson is committed
by the theory of evidence and the reply to skepticism he advances in
Knowledge and its Limits.
Page 10 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
3. E = K AND WILLIAMSON'S IMPLIED RESPONSE TO EPH
SKEPTICISM
With respect to the skeptical argument External World, the same‐justification
assumption (SJA) holds that whatever justifies me in believing Cube if I
really do know Cube will also justify me in believing Cube if the skeptical
hypothesis H is true, and vice versa.
Williamson does not consider skepticism in its EPH form, nor does he
explicitly consider SJA. He does, however, consider a version of external‐
world skepticism that accepts what we may call the same‐evidence
assumption (SEA)—namely, that the evidence one has in Good is exactly the
same as the evidence one has in Bad. Applied to External World, SEA holds
that whatever is evidence for Cube for me in Good is also evidence for Cube
for me in Bad, and vice versa.
In responding to the version of skepticism he considers, Williamson argues
that the skeptic goes wrong in accepting SEA. The falsity of SEA follows from
two tenets of Williamson's theory of evidence:
EV E is evidence for P for S if and only if (i) S's evidence includes E
and (ii) Probold(P/E) >Probold(P).
E = K S's evidence includes E if and only if S knows E.
For suppose I know Cube (and am thus in Good and not in Bad). Then, by
E = K, my evidence includes Cube. And, since it is clear that Probold(Cube/
Cube) > Probold(Cube), it follows from EV that Cube is evidence for Cube
for me. Indeed, I can have no better evidence for Cube than Cube: since
Probnew(Cube) = Probold(Cube/Cube) = 1, Cube is conclusive evidence for me
that Cube. Thus, I have conclusive evidence for Cube in Good that I (p. 193 )
do not have in Bad—namely, Cube. And, since Prob(¬BIV/Cube) = 1, I also
have conclusive evidence for not BIV in Good that I do not have in Bad.
We are concerned with the External World instance of EPH—that is to say,
with:
1. I am not justified in believing Cube unless I am justified in
believing not BIV.
2. I am not justified in believing not BIV unless something other
than the fact that I am currently having such‐and‐such sensory
experiences as of Cube justifies me in believing not BIV.
3. There is nothing else to justify me in believing not BIV.
4. ∴ I am not justified in believing Cube.
Page 11 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
It is clear that Williamson would deny the conclusion of this valid argument.
But which of its premises would he deny? Given what he says about
“intuitive closure” (p. 119), we may infer that Williamson would accept (1).
What about (2)? I am not sure whether Williamson would accept or reject this
premise. It presents one problem for him if he accepts it, and another if he
rejects it. To see why, we need first to appreciate that, as already intimated,
the crux of his reply to the argument will be his denial of premise (3). Here,
I believe, he would claim that there is something other than the fact that I
am having such‐and‐such sensory experiences as of Cube to justify me in
believing Cube, because in Good my justification for believing Cube includes
evidence that I do not have in Bad—namely, that there is in fact a red cube
before me. I will elaborate on this presently. In the meantime, let us return to
the problem (2) presents.
I said that (2) presents one problem for Williamson if he accepts it, and
another if he rejects it. The problem in both cases turns on how Williamson
can account for my being justified in believing Cube in Bad. (It is clear that
it is possible for there to be a token of Bad in which I believe Cube—for
example, one in which I am only recently envatted—and that when I do I will
be justified in believing Cube, unless skepticism is correct and it is impossible
for anyone to have a justified perceptual belief about the external world.
And, of course, if I am justified in believing Cube in Bad, then, by the closure
principle JCB, I am also justified in believing not BIV in Bad.) Now, the crux of
Williamson's response to the version of skepticism he considers is that one
has evidence in good cases that one does not have in bad cases precisely
by virtue of having perceptual knowledge in good cases. The implication is
that this is what is required to respond to the skeptic—and presumably to the
skeptic about justified belief, as well as to the skeptic about knowledge. If,
therefore, Williamson can account for my being justified in believing Cube in
Bad in a way that does not entail the evidential difference he finds between
good and bad cases of perceptual belief, then he will have shown that the
response he gives to skepticism in his book is not required to account for
how perception can justify us in believing propositions about the external
world. That is the problem Williamson would (p. 194 ) encounter if he denies
premise (2), thereby endorsing a claim that entails that no evidence provided
by my knowing external‐world propositions is required for me to be justified
in believing not BIV. So it would seem that Williamson is constrained to
accept premise (2) on the grounds that I can be justified in believing not
BIV only by evidence provided by my knowing external‐world propositions
—in other words, on the grounds that one cannot have justified beliefs in
bad cases unless one has knowledge in good cases. He has a plausible
Page 12 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
way of making that case, but only if it is plausible for him to claim that it is
impossible for me to believe Cube if I have been a brain in a vat my whole
life. We know the twin‐earth case to be made for that impossibility; the
trouble is that there is some doubt about how good it is when applied to
propositions like Cube or BIV. On the other hand, if it is possible only for the
recently envatted to believe propositions like Cube, then Williamson might
reasonably argue, say, that it is precisely by virtue of knowledge gained in
good cases that one can be justified in believing that one is not a brain in a
vat.9 In any case, I propose that this issue be bracketed for the rest of this
chapter and that we proceed on the assumption that Williamson can justify
his accepting (2) provided he can justify his not accepting (3).
So how, specifically, might Williamson argue against premise (3) of External
World? It would not be eristically effective to argue against (3) in a way
that presupposed that I was justified in believing Cube, but, if Williamson is
justified in doubting (3), then he should have at hand an argument to show
that the EPH skeptic has not shown herself to be warranted in asserting (3).
He would have such an argument if he could argue that the EPH skeptic
failed to see that there was something other than the mere fact that I am
having sensory experiences as of Cube that would be available to justify me
in believing Cube if I was in Good and thus knew Cube. And it is apt to seem
that Williamson has such an argument if his theory of evidence is correct,
an argument that in effect showed that his case against SEA also provided
the wherewithal for a case against SJA. The argument to which I allude is as
follows:
1*. If I am in Good and thus know Cube, then Cube is conclusive
evidence for me that Cube.
2*. If Cube is conclusive evidence for me that Cube, then Cube
is available to justify me in believing Cube and thus, via JCB, in
believing not BIV.
3*. ∴ That part of SJA is false that claims that whatever can justify
me in believing Cube if I am in Good and thus really do know Cube
will also be available to justify me in believing Cube if I am in Bad
and BIV is true.
4*. The EPH skeptic's case for premise (3) of External World
presupposes that false part of SJA.
•
(p. 195 )
5*. ∴ The skeptic is unwarranted in asserting premise (3) (since her
case for it relies on an unwarranted false assumption).
Page 13 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
Let us call this argument W. Might the EPH skeptic have a way to question
W?
I think she may; I think she might well have doubts about W's premise (2*).
Given that E is conclusive evidence for P for me if my evidence includes E
and Prob(P/E) = 1, then it does follow from Williamson's theory that Cube
is conclusive evidence for Cube for me. And it does seem right that, if E is
conclusive evidence for P for me, then E is a conclusive justification that I
have for believing P. But in distinguishing the three justification relations IS,
HAS, and IN, we saw that E can be a justification that one has for believing
P but yet not be what justifies one in believing P, even when one is justified
in believing P. So, while Williamson's theory of evidence might entitle him to
claim that Cube is a conclusive justification that I have for believing Cube,
given that I know Cube, he has not thereby shown that Cube is available to
justify me in believing P, given that I know Cube. Even when we grant his
theory of evidence, we may still question whether Williamson is in a position
to claim that Cube is something that may justify me in believing Cube, given
that I know Cube.
But is it not analytic that, if E is conclusive evidence for P for me, then E at
least stands available, as things are, to justify me in believing P? Actually,
it is not true, let alone analytic, that E stands available to justify me in
believing P if E is conclusive evidence for P for me. For suppose I see that my
patio is wet and on the basis of that evidence come to know, and thus to be
justified in believing, that my patio is wet because it rained during the night.
If Williamson's EV and E = K are correct, then the fact that my patio is wet
because it rained during the night is conclusive evidence that my patio is
wet; in fact, evidence does not get any better than that. But the fact that my
patio is wet because it rained during the night is not—and cannot be, given
the facts of the story—what justifies me in believing that my patio is wet.
What justifies me in believing that my patio is wet, and all that is available in
the circumstances to justify me in believing that my patio is wet, is that I saw
that it was.
In fact, Williamson himself implicitly acknowledges that E's being conclusive
evidence for x for P does not secure that E stands available to justify x in
believing P. The following passage leaves little doubt that Williamson would
agree that the awkward symmetry noted in the patio example presents a
counterexample to the claim that, if E is conclusive evidence for P for me,
then E is available to justify me in believing P:
Page 14 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
If all knowledge is evidence, then EV . . . [has] the effect of
making evidential interconnections within one's knowledge
symmetric. For Prob(P/Q) > Prob(P) if and only if Prob(P &
Q) > Prob(P)Prob(Q); since the latter condition is symmetric
in P and Q, Prob(P/Q) > Prob(P) if and only if Prob(Q/P) >
Prob(Q). Thus, given that S's evidence includes both P and
Q, P is evidence for Q for S if and only if Q is evidence for P
for S by EV. Consequently, given that one knows P and Q and
that all knowledge is evidence, (p. 196 ) EV implies that if
P is evidence for Q for one then Q is evidence for P for one.
We could avoid this result by modifying EV. For example, we
could stipulate that E is evidence for H for S only if S's belief
in E does not essentially depend on inference from H. But
it might be neater to retain EV unmodified and say that E is
independent evidence for H for S only if S's belief in E does not
essentially depend on inference from H. (p. 204)
If we accept Williamson's theory of evidence, then in Good Cube is conclusive
evidence for Cube for me. But we have just seen that even Williamson must
admit that something can be conclusive evidence for P for me yet incapable
of justifying me in believing P. So, given that we accept Williamson's theory
of evidence and given that E is conclusive evidence for P for me, what else
must be true of E in order for it to be able to justify me in believing P?
Williamson's “independent‐evidence” fix suggests that he would say:
•
E justifies S in believing P only if E is independent evidence for P for
S,
from which it follows that
•
Even if E is extremely strong or conclusive evidence for P for S,
E is incapable of justifying S in believing P if E is not independent
evidence for P for S.
(E is independent evidence for P for S if and only if (i) E is evidence for P
for S and (ii) S does not believe E on the basis of P (“S's belief in E does not
essentially depend on inference from” P).)
Can we also say that
•
E is capable of justifying S in believing P if E is extremely strong or
conclusive independent evidence for P for S,
Page 15 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
or are there still further necessary conditions that extremely strong or
conclusive independent evidence must satisfy if it is to be capable of
justifying S in believing P? I believe that the following three examples
show that the displayed condition is false and that, therefore, some further
condition is required.
Raven example. Suppose I know that the next observed raven will be black
on the basis of knowing that all observed ravens have been black. It is surely
preposterous to say that even part of what justifies me in believing that the
next observed raven will be black is that the next observed raven will be
black (what justifies me in believing that the next observed raven will be
black is that all observed ravens have been black). But the fact that the next
observed raven will be black is for me conclusive independent evidence that
the next observed raven will be black.
Smithers example. I know (because his instructor told me) that Smithers
failed his logic final and on that basis know, and am justified in believing,
that a D is the best grade he can receive in the course (D, for short). I also
independently know that Smithers did not study for the final, and that is
pretty good evidence for me that D. But there is this asymmetry between the
two evidence facts. The fact that Smithers failed the final has its evidential
status for me regardless of (p. 197 ) whether or not Smithers studied for
the final: I can infer D from that whether or not I even believe that he did
not study, but I could not infer D from the fact that he did not study unless
my reason for believing that he failed the final was just that he did not
study for it. Here the fact that Smithers did not study may be strong enough
independent evidence for D for me—independent because I did not infer that
he did not study from D—but, nevertheless, incapable in the circumstances
of justifying me in believing D because of the way it is screened off from the
only thing in the circumstances that could justify me in believing D—namely,
the fact that Smithers failed the final.
Coke example. I infer, and thereby come to know, that the Coke machine
is sold out from the fact that the machine's “Sold Out” sign is lit. I would be
justified in inferring that the machine is sold out from the fact that it says it is
sold out whether or not the machine is sold out; but, as I have no other way
in the circumstances of inferring that the machine is sold out, I justifiably
would not believe that the machine was sold out unless I inferred that from
the fact that the machine says it is sold out. Now, in the circumstances, the
fact that the Coke machine is sold out is conclusive independent evidence
for me that the Coke machine is sold out, but that is not what justifies me
Page 16 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
in believing that the machine is sold out. What justifies me in believing that
is that the machine says it is sold out. So, once again, we see that E can be
conclusive independent evidence for P for S yet incapable of justifying S in
believing P.
Let me suggest then the following criterion, which assumes that Williamson's
theory of evidence is correct (and which uses “infer” in Williamson's sense, a
sense some might think is better expressed by “on the basis of,” especially
as regards the way in which sensory experiences function to justify the
beliefs they induce10):
E ≠ J Even if E is very strong or conclusive independent evidence
for P for S in circumstances C, E is incapable of justifying S in
believing P in C if in C there is evidence E′ such that (i) S can
become justified in believing P in C only by inferring P from E′, and
(ii) S's becoming justified in believing P in C by inferring P from E′
doesn't depend on E's being true.
Thus, in the raven example, E = P = the fact that the next observed raven
will be black, and E′=the fact that all observed ravens have been black; in
the Smithers example, E = the fact that Smithers did not study for the final,
E′=the fact that Smithers failed the final; and P = the proposition that a D is
the best grade Smithers can receive in the course; and, in the Coke example,
(p. 198 ) E = P = the proposition that the Coke machine is sold out, and E
′=the fact that the machine says that it is sold out.
Now, by definition of Good, I know Cube (= that there is a red cube before
me) in Good and do not infer Cube from Cube, and therefore, given
Williamson's theory of evidence, Cube is conclusive independent evidence
for Cube for me in Good. But if E ≠ J is correct, Cube is not available in
Good to justify me in believing Cube. For (i) in Good I come to be justified in
believing Cube by inferring it from the fact that I am having such‐and‐such
sensory experiences as of Cube, and I cannot become justified in believing
Cube in Good other than by inferring it from that evidence; and (ii) my
becoming justified in believing Cube by inferring it from the fact that I am
having those sensory experiences does not depend on Cube's being true—
I would become justified in believing Cube by that inference even if all else
were the same except that Cube was false.
So I provisionally conclude that, while Williamson may have given us reason
to disbelieve SEA—the assumption that I have the same evidence for Cube
in Good and in Bad—he has not given us good reason to disbelieve SJA—
the assumption that what justifies me in believing Cube in Good is the same
Page 17 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
as what justifies me in believing Cube in Bad. Applied to the argument W
—the argument one might think one discerns in Williamson—we see that
Williamson has not entitled us to think that W is sound, because, even if we
concede his theory of evidence and allow that in Good Cube is conclusive
evidence for Cube for me, he still has not entitled us believe that premise
(2*) is true. Further, since it is plausible that one knows a proposition only if
one is justified in believing it, Williamson also has not shown that it is even
possible for me to be in Good.
4. SOME POSSIBLE REPLIES
I reckon the probability that Tim Williamson will accept my argument to show
that he has not provided a solution to EPH skepticism to be, say, ≤ 0.000013.
But how will he respond to it? If I have correctly represented how he would
respond to EPH skepticism, he must either deny that the application of E ≠
J to Good shows that Cube is incapable of justifying me in believing Cube in
Good, or else he must deny the criterion E ≠ J.
There are in principle two ways to deny my claim about the application
of E ≠ J to Good. One might deny that condition (i) is satisfied by arguing
that I can become justified in believing Cube in Good in some way other
than by inferring it from Experience (= the fact that I am having such‐and‐
such sensory experiences as of Cube), or one might deny that condition (ii)
is satisfied by arguing that Cube does have to be true in order for me to
become justified in believing Cube in Good by inferring it from Experience.
Both ways seem unpromising to me.
The first way requires my becoming justified in believing Cube in
some way other than by inference from Experience. What could such a way
possibly be? It cannot be that one becomes justified in believing Cube in
Good by inferring it from Cube. If one did infer Cube from itself, then Cube
would not be independent evidence for itself, and thus, evidently, ruled out
on that account as being that which justifies me in believing it. There are
cases where it is perhaps not unreasonable to suppose that the fact that
P justifies believing P. One might hold that what justifies one in believing
that one is in pain is just the fact that one is in pain. But, in the first place,
perceptual beliefs do not seem at all like that, and, in the second place,
Williamson seems not to be in a position felicitously to hold even that the
fact that Sally is in pain justifies her in believing that she is in pain. For what
is not altogether implausible is that what justifies Sally in believing that
she is in pain is just the fact that she is in pain; but it does not seem at all
(p. 199 )
Page 18 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
plausible that what justifies Sally in believing that she is in pain is that she
knows that she is in pain and infers that she is in pain from the fact that
she is in pain. One can hardly become justified in believing a proposition
by inferring it from itself. I suppose Williamson would have to say that Sally
has underived knowledge that she is in pain and that that is what makes her
justified in believing that she is in pain. To reconcile this with his doctrine
that only evidence can justify, he could say that the fact that she is in pain
justifies her in believing that she is in pain somehow by virtue of its being
conclusive evidence that she is in pain, but not by virtue of her inferring that
she is in pain from that evidence. One wants to hear more, but in any case
the model does not fit my knowing Cube by perception.
The second way to deny my claim about the application of E ≠ J to Good—
denying that condition (ii) is satisfied—strikes me as even more unpromising.
If I am not justified in believing Cube in Bad, it will be because the EPH
skeptical argument is sound. If it is possible for me to be justified in believing
Cube at all, then I am surely justified in believing it in Bad. Should I learn
that BIV was true, I certainly would not conclude that I was not justified in
believing Cube. But if I am justified in believing Cube in Bad, then it is surely
by inference (given Williamson's theory of evidence, which I am taking as
given). So, as Cube is false in Bad, Cube's being true cannot be a necessary
condition of my becoming justified in believing Cube by inferring it from
Experience. And, if it is not a necessary condition in that way in Bad, then
it is very implausible that something about Good makes it a necessary
condition in Good.
So much for denying the application of E ≠ J to Good. Perhaps denying
the criterion E ≠ J will yield a more promising response. There are, after
all, prima facie counterexamples to E ≠ J. For example, when asked what
justifies him in thinking that Alice kissed Ben, it might be appropriate for
Harold to reply that Alice informed him that she kissed Ben. Harold would
not have come to believe that Alice kissed Ben by inferring that Alice kissed
Ben from the proposition that (p. 200 ) Alice informed him that she kissed
Ben, since in order for him to believe that Alice informed him that she kissed
Ben he would already have to believe that Alice kissed Ben. This is apt to
appear to be a counterexample to E ≠ J because the fact that Alice informed
Harold that she kissed Ben is conclusive evidence that she kissed Ben (x
informed y that P entails P), but in the circumstances Harold could become
justified in believing that Alice kissed Ben only by inferring that she did from
the evidence that she told him that she kissed Ben, and Harold's becoming
Page 19 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
justified in that way in believing that Alice kissed Ben does not depend on its
being true that Alice kissed Ben.11
It is unclear whether the example provides a counterexample because being
asked what justifies someone in believing a proposition is a request for an
explanation, and we often appropriately respond to such questions in ways
that do not actually give the correct explanation or give the explanation
embedded in information that is not essential to the explanation, as when
we explain that the car will not start because something is wrong with the
ignition, or that the window broke because your niece Wilma kicked her
new orange soccer ball into the window. Still, a more systematic way of
challenging E ≠ J might proceed in the following way:
•
We need to distinguish the way in which x becomes justified in
believing P from that which justifies x in believing P. The idea is that
while I become justified in believing Cube in the same way both
in Good and in Bad—namely, by inferring Good from Experience
—the justification I acquire in that way in Good differs crucially
from that which I acquire in Bad. Roughly speaking, the justification
I acquire in Good includes the justification I acquire in Bad, but
has as an additional component the fact that Cube. I gain one
justification for believing Cube when I infer it from Experience,
but I gain an even better one when the fact that I had such‐and‐
such sensory experiences as of Cube was caused by the fact that
there was a red cube before me. Both in Good and in Bad I become
justified in believing Cube by inferring it from Experience, but in
Bad the justification I have for believing Cube consists just in the
fact that I had such‐and‐such sensory experiences as of a red cube,
whereas in Good it also contains the additional evidence for Cube
that is owed to the fact that my having such‐and‐such sensory
experiences as of a red cube was caused by the fact that there was
a red cube before me.
There may be more than one thing wrong with this response, but the main
thing wrong with it is that (a) I would not be justified in being more confident
of Cube in Good than I am in Bad, but (b) I would be so justified if I had a
better justification, one based on better evidence, for believing Cube in Good
than I (p. 201 ) have for believing it in Bad.12 Let me motivate (a) by starting
with a change of example.
I wake up one February morning and look out the window. I see that
Washington Square Park and the surrounding streets are covered in snow,
Page 20 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
and I infer that it snowed during the night. I have no positive reason,
skepticism aside, to suspect that it did not snow, but of course I am aware
of the possibility of various ways in which, compatible with what I seem to
see, it did not snow during the night, and thus the degree of confidence that
I am justified in having is less than complete confidence, though still pretty
high. Let us pretend that degrees of confidence can be measured by real
numbers in the interval [0, 1] and suppose I am justified in being confident
to degree 0.93 that it snowed during the night. Now, my description of the
scenario is compatible with two more complete descriptions of it. In one, it
did snow during the night, and that is why I see the snow. In this completion,
I count as knowing that it snowed during the night. In the other completion,
though I had no reason at all to suspect it, the snow did not fall from the sky
but was artificially manufactured and placed on the ground by a film crew
that was not visible when I saw the snow. By construction of the example, I
remain confident to degree 0.93 that it snowed in both completions. I submit
that my being justified in having that degree, but no greater degree, of
confidence is unaffected by which completion obtains. The parallel with the
ongoing Cube example should be obvious. I seem to see a red cube before
me and I have no reason (skepticism aside) to doubt that my experience is
veridical other than my knowledge of the possible ways in which it might
not be. So I am not justified in being absolutely confident that there is a
red cube before me, but I am justified in being pretty confident. Let us say
I am confident to degree 0.93. I submit that I remain justified in having
that degree, but no greater degree, of confidence in Cube, whether the
completing description of my situation places me in Good or in Bad.
So much for (a). Might (b) be denied? If my justification for believing Cube
in Good is better than my justification for believing it in Bad, then I am more
justified in believing Cube in Good than I am in Bad. By construction of the
example, my degree of confidence in Cube is the same in both Good and
Bad. If I am more justified in believing Cube in Good than I am in Bad, then
I should be more confident of Cube in Good. If I am less confident than I
should be, then I am not justified in having the degree of confidence I have.
As Silins makes clear,13 it would be rather bizarre to hold that my degree
of confidence in Cube is justified in Bad but not in Good. I see no reason to
suppose I am doing anything epistemically wrong in Good. On the contrary,
what would be epistemically wrong would be for me to be more confident of
Cube in Good than I am.
I suppose Williamson must disagree. After all, he says that, for any
proposition P, if you know P, then P has evidential probability 1 for you,
(p. 202 )
Page 21 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
and he also says that “rationality requires one to conform one's beliefs to
one's evidence” (p. 12), where by this he means that “the norm of credence
is to proportion one's degree of belief to the evidence.”14 This, I take it,
means that rationality requires me to believe Cube to degree 1 in Good.
Still, Williamson is explicit about our needing “a conception of rationality on
which we are not always in a position to know what it demands” (p. 15). So
perhaps he would say that, while I am being perfectly reasonable in believing
Cube only to degree 0.93 in Good, this is because I am not in a position to
know what rationality requires of me. But it is not clear that he can say that.
When Williamson acknowledges that we are not always in a position to know
what rationality requires of us, in requiring us to respect our evidence, it is
because we are not always in a position to know what our evidence is. Now,
for Williamson, who holds that E = K, if I do not know what my evidence is,
this can only be because I do not know what I know. But, in a normal case
of Good, I would not only know Cube, but would also know that I know Cube,
and therefore I would know what my evidence is, and thus, presumably,
would be in position to know what rationality requires of me. Could he argue
that I might know what my evidence is but still not know what rationality
requires of me, either because I do not know that the probability of Cube
on my evidence is 1 or that I do not know that “the norm of credence is to
proportion one's degree of belief to the evidence”? I doubt it. I doubt that
Williamson would want to say that the only people who are in a position to
know what rationality requires of them are those who accept his theory of
evidence and rationality. In believing Cube to degree 0.93 in Good, I seem
neither to be acting irrationally nor failing to know what rationality requires
of me. I see no reason to doubt that appearance.15
Notes:
(1) Williamson's equating a person's evidence with her knowledge—an
equation he calls E = K (p. 185)—is a cornerstone of his theory of evidence
(unless otherwise noted, all page references for Williamson are to Knowledge
and its Limits). The doctrine that only evidence can justify belief occurs in a
few places (e.g., p. 208), and is evidently also pretty central to Williamson's
theory. It has, however, a weak and a strong reading. The weak reading
is that if E justifies one's believing P, then E is known, and thus, by E = K,
belongs to one's total evidence. The stronger reading is that, if E justifies
one's believing P, then E is evidence for P for one. Williamson sometimes
gives the impression that he accepts the stronger reading, as when he says
that “evidence for a mathematical conjecture may consist of mathematical
knowledge” (p. 207), but here he is probably using “evidence” in a loose
Page 22 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
vernacular way, since on his account of evidence, nothing can be evidence
for a mathematical proposition, and no mathematical proposition can be
evidence for any proposition. This is because E is evidence for P only if it
raises the probability of P, in the sense that Prob(P/E) > Prob P, and for
Williamson every mathematical proposition has probability 1 or 0. The
fact that nothing can be evidence for a mathematical proposition may be
taken to be a problem for Williamson's theory of evidence, since we may
well want to say such things as that my evidence for P's being a theorem
of number theory is that the brilliant number theorist Jones told me that
it was. We needn't, however, bother about any of this, since all the issues
in this chapter about what a person is justified in believing pertain only to
contingent propositions.
(2) I hope my use of “a certain time t*” is clear enough. To do the
quantification over times properly would make for a less neat statement of
the argument. I shall omit temporal references when doing so is harmless.
(3) It seems clear that, if one can be justified in believing Cube in Good,
then one can also be justified in believing Cube in Bad, if one can entertain
Cube in Bad. A person who only recently became disembodied and envatted
can entertain Cube, but it may be arguable that a creature who has been
envatted its entire life would not have the concepts required to entertain
Cube. This issue matters with respect to a possible problem for Williamson
that I discuss below, but otherwise we should understand BIV in a way that
allows for me to entertain Cube in Bad.
(4) Dretske (1970). Robert Nozick (1981) denies closure for knowledge but
not for justified belief.
(5) Pollock (1986), Pryor (2000), Burge (2003a), and Peacocke (2004).
(6) See, e.g., Vogel (1990).
(7) Wright (2004); see also, e.g., White (2006).
(8) McDowell (1982); see also Martin (2004).
(9) Nico Silins (2005) exaggerates the extent to which having to account for
justified beliefs in bad cases is a problem for Williamson.
(10) Many philosophers think that, e.g., a creature's having a visual
experience as of P can justify it in believing P even though it does not know,
or even believe, that it is having that visual experience. Williamson must
Page 23 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013
deny this, since he holds that E = K and that only evidence can justify a
belief. He argues against the claim that perceptual experience is a kind of
non‐propositional evidence on pp. 197–200.
(11) This sort of example was pressed on me by Anna‐Sara Malmgren and
Nico Silins.
(12) This objection derives from the “equal‐justification” problem Nico Silins
(2005) raises for Williamson's theory of evidence.
(13) Silins (2005).
(14) Williamson (2005b: 432).
(15) Earlier versions of this chapter were given as talks at Rutgers University
and the University of St Andrews, and presented in a seminar I gave at NYU,
all in fall 2005. The final version benefited from the discussions at those
events, and from written communications or comments from Adam Elga,
John Hawthorne, Anna‐Sara Malmgren, Nico Silins, and Dean Zimmerman.
Page 24 of 24
Evidence=Knowledge: Williamson's Solution to Skepticism
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2013.
All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a
monograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: null; date:
02 April 2013