Marketing and Interdependent Behaviour
Marketing and Interdependent Behaviour
Marketing and Interdependent Behaviour
Engendering Change
Joshua S. Gans
2
The terminology of “accommodation” and “escape” I borrow from Myrdal (1957)
and Galbraith (1979).
392 Joshua S. Gans
z
x
x
Figure 1. Multiple Equilibria
What are the possible equilibria of this type of game? To simplify
matters, I will assume for the rest of the paper that all workers have the
same underlying economic characteristics (although their observed
characteristics may ultimately differ in equilibrium) and focus my attention
on pure strategy symmetric Nash equilibria (SNE). As such, I will suppress
the worker subscript in what follows. x̂ is, therefore, a SNE strategy profile
for the discrimination game if (i) x̂ c B(x), ¼i ; and (ii) x = f({x̂}; h ). Thus, in
equilibrium, workers choose levels of investment that maximize their
payoffs, and the aggregate level of education used by employers is consistent
Engendering Change 395
of the kind faced here. So while these models have, in the past, pointed out
the need for change, there has been little discussion of what alternative
mechanisms would be best for actually engendering change.
2 Dynamics of Escape
Gunnar Myrdal was the first economist to recognize the possibility that a
virtuous circle could break the equilibrium of discrimination. Having
outlined the feedbacks generating the problem, Myrdal continued,
White prejudice and low Negro standards thus mutually “cause” each other. If at a
point of time things tend to remain about as they are, this means that the two forces
balance each other: white prejudice and the consequent discrimination against the
Negroes block their efforts to raise their low plane of living; this, on the other hand,
forms part of the causation of the prejudice on the side of whites which leads them to
discriminatory behavior.
In showing how this is so, the first order of business is to make some
assumptions about how beliefs evolve over time. It has already been assumed
that employer beliefs about a worker’s investment are some nondecreasing
function of the current actual education investments of the group, i.e..,
x = f({x i } icL ) . What is crucial, however, is that workers be persuaded to
change their behavior. This will depend on their expectations regarding
what the future level of employer beliefs will be. To see this, observe that at
time t, each worker solves, max xi,t cX o(x i,t , x t ). Here, each worker maximizes
their payoff contingent upon their expectation regarding the aggregate
employer beliefs in that period. The dynamic sequence of observation and
action is depicted in Figure 2. For simplicity, it is assumed that when there
are multiple best responses to a set of beliefs, then the highest strategy is
chosen. Note, however, that is possible that sophisticated agents forming
rational expectations could, even at strategies close to the high equilibrium,
form expectations that drive them back to the low equilibrium. Thus, some
restrictions on how workers use past observations of the aggregate to form
their expectations are required to ensure that an escape, once begun, will
continue.
Given this, how might workers adjust their expectations over time? x t is
considered to be the state variable in the analysis that follows. Consider the
following very weak definition of adaptive expectations.
7
A probability density function, g(x; l) satisfies the monotone likelihood ratio
g(x;l)
property (MLRP) in a parameter l if g(x;lÂ) is monotone nonincreasing in x for
all l < l . If G(x; l) is the probability that the random variable exceeds x, then
the MLRP implies thatG(x; l) [ G(x; lÂ) , for all x. This definition does not,
however, allow for comparisons when changes in the parameter ,l, alter the
support of the density. Suppose that x c · , and let S(l) h x g(x; l) > 0 .
Then g(x; l) satisfies the (generalized) MLRP if given any x c S(l) and
g(x;l)
y c S(lÂ) , (i) min[x, y] c S(l) and max[x, y] c S(lÂ) ; (ii) for all l < l , g(x;lÂ)
is monotone nonincreasing in x for all x c S(l) 3 S(lÂ) . The (generalized)
MLRP is shown by Athey (1994) to be equivalent to Ormiston and Schlee’s
(1993) definition of MLR dominance. She also shows that the MLRP is a special
case of the (generalized) MLRP. I allow for the more general definition here to
allow for the possibility that agents’ expectations put unit one mass on a single
level of x, something essential in game theoretic contexts. This definition is also
applied in Gans (1995).
Engendering Change 399
8
Note also, that if agents were forward looking and maximized the present value of
payoffs this period, i.e.., solved max {xi,t } S smt d s−t o(x i,s , x s ), 0 < d < 1 ,
Theorem 1 would continue to hold. In addition, allowing for heterogeneous
payoffs does not alter the momentum result if the player set is assumed to be
finite. In that case, the result would state that if ever there was a time that a single
worker adjusted optimal investment upwards, systemic momentum would follow.
400 Joshua S. Gans
will exist some critical level of the aggregate such that if this is generated all
future paths will converge to the high equilibrium.10
The other method by which one could incorporate more sophisticated
expectations formation assumptions into adjustment dynamics and still
guarantee convergence to the high equilibrium, is if the use of government
policy actually eliminated the low equilibrium. Milgrom and Roberts (1991)
have analyzed learning and adjustment processes in games. They define a
class of learning processes that includes best reply dynamics and more
sophisticated types of dynamics—such processes are consistent with
adaptive learning. If educational changes were irreversible to some degree,
then intervention may remove the low equilibrium. Then, as Milgrom and
Roberts (1991) have shown, play will converge to the unique higher
equilibrium regardless of the dynamic process assumed—whether
sophisticated or merely adaptive. Gans (1994) demonstrates this process in
more detail and the circumstances under which it might be relevant.
In summary then, a necessary element of any successful government
policy to engender change is to ensure a sustained escape. Indeed, it could be
argued that when considering policy in the face of coordination failure, it is
critical that the details of the situation at hand imply some dynamic
adjustment behavior that is path dependent for the government to intervene
successfully. However, in situations where the dynamic permits a significant
role for history, the goal of the government is to lift the aggregate of
employer beliefs above some critical level, f &. Beyond that level, transition
will be completed by the adjustment behavior of individual workers. But
generating that critical level depends on changing individual behavior
already in the grip of accommodation. In order to avoid adding complicating
conditions to the following analysis, I will suppose that the expectations of
workers only depend on the immediate past level of aggregate employer
beliefs. This removes any additional difficulties in generating the critical
aggregate caused by long-standing low expectations since expectations will
evolve in a similar manner to best reply dynamics. If this were not the case
then, regardless of the dynamics adjustment behavior assumed, a
government may have to intervene for longer periods of time in order to
convince workers to improve their education in the face of greater employer
beliefs. The other issues involved in achieving the critical aggregate are the
subject of the next section.
10
For an excellent discussion of the roles of history and expectations along these
lines see Krugman (1991)
402 Joshua S. Gans
(5) f =
& ° x di &a
e x& = f &
0
Note that x & does not depend upon α, due to the (assumed)
homogeneity of the employer belief function. The critical mass for any
unbalanced mechanism with target worker investment, x̃, is determined by,
1
k & (x̃) 1 a
f & a −y a
(6) f & = ° x̃ a di + ° y a di g k & (x̃) = x̃ a −y a
0 & k (x̃)
Under this parameterization, therefore, k & (x̃) is a continuously
differentiable function from X into [0,1].
If c(y,x) is also smooth we can represent the government’s transition
minimization problem as in Figure 3. The curve g represents the function
c(y, x̃(k & )) , where x̃(k & ) is the inverse of k & (x̃) . This inverse exists because
k & is monotonically decreasing in x̃. A simple check also verifies that so
long as c(y,x) is not too concave in x, g is convex. The curve TC represents
the total transition cost function,
(7) c(y, x̃) =
TC
k & (x̃)
Figure 3 depicts the types of optimal policies that are possible. In (a),
the balanced mechanism minimizes transition costs, whilst in (b) an interior
solution is depicted. In Figure 3 (c) targeting a small number of workers to
use a high strategy is optimal.
Engendering Change 407
(a )
c ( y ,x ) g
T C
*
c (y , x )
1 k
*
(b )
c (y ,x ) g
T C
c ( y , x̃ )
*
c (y , x )
k
*
( x̃ ) 1
(c )
c ( y ,x )
T C
*
c (y ,x )
1 k
*
basin of attraction of the high equilibrium shrinks. This means that the
critical aggregate that ensures convergence a successful escape is greater
and hence, a more unbalanced mechanism will be preferred.
Another potential influence on the choice of mechanism is the level of
individual increasing returns. If the total costs associated with raising
personal investment rise at a slower rate, then the marginal increase in
individual transition costs associated with a higher target strategy could be
lower. This could be the case because of initial startup costs in improving
human capital. Thus, we could imagine individual transition costs to be
some function c(y,x;b) where b parameterizes the marginal cost increase of a
higher x. It is straightforward to show that lower levels of b imply a greater
target strategy and hence, a more unbalanced mechanism. Thus, greater
individual returns to scale of investment will tend to cause the government
to favor a more unbalanced mechanism.
In summary, in this section, it has been shown that the government will
find a more unbalanced mechanism to be cost minimizing the more flexible
are employer beliefs, the higher the critical aggregate is, and the more
personal investment is characterized by individual increasing returns to
scale. Indeed, for a resource starved policy-maker, paying attention to these
economic characteristics may determine what type of successful escape is
feasible at all.
5 Conclusions and Extensions
The particular policy choices facing a government in its coordination role
have been neglected by economists until now. This paper has highlighted,
within the context of a model of statistical discrimination in the labor
market, some of the issues confronting governments attempting to change
an economy or game from one equilibria to another. In so doing, the
possibility of escape (under adaptive expectations) was identified. Moreover,
the notion that individual agents need to be convinced to change their
behavior by a sufficient amount to break the hold of accommodation was
emphasized. In such situations, the policy choices facing a government
involve how best to change individual behavior to move them out of the
basin of attraction of the low equilibrium. Note though that these
considerations apply to many models with public good elements that exhibit
strategic complementarities, beyond the application discussed here.
Given these findings, this paper has turned to focus on whether a
government should target a small number of individuals for change or adopt
a wider coverage. In the context of discrimination in the labor market, the
flexibility of employer beliefs and individual returns to scale were singled
out as critical determinants of whether a balanced or unbalanced mechanism
was cost minimizing. But the assumptions of the game presented abstract
410 Joshua S. Gans
from other factors that might affect the choice of balanced or unbalanced
change.
First, the worker’s strategy choice is currently assumed to be
unidimensional. One could imagine that it is more complex than this.
Indeed, it may be multidimensional taking into account differing aspects of
education and other investments that improve productivity. Much of the
analysis will continue to hold if vector of strategy variables available to an
agent were in turn complementary with one another (Milgrom and Roberts
1990). If this is the case, one could then expand the range of mechanisms
available for change. For instance, one might have unbalanced mechanisms
that attempt to change an individual’s behavior on all dimensions or perhaps
target some variables by a large amount, leaving the rest to adjust by later
momentum.
Second, the game as presented is symmetric in that all workers possess
the same payoff functions, face the same aggregate and have the same
impact on the aggregate. Introducing heterogeneity complicates matters by
making the definitions of balanced and unbalanced mechanisms less clean.
Suppose, however, that agents only differed in their costs of investment.
That is, o i = w(t, x) − c i x , where c i is the individual investment cost. In that
case, since all agents make the same contribution to aggregate employer
beliefs, it is clear that the definition of a balanced mechanism remains the
same, while the least cost unbalanced mechanism would have those with the
lowest investment costs being targeted first. This would continue to be the
case if those with the lowest costs also had the greatest impact on the
aggregate. However, if this were not the case, then a tradeoff between low
costs and greater contributions to the aggregate exists. Nonetheless, a
complete analysis of the issues of the optimal composition of a critical mass
lie beyond the scope of the dissertation.
Throughout the paper the government was assumed to be a purely
external facilitator of change and to possess an external source of resources.
Government intervention did not change, permanently, the best response
correspondences of agents or if it did, it did so positively. But it is well
documented from social psychology that social interventions can have
unintended negative feedback effects. In the 1930s, what has become known
as the Cambridge-Somerville experiments were conducted in impoverished
neighborhoods near Boston. The idea was to take a selection of children
from these neighborhoods and devote (virtually) unlimited social work and
other resources to helping them escape poverty traps. Thus, education and
health care were provided. Regular visits, monitoring and counseling was
provided by social workers. Basically, all the ingredients that one could hope
for. Nonetheless, years later, the basic social statistics for measuring an
Engendering Change 411
15
For a discussion of this experiment see Ross and Nisbett (1991)
412 Joshua S. Gans
Ross, L. and Nisbett, R. E., 1991. The Person and the Situation:
Perspectives in Social Psychology, McGraw-Hill, New York.
Sowell, T., 1983. The Economics and Politics of Race, Morrow, New York
Steele, C., 1992. “Race and the Schooling of Black Americans”, The
Atlantic Monthly, April: 68-78.
Swan, T., 1962. “Cumulative Causation”, Economic Record, December:
421-426.
Van Huyck, J. B., Cook, J. P., and Battalio, R. C., 1992. “Adaptive Behavior
and Coordination Failure”, mimeo.