Rakova Philosophy of Mind A Z
Rakova Philosophy of Mind A Z
Rakova Philosophy of Mind A Z
Marina Rakova
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
Volumes available in the Philosophy AZ Series
Christian Philosophy AZ, Daniel J. Hill and
Randal D. Rauser
Epistemology AZ, Martijn Blaauw and Duncan Pritchard
Ethics AZ, Jonathan A. Jacobs
Indian Philosophy AZ, Christopher Bartley
Jewish Philosophy AZ, Aaron W. Hughes
Philosophy of Religion AZ, Patrick Quinn
Forthcoming volumes
Aesthetics AZ, Fran Guter
Chinese Philosophy AZ, Bo Mou
Feminist Philosophy AZ, Nancy McHugh
Islamic Philosophy AZ, Peter Groff
Philosophical Logic AZ, J. C. Beall
Philosophy of Language AZ, Alessandra Tanesini
Philosophy of Science AZ, Stathis Psillos
Political Philosophy AZ, Jon Pike
Philosophy of Mind AZ
Marina Rakova
C Marina Rakova, 2006
Philosophy of Mind AZ 1
Bibliography 195
Series Editors Preface
the science of the mind, and Marina Rakova has done us all
a service in providing a clear and comprehensive guide to the
terminology.
Oliver Leaman
Introduction
All the students I have ever taught and who have taught me
that things have to be both clear and informative, and that
this is the only way.
Marina Rakova
Philosophy of Mind AZ
A
Abduction: the notion introduced by Peirce to classify syllo-
gisms of the type: (1) As are Bs; (2) Cs are Bs; (3) therefore,
Cs are As. Although this form of reasoning is formally
fallacious, Peirce viewed it as pertaining to scientific dis-
covery. Abductive reasoning is also characteristic of our
everyday reasoning as inference to the best explanation
on the basis of limited evidence. Being non-algorithmic,
which is not easily formalisable through the application
of a set of rules, sensitive to context and ones overall
knowledge, it presents problems for the computational
theory of mind.
cat cause of cat did not hold, the law dog cause
of cat would not hold either, but if the law dog cause
of cat did not hold, the law cat cause of cat would
hold anyway. To deal with Twin-Earth cases, the third
condition states that some tokenings of a mental repre-
sentation R must be actually caused by Rs.
Further reading: Fodor (1987)
B
Background, The: the notion introduced by Searle to des-
ignate a set of abilities, skills, dispositions and presup-
positions which, being non-intentional, are necessary to
16 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
C
C Fibres see Pain
Someone who can think that cats eat fish must have
the concepts cat, eat and fish. Small capital letters are
the accepted notation used to distinguish concepts from
words and discussions centre on (1) concepts expressed
by predicates (is a cat), (2) lexical concepts expressed
by simple morphemes and corresponding to a languages
lexicalised vocabulary. Many issues about concepts are
part of the larger issue of content and intentionality,
but the problem is also addressed in cognitive psychol-
ogy and the questions of what concepts are and what it
is to possess a concept are answered differently by the
older image theory and definitional theory and the more
recent functional role semantics, prototype theory, ex-
emplar theory, theory theory and informational atom-
ism. Arguably, a theory of concepts must explain con-
cept robustness (stability of content), compositionality
and shareability (in order to communicate different peo-
ple must have the same concepts). However, according
to Fodor, only informational atomism meets these con-
straints. Thus most theories connect having concepts with
having knowledge or epistemic capacities: someone who
has the concept cat knows how to tell cats from non-
cats, what judgements are true of cats, what typical cats
look like and what other features they have. Psycholo-
gists sometimes talk about conceptual change which is
characteristic of childrens acquisition of adult-like con-
cepts (conceptions) and adults scientific development.
But what knowledge or beliefs are constitutive of con-
cept possession? If this view leads to holism, the connec-
tion between psychology and epistemology may seem less
convincing.
Further reading: Margolis and Laurence (1999);
Murphy (2002)
D
Davidson, Donald (19172003): American philosopher, the
originator of anomalous monism. In his philosophy of
language, Davidson employs the notion of truth definition
developed by Alfred Tarski (190183) for analysing truth
in formalised languages (for example, Snow is white is
true iff snow is white; convention T). But whereas Tarskis
analysis is neutral on the issue of mental representation,
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ 41
Dualism: the view that the mental and the physical consti-
tute two different realms of reality. Substance dualism is
the view, associated with Descartes, that minds and bod-
ies belong to completely distinct kinds the immaterial
thinking substance and the material extended substance
which, nonetheless, can enter into causal interactions
(Cartesian interactionism). Attribute dualism (double- or
dual-aspect theory) is the view, associated with Spinoza,
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ 51
E
Ecological Perception see Direct Perception
Embodiment: the fact that we are not pure minds but minds
embedded in bodies. The thesis that organisms cognition
is shaped by their gross bodily form allows for readings
of different strength. Thus Dana Ballard argued that ori-
enting movements may constrain the way information
about objects is processed at a less abstract level than
that of symbolic reasoning (local problem-solving mech-
anisms). The more radical views are that concepts emerge
from embodied schemas (George Lakoff, Mark Johnson)
or that intelligent action does not require representation
(dynamical systems, extended mind, direct perception,
Merleau-Ponty).
Further reading: Ballard et al. (1997)
level above the biological level) has its own novel causal
properties irreducible to those of a certain constellation
of lower-level properties. Note that emergentism viewed
reduction as an explanatory rather than ontological is-
sue: consciousness is emergent and irreducible because we
cannot explain why a certain level of complexity of physi-
ological organisation should possess it. This distinguishes
emergentism from many versions of contemporary non-
reductive physicalism, although both approaches face the
problem of accounting for the irreducibility of the mental
without violating the causal closure of the physical.
Further reading: Broad [1925] (1976)
nor short.) The same difficulty later arose for logical pos-
itivism (see definitional theory). In order to explain con-
ceptual content one must recognise a set of innate primi-
tive (non-decomposable) concepts whose identity remains
constant across experiences. For Locke and Hume these
were sensory concepts (concepts of colour, taste, shape,
etc.), but the difficulty they had with deriving from them
the supposedly complex concepts (like those of whole and
part) still remains in force.
Further reading: Barsalou (1999); Cowie (1998)
Explanatory Gap: Joseph Levines term for the view that noth-
ing known about the physical world can explain phenom-
enal consciousness. Some philosophers believe that the
gap cannot be closed because the existence of qualia can-
not be deduced from any physical facts.
Further reading: Levine (1983)
F
Factive see Propositional Attitudes
Faculty Psychology: the view that the mind is divided into sep-
arate faculties or capacities (perception, memory, imag-
ination, judgement) developed by Franz Joseph Gall
(17591828) into phrenology the theory that different
faculties have discrete brain localisation and their promi-
nence correlates with cranial prominence (bumps on the
skull).
G
Gestalt: perceived configuration arising from a spatial ar-
rangement able to give rise to different interpretations. If
you look at an arrangement of lines and see a human face,
this representation has a gestalt quality (due to the brains
tendency to compensate for degenerate stimuli). Gestalt
or figure-ground switching, as in the famous duck-rabbit
switch, poses questions about the nature of visual con-
sciousness and the minds structuring of perceptual ex-
perience. The school of Gestalt psychology, founded by
Max Wertheimer, Kurt Koffka and Wolfgang Kohler in
1910, rejected associationism and held that psychological
structures generally are more than sums of their parts. Al-
though their view that gestalts exist in the world proved
erroneous, their study of visual illusion was an important
contribution to perception research.
H
Hallucination: the experience of having a perception of a
real-world object when no such object is being perceived
(Macbeth seeing a bloody dagger in front of him).
Holism: the view that the whole has priority over its parts.
Confirmation holism formulated by French physicist
Pierre Duhem (18611916) and Willard van Orman
Quine is the thesis that scientific theories stand the tri-
bunal of evidence as whole systems of beliefs. But holism
about belief confirmation must be distinguished from se-
mantic holism, the thesis that the content of a concept
depends on the concepts place within the whole system
of beliefs. Semantic holism is motivated by the view in
philosophy of language that the meaning of a sentence,
hence a word, depends on its role in a language (often
the combination of confirmation holism with verifica-
tionism about meaning), and the view that mental states
are individuated by their functional roles (functionalism).
Holism of the mental seems highly plausible: if some-
one has the belief that there is milk for the coffee in the
fridge, they must have a whole lot of beliefs about fridges,
coffee, milk and relations between them. But if this en-
tails semantic holism, something seems to be wrong, for
it follows that no two people, nor the same individual at
different times, share concepts. This conclusion appears
74 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
I
Idealism: the view that everything existing is mental in nature.
Idealism is traced to Platos theory of universals as pre-
ceding things, the view later developed by Leibniz, Kant,
Frege and Husserl. But this is transcendental idealism
which does not deny the existence of the physical world
and must be distinguished from the subjective idealism of
Berkeley (usually referred to as idealism), according to
which things exist only inside the mind. It is further dis-
tinguished from the absolute idealism of Hegel and other
nineteenth-century idealists.
that Fido means Fido does not explain how people rep-
resent Fido in thought), that it allows for the existence of
punctuate minds (minds with only one belief; the prob-
lem of the holism of the mental) and that it assumes
radical concept innateness.
K
Kant, Immanuel (17241804): German philosopher, the
founder of critical philosophy. In his later writings, Kant
distinguished four types of knowledge along the dimen-
sions of a priori, a posteriori, analytic and synthetic.
96 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
L
La Mettrie, Julien Offroy de (170951): French doctor and
philosopher, a defender of materialism. In LHomme ma-
chine (1748, Man a Machine) he argued that irritation
of the nerves can explain both reflexive and intelligent
behaviour, in animals and humans.
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ 101
M
Machine Functionalism: (inputoutput, empirical functional-
ism or psychofunctionalism): the variety of function-
alism which identifies mental states with higher-order
computational or functional states of a system. Putnam
proposed to view the mind as a probabilistic Turing ma-
chine where transitions between states occur with various
probabilities rather than being deterministic. Putnam saw
108 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
Monism: the view that there is only one kind of thing under-
lying all reality. It encompasses materialism and idealism
and is opposed to dualism.
Myth of the Given: Wilfrid Sellars term for the view that
sense experience gives us secure foundations for knowl-
edge (foundationalism). Sellars rejected it arguing that
experience gets conceptualised by reason and these con-
ceptualisations may be mistaken.
N
Nagelian Reduction: the first formulation of intertheoretic re-
duction proposed within the framework of logical pos-
itivism by Ernest Nagel (190185). According to it, a
higher-level theory (HT) can be reduced to a lower-level
theory (LT) if the laws of the former can be logically de-
rived from the laws of the latter via so-called bridge laws
(bridging principles) which establish empirical type-type
biconditional correlations between elements of the two
theories (FHT GLT ). The idea influenced many pro-
ponents of the identity theory (though not its originators),
but later lost its appeal because of multiple realisability
arguments and the fear (prompting eliminative materi-
alism) that it implies not only that mental phenomena
124 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
Naturalism: the view that the mental forms part of the nat-
ural order and that its explanation must be continuous
with explanations in natural sciences (be compatible with
physicalism).
Further reading: Papineau (1993)
O
Occasionalism: the view that all sequences of events conceiv-
able of as cause and effect are occasioned by God, to
whom alone causal powers must be ascribed. Occasional-
ism arose in Islamic thought in the ninth century, becom-
ing especially prominent in the philosophy of Abu Hamid
Muhammad Al-Ghazali (10591111). In modern philos-
ophy it was held by Johannes Clauberg, Arnold Geulinex,
Louis de la Forge and Nicolas Malebranche. Occasional-
ism may be best understood in the context of the theory
of ideas which views causal laws (including general laws
of the union of soul and body) as propositions in the
134 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
P
Pain: an unpleasant sensation normally arising from the ap-
plication of noxious stimuli to a group of sensory neurons
with peripheral terminals (primary afferent nociceptors,
types A and C). Pain has been the most discussed ex-
ample in the context of the mindbody problem since
behaviourism. Kripkes argument that pain and C-fibres
firing are related only contingently questioned the iden-
tity theory. Because damage to the pain pathway (spinal
cord, thalamus, cortex) will prevent cortically based pain
experience, this is true, but pain researchers do not agree
that pain cannot be identified with any physical property.
The reductivenon-reductive physicalism debate posed
other important questions: is there such a thing as pain
in general? do all pain-feeling organisms experience the
same pain and how can one determine what organisms
are capable of feeling pain? Viewing pain as a single
property prevents its reduction (for example, different
molecular mechanisms are implicated in different kinds
of headaches). However, there is also a strong intuition
that our mental concept of pain picks out a single prop-
erty. Functionalism captures this intuition, but cannot
explain pains phenomenal feel (pain does not disturb
frontal lobotomy patients; phantom limb pains are ap-
parently non-functional). Finally, whereas epiphenome-
nalism about pain is probably true (pain does not cause
withdrawal; but not if quantum information travels back
in time, as holds Stuart Hameroff), there is also an issue
of mental causation and placebo effects (how do beliefs
that some stuff will work cause pain to go away?).
136 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
qua problem: arises for the causal theory of reference and the
informational theory of content. The problem is to ex-
plain how we manage to refer to or represent a certain
kind of things, say, tigers qua tigers rather than qua ani-
mals as the same individual that serves to fix the reference
of tiger is both a tiger and an animal.
Further reading: Sterelny (1983)
R
Radical Interpretation: the thesis developed by Quine and
Davidson that the ascription of meanings to individual
words of a language is derivative from the ascription of
meanings to all words of that language. Because the as-
cription of mental states is similarly holistic, mental states
would be exhaustively ascribed to individuals by a radical
interpreter having at his disposal complete behavioural
linguistic evidence (interpretivism). As interpretation is
thought to be radical (from zero) and taking place within
a different linguistic medium, the indeterminacy of trans-
lation follows.
Relativism: the view that the way people perceive and think
about the world is determined by the language they speak
(linguistic relativism) or the practices of their community
(cultural or conceptual relativism), and that knowledge
160 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ
S
Sartre, Jean-Paul (190580): French philosopher who devel-
oped an existentialist version of phenomenology. Con-
cerned with the issues of intentionality and conscious-
ness, Sartre began with studying imagination where the
relation of consciousness to the non-existent is the most
evident. He opposed Husserl, whom he interpreted as
holding that reality is immanent to consciousness, and
later introduced the categories of the in-itself (en-soi), the
transphenomenal being of things extending beyond ap-
pearances, and the for-itself (pour-soi) or consciousness
constantly reconstituting the phenomenal being includ-
ing itself. With the pour-soi nothingness comes into be-
ing because it is the nihilation (neantisation) of the en-soi:
looking for someone who is not there we introduce noth-
ingness into the otherwise complete being. Sartres under-
standing of consciousness as non-substantial (one is not
a self but a presence-to-self) underlies his views on abso-
lute human freedom: at every moment one has to choose
oneself and is the true author of ones actions. Thinking
that ones actions are determined by ones external situ-
ation or ones internal nature is a kind of self-deception,
bad faith (mauvaise foi) which leads to anguish.
Further reading: Sartre [1943] (1953)
Solipsism: the belief that only ones own mind and immediate
experience really exist.
T
Tacit Knowledge: a set of internally represented innate know-
ledge structures that explain our folk non-scientific com-
petence in various domains of experience. Inspired by
Chomskys idea of universal grammar, developmental
psychologists proposed theories of folk physics (from in-
fancy peoples interaction with objects is guided by the
principles of continuity and solidity Elizabeth Spelke),
folk biology (essentialism Frank Keil) and folk psychol-
ogy (theory of mind).
Further reading: Keil (1989); Spelke (1990)
U
Unconscious: a state or process is unconscious if it belongs to
a low level of information processing and is in principle
unavailable to subjective awareness or if it is not expe-
rienced but could have been had attention been focused
on it. A person is considered unconscious if there is no
information processing at all and they are non-responsive
to themselves or the environment. Without further qual-
ification the term seldom has today the meaning given to
it by Freud.
V
Veil of Perception ( experience, appearance): the prob-
lem for theories of indirect perception from which it fol-
lows that there is something like a thin film of mental
entities separating perceivers from access to the external
world.
W
Wason Selection Task: a psychological tool for testing condi-
tional reasoning (evaluating conditional rules of the form
if P then Q) designed by Peter Wason in the 1960s. The
subject is presented with four cards, for example D, F,
3 and 7, and is asked to determine whether the rule if
D is on one side, then 3 is on the other side holds. The
subject is allowed to turn over only two cards. The right
cards are D and 7, but about 90 per cent of subjects
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AZ 191
Z
Zombies: beings physically identical to humans but lacking
phenomenal consciousness. If we can imagine them with-
out any contradiction, they are conceivable and thus pos-
sible. David Chalmers recently resurrected the zombie
idea as an argument against physicalism intended to show
that the identity of mental states with brain states cannot
be necessary because there is no a priori entailment from
physical to phenomenal facts. Critics question the move
from conceivability to possibility or address the special
nature of phenomenal concepts.
Bibliography
Useful collections
Bibliography