The Moral Staus of Animals by Martha Nussbaum 2006
The Moral Staus of Animals by Martha Nussbaum 2006
The Moral Staus of Animals by Martha Nussbaum 2006
Craig R. Sholley
By Martha C. Nussbaum
This essay originally appeared in the Chronicle of Higher Education,
February 3, 2006. Our many thanks to Dr. Nussbaum for permission
to offer it here.
In my new book, Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership, I consider three urgent problems
of justice involving large asymmetries of power: justice for
people with disabilities, justice across national boundaries, and justice for nonhuman animals. During the past
35 years, theories of justice have been elaborated and
refined with great subtlety and insight, stimulated by John
Rawlss great books, which built, in turn, on the classical
doctrine of the social contract in Locke, Kant, and Rousseau. The social-contract tradition has enormous strength
in thinking about justice. Devised in the first instance to
help us reflect on the irrelevance of class, inherited wealth,
and religion to just social arrangements, its theories have
been successfully extended, in recent years, to deal with
inequalities based on race and gender. The three issues
that are my theme, however, have not been successfully
addressed by such theories, for reasons inherent in their
very structure or so I argue.
In each case, a capabilities approach I have developed
provides theoretical guidance. It begins from the question,
What are people actually able to do and to be? It holds
that each person is entitled to a decent level of opportunity
in 10 areas of particular centrality, such as life, health,
bodily integrity, affiliation, and practical reason.
On the question of animal entitlements, the approach
gives better results than existing Kantian theories
which hold that respect should be given to rational beings
or Utilitarian approaches which hold that the best
choice is to maximize the pleasure or satisfaction of preferences. A capabilities approach can recognize a wide range
of types of animal dignity, and of what animals need in
order to flourish, restoring to Western debate some of the
complexity the issue had in the time of Cicero, which it
has subsequently lost.
As Richard Sorabji argues in his excellent book Animal
Minds and Human Morals: The Origins of the Western
Debate (Cornell University Press, 1993), the ancient
Greek and Roman world contained a wide range of views
that held promise for thinking about the moral status of
animals. However, Stoicism, with its emphasis on the
capacity of humans for virtue and ethical choice, exercised
far more widespread influence than any other philosophical school in a world of war and uncertainty but it had
a very unappealing view of animals, denying them all
capacity for intelligent reaction to the world, and denying,
in consequence, that we could have any moral duties to
them. Because of the attractiveness of Stoicisms view of
human virtue and choice, that picture of animals became
widespread. I think we need to add to Sorabjis account
the fact that Stoic views of animals fit better than others
with the Judeo-Christian idea that human beings have
been given dominion over animals. Although that idea has
been interpreted in a variety of ways, it has standardly
been understood to give humans license to do whatever
they like to nonhuman species and to use them for
human purposes.
Kant argues that all duties to animals are merely indirect
duties to human beings: Cruel or kind treatment of animals
strengthens tendencies to behave in similar fashion to our
fellow humans. So animals matter only because of us.
Kant cannot imagine that beings who (as he believes) lack
self-consciousness and the capacity for ethical choice can
possibly have dignity, or be objects of direct ethical duties.
The fact that all Kantian views ground moral concern in
our rational and moral capacities makes it difficult to treat
animals as beings to whom justice is due.
Classical Utilitarianism has no such problem. It begins,
admirably, with a focus on suffering. Its great theoretical pioneers, Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, had
intense concern for the well-being of animals. Bentham
famously argued that the species to which a creature
belongs is as irrelevant, for ethical purposes, as race: It
does not supply a valid reason to deprive a sentient being
of a decent life. If, as Utilitarianism holds, the best choice
is the one that maximizes total (or, in some versions, average) utility, understood as pleasure and/or the absence
of pain, good choice would lead to radical change in our
treatment of animals. Peter Singers courageous work on
animal suffering today follows the Utilitarian paradigm.
Singer argues that the right question to ask, when we think
about our conduct toward animals, is, What choice will
maximize the satisfaction of the preferences of all sentient
beings? That calculation, he believes, would put most of
our current pain-inflicting use of animals off limits.
Nevertheless, valuable though Utilitarian work on animal
suffering has been, it has some serious difficulties. One
notorious problem concerns the Utilitarian commitment
to aggregation: that is, to summing together all pleasures
and pains. The choice maker is instructed to produce the
largest total (or average) pleasure. That can allow results
in which a small number of creatures have very miserable
lives, so long as their miseries are compensated for by a
great deal of pleasure elsewhere. Even slavery is ruled out
if it is only by fragile empirical calculations urging
its ultimate inefficiency. It remains unclear whether such
a view can really rule out the cruel treatment of at least
some animals, which undoubtedly causes great pleasure
to a very large number of meat eaters, or the infliction of
Jurek Wajdowicz
Jurek Wajdowicz
individual creature: in Rachelss words, moral individualism. Utilitarian writers are fond of comparing apes to
young children and to mentally disabled humans, suggesting that the ethical questions we should consider are the
same in all those cases. The capabilities approach, by
contrast, with its talk of characteristic functioning and
forms of life, seems to attach some significance to species
membership as such.
What type of significance is that? There is much to be
learned from reflection on the continuum of life. Capacities
do crisscross and overlap: A chimpanzee may have more
capacity for empathy and perspectival thinking than a
very young child, or than an older child with autism.
And capacities that humans sometimes arrogantly claim
for themselves alone are found very widely in nature.
But it seems wrong to conclude from such facts that
species membership is morally and politically irrelevant.
A child with mental disabilities is actually very different
from a chimpanzee, though in certain respects some of
her capacities may be comparable. Such a childs life is
difficult in a way that the life of a chimpanzee is not
difficult: She is cut off from forms of flourishing that,
but for the disability, she might have had. There is something blighted and disharmonious in her life, whereas the
life of a chimpanzee may be perfectly flourishing. Her
social and political functioning, her friendships, her ability
to have a family all may be threatened by her disabilities,