Soc (2013) 50:602–609
DOI 10.1007/s12115-013-9718-1
SYMPOSIUM: FACTS, VALUES, AND SOCIAL SCIENCE
Sociology Rediscovering Ethics
Stephen Turner
Published online: 9 October 2013
# Springer Science+Business Media New York 2013
Gorski tells us that the fact-value distinction is dead, that we
know what human flourishing is and therefore relativism is
wrong, and concludes that sociologists ought to throw off their
self-imposed shackles and get into the business of telling other
people how to live their lives, but only after sociologists listen
to other people who are already in this business, especially from
ethics and religion. In one sense this advice is misdirected,
because, as I shall explain briefly below, sociologists have long
been concerned with exactly the thing he suggests they should
be concerned with, flourishing, eudaemonia or happiness, and
continue to produce research on the topic in several subfields of
the discipline. Morever, there have been many attempts to do
exactly what he is recommending. The results, however, including my own attempt with Mark Wardell in the 1980s,1 have
not been especially successful. In this comment I will try to
point out some of the philosophical obstacles to this kind of
work. The sociological obstacles are also serious: the intellectual cultures of ethics and sociology are so radically divergent
that dialog is virtually impossible. Nevertheless, there is no
reason to give up. In this respect I agree with Gorksi. My
dissenting point will be a simple one: there is are multiple
relations of fit between sociological ideas and ethical theories,
not just the one he describes, and some ethical theory is in
outright conflict with normal social science.
What has been tried? Attempts by sociologists to do exactly what Gorski is advocating would include, a generation ago,
Derek Philips’ attempt, in Toward a Just Social Order, 2 to
1
Wardell, Mark and Stephen Turner. 1986. Sociological theory in transition.
London: Allen and Unwin.
2
Philips, Derek L. 1986. Toward a just social order. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
S. Turner (*)
Department of Philosophy FAO 226, University of South Florida,
Tampa, FL 33620, USA
e-mail: turner@usf.edu
derive something from Alan Gewirth’s account of the ethics of
agency; Habermas’s discourse ethics, which is a form of
Kantian constructionism (meaning that it involves the results
that ideal speakers or thinkers would arrive at), and more
recently Oxford sociologist Stein Ringen’s What is Democracy
For?, 3 which also embraces Aristotle and flourishing. Moreover, there are philosophers who have a more or less sociological rather than moral realist approach. Gorski mentions two,
Charles Taylor and Alasdair MacIntyre. These thinkers might
provide a better opening for common discussion with sociologists, and indeed this is already happening with Habermas
and Taylor under the religion program of the Social Science
Research Council (SSRC).4 One might add Phillip Pettit,
whose idea of common knowledge resembles Durkheim’s
collective conscience.5 Pettit is non-relativistically against
domination, but leaves the determination of what that is to
mean in a particular state up to common knowledge, i.e., the
culture, of the citizens of that state. These are not exactly
negligible figures, and their ideas have had public influence:
Pettit’s ideas have been taken up by the Spanish government;
Ringen’s by the Norwegians.
Surveying this mass of writing will not be my concern here.
The real interest of Gorski’s article lies elsewhere, with the
problem of the relation between social theory and sociology
and various hard meta-ethical claims, and specifically with a
subset of these claims. Among the various writers Gorksi
mentions, there is a prominent group of ethicists who are
3
Ringen, Stein. 2007. What is Democracy for? On freedom and moral
government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
4
Cf. VanAntwerpen, Jonathan. 2010. Varieties of secularism in a secular
age. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 2011. The power of
religion in the public sphere. New York: Columbia University Press.
http://blogs.ssrc.org/tif/author/vanantwerpen/
5
Pettit, Philip. 1997. Republicanism: a theory of freedom and government.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Soc (2013) 50:602–609
“moral realists” (and beyond them Kantians of various kinds,
notably constructionists, a term with a quite different meaning
than its sociological one). The questions raised by moral
realism (and these forms of Kantianism) are novel and interesting for social theory, and perhaps for sociology, because of
the radical nature of their claims about motivation and the
explanation of human action. Moral realism in some of its
most prominent forms, to be brief about it, is a competitor to
sociological explanation and attempts to explain things that
sociologists traditionally thought they explained.6 There is a
strong, outright conflict between these claims and conventional social science and psychology.
I think the claims of many of these authors are irretrievably
confused when they are not false, and pernicious when they
reinforce moral dogmatism, which is their main rhetorical
function. But my concern here will not be with consequences.
Instead it will be with the ways in which these claims conflict
with, and assert superiority, over normal social science explanation. But before coming to this topic, it will be worthwhile
to review some of the methodological issues in the social
science literature itself over the problem of the relation between subjective and objective facts, especially in the case of
happiness.
Gorski’s State of the Field Account
If I may rather brutally reconstruct it, Gorksi’s argument is
this: we have entered a new era in which ethical truth of some
sort is readily available, because philosophers and religionists
have finally figured it out. This implies that the fact value
distinction is dead, because we can now treat at least some
things in ethics as fact-like. “Flourishing” is such a known
good. It is found in a “middle kingdom of moral facts, situated
somewhere between the realms of fact and value, an independent territory, containing discoverable truths about the good
life and the good society.” It follows that moral relativism is
wrong. We now also know that science is not value-free,
because it involves conflicting cognitive values. And because
non-cognitive values enter into our choices of research topics,
what we know is influenced by values even if we keep values
out of our actual claims. It follows that Weber’s scruples about
mixing factual and valuative claims are obsolete.
6
I leave the issue of theology for others, but note that the influential work
on Theology and Social Theory by John Milbank also claims that Christian sociology is a competitor to “secular” sociology, and derides the kind
of theology that “has sought to borrow from elsewhere a fundamental
account of society.” Milbank, John. [1990] 2006. Theology and Social
Theory: beyond secular reason, 2nd edn. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley &
Sons, p. 382.
603
Gorski cites various writers in ethics who hold to one or
another of the many (and conflicting) accounts of moral
realism, and points also to eudaimonianism, which is something else entirely, as well as to the Sen-Nussbaum idea of
capabilities from development ethics. Do these citations, and
others he might have made as representing current ethics,
support the idea of such a middle kingdom and the idea that
the fact value distinction is dead? And what exactly is in this
middle kingdom, and how does it get discovered?
Answering this question is more difficult than one might
think. Begin with the question of what sort of consensus,
however contested, exists. First it is necessary to distinguish
ethics from meta-ethics. Meta-ethical theories or theories
about the nature of morality are highly diverse, and conflict
wildly. But the tradition of analytic philosophy is to test such
theories against our ethical intuitions. So the aim of all of these
accounts is to come up with (or explain the fact that people
accept) more or less the same ethical conclusions. Virtue
theories, deontological or obligation theories, and consequentialist theories explain the same thing: conventional morality.
Moreover, there are reasons why they mostly converge: after
all, a pattern of behavior that was obligatory but systematically hurt others would soon be seen to be bad and to be altered,
and the virtue of the people who pursued it questioned. Good
results, for example the benefits of courteous driving, would
come to be seen as obligatory. These basic senses of what is
right and good tend to be stable and congeal into intuitions,
which in turn can be used to “test” ethical theories by asking
whether the claims made by the ethical theory, the “analysis” it
provides, actually fits the intuitions. There are, however, marginal differences in the range of intuitions that are explained by
different meta-ethical approaches, and this is the basis for preferring one meta-ethical account over another. This is why cases
such as the Trolley problem7 are so important for ethics: they are
the relatively rare cases in which there are clear conflicts between intuitions, and one set of intuitions is explained by one
metaethical theory and the other by a different one.
In short, in this cozy world of ethical theory (as distinct from
applied ethics) there is no big conflict over first order ethical
questions. But this is only because these are the rules of the
game of meta-ethics: the one with the best match to our
intuitions wins. However, not every ethical account plays by
these rules. MacIntyre, for example, does not: instead he
problematizes conventional liberal morality. Other ethical or
at least philosophical positions are also in outright conflict with
conventional norms. One example is the kind of philosophy
that promotes “authenticity.” Authenticity demands something
different than the fulfillment of conventional obligations or
having the politically correct attitudes, and indeed is normally
set against them. Applied ethics is a different story as well. Our
7
cf. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Trolley_problem; http://people.
howstuffworks.com/trolley-problem.htm
604
intuitions about abortion, for example, radically conflict: it is a
human life, but the consequences of birth may be bad for
everyone involved. Here is where convoluted arguments and
religious ideology prosper, and disagreements seem insoluble.
Leave aside the fact that “our” intuitions are the intuitions
of comfortable, mostly secular westerners in academic positions. If one obliterates a few differences at the first-order
level, and ignores ethical accounts that don’t buy this standard
for evaluating ethical theories, one could indeed say that there
is something like a consensus about the requirements of
ethics, with a lot of people outside the consensus. One could
even detect something like a much more modest miniconsensus on the meta-ethical level, on something like “moral
realism.” Forms of moral realism do indeed make claims to
the effect that there are moral facts, and all of them reject the
characterization of the moral sphere in terms of “values” that
are grounded solely in the individual decisionistic acts of
valuation of individuals—the picture we inherit from Weber.
So Gorski is right to think there is something different here,
and that there is a conflict between moral realism and Weber.
But what the conflict implies is not clear. The fact value
distinction is perhaps the place one needs to begin.
Start with a contradiction. Gorski mentions the idea that
science or scientific theories fulfill cognitive values, and that
these sometimes conflict. He cites this as evidence of the
inseparability of fact and value. But this claim actually creates
a problem for him: it assumes that the conflicts between
cognitive values are not “factually” decidable, and also assumes that value questions are different in kind from factual
ones, however much values enter into science. The use of the
concept of cognitive values in theory choice in science observes the same distinction: values are not empirical facts.
And here the emphasis of the literature goes against Gorski’s
general point: cognitive values conflict and have to be chosen
between on non-factual grounds rather than converge into
some sort of quasi-factual valuative truth.
This fits with thinkers in ethics as well, where the literature
reproduces the fact value distinction in all but name. Ethical
theorists are insistent that ethical questions cannot be settled
by reference to “natural” facts. So they also insist on a distinction. They even say that a separate epistemology is needed
to establish normative truths.8 One should thus not be misled
by the discussion of the term “fact”: whatever sorts of facts
ethical facts are, they are taken to be different in kind from the
facts of sociology, even and indeed especially by the people
who think they are very hard facts.
There is a big reason for the fact value distinction within
ethics itself: G. E. Moore’s open question argument. There are
many interpretations of this argument, but the basic claim is
this. If we say that something natural—a source of pleasure, for
8
Copp, David. 1990. “Normativity and the very idea of moral epistemology.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy XXIX: 189–210.
Soc (2013) 50:602–609
example—is good, we mean that it feels good; there is always
an open question as to whether it is really good. If we present
(factual) evidence that people think a particular kind of pleasure
is good, it can still be asked whether they are right, and whether
this is just a subjective feeling. This bears directly on the utility
of the most interesting recent findings on neuroscience and
morality. Fehr and Gächter have shown that people experience
pleasure by punishing free-riders.9 This explains an important
mystery about morality: from a pure rational choice perspective, for the individual, expending the effort to punish free
riders is not commensurate with the benefits, so it is irrational.
But people do it. If punishing is itself a source of pleasure, the
empirical mystery is solved. This, then, is a real mechanism for
enforcing norms operating in the real world. But one can ask, á
la Moore, whether it is really good to punish free riders. No
ordinary fact, either about game-theoretic rationality or our
neurophysiology, can answer that question.
Empirical Eudaemonism
Moore’s argument opens up a breach between the facts of
morality, which presumably would answer this question, and
the actual operative facts of moral life, that is to say what
people really do, really are motivated by, and so forth. The
open question argument removes questions about the good
from any consideration that could be settled by ordinary facts,
and reaffirms the distinction between ethical “facts,” if there
are such things, and ordinary facts. The open question argument thus creates an unbridgeable divide right in the heart of
the middle kingdom Gorski describes, and places the ethical
on the non-empirical side of this gap. Nothing about subjective happiness, subjective flourishing, and so forth, can possibly answer the question of whether it is really good.
Eudaimonism and the capabilities approach seem to finesse
this problem, however. The capabilities approach doesn’t
answer the question of what one should do with one’s capabilities, other than preserve them, so it makes no claims about
Moore’s question. It leaves the choice of ends to the people
who are being made capable. Happiness and flourishing, on
the other hand, seem to be good by definition, and therefore no
conflict with empirical facts is possible.
One problem with this happy solution is that if one asks
people about happiness, they give quite different answers than
this account would, if it were an empirical theory along the
lines of Ringen’s.10 Ringen compares countries using an index
of his own devising, representing his ideas of the good life and
the good society. But is he right? Contrast his results, which
9
Fehr, Ernst and Simon Gächter. 2000. “Cooperation and punishment
in public goods experiments.” The American Economic Review, 90(4):
980–94.
10
Ringen, Stein. 2007. What is Democracy for?
Soc (2013) 50:602–609
rate Scandinavia high and everyone else low, with a recent
Gallup survey comparing countries. It found that seven of the
ten happiest were in Latin America, and the list included poor
countries with little in the way of Sen-Nussbaum capabilities.
Why are they so happy? The traits that correlated most were
these: being well rested; being treated with respect; smiling;
laughing a lot; learning new things; and feelings of enjoyment
on a daily basis. The countries that reported the highest rates
of “yes” answers to these questions were Panama and Paraguay, with an 85 % positive rate each. El Salvador and
Venezuela were next, followed by Trinidad and Tobago, Thailand, Guatemala, the Philippines, Ecuador and Costa Rica.11
What does one say about this? That these people are not
really happy, or flourishing? That their subjective experience
does not matter? That they are afflicted with false consciousness and would be better off listening to Mahler by night and
pushing government paperwork around by day? This seems
absurd, at least for an ethics that purports to be about
flourishing and happiness. In short, the trick of making happiness and flourishing good by definition means that one has
left the specification of these terms to some other kind of
consideration. “Objective” specifications of these things, such
as Ringen’s attempt to tell us the conditions of flourishing,
turn out to be ideological or cultural, or merely expressions of
personal taste. One can of course give up on objectivity and
accept that the natural facts of people’s subjective experience
are decisive. But this is to give up on moral realism and more
generally on the idea that ethics can be a guide of some sort.
Subjective and Objective
Yet there is more to the story. Gorski alludes to the fact that
psychologists don’t have a problem giving advice, but says
nothing about the long-running literature on human happiness,
which is nicely summarized in recent work by Eric Angner.12
This literature includes a lot of sociology: the literature on
marital happiness was a central part of prewar sociology, for
example,13 and various forms of this kind of life satisfaction
research have continued to the present. Gerontologists made
assessing well-being a centerpiece of the field, producing a
plethora of measures, conceptualizations, and so forth. The
concept was largely taken over by the mental health literature,
which derived from a variety of sources, but which contained a
11
Clifton, Jon. 2012. “Latin Americans most positive in the world.
Singaporeans are the least positive worldwide.” Gallup World December
19, 2012.
http://www.gallup.com/poll/159254/latin-americans-positiveworld.aspx
12
Angner, E. 2011. “The evolution of eupathics: The historical roots of
subjective measures of wellbeing.” International Journal of Wellbeing,
1(1): 4–41. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=799166
13
Burgess, E. W. and Cottrell L. S. 1939. Predicting success or failure in
marriage. New York, Prentice-Hall.
605
large sociological component. But there were direct attempts as
well. As Angner explains the history, Hornell Hart, a professor
of sociology at Duke University, constructed operational definitions of happiness in his Chart for Happiness, 14 and asked
the eudamonian question social scientifically: “One of the
basic purposes of mankind is to be happy. Can recent advances
in scientific thinking tell us more and more effectively what to
do in order to be happy, and in order to help make our fellow
human beings happy?”.15 Angner summarizes the motives
behind this literature thus: “The main impetus behind measures
of happiness and satisfaction appears to have been a moral
impulse to understand and improve society, specifically, an
ambition to identify the causal antecedents of happiness in
order to build a happier, and therefore better, society.”16
The contributors to this vast literature were not crippled by
Weberian scruples. They were attempting to construct objective measures that corresponded to the kinds of valueconstituted facts about the social world we are interested in
explaining. This is the Weberian recipe: valuative concepts
and interests are the starting points and both motivate and
serve to conceptually order the material; but the explanations
and descriptions are objective, and the “scientific” conclusions do not go beyond these objective facts. Doing this
research requires no novel range of discoverable objective or
quasi-objective moral facts. It simply requires utilizing our
audiences’ and subjects’ subjective ideas about what is good.
What is wrong with this approach? The answer of the moral
realists would go something like this: all this research can do is
deal with subjective feelings. Moral truths are hard realities of
their own. They are accessible in a totally different way: reflection on our intuitions. If we leave the answer at this, we simply
have two different problems that are unrelated to one another:
the non-empirical facts of moral truth and the empirical facts of
subjective happiness. But moral realism in its most aggressive
form does not leave things at this. Moral realism claims that the
truth of moral realism is an explanatory necessity: that there are
real non-normative facts that can only be explained by the
existence of normative realities or forces of a particular type.
This is not a claim that is taken seriously or even addressed
by empirical researchers. It depends on tricky circular arguments of various kinds (but mostly involving supposed explanatory necessities) which I have discussed at length elsewhere.17 But the issues can be more simply seen in a parallel
problem in the current psychological literature on “moral
error” and moral judgment. The moral realist would pounce
on this usage and say that the term “moral error” presupposes
moral truth, so that appealing to moral truth is an explanatory
necessity in the study of moral error, and moral error is a real
14
Hart, Hornell. 1940. Chart for happiness. New York: The Macmillan
Company.
15
Hart, Chart for happiness, 1940: 16.
16
Angner, “The evolution of eupathics,” 2011: 21.
17
Turner, Stephen. 2010. Explaining the normative. Oxford: Polity Press.
606
fact, not just a normative claim. There is a typical argument in
ethics to the effect that one cannot have a counterfeit coin
without there being a real one, and that therefore to acknowledge moral error is to acknowledge moral truth.18
This claim is specious, but specious in a way that is
common to these arguments: it conflates moral error as
an objective concept with moral error from a point of
view, such as the point of view of the person making the
error. Empirical work on this problem does not require,
and is not helped by, claims about objective moral standards. The point is nicely made by the psychologists
Pizzaro and Uhlmann, commenting on work by Cass
Sunstein.
We do not wish to debate the virtues and vices of any
normative moral theory—this is a task best left to philosophers. However, we do question the necessity of
positing a normative framework for understanding the
psychology of moral judgment. Does a good theory of
moral judgment require an objectively “right” set of
moral criteria with which to compare lay judgments?
Perhaps not. We believe that the research reviewed by
Sunstein is extremely informative without the additional
claim that individuals are making mistakes. For example, knowing and predicting the conditions under which
individuals rigidly adhere to principles despite consequences is important for any successful moral theory. So
the fact that individuals are willing to accept a (slightly)
increased risk of dying in order to punish a betrayal is
quite provocative—but does it add more value to claim
that this is an error?19
Subjective error and the subjects’ own standards do all the
explanatory work.20 The extra explanatory work that the claim
of explanatory necessity made by moral realists or normativists
depends on is a product of description: describing something
as “error” as such rather than the empirically equivalent “error”
from the point of view of lay judgments.
Moral Realism and Motivation
Moral realism comes in various forms, but the bottom line—
and traditional problem21—has been the question of how
these supposed objects or properties (or whatever they are—
Soc (2013) 50:602–609
accounts vary on this as well) interact with the causal or
human world. Moral realism is not merely the belief that there
are moral truths. It is the belief that they refer to something
real. Moreover, the belief in moral realism normally involves
the claim that the moral realities in question are explanatory
necessities—that, contrary to the argument of Pizarro and
Uhlmann, there is something true in the empirical world that
cannot be true unless there are the relevant moral realities.
There are many solutions to this problem, none of which
are appealing to both sides of this discussion. One solution,
from the naturalistic side, is to treat the “realism” as an
illusion: Michael Ruse has suggested that moral realism is a
product of evolution: “human beings function better if they are
deceived by their genes into thinking that there is a disinterested objective morality binding upon them, which all should
obey,”22 and as he said later, that “Substantive morality stays
in place as an effective illusion because we think that it is no
illusion but the real thing.”23 Ruse thought this error was
important to holding societies together, so this kind of error
had an evolutionary point. The major recent text in ethics is
Derek Parfit’s On What Matters. 24 Parfit thinks that these
forms of moral realism rest on an error: conflating motivation
with moral truth. His view is that moral truths are just true.
They don’t need to be motivational forces, any more than an
empirical truth is. For him, there are moral facts, but they are
causally and motivationally inert. What influences action is
belief in the facts, not the facts themselves.
Parfit’s is a radical position. The usual arguments for normativism, when normativists get around to considering the problem
of explaining action at all, do involve motivation, and reject this
idea that moral truths are motivationally inert. This is the link to
the empirical world. Current Kantians say things like this
. . . the normativity of obligation is, among other things,
a psychological force. Let me give this phenomenon a
name, borrowed from Immanuel Kant. Since
normativity is a form of necessity, Kant calls its operation within us—its manifestation as a psychological
force—necessitation.25
The religious roots of this idea are evident. Paul writes to the
Corinthians that anything good that they do is done with the
aid of the Holy Spirit. The Holy Spirit, in short, is a causal
force in the world, without which some things would not
happen. This gets slightly secularized in Kant: the idea of duty
arising from the rational moral law is also the incentive to act.
18
Cf. Strawson, P. F. ([1962] 1982) “Freedom and resentment. Reprinted in
Gary Watson, ed., Free Will, Cambridge: Oxford University Press, pp. 59–80.
19
Pizarro, D.A. and Uhlmann, E. 2005. “Do normative standards advance our understanding of moral judgment?” [commentary] Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 28: 558.
20
See Pizarro, D.A. and Uhlmann, E. 2005, “Do normative standards
advance our understanding of moral judgment?”.
21
Beiser, Frederick C. 2009. “Normativity in neo-Kantianism: its rise and
fall.” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17(1): 9–27.
22
Ruse, Michael and Wilson, Edward O. 1986. “Moral philosophy as
applied science.” Philosophy, 61(236): 173–192, 179.
23
Ruse, Michael. 2010. Science and spirituality: making room for faith in
the age of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 310.
24
Parfit, Derek. 2011. On what matters, 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
25
Kant, Immanuel [1797] 1991. The metaphysics of morals, trans. Mary
J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 06: 219.
Soc (2013) 50:602–609
This leaves out the Holy Spirit, but leaves the mystery of how
all this arising and incentivizing works. Needless to say, this
sort of claim runs directly into the claims of psychology and
social science, which never invoke such forces, nor do they
think they need to. The standard account of intentional action
in psychology makes do with belief in norms, as does the
conventional belief-desire model of action explanation. Sociologists are content with saying that people believe things, and
act accordingly, As Mauss’s famous formulation put it, the
task of sociology is to see what people believe and who
believes it. For sociology in the Maussian sense, goodness is
irrelevant: beliefs about goodness do the work of explaining
action, and beliefs can be explained without resorting to
claims about the intrinsic correctness of the belief.
The arguments take various forms. One involves action
explanation itself, where the issue is this: does “agent y
believes x is good” explain everything about agent y’s behavior that “x is good” explains? Elaborate arguments are given in
support of the idea that “x is good” explains something more
than “y believes x is good” and that “x is good” constitutes a
sufficient explanation such that inquiring into how y came to
believe x is good adds nothing and is a unneeded distraction
from the correct “x is good” explanation.26 Needless to say,
these anti-sociological not to say anti-intellectual arguments
are not found in social and behavioral science.
The problems with the “real” in moral realism, come down
to this: the reason we can treat moral things—obligations, for
example (and this is the usual example)—as “real” is that we
“feel” them as real. There are of course explicit obligations,
written into contracts, laws, and so forth. But feelings of
obligation, such as the obligation to return an invitation after
being invited to dinner, are tacit, and although they can be
articulated in etiquette books, what makes them binding or
real is the tacit feeling that the etiquette book articulates, not
the rule in the book itself. This tacit sense provides the
motivation for calling obligations or other moral demands
“real.” But this produces another problem. If there is something here other than a subjective psychological fact about
feeling, a “real” obligation behind the feeling, so to speak,
how does the real thing interact with good old causal reality?
Do people bump up against these real things? Are they
stopped or propelled by them?27
607
The idea that moral reality took the form of motivation
seemed like an answer—the only answer—to these questions.
People give moral reasons; reasons are simultaneously explanations, justifications, and motivators. So moral “reality”
could sneak into explanation, into “the real,” under the guise
of “good reasons” for action. One would then argue that good
reasons were sufficient to explain the actions they justified;
that no further explanation was needed, or that they were
themselves a force. Motivation thus tells you what a moral
reality has to be—a cause that is dependent on no prior causes,
a prime mover unmoved. These accounts have the bonus that
our motivations are in some sense internal, and therefore
available to reflection, which allows for the thought that we
can establish universal facts about morality and the nature of
normative truth merely by reflecting on our own motivations.
And this bonus is difficult to give up: it provides the ethical
theorist with a ground for ethical claims. In short, the motivation account solved a problem in ethics at the price of
conflicting with ordinary social science explanations of action
and belief.
Of course there are multiple conflicting varieties of moral
realism or, more broadly, what I call normativism. What is
common to them is the idea that they are describing facts or
moral truths that have motivational force of some sort. As one
might expect, there are numerous strange variations on these
motivational ideas in the philosophical literature. One is that
semantics provide motivational force.28 Searle used to invoke
collective intentionality, which he claimed to be based on
special neuronal capacities.29 Searle now claims that intrinsic
neuronal conditions of satisfaction for representations provide
this force.30 The strangeness comes from the same source:
these are attempts to simultaneously explain ordinary facts
and normative facts about validity.
The issues with these claims divide into two groups: one set
of claims of motivation involve universal forces or facts; the
other involves local ones, for example those which arise from
the semantics of a particular language, for example, or a
particular social group with an ethical scheme to which people
are committed and which secures its validity or bindingness
from this commitment. The “local” accounts are a kind of
pseudo-sociology. The “universal” accounts are a kind of
pseudo-psychology or cognitive science. But with these accounts some useful dialog with cognitive science has begun.
Perhaps the same could happen with social science.
26
Cf. Raz, Joseph (2009) “Reasons: explanatory and normative. In
Constantine Sandis (ed.) New essays on the explanation of action, New
York: Palgrave/McMillan, pp. 184–202, 184.
27
These are of course familiar Durkheimian questions as well. Cf. Turner,
Stephen. 1993. Emile Durkheim: sociologist and moralist, London:
Routledge; Turner, Stephen and Bertha, Carlos. 2005. “The socratic
Durkheim,” In Terry Godlove (ed.) Teaching Durkheim, New York: Oxford
University Press, pp. 171–85. But the Durkheimian answer to Kant is found
in Marcel Mauss’s 1967, The gift: forms of function and exchange in
archaic societies, New York: W. W. Norton & Company, as I show in
Explaining the normative, 2010: 59–63, 140.
28
Wedgewood, Ralph. 2007. The nature of the normative . Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
29
Searle, John. 1990. “Collective intentionality and action.” In P. Cohen,
J. Morgan, and M. Pollack (eds.) Intentions in communication ,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, p. 402; Searle, John. 1995. The construction
of social reality. New York: The Free Press, p. 407; Turner, Stephen.
2002. Brains/Practices/Relativism, Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, pp. 40–41, 46–47.
30
Searle, John. 2010. Making the social world: the structure of human
civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
608
Soc (2013) 50:602–609
What Can Sociology and Ethics Say to Each Other?
Does moral realism provide the sort of nearly achieved
consensus on ethics that sociologists can engage with as
though it contained almost-facts? It is difficult to see what
sort of engagement this would be: the basic idea of moral
realism is that moral facts are real and that they have a role in
the actual world of motivation. Sociologists already think that
there are norms and values that explain people’s behavior.
Even rational choice/game theoretic philosophers of norms
rely on the sociological definitions.31 The major difference
between them and moral realists is that moral realists think
that (some) norms have a quality of rightness that in itself
explains something about motivation.
There is a huge gap here, and there is a conflict between
explanations. There is no prospect of closing the gap in some
cases, such as the Kantianism of the formulation from
Korsgaard quoted earlier. The same is true of many other
forms of normativism: they are attempts to explain social
science facts by occult means, or by fictions such as
contractarianism, by pseudo-sociological theories or by bad
theories. Naive functionalism makes frequent appearances in
these arguments, for example in James Rachels famous discussions of relativism.32 But the very fact that these arguments
are offered in the first place is intriguing: very few forms of
ethical argument can work without making factual and explanatory claims that resemble those of social theory and
sociology. And in many cases the gap can be closed.
One case is surprising: even among the Kantians, it is
possible to close the gap. David Velleman offers a “kindaKantian” account in which humans seek intelligibility or
mutual intelligibility.33 This is only “kinda” Kantian because
it substitutes a weak but psychologically plausible motivator
for the strong but psychologically implausible motivator of
reason itself. Better yet, intelligibility can be taken to be
simultaneously psychological and normative. This approach
to human interaction would be congenial to, if not the same as,
the kind of depiction of human sense-making one finds in
Erving Goffman, or even some forms of ethnomethodology.34
Velleman’s case is suggestive: there is a whole range of
possible relations between ethical theory and sociology, from
a close fit and mutual enrichment to stark opposition. One
model, closely related to this one, is found in Derek Phillips
and in Stein Ringen35: find an ethical doctrine one likes and
apply it with the help of sociological knowledge about such
things as income distributions, but without any hope of talking
back to the original doctrine. This one-directional relation, it
should be noted, is all that is allowed by much of ethical
theory. Kantian dogmatism, for example, which purports to
generate moral truth out of the resources of reason itself, has
no use for empirical knowledge except in applying “reason.”
Another model would be the one represented by Taylor and
MacIntyre36: these are themselves exercises in social theory
that attempt to explain moral ideas. So is Richard Joyce’s
recent, important, The Myth of Morality.37 Utilitarianism and
rational-choice approaches have a close affinity if they are not
the same. Yet another model is represented by Heidegger and
existentialism: to attend the empirical facts of the world, das
Man or the ordinary social person in Heidegger, in order to
transcend their limitations. One could go on at length with this
list: various meta-ethical doctrines, such as virtue theory,
expressivisms of various kinds, and so forth, match up with
or conflict with different social theories or sociological
approaches.
The classic figures of social theory can also each be identified with an ethical theory that more or less closely fits their
social theory. Marx followed a tradition of Saint-Simonianism
that historicized ethics, but his notions of species-being and
disalienation fit with the kind of critique and rejection of
conventional morality found in “authenticity” thinking.
Durkheim’s dualism between the social and individual consciousness is genetically linked to the idea that normativity is
rooted in collective intentions through Durkheim’s successor
and follower Bouglé.38 MacIntyre described Weber as an
emotivist: today he might say he was an expressivist. Weber’s
follower Jaspers was an existentialist, and this fits Weber as
well. And there are overt conflicts. Spencer divided sociology
from ethics when he argued that intuitions, the evidential base
for ethical theory, evolved.
This much is true about Gorski’s argument. There is something to say, sometimes, between ethics and sociology. With
the exception of dogmatic Kantians and religious dogmatists,
ethical theory has to connect to empirical reality, either
through claims about human nature or in other ways, such as
31
35
Philips, Derek L. 1986. Toward a just social order. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press; Ringen, Stein. 2007. What is democracy for?
on freedom and moral government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
36
Taylor, Charles. 2004. Modern social imaginaries. Durham, NC: Duke
University Press, 2004; MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After virtue. Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
37
Joyce, Richard. 2001. The myth of morality. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
38
Bouglé, C. 1926. The evolution of values: studies in sociology with
special applications to teaching, trans. Helen Sellars. New York: Henry
Holt& Company
Bicchieri, Christina. [1993] 1996. Rationality and coordination 2nd
edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Bicchieri, Christina. 2006.
The grammar of society: the nature and dynamics of social norms. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
32
Rachels, James. 1999. “The challenge of cultural relativism.” In The
elements of moral philosophy, 3rd edn. NY: Random House, pp. 20–36;
Rachels, James. 1986. “Morality is not relative.” In The elements of moral
philosophy, 1st edn., New York: McGraw Hill, pp. 451–60.
33
Velleman, J. David. 2009. How we get along. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
34
Cf. O’Neill, John. 1974. Making sense together: an introduction to
wild sociology. New York: Harper & Row.
Soc (2013) 50:602–609
through claims about intuitions, or simply because for such
things as happiness, too much distance from subjective experience is absurd, or because the extended notion of “reason”
on which Kantian ethics trades has to bear some resemblance
to the way people actually reason. Sometimes the connections
are more close, so much so that ethical writers are indistinguishable from sociologists. But the sheer diversity of views
in ethics as well as in social theory means that there is no
simple meeting ground. The fact that sociologists have
retreated from theorizing the normative since the days of
Talcott Parsons perhaps means that they have little new to
add. But the classical writings, especially those rooted in the
rebellion of social scientists against Kantianism, for example
609
in Mauss’s The Gift, still have relevance. If Gorski’s programmatic statement helps to revive interest in these issues, it will
have done a great service.
Stephen Turner is Distinguished University Professor in Philosophy at
the University of South Florida. His books include the standard history of
American Sociology, The Impossible Science, with Jon Turner, The
Social Theory of Practices 1994, and many articles and chapters and
several books on Weber, including two with Regis Factor, Max Weber
and the Dispute Over Reason and Value: A Study in Philosophy, Ethics,
and Politics, 1984.and Max Weber: The Lawyer as Social Thinker, 1994.
His most recent book is Explaining the Normative, 2010.