Department of Philosophy and Center For Ethics of Science and Technology, Chulalongkorn University, Thailand
Department of Philosophy and Center For Ethics of Science and Technology, Chulalongkorn University, Thailand
Department of Philosophy and Center For Ethics of Science and Technology, Chulalongkorn University, Thailand
Soraj Hongladarom
Department of Philosophy and Center for Ethics of Science and Technology,
Chulalongkorn University, Thailand
Abstract
The paper argues that there is a way to justify privacy without relying on the
metaphysical assumption of an independently existing self or person, which is
normally taken to underlie personal identity. I propose furthermore that
privacy is a contingent matter, and that this conception is more convenient in
helping us understand the complex issues surrounding deliberating
thoughtfully about privacy in many dimensions. It is the very contingency of
privacy that makes it malleable enough to serve our purposes. Basically, the
argument is that it is possible for there to be a society where individuals there
do not have any privacy at all, but they are still autonomous moral agents. This
argument has some close affinities with the Buddhist perspective, though in
this paper I do not intend to presuppose it. Then I discuss the issue of group
privacy. This is a rather neglected issue in the literature, but group privacy has
become more important now that contemporary genomics and bioinformatics
have the power to manipulate large amount of population data, which could
lead to discrimination. The proposed conception of privacy is more suitable for
justifying group privacy than the one that presupposes the inherently existing
individual.
Introduction
significant economic growth in recent decades. This concern has led many
scholars to ponder on how the concept of privacy and its implementation could
be justified, especially in the context of the East where privacy is generally
perceived to be a part of the modern West where Asia has had no exact
counterpart, a situation that prompted many papers on how privacy could be
justified in Asian contexts (E.g., Ess, 2005; Lü, 2005; Kitiyadisai, 2005;
Rananand, 2007; Nakada and Tamura, 2005; Hongladarom, 2007). What I
would like to accomplish in this paper is related to those attempts; however, the
paper is not intended as another contribution to how privacy is to be justified or
even criticized from the Asian perspective. It is instead an attempt to map out
the conceptual terrain of privacy without relying too heavily on the literature of
the traditions of Asia, which in fact has been my concern elsewhere
(Hongladarom 2007). That is to say, I intend what follows in the paper to be
generally applicable in most cultural contexts. This should not be taken to be an
argument for the supremacy of one culture over others; rather my concern is to
find out a common ground that should be acceptable for all cultures, without
privileging one over another.
The overall aim of this paper is, then, to present a philosophical analysis
and justification of privacy that differs from what is available in most literature
on the topic. I would like to be able to argue that this new conception appears
to be better suited to deal with problems arising from current technologies of
manipulation of personal information. It is well known that current
technologies, such as genetic databanking, smart ID cards, and others have
made it possible to collect, store, and systematize a vast amount of information
related to particular individuals. In Thailand, for example, the previous
government introduced what is called ‘smart ID cards.’1 Basically these are
supposed to function as identification cards for each and every Thai citizen,
which has been around in Thailand for decades. However, in recent years the
government ordered that a new type of card be issued with a microchip, which
is capable of storing a very large amount of information. The rationale was that
this new type of card would facilitate interaction with public agencies, as
important information that is required for an individual to contact the
1
“Thailand introduces national ID with biometric technology,” available at
http://www.secureidnews.com/weblog/2005/04/15/thailand-introduces-national-id-with-
biometric-technology/, retrieved May 9, 2007.
3
2
Rananand also discusses the situation in Thailand as a surveillance state and how this affects
the right to privacy in Rananand (2007), and Kitiyadisai gives a detail about the policy
concerning the smart ID card in Thailand in Kitiyadisai (2005).
3
A possible corollary to the argument presented here is that I am in favor of emphasizing the
right to privacy and its irreducibility to other rights. In fact there have been many debates on
whether there is such a thing as the right to privacy. See, for example, Thompson 1975; Scanlon
1975; Rachels 1975; Reiman 1976. However, there is not much literature on group privacy at all
at the moment.
4
I examined the core set of information in bioinformatics in Hongladarom (forthcoming).
4
Justifications of Privacy
5
Providing definitions of privacy appears to be a thriving academic industry. In a well known
article, Fried writes: “It is my thesis that privacy is not just one possible means among others to
insure some other value, but that it is necessarily related to ends and relations of the most
fundamental sort: respect, love, friendship and trust. Privacy is not merely a good technique for
furthering these fundamental relations; rather without privacy they are simply inconceivable”
(Fried, 1968, p. 477). In roughly the same vein, Parent states: “Privacy is the condition of not
having undocumented personal knowledge about one possessed by others. A person’s privacy
is diminished exactly to the degree that others possess this kind of knowledge about him,”
(Parent, 1983, p. 269) where personal information “consists of facts which most persons in a
given society choose not to reveal about themselves (except to close friends, family, . . .) or of
facts about which a particular individual is acutely sensitive and which he therefore does not
5
not want other people to peer into her house, or data about herself, her
‘personal’ information (Parent 1983). What justifies this right to privacy is that,
as an individual citizen, she is entitled to some form of protection against
unwanted intrusion, which is considered to be a breach to her autonomy. In a
hypothetical polity where the state has unlimited power to take any
information concerning its citizens as much as they like, and to have a
surveillance scheme, Big Brother style, that provides every detail of the lives of
the individuals, in that case it would be correct to say that the individuals do
not have any privacy. What is missing is that the individuals do not have a
means to operate without the seeing eyes of Big Brother. They do not have a
leeway, so to speak, within which they can function on their own without
always being aware that their action is constantly being watched. So we might
call what is missing here ‘personal space’ where the individual would feel to be
free to do their things as they please, so long, of course, that these do not
infringe on the rights and liberties of others. Talking about the potential loss of
privacy by employees due to increased use of surveillance technologies by the
employers, Miriam Schulman quotes Michael J. Meyer as follows: “Employees
are autonomous moral agents. Among other things, that means they have
independent moral status defined by some set of rights, not the least of which is
the right not to be used by others as a means to increase overall welfare or
profits” (Schulman 2000, p. 157). Meyer then continues: “As thinking actors,
human beings are more than cogs in an organization--things to be pushed
around so as to maximize profits. They are entitled to respect, which requires
some attention to privacy. If a boss were to monitor every conversation or
move, most of us would think of such an environment as more like a prison
then a humane workplace” (Schulman 2000, p. 157). The key phrase here is
‘autonomous moral agents,’ and in fact we could extrapolate Meyer’s statement
to include privacy for individuals in general. The linchpin of a standard
justification for privacy is, then, that individuals are autonomous moral agents,
which imply that they are entitled to some personal and private space where
they feel comfortable and where they do not have to behave as if they are being
watched all the time.
choose to reveal about himself, even though most people don’t care if these same facts are
widely known about themselves” (Parent, 1983, p. 270).
6
aware that the authority is watching them, but they don’t mind since they trust
the authority completely, then would we also say that their privacy rights are
threatened? According to Meyer, privacy appears to be an inherent property of
an autonomous agent, but these scenarios seem to complicate the picture a
little. Privacy may still be an inherent property in the case where people
willingly put up webcams in their bedrooms and even their bathrooms, and in
the case where the people trust the all seeing authority completely, but even so
their inherent property here is not expressed. Even if the property is there, it
lies dormant, so to speak, since the people willingly forego it. However, if this is
really the case, then what is the difference between someone’s having the
inherent characteristic of privacy but it lies dormant and someone’s not having
the right to privacy at all?
The difference, of course, lies in the fact that in the first case someone
could decide at any time to enforce her privacy right, which happens when, for
example, somebody shuts down her webcam, whereas in the second case that is
not possible. But if this is so, then the justification of privacy is not simply a
matter of someone’s being an autonomous moral agent who deserves respect,
his or her relation with those around her also play a crucial role. If she trusts the
all seeing authority completely, or if she does not think her private life should
be kept to herself alone and welcomes the world to see all of her, then the
trusting and the willingness to let others enter one’s private domain become
important. These are all relational concepts; one trusts another person, and one
willingly lets others enter one’s private life. After all, protecting privacy means
that one is protecting someone’s private domain from encroachments by others.
If one lives alone, like Robinson Crusoe, then there is no need to even start
talking about privacy.6
Another point is that it seems that one can even remain an autonomous
moral agent without one’s having privacy. In the scenarios described above, the
one who trusts the authority completely, who lives in an environment where
the authority is fully trustworthy, and who willingly foregoes privacy can still
be an autonomous moral agent, since all her decisions are made through her
free will in her rational capacity. An autonomous moral agent that willingly
6
In the same spirit, Priscilla Regan also argues for the concept of privacy being relational,
adding that the concept would be more useful if considered as relational rather than singular
(Regan, 1995).
8
puts up webcams around her house is still so. But if this is the case, then the
standard justification of privacy is in need of qualification. Being an
autonomous moral agent alone is not sufficient, one also needs to relate with
others and live in a certain kind of environment (such as one where it is not
possible to trust the authority completely), in order for the right to privacy to
actually have a force. Nevertheless, an objection to this line of argument is that
in these scenarios the individuals always have their privacy rights all along, but
as we have seen there does not seem to be much of a difference between having
the right to privacy and keeping it dormant (perhaps always so) and not having
it at all. This, let me emphasize, is tenable only in a very special case where the
authority can be trusted completely and where the individuals are willing to let
others view their lives, and this could be extended to include the individuals’
information about themselves, their communication and others (Regan 1995).
who that person is and nobody else without having to enter into any relation
with anything outside. So it would naturally appear that, according to the
standard argument for privacy, the existence of a self subsisting person is
presupposed. This standard justificatory picture is much in accordance with
common sense. After all, when one is justifying or defending privacy, one
naturally presupposes that there has to be a person whose privacy is to be
justified and that the person has to be metaphysically objective. Otherwise it
would be difficult to find a conceptual link between the metaphysically
objective person here and her status as an autonomous moral agent. Being an
autonomous moral agent would seem to presuppose that there is something
deep down inside functioning as the holder of the qualities of being
autonomous, being moral and being an agent.
Defending a conception of privacy that is closely related to that of
personhood, Jeffrey Reiman writes: “Privacy is a social ritual by means of
which an individual's moral title to his existence is conferred” (Reiman 1976, p.
39). An individual is recognized as one who deserves to be treated morally, i.e.,
as one who is morally entitled to existence, when his or her privacy is
respected. Respecting someone’s privacy, according to Reiman, is to recognize
that he or she exists as a human being who deserves to be treated as an end and
never as a means, to use Kant’s terms. Furthermore, Reiman adds that privacy
is necessary for the creation of the individual self (Reiman 1976, p. 39); for
without privacy, there is no way, according to Reiman, to an individual to be
recognized as such, since there would be no way for her to recognize that the
body to which she is attached is her own, to which she has exclusive rights
(including that of privacy). That recognition is the process by which the sense of
self of the individual is created, and it is in this sense that Reiman makes his
startling claim. Reiman further states: “[P]rivacy is a condition of the original
and continuing creation of ‘selves’ or ‘persons’” (Reiman 1976, p. 40). That is, so
long as someone’s privacy is respected, to that extent her selfhood and
personhood is thereby respected and recognized. Privacy, for Reiman, is a sine
qua non for the selfhood or personhood of someone; in other words, privacy
necessarily belongs to someone in virtue of her being ‘someone’ or ‘a person’ in
the first place.
If one were to search for strong arguments attempting to link privacy
with selfhood or personhood, Reiman’s must be among the first ones in the list.
10
7
Reiman might counter this argument saying that in the lack-of-privacy scenario, the
individuals there still possess their privacy right, even though they choose not to exercise them.
But then the difference between his and my conception in this case would be then that
according to Reiman, the privacy right is kept inside, unexpressed whereas in mine there is no
privacy in the first place. Assuming that there is no condition coming up that forces people to
exercise their dormant privacy rights, then there is no difference between his and my
conceptions at all. The individuals there would go about their lives and their lack of privacy,
and everything would remain the same no matter they actually have some privacy rights
hidden inside their own selves or not. But if the condition requiring people to enforce privacy
rights comes to the fore, such as when the authority is abusing their power, then according to
my conception the people can well devise ‘privacy rights’ as a means to counter the authority.
This devising does not seem to require that the concept is already there inside their selves.
11
8
Here Priscilla Regan is absolutely right when she said that the concept of privacy is relational
and is necessary for democracy. Democracy is certainly one of the desired goals brought about
by recognizing and enforcing the right to privacy. This is one of the best justifications for
privacy (Regan 2002, p. 399).
12
and it does not have to be there since the beginning where there is no need for
it.
beings, which is absurd, but that there is no substantive core that functions as
the ‘seat of identity,’ so to speak. Again this does not mean that humans have
no identities, which is also absurd. Having no substantive core means only that
the identity of a particular human being is a relational concept and is
constructed out of the human being’s interaction with her society and her other
contextual environments. As many research works have shown, one’s identity
is constructed out of one’s interaction with one’s friends, enemies, relatives, co-
workers, and society at large.
The relevance of this argument to the analysis of privacy is that there is a
way to justify privacy without relying on the idea of there being a metaphysical
concept of the person. One can rely only on what is obtainable through
empirical means. This way of providing justification is as strong as it can be,
because for one thing it is based on publicly observable entities and not on
metaphysical construction.9 The normative force of the argument related to
privacy would then be derived from shared meanings and understandings
rather than from abstract rationalization. Since identity of the person is
constructed through her interaction with the world, her privacy would
presumably be constructed out of such interaction also. And in more concrete
terms this would mean that the social world finds privacy to be important and
devise ways and means to enforce it. Since privacy is an imaginative line as we
have just seen, it is then constructed out of shared meanings and
understandings that members of the social group have together.
A common objection to the idea of basing privacy on the conception that
presupposes the person to be empirically constructed is that such a conception
of person would be too weak. A conception of the person that is empirically
based would, so the objection goes, not be appropriate to be a foundation for
the autonomous moral agent that seems to be required for a viable conception
of privacy. To put the point simply, if the person is always changing and
something that is constructed, then whose privacy is one trying to justify? If the
person is continuously changing without any substantial identity, then who
will be the autonomous moral agent? And without the agent where will the
concept of privacy come from? But if the autonomous moral agent is not
sufficient for privacy as we have seen, then the argument here loses much of its
9
But how to avoid the charge that this conception is relativist?
14
force. In fact the force of the objection is that, without the autonomous moral
agent, there would be no privacy, which implies that the autonomous moral
agent is necessary for privacy. But if the proposed conception of the person
which is based on empirical observation rather than metaphysical assumption
is tenable, then, on the assumption that the autonomous moral agent needs to
be a metaphysically substantial person, which seems to be accepted by those
who favors this line of argument, the autonomous moral agent is not even
necessary for privacy either.
That the autonomous moral agent is neither sufficient nor necessary for
privacy should come as no surprise, for the agent here is commonly taken to be
the substantially existing person whose identity is based on the metaphysical
assumption that grounds her identity even though no empirical correlate has
been found. And this should by no means be understood to mean that the
justification of privacy proposed here assumes that privacy is not a moral
concept. The conclusion that the autonomous moral agent is neither sufficient
nor necessary does not imply that privacy is not a moral concept because the
individuals in society can well construct a concept such as privacy as a tool for
regulating their lives and defining the relations between themselves and the
political authorities without thereby depending on metaphysical assumptions.10
This conception has another advantage to the standard one in that it fits
better with the emerging scenario where non-humans are becoming more like
humans and therefore deserve moral respect.11 As far as I know no robot has
been accorded with the right to privacy yet. We feel that we can watch and
monitor a robot and to mine any information from it (him?) to our heart’s desire
10
In addition, that the autonomous moral agent is neither sufficient nor necessary for privacy
should not be understood to imply that people are not autonomous moral agents in the sense
that they are capable for making moral judgments and decisions on their own. Nothing in my
argument leads to that absurd conclusion. The individuals in the no-privacy world, as we have
seen, are as moral and as autonomous as any in our world; only that they do not seem to take
privacy seriously and are happy leading their lives totally in public view. To them there is
nothing wrong with that. This does not mean that they are not moral agents.
11
Recently there has been an interest in how robots should be accorded with moral respect and
moral rights in some form. This is known as ‘roboethics.’ For example, Luciano Floridi and John
Sanders (2007) argue for a concept of moral agents and patients could be applied to non-
humans even though they are not capable of feeling or free will, such as early stage robots and
animals. Another interesting source is “Robots may one day ask for citizenship” (2007).
15
without infringing upon its (his?) privacy. But as robots mature enough and are
beginning to think and be conscious, then the question about robot privacy
presents itself. One way to think about this is, of course, to think that robots are
starting to attain the status of ‘autonomous moral agents;’ that is indeed the
case if being an autonomous moral agent does not imply that robots somehow
instantiate the abstract model of rationality that have informed humans being
long before. Instead of assuming that the autonomous moral agent is a
metaphysically substantive entity, we might consider robots more simply as
ones who are starting to become like us humans. That is, they are becoming
capable of talking, understanding, planning, desiring, dreaming, and so on,
characteristics that have defined humans. In this case they deserve privacy. At
any rate, it is simpler just to view robots as becoming more like humans than to
assume that they are starting to instantiate the abstract model of rationality and
moral agency, assumption that incurs the added burden of explaining the
identity and the justification for the existence of the said model.
Group Privacy
So how does the proposed conception play out in real life? Here is
another distinct advantage of the proposed conception over the mainstream
one. In emphasizing the role of the individual, the mainstream conception
appears to neglect the importance of families and social groups, whose privacy
needs to be protected also.12 Privacy of families is violated when the authority
or somebody intrudes upon family life with no justified reason. What is
happening inside a family seems to be a private matter to the family itself;
intrusion is justified only in case where it is suspected that there are physical or
verbal abuses going on within the family, in which case the rights of individual
family members to bodily integrity trumps over the family’s right to privacy.
Here the proposed conception fares better because it is not tied up with
justifying privacy through the individual. According to the standard picture,
12
There are only a few references in the literature on privacy that pay attention to group
privacy. Olinger, Britz and Olivier (Olinger et al. 2007) discussed the African concept of Ubuntu,
which puts the interests of the group before those of the individuals. Patton (2000) recognizes
the value of group privacy and sees that sociality plays a complimentary role in the analysis
and justification of privacy.
16
13
I discussed some of the issues surrounding this problem in Hongladarom (forthcoming).
18
protected against the potential abuse by the authority, so too needs the privacy
of a group.
Conclusion
References
14
Research leading to this paper is partly funded by a grant from the Thailand Research Fund,
grant no. 4980016. I would like to thank Prof. Vichai Boonsaeng for his unfailing support.
19
Rachels, James. (1975). Why privacy is important. Philosophy & Public Affairs,
4(4), 323-333.
Rananand, Pirongrong Ramasoota. (2007). Information privacy in a
surveillance state: a perspective from Thailand. In S. Hongladarom and
C. Ess (Eds.) Information Technology Ethics: Cultural Perspectives (pp. 124-
137). Hershey, PA: Idea Group Reference.
Regan, Priscilla M. (1995). Legislating Privacy: Technology, Social Values, and
Public Policy. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Regan, Priscilla M. (2002). Privacy as a common good in a digital world.
Information, Communication and Society, 5(3), 382-405.
Reiman, Jeffrey H. (1976). Privacy, intimacy and personhood. Philosophy &
Public Affairs, 6(1), 26-44.
Robots may one day ask for citizenship, available at
http://media.www.guilfordian.com/media/storage/paper281/news/2
007/03/23/World/Robots.May.One.Day.Ask.For.Citizenship-
2788091.shtml, retrieved May 13, 2007.
Sandel, M. (1998). Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. 2nd ed. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Scanlon, Thomas. (1975). Thomson on privacy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 4(4),
315-322.
Taylor, Charles. (1975). Hegel. Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, Charles. (1989). Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Thailand introduces national ID with biometric technology, available at
http://www.secureidnews.com/weblog/2005/04/15/thailand-
introduces-national-id-with-biometric-technology/, retrieved May 9,
2007.
The Dalai Lama. (1996). The Buddha Nature: Death and Eternal Soul in Buddhism.
Woodside, CA: Bluestar Communications.
Thompson, Judith Jarvis. (1975). The right to privacy. Philosophy & Public
Affairs, 4(4), 295-314.
Varela, Francisco J. and Bernhard Poerksen. (2006). “Truth Is What Works”:
Francisco J. Varela on cognitive science, Buddhism, the inseparability of
subject and object, and the exaggerations of constructivism—a
conversation. The Journal of Aesthetic Education, 40(1), 35-53.